Statistical Thermodynamics
Statistical Thermodynamics
Statistical Thermodynamics
STATISTICAL THERMODYNAMICS
Introduction
Encyclopedia of Polymer Science and Technology. Copyright John Wiley & Sons, Inc. All rights reserved.
Vol. 8 STATISTICAL THERMODYNAMICS 71
Macroscopic objects contain many atoms and molecules. Although these elements
may obey the laws of (quantum) mechanics, it is extremely costly, and often mean-
ingless, to know the mechanical motion of each element. Fortunately, these objects
obey their own macroscopic laws, as demonstrated empirically. Typical examples
of these laws are thermodynamics and hydrodynamics. These laws describe rela-
tions among macroscopic observables. They are usually called phenomenological
laws and are often regarded as less fundamental than, eg, the laws of mechanics.
However, the laws of, eg, thermodynamics are asymptotically exact, and should
not be regarded as an inaccurate approximation of something more fundamental.
It should not be forgotten that the laws of mechanics are also empirical laws. The
founding fathers of statistical mechanics, including Gibbs and Einstein, tried to
justify thermodynamics with mechanics, but the subsequent history tells us that
the mechanics they relied on was less reliable than thermodynamics.
To understand systems consisting of many elements with the aid of thermo-
dynamics and mechanics is the objective of statistical thermodynamics. The ad-
vent of single macromolecule experimental methods emphasizes the importance
of the study of mesoscopic systems and fluctuations. Macroscopic and mesoscopic
observables (henceforth simply called macro-observables) are interpreted as sums
of many microscopic quantities or coarse-grained stochastic quantities. Thus, elu-
cidating macroscopic or mesoscopic behavior in terms of the properties of elements
inevitably becomes statistical. The laws of large numbers and the large deviation
principle (8) become the key mathematical tools.
The problems in statistical thermodynamics fall into two categories. The first
category involves the study of the structure of phenomenological framework and
the interrelations among macro-observables without calculating their actual val-
ues. The second category involves the calculation of the actual values of param-
eters appearing in the phenomenology from more microscopic parameters. The
first category concerns finding and explaining the relationships among macro-
observables appearing in the description of a class of states of materials. The
two main problems are to recognize well-defined classes of phenomena, called
universality classes, and to construct suitable models (the so-called minimal mod-
els) for these classes. These models are statistical but their elements need not
be molecules or atoms. There is a wide range of choice of elementary objects;
truly atomistic pictures can even be counterproductive. A typical problem in the
second category is to compute phenomenological parameters, eg, viscosities or
phase-transition temperatures, which, by definition, reflect the specificity of the
individual systems. For the second-category problems, the source of the micro-
scopic parameters is delicate; they are often obtainable only through macroscopic
comparisons. Thus, it is difficult to obtain model-free conclusions, although prac-
tically useful results may be obtained.
Equilibrium Problems
1 − H({q})/kB T
P({q}) = e (1)
Z
with the micro–macro relation dictated by the expression for the Helmholtz free
energy A:
A= − kB T log Z (2)
satisfies the above compatibility requirement. Here, {q} collectively denotes the
microscopic coordinates, H({q}) is the Hamiltonian of the system, kB is the Boltz-
mann constant, and T is the absolute temperature. Z is the normalization constant
of the distribution called the canonical partition function:
Z= e − H/kB T (3)
where the summation is the sum (integral) over all the microscopic states. A phys-
ical derivation of the canonical ensemble was given by Einstein, whose starting
point was the principle of equal probability: the probability of finding a microstate
on a constant-energy surface is independent of the microstate (the microcanoni-
cal ensemble). Einstein introduced the canonical ensemble as a subensemble of
a microcanonical ensemble. Then, he identified heat as the energy imported to
the microscopic degrees of freedom, and derived equation 2 (for a historical ac-
count see Ref. 10). There are many arguments demonstrating the naturalness of
the canonical distribution. Lenard (11) demonstrated, crudely put, that the dis-
tribution of microstates as given by the canonical distribution is equivalent to
Vol. 8 STATISTICAL THERMODYNAMICS 73
the second law in the form of “passivity”, A ≤ W, where W is the work done to
the system to change it from an initial to a final equilibrium state at the same
temperature, with A being the free-energy change between these two states. A
stronger statement is possible [Jarzynski’s equality (12)]
e − W/kB T = e − A/kB T (4)
Nonequilibrium Problems
Even more challenging problems than those discussed above arise from the con-
sideration of time-dependent and nonequilibrium properties of macroscopic sys-
tems. Unfortunately, there is no general theoretical framework tantamount to the
Gibbs statistical mechanics. Most likely, there is no universality class that can
be called the macroscopic nonequilibrium class. There is, however, a class that
may be called the linear nonequilibrium class. Its phenomenological framework is
the linear nonequilibrium thermodynamics, which contains several fundamental
laws: the second law as the positivity of entropy produced inside the system as a re-
sult of dissipation; phenomenological linear force–flux relations; and the Onsager
reciprocity stating the symmetry relations among kinetic coefficients (19,20). We
also assume that thermodynamic relations hold locally in space (this is called the
local equilibrium assumption).
The fundamental statistical thermodynamic idea for the linear nonequilib-
rium class is that fluctuations can spontaneously realize nonequilibrium states in
74 STATISTICAL THERMODYNAMICS Vol. 8
dA δF
= v(A) − L + f (5)
dt δA
BIBLIOGRAPHY
“Statistical Thermodynamics” in EPSE 2nd ed., Vol. 15, pp. 614–625, by Y. Oono, University
of Illinois.
1. M. Toda, R. Kubo, and N. Saito, Statistical Physics I Equilibrium Statistical Mechanics,
Springer-Verlag, New York, 1983.
2. R. Kubo, H. Ichimaru, T. Usui, and N. Hashitsume, Statistical Mechanics, North Hol-
land, Amsterdam, 1965.
3. L. D. Landau and E. M. Lifshitz, Statistical Mechanics, Pergamon Press, London,
1980.
4. R. Kubo, H. Ichimaru, T. Usui, and N. Hashitsume, Thermodynamics, North Holland,
Amsterdam, 1968.
5. H. B. Callen, Thermodynamics, Interscience Publishers, New York, 1960.
6. L. D. Landau and E. M. Lifshitz, Mechanics, Pergamon Press, London, 1976.
7. G. A. Baym, Lectures on Quantum Mechanics, Benjamin/Cummings Publishing Co.,
Reading, Mass., 1973.
8. R. Durrett, Probability: Theory and Examples, Wadsworth & Brooks Cole, Pacific Grove,
Calif., 1991.
9. E. H. Lieb and J. Yngvason, Phys. Rep. 310, 1 (1999).
10. L. Navarro, Arch. Hist. Exact Sci. 53, 147 (1998).
11. A. Lenard, J. Stat. Phys. 19, 575 (1978).
12. C. Jarzynski, Phys. Rev. Lett. 78, 2690 (1997).
13. J. Liphardt, S. Dumont, S. B. Smith, I. Tinoco Jr., and C. Bustamante, Science 296,
1832 (2002).
14. D. Ruelle, Statistical Mechanics, Rigorous Results, Benjamin, New York,
1969.
15. R. B. Israel, Convexity in the Theory of Lattice Gases, Princeton University Press,
Princeton, 1979.
16. J.-D. Deuschel and D. W. Strook, Large Deviation, Academic Press, New York,
1989.
17. R. S. Ellis, Entropy, Large Deviations, and Statistical Mechanics, Springer-Verlag, New
York, 1985.
18. Y. Oono, Prog. Theor. Phys. Suppl. 99, 165 (1989).
Vol. 8 STATISTICAL THERMODYNAMICS 77
52. B. Dünweg, D. Reith, M. Steinhauser, and K. Kremer, J. Chem. Phys. 117, 914
(2002); P. Ahlrichs, R. Evraers, and B. Dünweg, Phys. Rev. E 64, 040501(R)
(2001).
53. Y. Shiwa, Y. Oono, and P. W. Baldwin, Mod. Phys. Lett. B 4, 1421 (1990).
YOSHITSUGU OONO
University of Illinois