Journal of Philosophy, Inc. The Journal of Philosophy
Journal of Philosophy, Inc. The Journal of Philosophy
Journal of Philosophy, Inc. The Journal of Philosophy
Review
Author(s): John Boler
Review by: John Boler
Source: The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 73, No. 22 (Dec. 16, 1976), pp. 863-870
Published by: Journal of Philosophy, Inc.
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2025762
Accessed: 24-06-2016 20:30 UTC
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The
Journal of Philosophy
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Fri, 24 Jun 2016 20:30:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
BOOK REVIEWS 863
BOOK REVIEWS
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Fri, 24 Jun 2016 20:30:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
864 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Fri, 24 Jun 2016 20:30:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
BOOK REVIEWS 865
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Fri, 24 Jun 2016 20:30:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
866 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Fri, 24 Jun 2016 20:30:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
BOOK REVIEWS 867
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Fri, 24 Jun 2016 20:30:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
868 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
on to identify who are the winners and losers, we are left still
wondering what the game was.
The impact carries through to the more wide-ranging hypotheses
suggested in Leff's subtitle. At the level of the history of ideas, Leff's
major concern is with Ockham's role, conscious or not, in the shift
from a medieval emphasis on metaphysical structures of the world
to modern philosophical attitudes which stress conceptual struc-
tures: how we know. Now any such broad generalization needs some
adjustment on both ends. There would, after all, be no such thing
as idealism in modern thought had not some philosophers then
been more than a little concerned with metaphysical structure.
And Scotus's most notorious metaphysical entities (the formalities)
are characterized by a faithful commentator as on the order of
"what a truly knowing mind would conceive" 2; an analogous point
could be made for Aquinas (cf. Summa Theologica, I, Question 79,
article 3). But suppose we grant the general contrast. There remain
the questions: To what extent does Ockham contribute to the
change? Does this help us to understand his own achievement
rather than his influence on others (xiii)?
One theme Leff stresses is Ockham's insistence on the starting
point of knowledge in experience of individuals-I take it that is
what he means by "an epistemology of individual cognition" (124).
I would not deny that there is something to this, but I find the ac-
count of Ockham's "individual cognition" unclear and the implied
pictures of his predecessors a distortion. For my part, it seems
more promising to stress the affinity of Ockham's empiricism with
the "atomism" of logical positivism-a theory not much in favor
now but nonetheless clear enough in its motivation.
Leff's other major theme in the history of ideas is Ockham's
emphasis on the "discrepancy between individual things and our
concepts of natures and essences" (125). "Ockham was the first
thinker systematically to explore their differences whilst accepting
their interdependence" (xx; cf., 77, 237, 315). Now explicit concern
for the subtitles of forms of language as over against forms of being
is at least as old as Anselm. And, to take only the better known fig-
ures, Abailard, Aquinas, and Scotus insistently repeat, each in his
own favorite terminology, Aristotle's charge against Plato's Forms:
that they result from attributing to things the properties of signs.
Ockham's extension of this problematic to the categories is surely
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Fri, 24 Jun 2016 20:30:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
BOOK REVIEWS 869
important, but we will not know its full significance until we know
what is going on in Ockham's handling of the categories-the prob-
lem I alluded to before.
It is possible, even, that Ockham's epistemology may turn out to
be altogether too naive. He seems, at times, to assume that one can
simply look at things and then look at thoughts and compare
them; and this may be a correlate to his alleged insensitivity to the
logical aspects of Scotus's handling of the formalities. Moreover, in
contrast to the sophistication Ockham shows in many of his analyses
of language and logic, the concept, in his system, would seem to be
a virtus dormitativa: whatever is needed to fill the gap created by
his dismissal of the apparatus of concept formation in earlier
scholastics. (T. K. Scott's article, criticizing Ockham's theory of
intuitive cognition in this regard, is mentioned in the bibliography
but not treated in the text.)
"Ockham is an innovator" (xiii). Yes, but of a peculiar sort.
Ockham nearly always identifies his position with the antiqui and
criticizes the moderni; and there is no reason to doubt the tradi-
tional and conservative motives that lie close to the surface in his
efforts to rehabilitate the true Aristotle. To this end, Ockham will
introduce new terminology or reorient and simplify problems
and distinctions-all with a confidence that is easiest to account for
given this very orthodox purpose. Moreover, while the well-known
razor is, in the accepted view, primarily an anti-metaphysical
weapon, it is instructive to see how freely Ockham used it on the
logical discussions of his contemporaries. If, for example, their
concern for the quasi-physical problems and the analytical tech-
niques characteristic of Sophismata prove to be as significant for
the history of science as some researchers hypothesize, Ockham's
handling of these and related issues may come to seem quite reac-
tionary indeed.
Leff correctly insists that his point about Ockham's role in the
transition to the modern period does not require that Ockham
was self-consciously ushering in a new age (563). The question still
remains, though, as to what part of the weight of the transition was
actually borne by Ockham's thought. To me, it seems more likely
that it was Ockham's terminology rather than his thought that was
influential. Consequently, I would turn inside out Leff's claim that
Ockham's philosophy served to justify the procedures of the new
science (563): I think the new science may have, in the historical
context, served to justify ockhamism. The important point for the
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Fri, 24 Jun 2016 20:30:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
870 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
This content downloaded from 178.250.250.21 on Fri, 24 Jun 2016 20:30:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms