(Lesson Seven) Utilitarianism
(Lesson Seven) Utilitarianism
(Lesson Seven) Utilitarianism
INTRODUCTION
What makes an action right so that we have a moral obligation to perform it? Is it
that it “comes from the right place,” as it were - in other words, is
the motive behind an action what endows the action with moral value? Or is it,
rather, the consequences of the action that determine its moral value?
Many people will want to say that the moral value of action depends upon the
motive behind the action, regardless of the action’s consequences. German
philosopher Immanuel Kant offered what is arguably the most rigorous philosophical
account of this ethical standpoint in history, and we will consider this account next
week. This position is often referred to as intentionalism.
Others, however, would point out that “the road to hell is often paved with good
intentions” - the purest motives, that is, can sometimes result in morally
objectionable outcomes. These people argue that the consequences of action
determine its moral value. In philosophy this position is
called consequentalism. This week we will be considering a very popular
consequentialist ethical standpoint called utilitarianism.
Here is another example: someone who loves wisdom studies philosophy, because
studying philosophy makes her happy. In this example, studying philosophy is an
instrumental good (so is philosophy itself) to the extent that it secures another good
thing, happiness. Ask yourselves, however, whether happiness is
another instrumentalgood.
Does the goodness of happiness depend upon its usefulness in securing something
else? Many people say no, claiming that happiness is something that is pursued for
its own sake, not for the sake of some further good. In other words, happiness is
good in itself, independently of any uses to which it may be put. Happiness, in short,
is an intrinsic good.
Critical reflection, however, reveals that this is an untenable standpoint. People tend
to value healthy living as a necessary condition for enjoying their lives or
living fulfillinglives, but these things - enjoyment and fulfilment - are attitudinal
varieties of ... happiness. Consequently, happiness in the form of joy or fulfilment
turns out to be the intrinsic good and healthy living is an instrumental good after all.
Most of us would question the value (or good) both of joyless healthy living and of
living healthily but in an unfulfilling way. The only exception to this is when healthy
living is itself a source of joy or fulfilment - only then we consider a life of healthy
living good. This still reduces healthy living to an instrumental good, however, since
it is a way of securing happiness as something good in itself.
Just think of it this way: imagine that medication existed that could ensure a disease-
free life span of two hundred years. The only drawback is an unavoidable side-effect
of the medication: taking it makes it impossible to experience any sort of happiness
ever again. If it were the case that happiness is good merely as a means to securing
health, then people would take the medication without question, since it is a
comparatively better means of securing health than happiness is. Would you take the
medication?
There are good grounds for thinking that happiness, however it might be understood
or characterized, is in fact an intrinsic good for most people. This factual assertion is
foundational to utilitarianism, but it does not tell us everything we need to know
about this quite interesting moral theory. Utilitarianism identifies happiness as the
ultimate intrinsic good not only as a fact but also in a moral sense. What this means
is that securing happiness not only is in fact the ultimate aim of life, but that it
also ought to be the ultimate aim of life, and that everything we do ought
to promote happiness.
According to the most widespread form of utilitarianism (which, for reasons that will
become clear later in this lesson, is called act utilitarianism) there is only one basic
moral principle, the principle of utility:
If you think that the morally right course of action is the one that makes the largest
number of people the most happy, then you are a utilitarian.
CONSEQUENTIALISM
Because utilitarianism makes the consequence of an action - specifically, whether or
not an action is optimific - the only relevant property when considering whether or
not the action is right or wrong, utilitarianism is correctly identified as a
consequentialist moral theory.
It is not the only such theory. There are at least two others: (1) ethical
egoism,according to which (as we have already seen) an act is right, and so ought to
be performed, if it promotes the greatest happiness of the agent him or herself,
regardless of what this means in terms of other people’s happiness; and (2) ethical
altruism,according to which an action is right, and so ought to be performed, if it
promotes the greatest happiness of the greatest number, but without taking the
agent’s own happiness into account.
By contrast, for utilitarianism any given unit of pleasure in one person is worth no
more or less, from a moral point of view, than the same unit of pleasure in any other
person. Who these people are - ourselves, our parents, our siblings, our friends,
strangers, people we dislike, our enemies - makes no difference whatsoever when
adding up pleasure units so as to choose our course of action. Consequently,
utilitarianism might require that we ignore our own happiness or the happiness of
our loved ones if doing so secures the greatest happiness of the greatest number.
UTILITRAIANISM AS HEDONISM
Most utilitarians would accept the identification of happiness with pleasure and the
absence of pain (and unhappiness with pain and the absence of pleasure). Generally
speaking, therefore, utilitarianism tends to be hedonistic. The standpoint
of hedonism, as was discussed in Lesson One, is that pleasure is and ought to be the
ultimate aim in life.
"The greatest happiness," however, does not necessarily just mean the
greatest quantityof happiness. “Greatest” here may refer to quality as well as
quantity. J.S. Mill held that some pleasures are better than others, even if the former
come in comparatively lesser amounts or involve comparatively more pain than the
latter.
John Stuart Mill and Helen Taylor. Helen was the daughter of Harriet Taylor and collaborated with Mill for
fifteen years after her mother's death in 1858. [Wikipedia]
What is the test for deciding which of two pleasures is of higher quality? If all or most
people with a knowledge of both pleasures prefer one over the other, even if the
one preferred comes in smaller amounts and involves more pain than the other,
then the one preferred is superior in quality to the other.
This position, while protecting high culture, has some problematic implications. What
if Plato-pleasure is assigned so much value that it is worth a colossal amount of
physical exertion? This might seem to justify putting a lot of people to work so that a
few people can enjoy Plato. Given the supposed strict impartiality of utilitarianism,
furthermore, it doesn’t matter who is doing the working and who is doing the
reading - making a majority work so that a minority can read at leisure is perfectly
compatible with the principle of utility, if you accept the strong comparative
valuation of high culture that Mill wants to promote.
If securing the greatest happiness of the greatest number is the only morally relevant
property of an action, then all sorts of conduct that we tend to consider immoral
from the standpoint of human rights or justice might be not only morally permissible
but morally obligatory, such as the persecution and even the extermination of
innocent human beings. If the greatest happiness of the greatest number depended
upon the unjust execution of an innocent human being, for example, then
utilitarianism would demand that the execution take place. We consider such actions
immoral, however, to the extent that we recognize human beings as having a right to
life, and forms of justice that can't be simply reduced to maximum happiness.
More recently, science fiction writer Ursula K. LeGuin wrote a short story “The Ones
Who Walk Away from Omelas,” which makes the same point. The community of a
fictional place called Omelas has managed to overcome all of the sources of suffering
that we continue to struggle with - poverty, disease, etc. Eventually, it is discovered
that the prosperity of Omelas depends upon keeping a young child locked in a dark
cellar, alone. Some of the members of the community, upon finding this out, leave
town, despite the prosperity they enjoy there, presumably because they believe that
some things are wrong regardless of whether or not they are "optimific."
UTILITARIANISM VS COMMITMENT
Philosopher Bernard Williams offered a particularly interesting criticism of
utilitarianism. Utilitarianism, he remarked, commits an assault upon human integrity,
which is maintained through the pursuit of projects in keeping with our most basic
commitments. Let’s say that you have devoted your life to something, but you have
found out that securing the greatest happiness of the greatest number requires that
you completely abandon the object of your devotion. In such circumstances,
utilitarianism morally obliges you to do so.
Williams offers a good example of this: let’s say that you are chemist and a pacifist
who has had some trouble finding work. A friend tells you that the military wants to
hire a chemist to develop chemical weapons, and the only candidate is a chemist
who loves the thought of people dying by inhaling, drinking, or eating poisonous
compounds that he has developed. Your friend can put in a good word for you with
the hiring committee, which will almost certainly result in your being hired. Another
near certainty is that there would be less happiness in the world if the homicidal
chemist were given the job than if you were. According to utilitarianism, you are
morally obliged to take the job.
But you don't want to make chemical weapons; you feel it is wrong. This sort of
requirement utilitarianism makes on you to take the job, Williams thought, makes
nothing of the deep commitments we actually have, the ones that endow our lives
with a purpose and direction. We can be called upon to totally abandon our
commitments to satisfy the principle of utility.
Under such circumstances we are likely to save our mothers, but the question is
whether or not there is any moral justification for doing so. Are people with whom
we have personal ties or bonds ever deserving of special moral consideration? Is
behaving as if they are so deserving morally impermissible given the alleged moral
requirement of complete impartiality?
This is a very attractive aspect of the theory, as it is consistent with some of our strongest moral
intuitions concerning the moral treatment of non-human animals. There seems to be something
right about making the capacity to suffer (as opposed to intelligence, for instance) the property
by which a being gains membership in the moral community.
What’s more, the moral value of our actions depends entirely upon whether or not
we manage to choose what in fact does secure the greatest happiness of the
greatest number, so the less we are able to know concerning the effects of our
actions, the more the moral value of those actions is a matter of luck.
Even assuming that we could somehow know everything we need to know to be able
to choose actions that do in fact secure the greatest happiness of the greatest
number, we would often need to be able to access and process this data in a very
brief span of time, since many situations that call for a moral decision do so with
urgency: for example, someone drowning in a river on whose bank you, an
experienced swimmer with a knowledge of CPR, are standing. Can utilitarianism
provide sure moral guidance in situations like this?
J.S. Mill offered a response to this objection. We can, he thought, rely upon
accumulated experience, not only our own but that of those who came before us,
concerning which actions and which kinds of actions tend to secure the greatest
happiness of the greatest number, so that we need not attempt to perform a
utilitarian calculation - to “reinvent the wheel,” as it were - every time we are faced
with a moral choice.
QUANTIFYING HAPPINESS
Although we can often roughly distinguish between very sad, sad, happy and very
happy states in ourselves, this is a very far cry from the precise pleasure-unit
arithmetic utilitarianism requires if it is to result in more than mere rough
estimations.
Some even deny that happiness or pleasure is really quantitative at all and, hence,
claim that it cannot be measured. Isn’t every pleasure qualitatively distinct from
every other pleasure and, hence, impossible to quantitatively compare with any
other pleasure? Can the pleasure you feel when reading a good book, eating a sweet,
meeting a friend after an extended time apart, and waking up after a restful sleep all
be reduced to quantities of interchangeable pleasure units?
RULE UTILITARIANISM
DEONTOLOGY
Kantian moral philosophy is referred to as deontological, which means that it
emphasizes duty or obligation in its account of morality. (“Deontology” comes from
the Greek deon, which means “obligation” or “necessity.”)
According to Kant, an action must be done from duty to have any moral worth. He
identifies four kinds of actions in relation to duty:
Here are examples of each of these four kinds of conduct, in relation to the duty to
tell the truth:
The only unproblematic example when it comes to assessing the moral worth of an
action is (1), whose moral worthlessness is easily discernible. The moral
worthlessness of (2) is not as clearly observable as that of (1), because the motive
could be concealed, but it is nevertheless beyond question, for if the motive behind
such conduct were clearly observable, it would be judged morally worthless.
With example (3), however, the moral worthlessness of the motive is less obvious:
Isn’t someone who finds happiness and for that reason seeks happiness in
performing his or her moral duty - in this example, truth-telling - a morally good
person?
Not according to Kant. The truth telling must be performed because it is a duty,
regardless of whether or not truth telling is a source of happiness. Acting in
accordance with a duty to tell the truth out of love for the truth is morally worthless,
Kant thought, while acting in accordance with a duty to tell the truth strictly because
it is one’s duty to do so, even if one has no feelings for or even hates the
truth, possesses full moral value. The person who does what is right because it is
gratifying to do so, on Kant’s view, is at best good-natured, but not moral.
Add to this, finally, that people often are also prone to self-deception and repression
regarding their own motives in their need or desire to appear morally good rather
than narrowly self-interested or malicious to themselves as well as to other people.
Modern philosophers and psychologists have found many problems with applying
Kant's standards to real human behaviour.
For Kant, however, none of this has anything to do with morality itself: morality is
what it is, regardless of whether or not human beings have or even can conduct
themselves according to it. It is an absolute. It is also very important to keep in mind
that Kant was not saying that the absence of any personal inclinations is a necessary
condition for acting from duty. Inclinations may be either present or absent in people
engaged in conduct possessing moral value, and may even be satisfied by that
conduct; it is only that the moral value of the conduct in question depends upon its
not being engaged in just because it may satisfy some inclination or other.