The Ethical Foundations of Marxism (PDFDrive)
The Ethical Foundations of Marxism (PDFDrive)
The Ethical Foundations of Marxism (PDFDrive)
MARXISM
Volume 3
EUGENE KAMENKA
First published in 1962
This edition first published in 2015
by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
and by Routledge
711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business
© 1962, 1972 Eugene Kamenka
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised
in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or
hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information
storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers.
Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered
trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to
infringe.
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Publisher’s Note
The publisher has gone to great lengths to ensure the quality of this reprint but
points out that some imperfections in the original copies may be apparent.
Disclaimer
The publisher has made every effort to trace copyright holders and would welcome
correspondence from those they have been unable to trace.
THE ETHICAL
FOUNDATIONS
OF MARXISM
by
EUGENE KAMENKA
I S B N o 7100 7360 7
Contents
Conclusions
ETHICS AND THE FOUNDATIONS OF MARXISM I91
BIBLIOGRAPHY OF WORKS CITED 200
INDEX 204
vi
Preface to the Second English Edition
i t is now almost ten years since this book was first published. I still
Canberra
1971
, EUGENE KAMENKA
ix
Preface to the Japanese Edition ( 1 9 6 5 )
xi
Preface to the First Edition ( 1 9 6 2 )
of a Marxist colour, with its insistence on ends and aims, its elevation
of economic rewards, did much to destroy what enterprise there was.
In their controversies with anarchists and syndicalists, Marxists may
have been able to expose much that was utopian in both movements.
But against the anarcho-syndicalist elevation of the free and enter
prising character of the existing working class, Marxists were upholding
a servile and unfree morality.
Partly as a result of Marx’s failure to deal positively with ethical
questions, as a result of his failure to highlight ways of life and organisa
tion over ‘ends’ and policies, ethical distinctions did not play a central
part in the splits and controversies that racked Marxism. The revision
ists in the 1890’s, it is true, made much ado about their Kantian ethics.
Bernstein proclaimed his seemingly sound slogan: ‘The movement is
everything, the goal is nothing.’ But Bernstein, for all this, preached
security and sufficiency all his life. The real issue confronting Marxists
was not ethics, but the consequences of their neglect of ethics. Marx
had been wrong in forecasting the imminent collapse of capitalism and
the growing pauperisation of the worker; no longer driven by needs,
Western workers were displaying their preference for rewards and
security over freedom and struggle. If one wanted to follow the
worker, the Marxist vision of a radically new society born of struggle
had to be abandoned. Socialism became a matter of negotiation and of
demand for improved conditions and greater security within the
existing society. This was the path of reformism. Notably, the Marxist
neglect of ethics prevented Marxists from attacking reformism for its
elevation of rewards and security: the orthodox Marxists had to argue
instead, quite implausibly, that the reformists were bound to fail, that
increased rewards and greater security could not last under capitalism.
Orthodox Marxists, clinging to the vision, had to find a substitute
for the proletariat. Lenin, drawing on Russian populism, found it in
the revolutionary intelligentsia and the centralised, hierarchical party
of professional revolutionaries acting as the ‘vanguard’ of the working
class, driving it beyond the bread-and-butter politics at which the
working class by itself would always remain. Enterprise was not to
be won by the worker, but for him.
The bringing of freedom and enterprise to somebody is not a free
but a despotic conception. Yet Marx, too, had seen freedom as some
thing that would be brought to the worker by ‘history’. Marx’s work
laid no foundations for thoroughly exposing the course the Communist
Party under Lenin was soon to follow. Indeed, his failure to see
xv
PREFACE
Karl Marx is still best known for the political and economic writings
of his maturity that were published in his own lifetime. These, and
these alone, form the popular corpus of Marx’s work; they have been
widely disseminated in English translations. For any thorough under
standing of Marx and his thought they are not enough. The ethical
enquirer, especially, must take into account Marx’s earlier, more
philosophical, writings and the notes and drafts not meant for publica
tion as they stood which Marx habitually made throughout his life.
Marx’s mature writings notoriously eschew any direct consideration
of ethical or philosophical questions; it is in the earlier writings and
private drafts that we shall find the key to his ethical views and their
puzzling place in his mature beliefs. The study that follows therefore
draws heavily on those of Marx’s writings that preceded the publication
of the Communist Manifesto in 1 848 and on the notes and drafts that
Marx compiled between 1850 and 1859. The former have been pub
lished in the language of composition (usually German) in the M arx-
Engels Gesamtausgabe, brought out by the Marx-Engels Verlag,
Frankfurt-Berlin, between 1927 and 1932. The latter, first published
in Moscow in 1939 and 1941, have been republished in the original
German by the Dietz Verlag, Berlin, under the title Grundrisse der
Kritik der politischen Oekonomie (1953). The major portion of these
writings has not been translated into English; the rendering of those
writings that have been translated is not always satisfactory. Greater
space than would otherwise be necessary has therefore been devoted to
the translation and presentation of relevant passages from these works.
Where the source reference is a foreign-language text, the translation
is my own unless otherwise indicated.
The Marx-Engels Gesamtausgabe was not completed, though it
contains all of Marx and Engels’ extant writings down to 1848 and the
entire Marx-Engels correspondence. Its original editor, the Communist
D. Riazanov, was removed; he died in a Stalinist prison. Some of
Marx’s writings had been tampered with in earlier editions and were
to be tampered with again in later Soviet editions; the Marx-Engels
Gesamtausgabe, most scholars agree, shows no signs of any conscious
xvi
PREFACE
1 Professor Lieber, of the Free University, Berlin, has very recently drawn
attention to a number of errors in the Gesamtausgabe version caused, he claims,
by the fact that Riazanov was working from photostat copies. None of the
suggested errors affects the citations or conclusions given below.
xvii
PREFACE
xix
7KLVSDJHLQWHQWLRQDOO\OHIWEODQN
Citations and Abbreviations
xxii
Preliminaries: Marx, Marxism
and Ethics
Truly great men and truly great works have something to say to
each generation. They do not come back as unrecognised elements of a
cultural inheritance; they come back, as Schumpeter put it, ‘in their
individual garb with their personal scars which people may see and
touch.’ 1 Each generation finds in them new features, new sources of
illumination. The specific predictions Marx made, which seemed so
important and challenging to earlier generations, now seem to us
false. The general canons that permeate Marx’s work—his recognition
of the relatedness of all social phenomena, his emphasis on the existence
of social conflict, on the impossibility of standing outside or of
manipulating society and on the importance of production in social
life— still need to be hammered home against voluntarists, individual
ists and social engineers; but poorly learnt as they may have been, they
bring us today no new, unsuspected insights. Yet Marx still has much
to say to us.
While the Marxist picture of capitalism still appeared to the less
able or more fanatical to be truthful and relevant, West European
Marxists were largely immersed in the task of ‘exposing’ the contradic
tions of capitalism. The relation of Marxism to ethics and the founda
tions of a positive morality of Communism did not seem burning
practical issues. When Marxists in the advanced industrial countries
did deal with ethics, they tended to concentrate on the Marxist critique
of morality, using it to distinguish their ‘scientific socialism’ from the
woolly, unscientific humanitarianism of liberals, social democrats and
revisionists. Even the serious critics of Marxism in this period, unless
themselves moralisers, mostly thought the Marxist relation to ethics a
side issue. On the whole, the attitude taken by Marxists accorded well
with the intellectual climate in capitalist countries. It could draw on the
science-worship of the late nineteenth century2 and the scientific
*3
7KLVSDJHLQWHQWLRQDOO\OHIWEODQN
PART ONE
If Marx was not a socialist at this stage, he was even more emphati
cally not a ‘scientist’, concerned with ‘brute facts’ rather than logical or
ethical ‘principles’. He did like to think of himself, from the beginning
of his intellectual quest, as an opponent of logical a priorism and
empty speculation. He saw himself as a man who derives logical
principles from reality and not reality from logical principles. As early
as 1837, he wrote in one of his verse epigrams:
But what Marx finds in the street is a logical ‘principle’, and generally
one of the most abstract and metaphysical kind. He does, of course,
criticise Hegel for a priorism; at least he does so in the first Hegel
critique if not yet in the dissertation. In the critique he attacks Hegel
vigorously for performing his deduction in the logical mind instead of
the actual mind and for treating world history as a mere illustration of
the mysterious life history of the Idea. He complains tellingly that
Hegel develops the world out of the logical concept, instead of develop
ing the logical concept out of the world. O f Hegel’s discussion of the
constitution, Marx exclaims: ‘Hegel gives us the constitution of the
concept instead of the concept of the constitution’ (M I, i-i, 420). But
it is with the concept of the constitution, or with the ‘concept’ of any
other thing, that Marx himself is concerned at this stage— not with the
actual existing thing itself. Nor is the ‘concept’ for Marx a ‘mere’
recognition of the common features of certain existing things. For him,
as for Hegel, it is their inner principle, the logical essence that deter
mines their development, but which in fact may not yet have broken
through into ‘empirical’ existence.
Marx, in fact, has as much contempt as Hegel for the ‘merely
empirical’, for treating things just as they are or ‘appear’. To do so,
Marx believed with Hegel, would be to see only the outer appearance,
and to see this one-sidedly, with the inevitable result of being caught
in seemingly irresolvable contradictions. True understanding can only
be gained by looking at the concept, the motive power which is in
things and yet outside them as their aim, the ‘energising principle’
which determines their character and development, not by external
compulsion, but as an inner self-realisation.
20
THE P HI L OS O P HY OF THE C ON C E P T
1 Marx, like Hegel, insists throughout his dissertation on equating what is seen
or conceived with our seeing or conceiving it. We are thus left with the impres
sion that when the Greeks changed their theory of the heavenly bodies the
heavenly bodies themselves changed. But this, of course, outrageous as it may
seem, is precisely what the Idealist denial of independence tends to suggest.
2 The above, necessarily brief, outline of Marx’s dissertation emphasises his
philosophical position rather than the mere anti-religious sentiment which it
helped to support and which was strongly expressed in Marx’s ‘Promethean*
preface, where those who rebel against the Gods were treated as the true heroes
of philosophy. For a fuller English summary of the dissertation see H. P. Adams,
K arl M arx in His Earlier Writings, pp. 27-41.
22
T HE P HI L OS O P HY OF T H E C ON C E P T
1 ‘That which is the Best/ Marx quotes approvingly from Aristotle in his
dissertation, ‘has no need of action but is itself the end/ Like the gods of Epicurus
and of Greek plastic art, it expresses the unlimited freedom of the subject in
dealing and grappling with objects.
23
T H E P R I M I T I V E E T HI C OF K A R L M A R X
once the dynamic form of all reality and its ultimate totality. Marx, on
the other hand, followed the Left Hegelians in identifying thought with
human self-consciousness, and the motive power of history with a
specifically human spirit or essence. We shall see later how Marx, in
consequence, rejects the non-human Absolute Idea as something alien
to humanity and to man, and regards its alleged social manifestations
(e.g., Hegel’s rational State and its organs) as attempts to erect authori
tarian social institutions ‘dominated by a spirit not their own’. This,
too, is why Marx can take the Hegelian criteria of rationality at face
value, and actually use them against Hegel’s complicated structure of
rights and duties. Similarly, Marx rejects Hegel’s notion of philosophy
as Nachdenken, as the passive analysis of the progress of the Idea after
the event. ‘The owl of Minerva’, Hegel had written in a famous passage
in his preface to the Philosophy o f Right, ‘spreads its wings only with
the falling of dusk.’ Marx, on the other hand, by identifying the motive
power of history with human self-consciousness, could see philosophy
as the critical activity of that consciousness, and hence as itself part
of the motive power. For Marx, at any rate when he wrote his disserta
tion, philosophy was thus the force which would change the world,
and not merely register its changes.
Marx’s rejection of Hegel’s attempt to straddle the issue between
immanent self-realisation and external necessity has one fundamentally
important result: it brings out even more clearly the Rousseau-Kantian
strain in Hegel, the emphasis on freedom as self-determination and on
the free will as the universal and universalisable will. To the youthful
Marx, the goal of human history is the free society—the universal
kingdom of ends— and men and institutions are judged by the Kantian
criterion of universalisability, with self-determination strongly
emphasised and the concept of duty entirely omitted. Marx believed, of
course, that, as Hegel had shown, the Kantian dualism must be over
come: the dichotomies of noumenal and phenomenal, of speculative
and practical reason, of duty and inclination, would disappear in the
‘truly human’ man and ‘truly human’ society. But the dualism, Marx
believed, was about* to be overcome— the rational society was hovering
in the wings of the theatre of history. Not until the end of 1843, when
his confidence in the immediate, almost unaided, coming of the rational
society had waned, did Marx pay any serious attention to the dialectic
process that would bring it about. Before that, he was not interested in
tracing historical progress through its succession of partial forms. The
rational society was at hand— it was no longer necessary to study the
24
THE P H I L O S OP H Y OF THE CONC EP T
25
2. The Free Individual
that the young Marx took his criteria of freedom and harmony to
establish positive moral and ethical ‘principles’, eternally and immut
ably true, his earliest work leaves no doubt. Thus, in his Remarks on
the Most Recent Prussian Instruction to Censors (one of the Anekdota
contributions, written in January-February, 1842), Marx notes that
the instruction has substituted the words ‘decency, propriety and
external decorum’ for the words ‘morality and the decent proprieties’
in the original law. ‘We see’, writes Marx, ‘how morality as morality,
as the principle of the world, which obeys its own laws, disappears, and
in place of the essential character we have external appearance, a
decorousness imposed by the police, a conventional propriety’ (M I,
i-i, 161). But for Marx, positive morality does not disappear, nor can
it be explained away. After arguing that censorship is evil in all its
aspects, he concludes: ‘That which is in general bad, remains bad, no
matter which individual is the carrier of badness, whether a private
critic or an employee of the Government. Only in the latter case, the
badness is authorised and regarded from above as necessary in order to
bring to realisation the good from below.’ (M I, i-i, 165.) This, for
Marx, is no excuse. ‘We have shown’, he writes in his Rheinische
Zeitung articles on the debates on freedom of the press in the sixth
Rhenish Diet, ‘that the press law is a right and the censorship law a
wrong. The censorship, however, itself admits that it is not an end in
itself, that it is not in itself good, that it therefore rests on the principle:
“ the end makes holy the means.” But an end which necessitates unholy
means is not a holy end.’ (M I, i-i, 211.) Again, when the representa
tive of the knights in the Diet argues that all men are imperfect and
need guidance and education, Marx insists that we cannot abandon
objective standards merely because all things are allegedly imperfect:
26
THE F R E E I N D I V I D U A L
‘If then all things human are imperfect by their very existence, shall
we therefore jumble up everything together, respect everything equally
the good and the bad, the truth and the lie?’ (M I, i-i, 201).
The positive distinction between the good and the bad stems for
Marx from the positive distinction between self-determination and
dependence. In his comment on the Prussian censorship instruction,
Marx emphatically distinguishes true morality from the spurious, evil
morality of religion: ‘Morality rests on the autonomy, religion on the
heteronomy of the human spirit’ (M I, i-i, 161). Again, in the Rhein-
ische Zeitung discussion of press freedom and censorship, he writes:
From the standpoint o f the Idea, it is self-evident that freedom o f the press
has a justification quite different from that o f censorship, in so far as it is
itself a form o f the Idea, o f freedom, a positive good, whereas censorship is
a form o f bondage, the polemic o f a Weltanschauung o f appearance against
the Weltanschauung o f the essence. It is something merely negative in
character.
(M I, i- i, 201.)
and again when Marx rejects the view that freedom of the press can be
defended as a case of freedom to exercise a craft:
The freedom to exercise a craft is just the freedom to exercise a craft and no
other freedom, because within it the nature o f the craft takes form undisturbed
according to its inner rules o f life; freedom o f the courts is freedom o f the
courts, if the courts follow their own rules o f law and not those o f some other
sphere, e.g., o f religion. Every specific sphere o f freedom is the freedom o f a
specific sphere, just as every specific way o f life is a specific nature’s way o f
living.
(M I, i- i, 221.)
the multitude and elevated above it. Dignity, however, can be afforded only
by that position in which we do not appear as servile instruments, but where
we create independently within our circle.
(M I, i —ii, 1 66.)
It is this psychological trait, too, which accounts for the fire in passages
like the following from his discussion of the debates on press freedom:
A country which, like the old Athens, treats boot-lickers, parasites, toadies
as exceptions from the general standard of reason, as public fools, is the
country of independence and self-government. A people which, like all
people of the best of times, claims the right to think and utter the truth only
for the court fool, can only be a people that is dependent and without
identity.
(M I, i- i, 184.)
Time and time again his aggressive independence and his moral
commitment to freedom burst out, in passages that punctuated his
work long after he had ceased to be a Young Hegelian, long after he
had stopped proclaiming a rational morality and had turned from
philosophy to his ‘scientific work’. ‘The social principles of Christian
ity’, he wrote angrily in the Deutsche-Briisseler Zeitung in 1847,1
‘preach cowardice, self-contempt, debasement, subjugation, humil
ity, in short, all the properties of the canaille, and the proletariat, which
does not want to be treated as canaille, needs its courage, its conscious
ness of self, its pride and its independence, far more than its bread/
Six years later Marx was writing in the New York Daily Tribune2 on
the village communities of India:
Twenty years after that, when one of his daughters handed him a
For the social conditions that would produce the free man Marx was
to struggle for the next forty years. In the intensity of the struggle he
never again turned to ask what the ‘realm of freedom* might mean.
That problem, he thought, he had solved before the struggle began.
From 1844 onward Marx’s primary interest was not in the nature of
freedom, but in the developments by which it would come about.
In his earliest work, this problem does not yet occupy his mind at
all. (The conditions of censorship under which he worked no doubt
helped to keep him away from it.) Against what he believed to be the
disintegrating conditions of servitude around him, he is concerned to
hold up the truly human morality, law and society. His conception of
the latter two we shall now examine.
3i
3. The Natural Law o f Freedom
The legislator must regard himself as a scientist. He does not make laws,
he does not invent them, he only formulates them, he enunciates the inner
laws of spiritual relationships as conscious positive laws.
(M I, i-i, 318.)
It is this view which a little later—in the first Hegel critique— enables
Marx to give a short answer to the antinomy that worried Hegel: the
fact that the legislator derives his authority from a constitution itself
created by legislators. ‘The legislative power/ Marx retorts, ‘does not
make the law; it only discovers and formulates it’ (M I, i-i, 468).
The process of ‘discovering’ the rational natural law is not one that
Marx is able to describe clearly. As in morality, so in law his position
makes it easier to state what is not moral or truly legal, than what is.
There is much vague talk of ‘concepts’— the ‘concept’ of the press
(which is taken logically to exclude censorship), the ‘concept’ of the
public service, the ‘concept* of marriage— from which positive rules
of law are supposed to flow with logical necessity. Marx’s most serious
attempt at a concrete treatment is in the article on divorce. Marriage,
he argues, is ‘according to its concept’ indissoluble—but some human
relationships no longer correspond to their ‘concept’, i.e., are no
longer marriages. The State may therefore dissolve them in law, but
only because they are already dissolved in fact.
The dissolution of a marriage is nothing but the declaration: this marriage
is a dead marriage, whose existence is a snare and a delusion. It is self-evident
of course, that neither the capricious will of the legislator nor the capricious
will of a private person, but only the essence o f the matter, can decide whether
a marriage is dead or not, for it is well-known that a declaration of death
depends on the facts of the case and not on the wishes of the parties concerned.
But if in the case of physical death you demand precise and unmistakeable
proofs, must not a legislator lay down a moral death only after the most
incontestable symptoms?
(M I, i-i, 319.)
What these ‘incontestable symptoms’ are, how we derive them
logically from the ‘concept’ of marriage, or how we would defend any
particular criterion against those who reject it, Marx is unable to
indicate. Conscious of the deficiency, he falls back on a vague
popularism:
The guarantee that the conditions under which the existence of a moral
relationship no longer corresponds with its essence will be laid down truly,
in accordance with the state of knowledge and of universal opinion, without
33
T H E P R I M I T I V E E T H I C OF K A R L M A R X
novel The Mysteries o f Paris and makes this point time and time again.
Each one of Sue’s characters who goes through ‘moral regeneration’,
according to Marx, comes out the less a man (or woman) in a moral
sense. Each ‘criminal’, originally full of vitality, is made dependent or
cringing, robbed of his or her talents, brought to anguish and
submission:
As Rudolph [the moral regenerator] kills Fleur de M arie by handing her
over to a priest and to consciousness o f sin, as he kills Chourineur by robbing
him o f his human independence and debasing him to a bulldog, so he kills
the gangleader by having his eyes gouged out so that he can learn to 'pray *
Marx’s own theory of punishment and regeneration rests squarely
on his belief in the truly human society of the truly self-determined
man. Marx contrasts what he considers to be Hegel’s merely apparent
demand that the criminal become the judge of his own crime with the
genuine fulfilment of this demand under ‘human’ conditions:
Hegel holds that the criminal must as a punishment pass sentence on himself.
Gans developed this theory at greater length. In Hegel this is the speculative
disguise o f the old ius talionis that Kant developed as the only legal theory o f
punishment. Hegel makes self-judgment o f the criminal no more than an
Tdea\ a mere speculative interpretation o f the current empirical penal code.
He thus leaves the mode o f application to the respective stages o f develop
ment o f the State, i.e., he leaves punishment as it is. Precisely in that he shows
himself more critical than his Critical echo. A penal theory which at the
same time sees in the criminal the man can do so only in abstraction, in
imagination, precisely because punishment, coercion, is contrary to human
conduct. Besides, this would be impossible to carry out. Pure subjective
arbitrariness would take the place o f the abstract law because it would
always depend on official ‘honest and decent* men to adapt the penalty to the
individuality o f the criminal. Plato admitted that the law must be one-sided
and must make abstraction o f the individual. On the other hand, under
human conditions punishment would really be nothing but the sentence
passed by the culprit on himself. There will be no attempt to persuade him
that violence from without, exerted on him by others is violence exerted on
himself by himself. On the contrary, he will see in other men his natural
saviours from the sentence which he has pronounced on himself; in other
words the relation will be reversed.
(M I, 3, 356; cf. H F 238-9.)
&
4. The ‘Truly Human’ Society
The divided State, the unfree State, stands to the rational State just
as the unfree animal stands to the rational man:
The unfree condition of the world demands rights of bondage, for while
human right is the existence of freedom, animal right is the existence of
bondage. Feudalism in the broadest sense is the spiritual kingdom of animals,
the world of divided humanity in contrast with the world of self-distinguish
ing humanity, whose inequality is nothing but the spectrum of equality.
(Discussion on wood theft laws, M I, i- i, 272.)
1 Just what these maxims are, or what precisely the ‘civic nature* of the State
is, never appears. At best, one might treat the passage above, like Kant's univer-
salisability principle or Mill's statement of liberty, as creating a presumption
against certain actions.
38
THE ‘ T R U L Y H U M A N ’ S O C IE T Y
In the first Hegel critique Marx takes up the same point. The Middle
Ages, which represented the form of bondage, which divided man from
his universal being, he says, ‘are the animal history of humanity, its
zoology’ (M I, i-i, 499).
Civic morality and the criticism of the State, then, reveal the same
ethical categories as Marx’s examination of the individual, whom Marx
indeed sees as above all a universal, social being. In the rational State,
man, as individual and as universal essence of the State, is self-deter
mined—the State is harmonious, stable and free from self-contradic
tion. ‘A State, which is not the concretisation (Verwirklichimg) of
rational freedom, is a bad State’ (M I, i-i, 248). The imperfect or bad
State is characterised by incomplete self-determination, division,
instability and self-contradiction.1
Above all, the rational State is the State of a truly unified humanity.
Its chief enemies, for the young Marx, are special interests, privileges
and the estate or class, all of which elevate social divisions into a
principle of social organisation:
Now in this concept of the rational State as the State of the human
essence, of truly unified humanity, there are obvious difficulties.
Basically, they resolve themselves into the general difficulty of deter
mining and describing the relationship between men as individuals,
as particular, empirical beings, and the State that is supposed to be a
form of their essence, the concretisation of their freedom. Marx himself
draws attention to the way this difficulty arises in paragraph 261 of
Hegel’s Philosophy o f Right, the paragraph with which Marx begins
the extant portions of his first Hegel critique. In that paragraph Hegel
says:
In contrast with the spheres o f private rights and private welfare (the family
and civil society), the State is from one point o f view an external necessity
and their higher authority; its nature is such that their laws and interests
are subordinate to it and dependent on it. On the other hand, however, it is
the end immanent within them, and its strength lies in the unity o f its own
universal end and aim with the particular interests o f individuals, in the fact
that individuals have duties to the State in proportion as they have rights
against it.
Neither in the first Hegel critique nor anywhere else in his work does
Marx make any real attempt to get to grips with the problem of relating
and distinguishing man’s universal essence, his JVesen, and his exist
ence as a particular, empirical, being. He does take up in the critique,
however, a political question connected with this problem: the question
of the relationship between the State as a concrete manifestation of
human freedom and the individual person within the State. Marx
rejects sharply Hegel’s view that the ‘rational will’ can be embodied in a
single individual (the Monarch) and argues instead that the rational
State, to be free, must be democratic. What Marx means by democracy,
however, must be examined carefully.
In his relatively popular polemical work for the Rheinische Zeitung
Marx was constantly fighting against the conception that civic affairs
could be the prerogative of a certain class or group. Often he sounded
as though he were demanding democratic control as something
requiring merely representative control. This was emphatically not his
conception. Like Rousseau, he would have conceded that the will of
the majority and the rational will are not necessarily identical, though,
again like Rousseau, he was not always anxious to stress the differences.
But the notion of representation Marx rejects emphatically, both on
the grounds that to be free is to be active, self-determining, and on the
grounds that representation undermines the truly universal character
of the State.
To be represented is in general something miserable; only the material,
spiritless, dependent, insecure need representation; but no element of the
State can be permitted to be material, spiritless, dependent, insecure.
(‘On the Committees o f Estates in Prussia’, M I, i- i, 334.)
In the first Hegel critique Marx reinforces this with a more general
point—representation converts civic affairs into sectional affairs, into
special interests, and thus destroys the very basis of the rational State.
It is the product of the divorce between political or civic affairs and
human affairs in general, of the gulf between the State and civil society.
This divorce, this ‘abstraction’ (in the Hegelian sense) of the political
State, Marx sees as a modern phenomenon. The medieval State, even
though the State of human nature in bondage, was nevertheless a State
of human nature, though not in its rational form. ‘Folk life and civic
life were identical’ (M I, i-i, 437.)1
1 Marx’s development of this point and his general conception of the relation
ship between civil society and political State will emerge more clearly in the
following Part. In the material dealt with here, his views are still sketchy.
43
T H E P R I M I T I V E E T H I C OF K A R L M A R X
Marx seeks to solve the problem by cutting through and rejecting both
alternatives:
The antinomy in its essential form is: all the individuals do it, or the indivi
duals do it as some, as not-alL In both cases allness remains only external
multiplicity or totality o f individuals. Allness is not an essential, vital, actual
quality o f the individual. Allness is not something through which he loses
the character o f abstract individuality; allness is only the full number o f
individuality. One individual, many individuals, a ll individuals. The one,
many, all— none o f these descriptions changes the essential being o f the
subject, o f individuality.
(M I, i- i, 539-40.)
47
7KLVSDJHLQWHQWLRQDOO\OHIWEODQN
P A R T TW O
hair-splitting with words. In other words, the Government has set me free
again.
(M I, i-ii, 294.)
By the end of that year Marx had proclaimed an ally more powerful
than these poor Rhenish Jews— the proletariat.
‘The weapon of criticism’, Marx had discovered, ‘can certainly not
supplant the criticism of weapons: material force must be overthrown
by material force.’2 Thus, in the D eutsch-franfosische Jah rbiicher 9
Marx proclaims his new political programme, the necessary union of
philosophic criticism and class agitation, the alliance of thinking
humanity which suffers and suffering humanity which thinks.3
Revolutions need a passive element, a material basis . . . It is not enough that
the thought strives to be made real, reality itself must strive toward the
thought.
(Second'Hegel critique, M I, i- i, 6 15-16 .)
Where, then, lies the positive possibility of German emancipation? Answer:
In the formation of a class with radical chains . . . the proletariat. . . Philos
ophy finds in the proletariat its material weapons.
(Ibid., pp. 619--20.)
1 That disfranchisement of the Jews is perfecdy logical in a Christian State,
and that the emancipation of Jews can therefore only follow the emancipation of
the State from Christianity.
2 Toward the Critique o f Hegel's philosophy o f Right: Introduction (the second
Hegel critique, published in the D .-f / .) , M I, i-i, 614.
3 Compare his second letter to Ruge, dated May 1843 and published in the
‘Correspondence of 1843*: ‘The existence of a suffering humanity which thinks
and of a thinking humanity which is oppressed will necessarily be unpalatable
for the passive animal world of the Philistines . . . The longer circumstances
give thinking humanity time to reflect and suffering humanity time to rally, the
more finished when bom will be the product that the world carries in its womb*
(M I, i- i, 565-6).
53
K A R L MARXES ROA D TO COMMUNISM
Marx had discovered that he needs the proletariat, but he has not
abandoned philosophy:
material life and his political life. It is the separation between civil
society and the political State, between private, egoistic interest and
common interest:
The consummate political State is in its essence the generic life o f man in
contrast with his material life. All the presuppositions o f this egoistic life
remain in civil society, as properties o f civil society outside the sphere o f
the State. Where the political State has reached its true form, man leads a
double life, a heavenly one and an earthly one, not only in thought, in
consciousness, but in reality, in life itself. He leads a life within the common
unity \Gemeinwesen\, in which he is himself a common or generic being, and
he leads a life in civil society, in which he acts as a private person, regarding
other people as means and demeaning himself into a means, so that he
becomes the football o f alien powers.
(On the Jewish Question’, M I, i- i, 584.)
The conflict between civil society and political State, then, is seen
primarily as the expression of a conflict within man himself, as an
example of that alienation which Hegel sees as an essential step in the
development of mind, and which Feuerbach strikingly developed in
the field of religion. Just as Hegel had argued in the Phenomenology o f
M ind that the feeling of estrangement between man and certain of his
own externalised powers becomes particularly acute at certain periods
of history, so Marx argued that the hostile confrontation of civil
society and political State is a modern phenomenon, the necessary
56
TH E N E W S O C I A L D I A L E C T I C
spirit, which, distributed in the various blind alleys of feudal society, had
been worn down and decomposed; it gathered together the scattered frag
ments, liberated the political spirit from its amalgamation with civil life and
constituted it into the sphere of common social being [Gemeinwesen], of
universal public affairs, theoretically divorced from the particular elements
of civil life. Specific activities and specific social situations sank to merely
individual significance. They no longer constituted the universal relationship
between the individual and the State totality. Public affairs as such became
the universal affair of every individual; the political function became his
universal function.
This perfection of the idealism of the State was at the same time the
consummation of the materialism of civil society. Shaking off the political
yoke meant at the same time shaking off those bonds which held fast the
egoistic spirit of civil society. Political emancipation was at the same time
the emancipation of civil society from politics, from even the appearance of a
universal content.
Feudal society was broken up into its basic element, into man. But [it was
broken up] into man in the shape in which he really was its basic element,
into the egoistic man.
(M I, i-i, 597-8.)
Here, then, is the basic structure of Marx’s new social dialectic. The
struggle between the particular, empirical nature of man and his
rational, universal essence is the struggle between his private, material
pursuits in civil society and the unity and universality expressed in the
political State. In feudal society the struggle was still unclear. Man’s
material life and his political life were welded together, everything he
did was treated as legitimately coming wTithin the sphere of religious
and political life. As a result, the feudal structure did to some extent
inhibit and suppress the naked divisiveness and individual conflict of
civil society, of man’s economic and material life. It tolerated no
economic ‘freedom’ to indulge openly in the helium omnium contra
omnes; it bound serfs to the land, fettered the ‘free’ land-holder in the
political chains of homage and fealty, controlled retail prices and
standards of workmanship through the guilds, forbade usury as an
offence against the Christian faith. But the unity and universality pro
claimed by feudalism were not the unity and universality of free men,
co-operating spontaneously. Feudal unity was an artificial, illusory
unity: a unity in bondage. Instead of overcoming division, feudalism
elevated it into a political principle and temporarily stabilised it by
force. Precisely because feudal society had not yet split human nature
into two, because the rational universal being of man had not yet
58
T H E N E W S O C IA L D I A L E C T I C
59
6. The Critique o f Politics
Judaism reaches its highest point with the perfection of civil society; but
civil society consummates itself only in the Christian world. Only under the
sway of Christianity, which makes all national, natural, moral and intellectual
relationships external to man, could civil society separate itself entirely from
the life of the State, rend all social bonds [Gattungsbande] of men, put
egoism, self-interested wants, in place of social bonds and break up the
human world into a world of atomistic mutually hostile individuals.
Christianity arose out of Judaism. Once again it has flown back into
Judaism.
Christ was patently the theorising Jew; the Jew therefore is the practical
Christian and the practical Christian is become Jew again.
Christianity overcame actual living Judaism only in appearance. It was
too respectable, too spiritualistic, to overcome the brutality of practical
needs except by raising itself into the sky.
Christianity is the sublime thought of Judaism and Judaism is the mean
practical application of Christianity, but this practical application can
become universal only after Christianity as the consummated religion has
completed in theory man’s self-alienation from himself and from Nature.
Only then could Judaism gain universal dominion and turn externalised
and estranged [entaussert] man and externalised and estranged Nature into
objects fallen into servitude to egoistic needs, into objects of barter.
Making things saleable is the practical side of alienation. Just as man, so
long as he is still caught within the limitations of religion, can only objectify
his essential being by making it into an alien, phantastic being, so under the
domination of egoistic wants he can only act practically, he can only create
objects in practice, by putting his products as well as his activity under the
domination of an alien being and giving them the significance of an alien
being—the significance of money. . .
As soon as society succeeds in destroying the empirical essence of Judaism,
buying and selling and its presuppositions, the Jew will become impossible
because his consciousness will no longer have an object, because the sub
,
jective basis of Judaism, practical wants personified, and the conflict of the
individual-sensual existence with the existence of man as a member of the
species will have disappeared.
For Marx at this stage the political State is not yet merely an instru
ment of class control, nor is it a mere reflection of the state of civil
society. On the contrary, like religion, it is not a reflection of civil
society but a compensation for it, an ideal completion of it. Just as
Marx regards Christianity as expressing not only real misery, but also
the protest against real misery, a ghostly rationality in another world
(second Hegel critique, M 1, 1 —i, 607), so he treats the political State as
an ideal assertion of the universal human essence, of that striving
toward universality, self-determination and natural co-operation
which has been entirely banished from modern civil society.
within its form therefore expresses sub specie rei publicae all social struggles,
needs, truths.
(‘Corr. of 1843’, M I, i-i, 574.)
The political State, however, is fatally limited by its form, by its
separation from civil society and from the actual, empirical being of
man with that society. It remains an ideal expression of his universal
being, powerless to conquer the actualities of man’s existence. It is
hence one-sided, logically incomplete and incoherent in precisely those
principles which it professes to apply to human society. The proof of
this, says Marx, can be seen in the French and American revolutions.
Professedly, they achieved the political emancipation of mankind. They
proclaimed man’s freedom, independence from religion and his ration
ality—as a political citiien. But as a man, they left him in bondage, thus
contradicting their own basis, bringing out their one-sidedness and
incoherence:
The boundary of political emancipation reveals itself immediately in the
fact that the State can free itself of a certain limitation1 without men becoming
truly free of this limitation, in the fact that the State can be a free State
without man being a free man.
(‘On the Jewish Question*, M I, i-i, 582.)
Thus, Marx argues, men proclaim themselves atheists politically by
declaring the State to be secular yet guarantee themselves the ‘right’ of
worship and so remain in religious bondage. Man decomposes himself
into the man, follower of a specific religion, and the citizen, member of
the atheistic State. The resultant tension expresses the real, this-worldly
tension between civil society and the political State, between the
bourgeois and the citoyen, between the private interest and the common
interest (M I, i-i, 583-91). Nor is this product accidental. It arises
from the very character of political emancipation, which robs religion
of even that limited connexion with man’s universal being which it
had in the feudal State and transforms it into an expression of the very
spirit of civil society. The same considerations apply to private
property:
The political annulment of private property [through the removal of property
qualifications for voters and candidates] does not destroy private property
1 Marx uses the word ‘limitation’ [Schranke, Beschranktheit] here and elsewhere
in the D .-f.J. to mean both the limitation or narrowness that prevents a subject
from being truly ‘universal’ and the limitation that sets limits to the subject
from without and thus makes it determined and not truly free. Both meanings
are essential to his argument.
63
K A R L M A R X ’ s R O A D TO COMMUNISM
but presupposes it. The State destroys distinctions of birth, estate, education
and occupation in its own way, when it takes distinctions of birth, estate,
education and occupation to be unpolitical distinctions, when it makes every
member of the people an equal participant in the sovereignty of the people
without reference to these distinctions, when it treats all elements of actual
civil life from the point of view of the State. For all that, the State nowise
prevents private property, education and occupation from acting and making
their specific being felt in their own way, i.e., as private property, as educa
tion, as occupation. Far from resolving these distinctions o f fa ct, the political
State exists only by presupposing them, it sees itself as a political State and
imposes its universality only in opposition to these, its elements.
(Op. cit., M I, i-i, 583-4.)
Who is the homme, as distinguished from the citoyen? No one but the member
of civil society. Why is this member called ‘man*, simply man; why are his
rights called the rights of man? How shall we explain this fact? By the
relationship of the political State to civil society, by the essential character
of political emancipation.
Above all, we assert the fact that the so-called rights of man, the droits de
Vhomme, as opposed to the droits du citoyen, are nothing but rights of the
member of civil society, i.e., of egoistic man, of man separated from man
and from the common life and being.
(Op. cit., M I, i-i, 593.)
We can see this clearly, says Marx, if we examine the rights of man and
of the citizen as laid down in the most radical constitution, the French
Constitution of 1793, which names the rights of freedom, property,
equality and security.
Freedom [if we examine the definition given in the Constitution] is therefore
the right to do everything which harms no one else. The borders within
which every man can move harmlessly are determined by the law, just as
the border between two fields is determined by a fence. The concern is with
the freedom of man as an isolated monad withdrawing into itself. . . The
human right of freedom is not based on the connexion of man with man but
rather on the separation of man from man. It is this right of separation, the
right of the limited individual, limited unto himself. . .
Man’s right of private property is the right to enjoy one’s property and to
64
THE C R IT IQ U E OF P O L IT I C S
dispose over it arbitrarily son gri], without considering other men, inde
pendently of society. It is the right of self-interest. Such individual freedom,
like this application of it, forms the basis of civil society. It allows every
man to find in other men not the realisation, but the limitation, of his
freedom . . .
Egaliti, in its non-political sense, is nothing but the equality of the liberty
described above i.e., that each man is* regarded equally as such a monad,
based on itself. . .
Security is the highest social conception of civil society, the conception
held by the police force that all of society exists only in order to guarantee to
each of its members the preservation of his person, his rights and his property
Civil society does not through the concept of security raise itself above its
egoism. Security is rather the guarantee of egoism.
None of these so-called rights of man goes beyond the egoistic man,
beyond man as a member of civil society, as a man severed from the common
social life and withdrawn into his private interests and private caprice. Far
from man being conceived in these rights as a generic being [Gattungswesen],
the life of the genus itself [Gattungsleben], society, appears in them as a
frame external to individuals, as a limitation of their original independence.
The sole thread that keeps them together is natural necessity, needs and
private interest, the preservation of their property and of their egoistic
person.
(Op. cit., M I, i-i, 593-5. 1 have omitted in this and in many subse
quent quotations those of Marx’s over-frequent italicisations which
seem to me merely pointless.)
This, then, is the result of a political emancipation confined to the
realm of politics, an emancipation based on the separation of political
State and civil society:
A people which is just beginning to free itself, to tear down all the barriers
between various members of the people and to found a common political
fellowship [politisches Gemeinwesen] . . . solemnly proclaims the vindication
of the egoistic man, severed from his fellow-man and from the common
fellowship . . .
The political emancipators lower the citizen and the common political
fellowship to the level of a mere means for preserving these so-called human
rights, so that the citoyen is made the servant of the egoistic homme. The
sphere in which man conducts himself as a universal, social being is degraded,
put below the sphere in which he conducts himself as a sectional being and,
finally, man as a bourgeois and not man as a citoyen, is taken for the essential
and true man.
(Op. cit., M I, i-i, 595.)
6j
K A R L M A R X ’ S R O AD TO COMMUNISM
Thus egoistic man, the member of civil society, now stands revealed
as ‘the basis, the pre-supposition of the political State, which recognises
him as such in the rights of man’ (op. cit., p. 598). The political man,
on the other hand, remains only ‘the abstracted, artificial man, man as
an allegorical person’ (ibid.). Because the political State is such an
allegory, such an ideal construct, based on the factual presupposition of
egoistic man in civil society, it is in fact powerless before civil society.
This is why, according to Marx, the Jews who are denied the right to
vote in the smallest European hamlet control the bourses of the great
European capitals.
The contradiction between the practical political power of the Jew and his
political rights is the general contradiction between politics and the power
of money. In thought, the former stands above the latter, in fact it has
become the latter’s slave.
(Op. cit., M I, i- i, 602.)
In the moments of its specific feeling for itself, political life seeks to suppress
its presuppositions—civil society and its elements—and to constitute itself
as the true, contradictionless generic or social life of man. It can do this only
through the forcible negation of its own conditions of existence, through
66
TH E C R IT IQ U E OF P O L IT I C S
The State cannot overcome the contradiction between the good intentions
of the administration on the one hand and its means and possibility of action
on the other without overcoming and destroying itself, for the State rests
on the contradiction. It rests on the contradiction between public and private
life, between universal interests and special interests. The administration
therefore has to confine itself to formal and negative action, for where civil
life and its work begin there the power of the administration ends. Impotence
vis-a-vis the consequences which spring from the unsocial nature of civil
life, from private ownership, trade, industry and the mutual plundering
engaged in by the various bourgeois circles is the natural law governing the
administration. This fragmentation, this oppression, this slavery to civil
society, is the natural foundation on which the modem State rests, just as
the civil society of slavery was the natural foundation on which the ancient
State rested . . . If the State wanted to overcome and destroy the impotence
of its administration, it would have to overcome and destroy the private
life of to-day.
(M I, 3, 14-5.)
Finally it reaches the class which no longer realises social freedom under
the presupposition of particular conditions that lie outside man but were
1 The original article by ‘a Prussian* was written by Arnold Ruge and pub
lished in Vorwarts (Paris) on July 27, 1844. Marx’s reply appeared in the same
paper on August 7, 1844. Ruge’s text is reprinted in MI, 3, 587-9 and Marx’s
article in M I, 3, 5-23.
67
K A R L M A R X ’ S R O A D TO COMMUNISM
yet created by human society. This class on the contrary organises all the
conditions of human life under the presupposition of social freedom.
(Second Hegel critique, M I, i-i, 619.)
In France, Marx believes, such a class might be activated by enthusiasm.
In Germany the French revolution took place only in ideas, in the
philosophy of Kant, and not in reality; the middle classes remained
powerless; here such a revolutionary class will be activated only by
needs. But there is such a class—
a class in civil society which is not a class of civil society, an estate which
represents the dissolution of all estates, a sphere endowed with universal
character because of its universal suffering and claiming no particular rights
because the wrong it is made to suffer is not a particular wrong but simply
wrong as such . . . a class which represents the utter loss of humanity and
which can therefore regain itself only by fully regaining the human. This
dissolution of society as a particular estate is the proletariat. . . When the
proletariat announces the dissolution of the social order that has existed
hitherto, it thereby only expresses the secret of its own existence, for it is
the effective dissolution of this order. If the proletariat demands the negation
of private property, it is only making into a principle of society that which
society has made into a principle of the proletariat.
(Op. cit., 619-20.)
I f Marx turned to the proletariat from practical considerations,
through realising the impotence of the German middle classes, he has
here given it the ‘speculative development’ which he claims Epicurus
gave to the atom. He sees in it not just the empirical existence, but the
logical category. The proletariat occupies a necessary place in the
dialectical schema; it is driven by ‘the secret of its own existence’ to
accomplish the dissolution and raising up into a new form of the old
order. And just as contradictions in the atom could not be resolved
without treating it as free, so the contradictions of the proletarian’s
position cannot be resolved without restoring to mankind its freedom,
its ‘universal soul’.
The fellowship [Gemetnwesen] from which the worker is isolated is a fellow
ship of a scope and order of reality quite different from that of the political
fellowship. The fellowship from which his own labour separates the worker
is life itself, physical and intellectual life, morality and customs, human
activity, human satisfaction, being human. Being human [Das menschliche
Wesen] is the true fellowship of men. Just as irremediable isolation from this
fellowship is incomparably more pervasive, unbearable, horrible and full of
contradiction than isolation from the political fellowship, so the dissolution
68
TH E C R IT IQ U E OF P O L IT I C S
69
7. The Critique o f Economics
acquired from the Young Hegelians roughly the same views, had
already preceded Marx in the task of subjecting political economy to
such criticism by publishing in the single issue of the Deutsch-fran[d-
sische Jahrbiicher of February, 1844 his ‘Outlines of a Critique of
Political Economy’. Marx thought highly of the article and became
interested in Engels, whom he knew only slightly, as a result. Yet a
comparison of Engels’ article with Marx’s manuscripts brings out how
much more thorough-going is Marx’s conception of the relation be
tween logical and ethical criticism. For Engels, political economy is
something he attacks both morally and logically; for Marx, these
attacks are not complete until they have been brought back to a single
base. Thus Engels begins with a moral-advocative onslaught: ‘Political
economy, or the science of becoming rich, arisen out of the mutual
envy and greed of merchants, carries on its brow the marks of the most
revolting self-seeking’ (M 1, 2,379); he ends (M 1, 2,400) by seeing in
man’s dependence on private property, competition and conflicting
interests his most complete degradation. His logical indictment is
complementary but distinct, mostly untinged by moral or ethical
overtones. It rests on the necessary vacillation in economic theories of
value, the ‘contradiction’ between a high ‘national income* and the
overwhelming poverty of the nation as a set of individuals, as well as
on the contradiction between the allegedly harmonious operation of
the laws of supply and demand and the increasing number of trade
crises. Marx, on the other hand, insists that ethical deficiency and
logical contradiction are necessarily connected. The criticism is not
complete until they have been shown to arise from a single cause, from
a ‘one-sided’ treatment of man or from a failure to see the human
content of social institutions which have been illegitimately ripped
out of their human context and treated as dead things. His whole
tour de force in the Paris Manuscripts is to proclaim that political
economy cannot be an ethically neutral study of so-called ‘objective’
relations between non-human things or laws and to bring it back into
the ethical sphere by reducing it once more to its human content. The
fundamental categories of political economy, Marx insists, are not
labour, capital, profits, rents, land. The fundamental category is man,
man and his human activities. These activities cannot be abstracted
from man; they must be seen as integral expressions of his humanity.
The categories of which traditional political economists speak are
nothing but abstractions (in the Hegelian sense) from the true essence
of society—man. The economists objectify, reify, set up in limited
7i
K A R L M A R X ’ S R OAD TO COMMUNISM
and abstracted shape, as dead objects, what are vital human activities,
activities that can only be grasped and correctly developed as part of
the whole social man.1
It is because Marx rejects the conception of ethical criticism as being
the application of ‘ideal’ standards and treats his ethico-logic as
grounded in the way things occur, that he can insist that his criticism
is purely empirical. ‘My results have been gained through a wholly
empirical analysis, founded on a conscientious critical study of political
economy’ (M I, 3, 33; cf. EPM 15-16). The first thing such a study
reveals to Marx is the utter inadequacy of the abstract(ed) laws of
political economy which fall into necessary contradictions and fail to
grasp the fundamental principle that makes these contradictions neces
sary. The political economist says that originally and by its nature the
entire product of labour belongs to the worker; at the same time he
grants that in fact the worker receives nothing but the smallest and
most unavoidable part of this product. He says that everything is
bought with labour and that capital is nothing but accumulated labour;
yet he grants that the labourer cannot buy everything but must sell
himself and his human qualities. He says that labour is the only un
changeable value of things; yet nothing is more contingent than the
value of labour; nothing is exposed to greater variations. The division
of labour, according to the political economist, increases the productive
power of labour and the wealth of society; yet it impoverishes the
worker. According to their own nature, land rent and capital profit
are deductions suffered by wages; in actual fact, wages are a deduction
which land and capital permit to the worker. While the political
economist claims that the interests of the worker are never in opposi
tion to the interests of society , society stands constantly and necessarily
opposed to the interests of the worker. (M I, 3, 4 3 - 5 ; EPM 28-9.)
By means of the political economist’s own words, then, Marx has
striven to show that labour, in so far as it increases work, is harmful.
This is the paradoxical result of the abstracted laws of political econ
omy. The worker sinks to the level of the most miserable commodity,
his misery standing in inverse relationship to the size and power of his
production. On the side of capital, the necessary result of competition
is the accumulation of capital in a few hands, i.e., the frightful re
imposition of monopoly. Thus the distinction between capitalist and
1 Two years later, in the Poverty o f Philosophy, Marx attacks Proudhon for
not seeing this: ‘The economist's material is the active, energetic life of man; M.
Proudhon's material is the dogmas of the economist' (PP 117).
72
TH E C R IT IQ U E OF EC O N O M IC S
product from the worker, but this alienation is possible only because
alienation is enshrined in the very activity of production, in the wor
ker’s labour itself. In what does this alienation within labour consist?
Firstly, in the fact that labour is external to the worker, i.e., it does not
belong to his essential being, in the fact that he therefore does not affirm
himself in his work, but negates himself in it, that he does not feel content,
but unhappy in it, that he develops no free physical and mental energy but
mortifies his body and ruins his mind. Therefore the worker feels himself
only outside his work, while in his work he feels outside himself. He is at
home when he is not working and when he works he is not at home. His
work, therefore, is not voluntary but coerced; it isforced labour. It is, there
fore, not the satisfaction of a need but only a means for satisfying needs
external to it. Its alien character emerges clearly in the fact that as soon as
there is no physical or other compulsion, labour is avoided like the plague.
External labour, labour in which man alienates himself, is labour of self-
sacrifice, of mortification. Finally, the external character of labour for the
worker appears in the fact that it is not his own but somebody else’s, that
in his labour he belongs not to himself, but to someone else . . . The worker’s
activity is not his own activity. It belongs to another, it is the loss of his self.
The result, therefore, is that man (the worker) no longer feels himself
acting freely except in his animal functions, eating, drinking and procreating,
or at most in his dwelling, ornaments, etc., while in his human functions he
feels more and more like an animal. What is animal becomes human and
what is human becomes animal.
Drinking, eating and procreating are admittedly also genuinely human
functions. But in their abstraction, which separates them from the remaining
range of human functions and turns them into sole and ultimate ends, they
are animal.
(M I, 3, 85-6; EPM 72-3.)
own universal being as a man and from other men, which may be
brought under one head by treating them as two aspects of man's
alienation from his genus or species.
The actual argument is more than somewhat metaphysical. It
depends upon a conception which Feuerbach expounds at the very
beginning of his Essence o f Christianity (pp. 1-5) and which we have
already met, in slightly different form, in Marx’s earliest works. Marx,
as we have seen, took man’s freedom and self-determined activity to
be the specifically human characteristic that distinguishes man from
the determined and conditioned beast. Feuerbach treats this freedom as
consciousness9 especially as consciousness of man’s generic being. The
animal has limited consciousness of itself as an individual, but that is
all; its inner life is one with its outer life. Man, on the other hand, has
both an inner and an outer life. ‘The inner life of man’, says Feuerbach,
‘is the life which has relation to his species— to his general, as distin
guished from his individual, nature.’ It is on this consciousness of
himself as a general, generic being that the functions of thought and
speech depend when they are performed alone, without another being
present. Marx, in the Paris Manuscripts makes this conception some
what more concrete. Both men and animals live from inorganic nature.
But the animal, according to Marx, ‘is directly one with its life-
activities. It does not distinguish itself from them. It is they.’ To be
sure, the animal, like man, is able to produce— a nest, a home, etc. But
it produces only what it needs directly for itself or for its young. It
produces only under the domination of direct physical needs. It pro
duces only itself—in the sense that it can produce only according to the
measure and the need of the species to which it belongs. Man, in con
trast, ‘makes his life-activities themselves an object of his willing and of
his consciousness. He has conscious life-activities.* It is because of
this and only because of this that his activity is free activity. When
man produces, he can produce even in the absence of physical needs;
indeed, he produces truly only in the absence of physical needs. In his
production, man is not bound by the measure and need of his own
species alone; he does not merely produce himself but reproduces the
whole of Nature. He can create according to the measure of all species
and knows how to fashion each object according to its own inherent
measure; hence he creates according to the laws of beauty. But man’s
consciousness of himself as a generic being depends upon his being
able to appropriate and dominate Nature and to see his own reflection
in it:
76
TH E C R IT IQ U E OF EC O N O M IC S
1 A year later, in The Holy Family, Marx was making the same point more
clearly: ‘The propertied class and the class of the proletariat present the same
77
K A R L M A R X ’ S R O A D TO COMMUNISM
We have seen how Marx in his article ‘On the Jewish Question*
already treated money as the power which turns man into a servile,
dependent being, into a commodity. In the Paris Manuscripts he
devotes a special section to money as the very essence of man’s
alienation. He quotes (M I, 3, 146) Mephistopheles in Goethe’s Faust:
Wenn ich sechs Hengste zahlen kann
Sind ihre Krafte nicht die meine?
Ich renne zu und bin ein rechter Mann
Als hatt ich vierundzwanzig Beine.1
and Shakespeare’s Timon apostrophising gold:
Thus much of this will make black, white; foul, fair;
Wrong, right; base, noble; old, young; coward, valiant. . .
Thou common whore of mankind, that putt’st odds
Among the rout of nations.
(Timon of Athens, Act IV, scene iii.)
Marx elaborates the same theme:
That which money can create for me, that for which I can pay (i.e., what
money can buy)—that 7, the possessor of the money, am. The extent of the
power of money is the extent of my power. The properties of money are the
properties and essential powers of me—its possessor. Thus what I am and
what I am capable of is in no way determined by my individuality. I am
ugly, but I can buy the most beautiful woman. Therefore I am not ugly,
for the effect of ugliness, its power of repulsion, is destroyed by money. I—
according to my individual nature—am lame, but money gives me twenty
legs, therefore I am not lame. I am a wicked, dishonest, unscrupulous, stupid
man; but people honour money, and therefore also its possessor. Money is
the highest good, therefore its possessor is good. Besides, money saves me
the trouble of being dishonest; therefore I am presumed to be honest; I am
stupid, but money is the real mind of all things; how can its possessor lack
mind?
(M I, 3, 147; cf. EPM 138-9.)
1 . . . When to my car
My money yokes six spankers, are
Their limbs not my limbs . . .
Mine all the forces I combine —
The four-and-twenty legs are mine.
(John Anster’s translation).
human self-alienation. But the former class finds in this self-alienation its con
firmation and its good, its own power: it has in it a semblance of human existence.
The class of the proletariat feels annihilated in its self-alienation; it sees in it its
own powerlessness and the reality of an inhuman existence* (M I, 3, 206).
78
TH E C R IT IQ U E OF E C O N O M IC S
From Shakespeare, says Marx, we can see the two leading character
istics of money:
(1) It is the visible divinity, the transformation of all human and natural
properties into their contraries, the universal confounding and overturning
of things; it binds together impossibilities.
(2) It is the common whore, the universal pimp, of men and nations.
The confounding and overturning of all human and natural qualities, the
coupling of impossibilities—the divine power—achieved by money arise
out of its essence as. the alienated, externalised generic being of man, which
.
has conveyed itself to another. It is the alienated ability or wealth1 ofmankind
(M I, 3, 147-8; EPM 139.)
factory workers in France call the prostitution of their wives and daughters
the xth working hour, which is literally correct.)—Or am I acting contrary
to political economy if I sell my friend to the Moroccans? . . . Then the
political economist answers: You are not transgressing my laws, but see
what Cousin Ethics and Cousin Religion have to say. My political economic
ethics and religion have nothing to reproach you with, but—But whom am
I to believe now, political economy or ethics?
(M I, 3, 131; EPM 120.)
It is thus, according to Marx, that political economy ignores the un
employed labourer, the man behind the work in so far as he is outside
the relationship of labour. ‘The thief, the swindler, the beggar, the
unemployed, the starving, miserable and criminal working man—
these are figures that do not exist for political economy, but only
for other eyes: for the eyes of the doctor, the judge, the gravedigger
and the bum-bailifP (M I, 3, 97).1
This, then, is Marx’s critique of economics and the doctrine of
alienation in terms of which he seeks to explain the necessary contra
dictions of ‘civil society’ or economic life. The fact of alienation—
the estrangement of nature and of such human functions as the political
power or State from man—had already been postulated by Hegel in the
Phenomenology o f Mindy as Marx emphasises; but Hegel develops the
concept of alienation only in the sphere of ideas, while Marx seeks to
show its practical nature in the concrete social and economic life of man.
The metaphysical foundations and empirical ethical content of the
concept of alienation we shall examine shortly, in Part III. The under
lying conception of man’s products as in some sense ‘truly part of
1 Marx concedes that there has been a partial revolution in the theory of
political economy, an attempt to bring some human content back into the field.
But the attempt was only partial, it failed to overcome the basic alienation on
which political economy rests. It thus parallels the Lutheran revolution in
religion. The Catholics, the fetish-worshippers of political economy, according
to Marx, were the mercantilists, who worshipped private property in its material,
symbolic, nonhuman, form— in the precious metals. Luther overcame the
objective extemalisation and estrangement of religion and made it subjective
by bringing it, through the doctrine of faith, back into the heart of the layman.
Similarly, Adam Smith overcame the external materialisation of wealth and
incorporated private property into man himself by translating wealth into its
subjective form, into labour. But to do this is not genuinely to overcome aliena
tion. Private property is not reduced to its human content as a function of man
— in taking private property into himself, man is himself reduced into a form of
private property. Thus Ricardo, quite consistently with the nature of political
economy, treats man as nothing more than a machine for consuming and produc
ing and man’s life as nothing more than a form of capital.
80
TH E C R IT IQ U E OF EC O N O M IC S
81
8. Communism and the Complete,
Unalienated Man
,
(3) The alienation of nature from man means the alienation of man from
his own universal generic social being. His generic social existence, instead of
representing his essential nature becomes a mere means for satisfying his
narrow, individual demands.
(4) The alienation of man from his universal being means also his alienation
from other men. Instead of being expressions of his own universal essence,
they confront him as hostile beings.
Political economy cannot escape or resolve these contradictions
because it does not criticise private property, because it does not see
that the true basis of private property is human alienation. But in the
Paris Manuscripts, at least, Marx insists on the logical priority of
alienation: it is not enough merely to criticise or reject private property
without recognising and resolving the human alienation that underlies
it. Thus he emphasises (somewhat obscurely) that instead of asking
‘What is the origin of private property?’, we should ask ‘How can we
82
COMMUNISM A N D TH E C O M P L E T E , U N A L I E N A T E D M AN
explain the alienation that broke out in the course of human develop
ment?’ 1 (M I, 3,93). Instead of studying laws of economic development
from the abstracted standpoint of private property, from within
alienation, we should ask: ‘What is the relationship between the general
nature of private property, as it has developed out of alienated labour,
and truly human and social property? Four years later, Marx (with
Engels) was to attack scathingly in the Communist Manifesto this treat
ment of alienation as something distinct from and more basic than the
economic facts supposed to follow from it:
It is well known how the monks wrote silly lives of Catholic Saints over the
manuscripts on which the classical works of ancient heathendom had been
written. The German literati reversed this process with the profane French
literature. They wrote their philosophical nonsense beneath the French
original. For instance, beneath the French criticism of the economic functions
of money, they wrote ‘Alienation of Humanity* and beneath the French
criticism of the bourgeois State they wrote, ‘Dethronement of the Category
of the General*, and so forth . . .
The French Socialist and Communist literature was thus completely
emasculated. And, since it ceased in the hands of the German to express the
struggle of one class with the other, he felt conscious of having overcome
‘French one-sidedness* and of representing not true requirements, but the
requirements of Truth; not the interests of the proletariat, but the interests
of Human Nature, of Man in general, who belongs to no class, has no reality,
who exists only in the misty realm of philosophical fantasy.
(SW I, 55.)
In 1844, without question, Marx still believed in the requirements of
‘Human Nature, of Man in general’, still insisted on alienation as some
thing more than a series of economic facts. It is hardly surprising that
the concrete value of his insistence that questions about private
property should be converted into questions about alienation remains
obscure. He does, however, in somewhat metaphysical form seek to
derive one concrete point from it—a criticism of the ‘crude Com
munism’ which fails to see the alienation behind private property.
1 To substitute the latter question for the former, according to Marx, is already
to advance a fair way toward the solution. But in point of fact he does not take
this question any further in the Paris Manuscripts. His subsequent comments in
the Poverty o f Philosophy (p. 36) and in Capital (Book I, chapter 1) give no
account of the origin of alienation but merely link it with commodity production
and emphasise that the acute form of alienation is a product of modem capitalism.
In the German Ideology alienation is traced beyond private property to the
division of labour, seen as the common ground from which both alienation and
private property arise. See infra, iv, 14.
83
K A R L M A R X ’ S R O A D TO COM MUNISM
the particular secret ‘of this still utterly crude and thoughtless Com
munism. Just as woman steps out of marriage into universal prostitu
tion, so the entire world of riches, of the objectified being of man, steps
from its exclusive marriage with private owners into the relationship
of universal prostitution with society. This Communism, in its univer
sal negation of the personality of man, is merely the consistent expres
sion of private ownership, which is the negation of human personality.
Universal envy constituting itself as power is only the hidden form in
which greed reappears, satisfying itself in a different way . . . How little
crude Communism’s overcoming of private property is a genuine
appropriation is shown by its abstract negation of the whole world of
education and civilisation, by its return to the unnatural simplicity of
the poor man without needs, who has not passed beyond private
property but has rather not even reached it yet.’ (M I, 3, 112.)
In the second stage, according to Marx, we have Communism still
political in nature—whether democratic or despotic— or Communism
already concerned with the dissolution of the State. In both forms,
Marx claims (again somewhat obscurely) that Communism already
recognises itself as standing for human re-integration, for the dissolu
tion of alienation, but it still has not grasped the positive essence of
private property or the human character of needs. Thirdly and finally
we have:
Communism as the positive dissolution and transcendence o f private propertyy
o f human self-alienation, and therefore as the real appropriation of the human
[
essence by and for man; therefore as the complete and conscious return o f
man to himself as a social gesellschaftlichen\, i.e., human, man— a return
fashioned with the whole wealth o f his past development. This Communism
is the consummated naturalism = humanism, the consummated humanism =
naturalism, it is the genuine resolution o f the conflict between man and
Nature and between man and man— the true resolution o f the strife between
existence and true being [Existen^ und Wesen], between objectification and
self-confirmation, between freedom and necessity, between the individual
and the species. Communism is the riddle o f history solved; and it knows
itself to be the solution.
(M I, 3, 114 ; EPM 102.)
The same point, Marx insists, applies to religion, family, State, juris
prudence, morality, science, etc.; they are all only particular forms of
production and fall under the general laws governing the transcendence
of alienation within production. The positive transcendence of private
property ‘through the appropriation of human life* is therefore the
85
K A R L M A R X ’ S R O A D TO COM MUNISM
86
PA RT TH REE
Critical Resume:
Ethics and the Young Marx
7KLVSDJHLQWHQWLRQDOO\OHIWEODQN
9» Ethics—Positive or Normative?
the assertion that X has the positive quality ‘good* would not imply
that I necessarily seek, commend or require it. To treat ‘good* as a
quality would be to open the way to making ethics a science and to
clarifying the distinction between ethical and non-ethical fields; but
it would also be to shear ethics of its advocative and its normative
pretensions. It would be to investigate the common characters, the
ways of working, of goods and the relations into which they are able
to enter as a result of these characters;1 but it would be to destroy the
illusion that such goods logically imply or require support or pursuit.
The question whether they are supported or pursued and by whom
would be logically independent of their character and could be raised
only after their common characters had been established.
The traditional moralist cannot afford to see ‘good’ as ‘merely* a
quality which some display or seek and others lack or reject. For him
it must also be a relation, something demanded, pursued, required,
which it is illogical— or ‘wrong*— to reject. A vicious attempt to
straddle the issue, to confuse and amalgamate quality and relation,
reveals itself in the popular traditional conception of ‘good’ as that
whose nature it is to be demanded or pursued. This is to treat a relation as
constituting the character or quality of a thing. But things cannot be
constituted by their relations: a thing must have characters before it
can enter into a relation; it must be jwragthing before it can be com
mended, rejected or pursued. I f we treat ‘good* (or ‘piety’ in Euthy-
phro’s case) as standing for a relation that anything may have, i.e., like
the word ‘burden’, for instance, then, as the Euthyphro shows, our
commendations would be entirely arbitrary, there would be nothing to
prevent anything from being treated as ‘good’, or as pleasing the gods,
just as there is nothing to prevent anything from becoming a burden.2
Normative conceptions of ethics with positive, scientific pretensions>
then, require the confusion or the amalgamation of qualitative and
relational treatments of good. This confusion is facilitated by the
1 While a quality cannot by itself imply a relation, relations which are not
purely spatio-temporal relations like ‘down*, ‘before’ or ‘left’ can and do imply
qualities in the terms that enter into these relations. Thus marriage implies the
sexual characteristics of the partners and only men can be uncles. But the fact
that X is a man implies neither that he is a husband nor that he is an uncle.
2 Cf. the seventeenth-century Cambridge Platonist Ralph Cudworth's ‘Second
Sermon’: ‘Virtues and holiness in creatures . . . are not therefore good because
God loveth them, and will have them to be accounted such; but rather God
therefore loveth them, because they are in themselves simply good’ (cited in
J. A. Passmore, Ralph Cudworth9 pp. 83-4).
90
E T H I C S — P O S I T I V E OR N O R M A T I V E ?
93
C R I T I C A L R E S U M E : E T H I C S A N D TH E Y O U N G M A R X
suppose there are ethical facts; if there are no ethical facts, there is
nothing to show that these judgments are ethical.
Anacharsis the Scythian, who came from the plains north of the
Black Sea some two centuries before Plato, is reputed to have said:
Nature is almost always in opposition to the laws, because she labours for
the happiness of the individual, without regard to other individuals who
surround him, while the laws only direct their attention to the relations
by which he is united to them, and because Nature infinitely diversifies our
character and inclinations, while it is the object of the laws to bring them
back to unity.
speak of the self-determined is to assert that the effect was its own
cause; that is, to say that there has been no change.1 The young Marx
and Hegel, in seeing the rational both as the end or ultimate effect of
history and as the original and ever-present cause of historical develop
ment, run squarely into this difficulty. Marx speaks of reason having
always been present but not in ‘a rational form’; it is difficult to see in
this anything but an attempt to have it both ways, to assert that reason
changes and is yet the same. The same difficulty arises for Marx
regarding his conception of an essential human nature. I f this nature
is the determining cause of all historical development, he cannot show
why there should be any development at all. If, on the other hand,
history is a series of transactions between this essential human nature
and its environment, then both will be affected in the process, then
there is nothing more ‘essential’ about the human Weseti than about
the occurrences on which it acts and which act upon it. Marx, indeed,
in seeking to maintain the distinction between the human essence and
empirical human interests, desires and ‘caprices’, is forced to disconnect
the two entirely, till there is no significant sense in which the two are
part of the same person or of the same development.
The attempt to establish the self-determined does not only imply
that it can have no history. It also implies that it can have no environ
ment. It must become, as Spinoza saw, the single, all-embracing
substance. It is no accident that Marx is forced to take all social institu
tions, even non-human objects, into man himself, forced to reconcile
Subject and Object by obliterating the distinction between them. But
the distinction will not be obliterated and in his view that man will
‘appropriate’ nature, will determine it instead of being determined by
it, Marx clearly reveals the anti-empirical, anti-deterministic, character
of the belief in self-determination. His anthropology, his human reduc-
tionism, is the inescapable outcome of his metaphysical assumptions.
In the name of determinism, of the continuity of human and non
human events, Marx has reduced everything to Man.
For the sake of self-determination, Marx had to destroy the distinc-
1 A certain superficial plausibility is lent to the notion of self-determination
by the observation of change and development within a system. But such change
is not the result of the system acting upon itself, but of the interaction of the
minor systems within the whole, acting upon each other externally. The changes
in the relationship between the minor systems, of course, will always be depen
dent upon external exchanges with the environment of the entire system.
view of causality I am putting is more fully argued. The logical material in this
section generally owes much to his work.
98
E T H I C S — P O S I T I V E OR N O R M A T I V E ?
tion between the human and the non-human. For the sake of self-
determination, he has also to destroy the distinction between one man
and another. If man is to be truly self-determined, he cannot be
determined by Nature, he also cannot be determined by other men.
Marx requires a human community in which not only conflict, but
even the very distinction, between one man and another has dis
appeared. This is the significance of his insistence that in the truly
human society each man represents every other, that every activity
carried out in this society is my activity. He bases this, as we have seen,
on a seemingly metaphysical notion of the human essence as truly
universal in a qualitative, intensional sense and not in a merely dis
tributive sense.
the latter, adopts his views and his ways o f dealing with situations. In this
way the patient’s previously pent-up motives find outlet. But the same may
take place within one person’s mind, when a conflict is resolved and a new
type o f activity emerges by the aid o f certain abiding motives or sentiments.
This is the process o f ‘sublimation’, where one motive finds for another a
means o f expression, provides it with a language, puts its own ‘ideas’ before
it as objectives. This is also the process o f education. It may be argued, then,
that all good motives have this power o f transference or conversion, whereby
from hitherto dissociated material a new motive is formed which can co
operate with the good motive. Goodness is associative, evil is dissociative;
goods have a common language, evils have not.1
105
io. The Rejection o f Moralism,
o f ‘Rights’ and o f Normative Law
demand for protection, the longing for comfort and consolation. But
he sees correctly that these evils are unable to overcome goods entirely
and that they can neither form a coherent, stable system of their own
or reach a stable and coherent accommodation with goods. It is thus
that he can point to the contradictions in ‘the rights of the citizen* and
‘the rights of man* {supra II, 6). The accommodation of political State
and civil society becomes a harmony of discord with harmony; the
freedom of evils becomes their ‘right* to seek to destroy each other.
‘The human right of freedom is not based on the connexion of man
with man, but rather on the separation of man from man . . . Man’s
right of private property . . . is the right of self-interest. . . It allows
every man to find not the realisation, but the limitation, of his freedom
. . . Security is the guarantee of egoism.’ (‘On the Jewish Question’,
supra II, 6.)
If we accept as the foundation of moral theory the utilitarian concern
with ends and neglect the character of the motives and activities
pursuing these ends, then— as Marx saw—we are necessarily driven
into incoherence. Acquisitiveness conflicts with acquisitiveness, greed
interferes with greed, security threatens security. Even if it were true
that all persons display these demands, the fact that they are common to
all still establishes no single common interest, no genuine basis for
co-operation. This, I should argue, is the empirical content of Marx’s
distinction between mere numerical universality and a qualitative,
intensional universality. For the utilitarian, with his elevation of
divisive demands, ‘society . . . appears as a frame external to indivi
duals, as a limitation of their original independence. The sole thread that
keeps them together is natural necessity, needs and private interest, the
preservation of their property and of their egoistic person.’ {Supra,
II, 6.) Thus— though Marx did not go on to say this explicitly— the
‘principles’ of civil society and of the utilitarian elevation of individual
ends cannot be formulated: the divisiveness of the ends accepted by the
utilitarian is reflected in the incoherence of his principles. The ‘right
to liberty’, for instance, cannot be proclaimed as such: it becomes the
right ‘to liberty that does not interfere with the liberty of others’,
and thus establishes as principle that I may not interfere with the liberty
of others, but their liberties may interfere with mine. Subsidiary shifts
have to be resorted to: we are exhorted to avoid unneccessary interfer
ence with people’s liberty, where what is ‘necessary’ can never be
established; we are told that the principle of liberty is after all not a
principle, but a defeasible presumption, the operation of which is
108
TH E R E J E C T I O N OF M O R A LISM
109
ii. Ethics and the ‘Truly
Human’ Society
cause they are wanted.* Neither can they be made to continue by being
prescribed. In the case of evils, on the other hand, the attempt to impose
prescriptive norms and the resultant appeal to hierarchical conceptions
of ‘authority* is a necessary condition for the allaying of internal dis
sension and conflict— dissension and conflict which, in fact, can only
be concealed but not suppressed. It is here that we find the subordina
tion of activities to ‘rules’, the substitution of ‘loyalty’ to institutions
and persons for ‘loyalty’ to movements and ways of life and the attempt
to shelter rules, ends, institutions and persons from discussion or
criticism.
Marx’s vision of Communism, then, is in no sense an ‘artistic’
vision; it rests on his sound, if unworked-out, perception of the
characteristic organisation and ways of working of goods; it rests,
that is, on an ethical and not on an aesthetic distinction. The real
reason his vision has been called artistic, it seems to me, is not because
it embodies aesthetic conceptions, but because the society he portrays
seems possible, to his critics, only as a society of artists. Immersion in
activity, neglect of rewards, spontaneous co-operation and disinterested
appreciation and emulation— the theory runs— are possible only to
those engaged in the ‘higher levels’ of creative activity, in ‘pure’
science and art. This seems to me patently false. Artists, as people, can
display hatred, envy and greed. They can be found subordinating their
work to ‘popular taste’, to religious requirements or to the demands
of the market; they can plagiarise, steal and intrigue. Soldiers, fisher
men, farmers and artisans can be found exhibiting love or courage,
displaying attachment to their activity for its own sake, co-operating
spontaneously with their fellows and neglecting all thought of the
‘rewards’ of their work. The distinction between the morality of goods
and the morality of evils is rather linked—as Georges Sorel suggests—
with the distinction between the morality of the producer and the
morality of the consumer. The producer emphasises activities, a way
of life, a morality; he is stirred by production everywhere and brought
together by the productive spirit with other producers. The consumer
emphasises ends, things to be secured; he subordinates himself and his
activity to these ends; his sentiments are not productive but proprietary
and consumptive; his relations with other consumers involve friction,
hypocrisy and envy.
The linking of ethical distinctions with productive and consumptive
moralities in history does not imply that men can be classified into
those who are producers and those who are consumers, or that the
u3
C R I T I C A L R ESU M & : E T H I C S A N D TH E Y O U N G M A R X
“5
C R I T I C A L R E S U M E : E T H I C S A N D TH E Y O U N G M A R X
things that I treat as evils— the desire for money or recognition, for instance
— are often necessary to produce scientific or artistic creation in a given
individual, and may thus be found ‘co-operating* with goods in a most
intimate fashion. Champion billiard players, orchid growers, etc., I have
been told, display all the characteristics I claim for artists and scientists:
their developments o f technique assist one another, they themselves keep
in touch with each other, exchange hints, inspire each other. ‘Yet this does
not seem to be o f any ethical interest.* I should argue, on the contrary, that
it is o f ethical interest; the orchid grower and billiard player who exchange
information freely with others in their fields, who are inspired by advances
in them, are displaying ethical qualities that assimilate their activities to those
o f the scientist and the artist and the producer in general and radically
distinguish them from those fellow-exponents o f their craft who are con
cerned with fame, with profit, with ‘getting one over* the men whom they
see as hostile competitors.
The allied suggestion that scientific and artistic production o f a high order
frequently display an extraordinary intertwining o f motives— o f intellectual
interest with unusual egotism, ambition or the desire for self-assertion—
raises more serious issues. It is true that a person’s immersion in good
activities may be intensified by evil motives: a man’s scientific work may be
goaded on by his desire for wealth, honour and the love o f women, as Freud
puts it. Nevertheless, it seems to me that such an alliance between good and
evil motives can only be o f the ‘extrinsic* kind outlined above. The length
o f time for which such motives can co-operate without overt friction will
depend upon purely fortuitous circumstances. At the same time, the assist
ance which evils can render goods in specific circumstances seems to me
akin to the assistance which non-mental occurrences— earthquakes, epidem
ics or poverty— can render goods and not at all akin to the assistance goods
render each other. In general, I should be inclined to suggest that evils,
where they assist goods, do so only by inhibiting other evils. A man’s love
o f money will prevent him from seeking luxury at a particular moment or
from showing his envy o f his colleagues if he has reason to believe that his
reputation and work as a disinterested scientist will get him greater money
in the end. But the love o f money cannot give him the conception o f dis
interestedness or the capacity to display it on those occasions that he does
display it.
The second and last o f the detailed arguments concerns the distinction
between goods as involving immersion in an activity in which the distinction
between means and ends is unimportant, and bads as involving the elevation
o f ends. It has been objected that the pursuit o f ends need not be the pursuit
o f possessions, that a man’s end may be the promotion o f a good activity,
the securing of conditions in which the activity can go forward. This kind
o f position is often put, with considerable sincerity, by Vice-Chancellors o f
116
E T H IC S A N D TH E ‘ T R U L Y H U M A N ’ S O C IE T Y
H7
7KLVSDJHLQWHQWLRQDOO\OHIWEODQN
PART FO UR
Already here we see how this civil society is the true source and theatre of
all history, and how nonsensical is the conception of history held hitherto,
which neglects the real relationships and confines itself to high-sounding
dramas of princes and States. Civil society embraces the whole material
intercourse of individuals within a definite stage of development of produc
tive forces. It embraces the whole commercial and industrial life of this stage
and, in so far, transcends the State and nation, though, on the other hand
again, it must assert itself towards foreign peoples as nationality, and in
wardly must organise itself as State . . . Civil society as such only develops
with the bourgeoisie; the social organisation evolving directly out of produc
tion and commerce, which in all ages forms the basis of the State and of the
rest of the idealistic superstructure, has, however, always been designated
by the same name.
(MI, 5, 25-6. Italics mine.)
What is society, whatever its form may be? The product of men’s reciprocal
activity. Are men free to choose this or that form of society for themselves?
By no means. Assume a particular state of development in the productive
forces of man and you will get a particular form of commerce and consump
tion. Assume particular stages of development in production, commerce
and consumption and you will have a corresponding social order, a cor
responding organisation of the family and of the ranks and classes. Pre
suppose a particular civil society and you will get particular political condi
tions which are only the official expression of civil society . . . the social
1 See Engels' well-known statement in his preface to Marx’s Revelations
Concerning the Communist Trial in Cologne: ‘When I visited Marx in Paris in the
summer of 1844, our complete agreement on all theoretical questions became
clear . . . When we met again in the spring of 1845 in Brussels, Marx had already
developed out of these foundations the main lines of his materialist theory of
history.’
122
TH E N E W E D I F I C E
history of men is never anything but the history of their individual develop
ment, whether they are conscious of it or not. Their material relations are
the bases of all their relations. These material relations are only the necessary
forms in which their material and individual activity is realised.
(SC 7-8.)
It is on this basis that Marx can turn viciously1 on his own earlier
conception 'of Human Nature, of Man in general, who belongs to no
class, has no reality, who exists only in the misty realm of philosophical
fantasy*. There is, he insists in the German Ideology, no essential Man
apart from real man and real men are shaped by economic forces:
This sum of productive forces, forms of capital and social forms of inter
course, which every individual and generation finds in existence as something
given, is the real basis of what the philosophers have conceived as ‘substance*
and ‘essence of man*.
(M I, 5, 28.)
,
sensibility, is conceived only under the form of the object or of con
templation, but not as human sensory activity practice [Praxis], not
subjectively* (M I, 5, 533; cf. SW II, 363). The point is developed in
the second thesis:
The question whether objective truth can be attributed to human thinking
is not a question of theory but is a practical question. In practice man must
prove the truth, i.e., the reality and power, the this-sidedness of his thinking.
The dispute over the reality or non-reality of thinking which is isolated
from practice is a purely scholastic question.
(M I, 5, 534; cf. SW II, 365.)
That this implies a pragmatic theory of truth— the position that true
beliefs are those which work or aid the solution of ‘tasks*— is taken to
be confirmed by the famous eleventh thesis:
Philosophers have only interpreted the world differently; the point, however,
is to change it.
(M 1, 5,535; SW II, 367.)
Now, in so far as the Theses are an attack on the Cartesian cogito,
on the doctrine of the passive mind merely confronted by the ‘external’
i*5
E T H I C S A N D TH E M A TU R E M A R X
with natural law, and prove the existence o f truth and accuracy in his case;
and that he, the prophet who has now arisen, has in his bag final and ultimate
truth, eternal morality and eternal justice. This has all happened so many
hundred and thousands o f times that we can only feel astonished that there
should still be people credulous enough to believe this, not of others, but of
themselves. ,. _
(AD 104-5.)
The central weakness of such relativism has been exposed by Plato
in the Theaetetus. The relativist, in claiming that all truth is relative,
does not put his own claims forward as relative but claims for them
‘absolute’, i.e., unambiguous, truth. There is in fact no other way of
conveying an issue: to say all truth is relative, however much the issue
may be confused by reference to what is ‘true for me’ is simply to say
that X both is and is not Y and thus to make discourse impossible.
That Engels has no real wish to do so is made sufficiently evident by
his shirking of the issue over mathematical truths and his admission,
in Anti-Diihringy that certain ‘trivial’ propositions— ‘twice two make
four’, ‘birds have beaks’, etc.— are unambiguously and not relatively
true. His position, indeed, depends entirely on the consideration of
more ‘complicated’ theories and assertions which, he claims, may be
true to a relative extent but not absolutely. He illustrates this by citing
Regnault’s discovery that Boyle’s law does not apply in certain cases—
a proof, according to Engels, that Boyle’s law is untrue and yet not
false. But the actual position, of course, is that Boyle’s law— the asser
tion that all gases have property X —is positively and not relatively
false, while a different assertion— that all A-gases have property X — is
positively and not relatively true.1 If neither assertion were unambig
uously true or false, there would be no way of choosing between them.
What Engels is really saying is that men are more prone to error
in general statements than in particular ones and in social and historical
fields than in natural sciences. This, far from implying the relativity
of all truth, requires the recognition of unambiguous truth, of a positive
and definite distinction between truth and error. Thus, when Engels
writes in Anti-Diihring (p. 101) that ‘the knowledge which has un
conditional claim to truth is realised in a series of relative errors . . .
through an endless eternity of human existence,’ it is clear that the
word ‘relative’ has no meaning here. It should simply be dropped. The
movement described by Engels is not a movement from relative to
1 For a fuller discussion of this particular example, and of Engels’ theory of
truth in general, from the realist standpoint I myself adopt, see John Anderson:
‘Marxist Philosophy*, A .J.P .P ., vol. XIII (1935), p. 24 et seq., esp. pp. 26-32.
128
THE N E W E D I F I C E
131
13. The Materialist Interpretation
o f History and Marx’s Critique o f
Moralities
1 See especially his chapters, in the first volume of Capital, headed ‘The
Working Day* (K I, 239-317; C I, 255-330) and ‘Machinery and Large-scale
Industry* (K I, 387-532, esp. pp. 505-29; C I, 405-556, esp. 526-52). Marx
implicidy concedes the devotion and independence of view of many of the factory
inspectors appointed under the Acts, and their attempts to expose the intolerable
nature of factory conditions and some of the worst legal abuses in the Reports,
from which Marx draws much of his material. Marx, and Engels in his addenda
to subsequent editiofis, note that some of the abuses (including the discrimina
tion against workers over breach of contract) have been, or are being, remedied.
Of course, this would not in itself show that all the features of the capitalist
137
E T H I C S A N D TH E M A TU R E M A R X
factory system which Marx exposes are merely temporary—but the interaction
of many factors in factory legislation, which Marx has to admit implicitly, raises
difficulties for his whole theory of economic determination with which he never
tries to cope.
138
TH E M A T E R I A L I S T I N T E R P R E T A T I O N OF H I S T O R Y
of the ruling class, or, as soon as the oppressed class has become powerful
enough, it has represented the revolt against this domination and the future
interests of the oppressed.
(A D 109.)
Thus Engels distinguishes in modern times the Christian-feudal
morality of the feudal aristocracy, the modern bourgeois morality and
the proletarian morality. Kautsky, following the Engels line in his
Ethics and the Materialist Conception o f History, argues that in the
ancient world the ethical question first emerged clearly as a result of
the class tensions that followed the Persian wars. These wars placed
the Greeks at the centre of widespread commercial activity and pro
duced three leading types of morality: the Epicurean, representing
those connected with private production; the Platonic and Neo-
Platonic, representing the section of the aristocracy not engaged in
personal control of production; the Stoic, representing several of the
remaining classes and acting as a mediating ethical theory.1
All this has its origin in a subtler and rather more intelligent treat
ment of historical moral codes by Marx and Engels in the German
Ideology. The interpretation given there does not lay itself open to a
voluntaristic ‘conspiracy’ theory of morality, by which moralities
come to be seen as consciously-fashioned tools in the struggle for
domination. In the German Ideology Marx and Engels consistently take
morality as aiming to express the common interests of a society. In the
rational society of Communism such interests will be truly harmonious
and universalisable; a perfectly coherent morality, in which private
and social interest will be completely fused, will therefore arise. In the
class society, the common interest is an illusion, an ideal which
alienates man’s social functions from man and sets them up to oppose
him. The moralities of class society are therefore necessarily fraudulent
and incoherent. They represent not the common interest of the whole
society, but only of a class; its particular economic interests disguised
as general social interests. The result is on the one hand a constant
changing of moralities as the social initiative passes from one class to
another, on the other a tension between the specific interests of the
class and its claim to represent society as a whole:
1 Most contemporary Soviet ethical philosophers, such as Sharia and Shishkin,
take the same line that each morality represents the economic interests and
attitudes of a class, though unlike Kautsky, they make no serious attempt to link
the fundamental ethical structure of a theory with its alleged class background.
They are satisfied instead with an occasional example of obvious ‘class' prejudice
in a moral philosopher, e.g., Aristotle's contempt for slaves.
139
E T H I C S A N D TH E M A T U R E M A R X
Each new class which puts itself in the place of the one ruling before it, is
compelled, merely in order to carry through its aim, to represent its interests
as the common interest of all the members of the society, put in an ideal form;
it will give its ideas the form of universality, and represent them as the only
rational, universally valid ones..
(GI 40-1; M I, 5, 37.)
This procedure, according to Marx and Engels is not, in the initial
stages of the new class struggles, entirely Machiavellian.
The class making a revolution appears from the start, merely because it is
opposed to a class, not as a class but as the representative of the whole
society; it appears as the whole mass of society confronting the one ruling
class. It can do this because, to start with, its interest really is more connected
with the common interest of all other non-ruling classes, because under the
pressure of conditions its interest has not yet been able to develop as the
particular interest of a particular class.
(GI 41; M I, 5, 37.)
The situation described here, Marx and Engels seem to assume, pro
vides evidence for their view that history displays a moral advance
toward true universality. After describing how the victory of the
French bourgeoisie over the aristocracy enabled many proletarians to
raise themselves into the ranks of the bourgeoisie, they conclude:
Every new class, therefore, achieves its hegemony only on a broader basis
than that of the class ruling previously . . .
(GI 41; M I, 5, 37.)
These are the most explicit and detailed comments on morality to
be found in the work of Marx the Communist, and the most sensible to
be found in the work of Engels. They are not enough. They tell us
nothing about the vexed question of interests; they eschew any
consideration of the truth or falsity of moral claims; they give no
account of the issues that have dominated the history or moral theory
and ethical controversy. They give us no basis for distinguishing
between the political programme and the ethical convictions of a class,
nor do they make any attempt to see whether there are constant
themes in the history of ethics and, if so, how they could be accounted
for. Moralists, after all, have condemned other things beside theft.
Where there is division of labour on a social scale there is also mutual inde
pendence among the different sections of work. In the last instance, produc
tion is the decisive factor. But when the trade in products becomes indepen
dent of production itself, it follows a movement of its own which, while it is
governed as a whole by production, still in particular cases and within this
general dependence follows particular laws contained in the nature of this
new factor; this movement has phases of its own and in its turn reacts on the
movement of production . . .
It is similar with law. As soon as the new division of labour which creates
professional lawyers becomes necessary, another new and independent
sphere is opened up which, for all its general dependence on production
and trade, still has its own capacity for reacting upon these spheres as well.
In a modem State, law must not only correspond to the general economic
position and be its expression, but must also be an expression which is
consistent in itself, and which does not, owing to inner contradictions, look
glaringly inconsistent. And in order to achieve this, the faithful reflection of
economic conditions is more and more infringed upon. All the more so, the
more rarely it appears that a code of law is the blunt, unmitigated, unadulter
ated expression of the domination of a class—this in itself would already
offend the ‘conception of justice* . . . Thus to a great extent the course of
the ‘development of law* only consists: first in the attempt to do away with
the contradictions arising from the direct translation of economic relations
into legal principles, and to establish a harmonious system of law, and then
in the repeated breaches made in this system by the influence and pressure of
further economic development, which involves it in further contradictions
(I am only speaking here of civil law for the moment).
The reflection of economic relations as legal principles is necessarily also a
topsy-turvy one: it happens without the person who is acting being conscious
of it; the jurist imagines he is operating with a priori principles, whereas they
are really only economic reflexes; so everything is upside down. And it
seems to me obvious that this inversion, which, so long as it remains un
recognised, forms what we call ideological conception, reacts in its turn upon
the economic basis and may, within certain limits, modify it. The basis of
the law of inheritance—assuming the stages reached in the development of
the family are equal—is an economic one. But it would be difficult to prove,
for instance, that the absolute liberty of the testator in England and the
141
E T H I C S A N D TH E M A T U R E M A R X
severe restrictions imposed upon him in France are only due in every detail to
economic causes. Both react back, however, on the economic sphere to a
very considerable extent, because they influence the division of property.
(SC 478, 481-2.)
Here, again, we have all the usual ambiguities. Law now reflects
economic relations and not class interests; though precisely how an
economic reflex or an economic relation becomes a normative legal
principle is not clear. Nor is it readily apparent why the translation of
economic reflexes into legal principles should lead to contradictions,
or how a materialist interpretation of history would account either for
the interest in harmony and consistency or for our conception of
justice. But what is clear is that Engels has conceded that ideologies
are not purely passive, and even that they may affect the economic base
‘to a very considerable extent*. There is no force after this in Engels’
attempt to save the situation by insisting that ‘in the last instance,
production is the decisive factor.’ If production is affected by ideology,
then the production that proves decisive is not the production that
formed the economic base. Once we grant even ‘relative’ independence
and multiple interaction in social events, once we recognise that law
may react back on economic forces and economic relationships, we
have to admit that history is not a single-factor story, that social action
does not move in only one direction, and that there is no way of setting
necessary limits to the possible social effects of social movements,
activities and beliefs.
the distinction between freedom and alienation, we have seen, was the
ethical leitmotif of Marx’s philosophical and political development.
What Hegel and Feuerbach had seen in the history of human thinkings
Marx saw in the history of human production and social life. It was
alienation that Marx discovered in the facts, as well as the theory, of
political economy; it was the tension and instability resulting from
alienation which would inevitably end in its collapse and the inaugura
tion of a new, unalienated, economic and social life. Yet in the econ
omic magnum opus of his mature period—Das Kapital—he does not
rely on the term ‘alienation’ at all. Was it, then, one of the casualties
of his tendency toward economic reductionism? Had it been dropped
as a ‘philosophic’ or ‘ethical’ concept having no place in his new
objective and scientific historical materialism?
The answer is no. The positive content which Marx gave to the
term ‘alienation’ remains central to the position he is expounding in
Capital. The mental process of objectifying one’s own product and
allowing it to dominate one Marx now calls the fetishism of commodi
ties (K I, 76-89; C I, 4); it remains the same process. Man’s loss of
control over his labour power Marx calls his dehumanisation; it, too, is
the same process—a process which for Marx remains of central im
portance to the understanding of capitalism. Man’s loss of control
over the product of his work Marx now calls exploitation; a term which
does not mean that Marx thinks the capitalist is getting too much—
more than is ‘reasonable*, but which underlines his insistence that what
belongs to one man, or to men in general, is being appropriated by
others, or by some men in particular. Exploitation is made possible by
the creation of surplus value; but its basic ground for Marx remains
144
H ISTO RICAL M ATERIALISM
the alienation of man from his labour power, the fact that man's
activity becomes a commodity. In the German Ideology and in Marx's
economic notes and drafts made between 1850 and 1859 the connexion
of all this with the term ‘alienation’ is made specific (cf., e.g., G I,
64-7; M I, 5, 56-9; Grundrisse, 73-82, 88-90, 151-62, 504-8). But
we do not need to have the connexion made specific, to have the actual
term flourished in the text, to see precisely the same theme in Wage
Labour and Capital, the Critique o f Political Economy and Capital
itself. ‘Marx's condemnation of capitalism', writes Karl Popper,1 a
critic not at all interested in alienation, ‘is fundamentally a moral
condemnation. The system is condemned, for the cruel injustice inherent
in it which is combined with full ‘formal’ justice and righteousness.
The system is condemned, because by forcing the exploiter to enslave
the exploited it robs both of their freedom. Marx did not combat
wealth, nor did he praise poverty. He hated capitalism, not for its
accumulation of wealth, but for its oligarchical character; he hated it
because in this system wealth means political power in the sense of
power over men. Labour power is made a commodity; that means that
men must sell themselves on the market. Marx hated the system
because it resembled slavery.'
Marx, of course, is not confronting capitalism with a moral principle
established independently of his enquiries and condemning it for not
being ‘what it ought to be’. Whatever the logical weaknesses Marx's
account of the distinction between dependence and freedom may have,
the distinction rests, as we have seen, on an empirical basis. If Marx and
his readers are drawn toward freedom and repelled by dependence and
alienation, this is not because he has striven to show that they ‘ought to
be'. It is rather because some goods, at least, operate in Marx and in
many of his readers, so that the morality of freedom, the sympathies
and antipathies of goods themselves, are something he and they can
also feel. Marx, of course, in his mature work as much as in his earlier
work, wants to go somewhat further than this. He wants to show that
history is inevitably working toward freedom, toward the Communist
society where men’s production will no longer enslave them, but will
become part of them, where tools will cease to be men's masters and
become their servants. But however unfounded this view may be, it,
too, is not—in Marx’s sense—a moral view. It neither presupposes nor
establishes a new moral obligation in place of those which Marx
exposed.
1 The Open Society and Its Enemies, vol. II, p. 199.
145
E T H I C S A N D TH E M A T U R E M A R X
In his mature work, then, Marx describes the same process and
predicts the same goal as he described and predicted in the Paris
Manuscripts. Much of the seeming gulf between the ‘philosophical’
terminology of these Manuscripts and the empirical descriptive
terminology aimed at in Capital has been bridged for us with the
publication of the Grundrisse. These notes and drafts reveal clearly
the extent to which Marx remained a philosopher, thinking in philo
sophical categories and then seeking for their empirical content. This
is what he did with ‘alienation’ and— less successfully—with ‘freedom’.
The results of his quest did not, it seemed to him, destroy these con
cepts: on the contrary, they gave these concepts richer content and
confirmed their value.
There is, of course, one obvious distinction between Marx’s con
ception of alienation in the Paris Manuscripts and his later conception.
In the Manuscripts, he still sees man as alienated from a generic, social
being which is at once the universal nature common to all men and the
essential nature underlying man’s empirical development. In the
Theses on Feuerlach, the German Ideology and the Communist Manifesto
he rejects this conception specifically. There is no eternal or essential
human nature from which man has become alienated, no ‘Man in
general, who belongs to no class, has no reality, who exists only in the
misty realm of philosophical fantasy’ ( Communist Manifesto, SW I,
55, supra, II, 8, III, 12). ‘Human nature [Wesen],9 he now writes (in
the sixth thesis on Feuerbach), ‘is no abstraction inherent in each
separate individual. In its reality it is the ensemble of social relation
ships.’ (M I, 5, 535.) But the metaphysical conception of an essential
human nature, however much Marx may need it for his conception of
Communism, is certainly not necessary for the portrayal of alienation
under capitalism, even in the form in which Marx depicts it in the
Paris Manuscripts. He has no difficulty in exhibiting the same aliena
tion, and the same features of it, in his later work. ‘The exercise of
labour power is the worker’s own life-activity,’ he writes in Wage
Labour and Capital1 (SW I, 77; M I, 6, 475), ‘the manifestation of his
own life. And this life-activity he sells to another person in order to
This alienation between man and the social character of his activity
can be seen in every sphere of capitalist society: it is presupposed by
the existence of law, religion, etc. But only under capitalism does this
alienation appear in all its nakedness. In feudalism, as we have seen
Marx stressing in his earlier work, man is dependent but not yet
divided; in capitalism his dependence is intensified in practice and his
division is accomplished in theory (K I, 82-7; C I, 88-96). The slave
sold his person, the serf sold part of his labour power, the worker
147
E T H I C S A N D TH E M A TU R E M A R X
under capitalism sells all of his labour power, but he sells it piecemeal.
His alienation is therefore more thorough-going, more complete, than
that of the slave and of the serf who preceded him in the arena of
history. (Cf. The German Ideology, M I, 5, 56-9, GI, 64-8; Grundrisse,
73-82; Capital, K I, 76-89, C I, 81-95.)
The final aspect of alienation brought out in the Paris Manuscripts
is man’s alienation from nature. Instead of controlling it, making it
part of his being, he is dominated by it, becomes part of its being. In
the Grundrisse and Capital the reference is more frequently to produc
tion, but the concept remains the same. Instead of making production
his activity, controlling its laws, man becomes a mere tool of produc
tion and develops according to its laws. In this sense, the capitalist is
as dependent as the worker. Both are shaped and determined, in their
character, their activity and their beliefs, by the inexorable laws of the
economic process. Thus the very epitome o f the laws o f historical develop
ment in the class society that forms the pre-history o f mankind— the
materialist interpretation o f history— is for M arx the ultimate and
fundamental expression o f human alienation: it recognises as law mans
subjugation by powers that should be and once were his own. The coming
of Communism, the supercession of alienation, means that man
ceases to be the product and slave of production, and becomes its
master.
There is no basis, then, for seeing Marx’s rejection of a ‘meta
physical’ human nature as radically affecting his use of alienation in the
economic and social contexts in which he had always thought its
value to lie. It is true— as the Institute of Marxism-Leninism of the
Central Committee of the C.P.S.U. puts it— that ‘by “ estrangement”
or “ alienation” , Marx means the forced labour of the labourer for the
capitalist, the appropriation by the capitalist of the product of a
worker’s labour and the separation of the labourer from the means of
production which, being in the capitalist’s possession, confront the
labourer as an alien, enslaving power’. (EPM, Introduction, p. 8.) But
this is not all he means. Dependence is not confined to capitalism: it
began with the division of labour and private property, capitalism is
only its most virulent and pervasive form. Economic dependence
necessarily produces human dependence in all other fields— in religion,
morality, law. The fact that Marx no longer uses the general term
‘alienation’ in Capital to sum up all these ramifications of economic
dependence, does not prevent him from taking every opportunity in
the same work to emphasise or display the pervasive dependence and
148
HISTORICAL M ATERIALISM
In the sweat of thy face shalt thou labour! was Jehovah’s curse, which he
gave to Adam. And it is thus as curse that A[dam] Smith regards labour.
‘Rest* appears as the adequate condition, as identical with ‘freedom* and
‘happiness*. A. Smith seems far from seeing that the individual, ‘in his
normal condition of health, strength, activity, capacity and skill,’ has also
the need for a normal portion of work, for an end to rest. It is true that the
amount of labour is itself determined externally, by the purpose sought and
the obstacles to the attainment of that purpose which must be overcome
through labour. But A. Smith has just as little conception of the fact that
this overcoming of obstacles is itself the activity of freedom—of the further
fact that the appearance of merely external natural necessity is stripped oft'
from external purposes and that these purposes are revealed as purposes
which the individual sets himself—of the fact, therefore, that the overcoming
of obstacles is self-realisation, objectification of the subject, therefore concrete
freedom, whose action is precisely work. He is right, however, in seeing
that in its historical forms as slavery, feudal services and wage labour,
labour always appears as something repulsive, as externalforced labour, and
that not working appears in relation to this as ‘freedom and happiness*. This
is doubly true: it is true of this contrasted labour, of the labour which has
not yet created the subjective and objective conditions . . . to make it travail
attractif self-realisation of the individual, which does not mean that it
becomes mere fun, mere amusement, as Fourier thinks with all the naivete of
a grisette. Truly free labour, e.g., composition, is damned serious at the
149
E T H I C S A N D TH E M A TU R E M A R X
same time, it is the most intensive exertion. The work of material production
can acquire this character only by (i) having its social character affirmed
(2) having a scientific character and being universal labour, the exertion o f a
man not as a tamed natural force, but as a subject which appears in the
process o f production not only in its natural form and development as part
o f nature, but as an activity regulating all natural forces.
(Grundrisse, 504-5.)
These notes were not meant for publication. But this is how Marx
reacts, this is how he saw dependence and freedom.
In the years between 1844 and the publication of the first volume of
Capital in 1867 Marx read and appropriated into his thinking an
enormous mass of economic material. As an economist he was not
shallow: he was not merely a Ricardian glibly seizing upon the labour
theory of value as a convenient tool for bringing out the alienation,
dehumanisation, exploitation inherent in capitalism. He was also, in
economics, a very learned and a very perceptive man. He became
engrossed in all the technical and professional details of his subject:
monetary theory, accumulation, constant and variable capital, prices,
absolute and relative surplus value, trade cycles, labour conditions and
factory organisation. What is amazing in view of this is not how much
new material came in as the Paris Manuscripts grew into the three
volumes of Capital, but how much of the old material and of the old
thought remained. Nowhere is Marx’s conception of the appropriation
of things external to man exemplified more clearly than in his own
intellectual work. He took materials from everywhere, but he sub
sumed them to his own purposes, moulded them into his system, strove
to weld everything into a single coherent structure whose fundamental
plan retained its original purpose and thrust.
Marx, we have seen, did come to reject any conception of an essential
and eternal human nature preceding and underlying the process of
production which has come to dominate man. The importance of this
rejection as a radical break in his development should not be over
rated. Already in the Paris Manuscripts, for all his alleged Young
Hegelianism, Marx had insisted that it is only in ‘working on the world
of objects’, in production, that man proves himself to be a generic or
social being. (M I, 3, 88, supra, II, 7). But there he still thought of the
generic being as somehow part of the ‘essence’ of man—proved rather
than created by production. Now, in his mature work, he combines
the belief in a universal, social, generic being of man with his historical
150
HISTORICAL MATERIALISM
o f labour develops and accumulation grows, the sharper are the forms that
this process o f differentiation assumes.
(M I, 5, 56, G I, 64; cf. K I, 368fF., C I, 385E )
What makes this division and separation possible is that with the
extended division of labour, production is no longer for use, but for
money, for exchange value.
The social division o f labour makes the labour [of the goods-possessor]
just as one-sided as it makes his needs many-sided. For this reason his
product can serve him only as an exchange value. It can acquire universal,
socially accepted forms o f equivalence through money, and the money is in
someone else’s pocket.
(K I, 1 1 1 ; C I, 119 .)
Since money does not disclose what has been transformed into it, everything
whether a commodity or not, is convertible into gold. Everything becomes
saleable and purchasable. Circulation is the great social retort into which
everything is thrown and out o f which everything is recovered as crystallised
money. Not even the bones o f the saints are able to withstand this alchemy;
and still less able to withstand it are more delicate res sacrosanctae extra
commercium hominum. Just as all the qualitative differences between com
modities are effaced in money, so money on its side, a radical leveller,
effaces all distinctions. But money is itself a commodity, an external object,
capable o f becoming the private property o f any individual. Thus social
power becomes a private power in the hands o f a private person.
(K I, 137-8 ; C I, 148-9.)
The division of labour, private property and money: these three (the
latter two made inevitable by the first) in turn make inevitable the
alienation, the dependence and separation that pervades the whole of
capitalist society. They create the division of town and country, of
worker and master, o f ‘individual* and ‘society’, of man and his labour.
They alienate man from other men, from his work, from his product,
from his society.
How, then, is this alienation to be overcome? By the inevitable logic
of the development of the productive process, which will end by
destroying private property and with it the division of labour and the
production for monetary gain. This is the point of Marx’s detailed
analysis of the capitalist economy: it shows, Marx believed, that
capitalism will be destroyed, and it shows this from ‘simple’, quite
unphilosophical, economic facts.
What Marx thought to be the basic outlines of the Communist
society of freedom are clear. The distinction between classes, resting
152
HISTORICAL MATERIALISM
Question 20— What will be the consequences of the final abolition of private
property?
Answer—Society, by taking out of the hands of the private capitalist
the utilisation of the various productive forces and means of intercourse,
as well as the exchange and distribution of goods, and controlling them
according to a plan based on the available means and needs of the whole
whole society, will above all abolish all those harmful effects which at
present are still connected with the operation of big industry. Crises will
disappear; increased production, which is over-production for the present
social order and a powerful cause of misery, will then not even prove
sufficient and will have to be increased far more. Instead of bringing misery
in its wake, over-production will reach beyond the immediate needs of
society to the satisfaction of everybody’s needs; it will create new needs and
at the same time create the means for their satisfaction. It will be the cause
and determining condition of new advances; it will bring about these ad
vances without throwing the social order into confusion, as has always been
the case in the past. Big industry, free of the pressure of private ownership,
will develop at an increased rate compared with which its present form will
1 ‘This is not possible without the community. Only in community with
others has each individual the means of cultivating his gifts in all directions; only
in community, therefore, is personal freedom possible . . . The illusory com
munity, in which individuals have up till now combined, always took on an
independent existence in relation to them, and was at the same time, since it was
the combination of one class against another, not only a completely illusory
community, but a new fetter as well. In the real community the individuals
obtain their freedom in and through their association* (G I, 74-5: M I, 5, 63-4).
153
E T H I C S A N D T H E M A TU R E M A R X
154
HISTORICAL MATERIALISM
also disappear. Wholly material causes already make the pursuit of agricul
ture and industry by the same men, instead of by two separate classes, a
necessary condition of the Communist order. The dissemination of the
peasant population on the land, compared with the crowding together of
the industrial population in the large towns, is a condition which corresponds
only to an as yet undeveloped stage of agriculture and industry, a barrier to
all further development which can already be felt strongly in the present time.
The universal association of all members of society for the common
planned exploitation of the forces of production, the increase of production
at a rate that will enable it to satisfy the needs of all, the end of a state of
affairs in which the needs of one are satisfied at the expense of others, the
total destruction of classes and their contradictions, the development of the
capacities of all members of society in all directions through the abolition
of the division of labour as known hitherto, through industrial education,
through the rotation of jobs, through the participation of all in the satisfac
tions created by all, through the fusion of town and country—these are the
main results of the abolition of private property.
(M I, 6, 516-19.)
Marx was an infinitely abler, subtler and theoretically more percep
tive man than Engels. Where Engels puts thing concretely, simply and
often naively, Marx tends to put them philosophically, subtly and
sometimes abstrusely. He would have liked to believe what Engels
believed— it is just possible that he did. Certainly, Marx, too, refers to
the disappearance of the distinction between mental and physical
labour (Critique o f the Gotha Programme, SW II, 23), to the shortening
of the working day (K III, 873-4; C III, 954-5), to the combination of
productive labour and education ‘as a method not only increasing
social production but as the only method of producing human beings
developed in all their aspects’ (K I, 509; C I, 530). But he is certainly
less emphatic about the social unity of Communism resting on the fact
that technology will be able to satisfy all of men’s needs. He speaks,
in the Critique o f the Gotha Programme (loc. cit.) of the ultimate period
when ‘the productive forces have also increased with the all-round
development of the individual and all the springs of co-operative
wealth flow more abundantly’ (my italics); ‘the realm of freedom’, he
insists, ‘begins in actuality only when labour which is determined by
need and external utility ceases’ (K III, 873; C III, 954); but he does
not see this as flowing from the satisfaction of all needs. Marx was
simply not the utilitarian that Engels was; he was not concerned with
how much a man had, but with the way in which he acquired what he
had, with the conditions under which he worked. The essential thing
155
E T H I C S A N D T HE M A T U R E M A R X
for Marx that makes production truly social is the abolition of money
as a circulating exchange value (K III, 932; C III), the fact that the
individual is no longer an abstract buyer and seller of commodities, but
a participant in the social business of production and of consumption.
In truly communal production
its communal nature is taken as the foundation o f production. The labour
o f the individual is taken from the start as social labour. Therefore whatever
the specific material form o f the product which he creates or helps to create
may be, that which he has bought with his labour is not a special specific
product, but a specific share o f the communal production. For this reason
he has no special product that he has to exchange. His product is not an
exchange value. The product does not have to be translated into a specific
character form in order to acquire a universal character for the individual.
Instead o f a division of labour, necessarily ending in the exchange o f exchange
value, we would have an organisation o f labour, which results in the par
ticipation o f the individual in communal consumption.
(Grundrisse9 88-9.)
What does this passage mean? It means, I think, that Marx was both
far less and far more naive than Engels about production under Com
munism. He foresaw tremendous improvements in working conditions,
a considerable decrease in the amount of labour needed from each man
as a result of technological advance and the abolition of any need for
labour-discipline of the capitalist type (K III, 103; C III, 100). In its
stead, there would be social determination, by the community, of the
working day and of the distribution of labour (K III, 213, 907; C III,
221, 992) and, naturally, increased but more centralised book-keeping.
That resources would still need to be husbanded, and allocated among
alternative uses, Marx understands quite well;1 that people would have
to do extra work on behalf of those in the community who cannot work
he himself mentions (K III, 932; C III, 1021-2). He is simply not con
cerned to portray Communism as the society of plenty; he is concerned
to portray it as a society of human dignity: a society in which labour
1 ‘If we think of society as not being capitalist, but Communist, then money-
capital disappears entirely and with it, therefore, the disguises that it carries into
transactions. The matter simply becomes that society must calculate beforehand
how much labour, how many instruments of production and provisions can be
expended, without upset, on branches of activity which, like the building of
railways, for instance, will produce neither instruments of production nor food
nor any useful effects for a length of time, a year or more, but which will draw
away labour, tools and provisions from the total production for the year/ (K II,
314; C II, 361-2.)
156
HISTORICAL MATERIALISM
acquires dignity and becomes free because it is carried out by full and
conscious participants in a community given over to co-operation and
common aims. The model of a co-operative, productive community
of artists or scientists (which Engels never understood) is again appo
site: its members may hunger, undertake enormous exertions, spend
hours on tasks not interesting in themselves— but they know what
they are doing and why they want to do it. In that lies their freedom
and their dignity. It is for these reasons, because Marx himself has the
productive morality, that he is more concerned with time than he is
with plenty:
Assuming communal production, the determination o f time remains impor
tant. The less time society needs to produce wheat, cattle, etc., the more
time it has for other production, whether material or intellectual. As in the
case o f the single individual, the universality o f its development, o f its
satisfaction and its activity, depends on saving time. Economy of time is
what all economics finally comes down to. Society must thus divide its
time usefully in order to arrive at a measure of production suitable to its
total needs; just as the individual must divide his time properly to gain
knowledge in suitable proportion or to satisfy the different demands on his
activity. (Grundrisse, 89.)
control o f production had been presupposed. Why? Marx could not quite
say this in terms of his historical materialism, but obviously his
answer is: because the individual’s attitudes to authority will be quite
different. The force of the authority will not flow from an external
structure imposed upon him, but from the nature of the activities in
which he is engaging freely and consciously. Those who have authority
will be fellow-producers, seeking the same productivity as he seeks:
their ‘authority* will rest on competence and experience he himself
recognises and admires.
In concrete human terms, this situation is again not entirely utopian.
Such voluntary acceptance of guidance and of the rules necessary for
the continuation of an activity can be found in institutions and teams
seized with the productive spirit. How such guidance and such rules
appear to any individual in the institution will, in fact, depend upon
his ‘attitude*, i.e., on the extent to which he himself is seized by the
productive spirit. This is not to say that conflicts of views or competing
interests will not break out in an organisation given over to production;
but in so far as the productive spirit is strong within the organisation
such conflicts will be subordinated to the needs and rules of the
productive activity itself.
What is utopian in Marx’s vision is his constant reliance on the
productive spirit, on the operation of goods in individuals, without
paying any attention to their character, to the conditions in which
they arise in any given individual and spread through a society, and
to the character of the forces opposing them. It is here that the ‘human
essence’ is still assumed in Marx’s mature work. Co-operation and
production are taken as the ‘normal’ way of working of the individual
freed from the pressures of external determination; a view for which
Marx provides no evidence and could provide no evidence. Above all,
he fails to consider the view—which his own concrete examples of
free activity suggest— that productive organisation can only result
from an already existing productive spirit: not merely from the inter
dependence created by capitalism, but from what Sorel calls ‘the heroic
values’ of enterprise, immersion in productive activity and indifference
to reward.
Here is the central weakness of Marx’s vision. Unlike Engels, Marx
was not a utilitarian; he was not trying to build a society of the future
on the enlightened self-interest of the individual, on the promise of
peace and plenty. The freedom and dignity he proclaimed as the goal
of history were not entirely a utopian vision: such freedom and such
159
ETHICS AND THE MATURE M ARX
dignity have been displayed by men and women in their life and work.
But only those who have such dignity and such freedom can bring it
about. Marx would have liked to believe that the industrial proletariat
was evolving such freedom, such enterprise, even under capitalism.
But he was not prepared to stake much on the conception. History
seemed a more powerful ally. The proletariat remained for him funda
mentally a vehicle of history: not a class displaying enterprise, produc
tion and co-operation, but a class denied enterprise, production and
co-operation, not a class that has freed itself from the shackles of
property, but a class denied property, a class whose whole character
consisted of nothing more than its exclusion from property, than its
suffering. In not seeing the proletariat as the bearers of enterprise, as
the class of free men, Marx may have been right; but if he was right
his vision was doomed. In fact, the proletariat proved more thoroughly
the child of capitalism than Marx had ever dreamt possible: the move
ment he founded helped to destroy the vision he worked for.
160
P A R T FIV E
Trotsky, in his Their Morals and Ours, took the same line. A gun in
itself is neither good nor evil; it becomes good in the hands of a
proletarian fighting for the classless society and evil in the hands of a
capitalist fighting for oppression and exploitation. At the same time,
within the party and within the Soviet Union the principle could
always be used to justify those who actually gained and kept power.1
History was on their side. It is this which plants the first seeds of doubt
in the mind of the anti-Stalinist Rubashov sitting in his prison cell in
Arthur Koestler’s Darkness at Noon; within Marxism he can find no
answer.
1 Quite typical is this attempt by Mehring’s translator, Edward Fitzgerald, to
defend Marx (in an addendum) against Mehring’s moral strictures over the
Bakunin episode: ‘Any discussion of “ the moral qualities” of the methods used
in the fractional struggles between Marx and Bakunin and their followers can be
of only very subordinate interest to day. Marx and Engels were not “ innocent
lambs” , but Bakunin and his friends were also not and they waged the fractional
struggle by no means in strict accordance with the categorical imperative. In
any case, all this is of very subsidiary importance. In the struggle between
Bakunin and his followers on the one hand and Marx and Engels on the other,
fundamental principles and history were on the side of Marx and Marxism and
therefore, we may assume, “ moral” justification also/ (Mehring: Karl Marx,
p. 556.)
167
1 6. Law and Morality in
Soviet Society
of these enemies had been accomplished. Thus, even the criminal law
was seen as a pure class measure dictated by the economic interests of
the proletariat. The Leading Principles o f Criminal Law, enacted by
the People’s Commissariat of Justice in 1919, expresses this attitude
bluntly:
the proletariat. The famous Article i of the Civil Code states this over
riding principle of the NEP conception of law: ‘Civil rights shall be
protected by law except in instances when they are exercised in contra
diction with their social-economic purpose/1 There is no suggestion
that these social-economic purposes themselves lay the foundation for a
positive system of distinctively socialist law.
This became absolutely clear in 1928, when the NEP compromise
was abandoned and replaced by the two Five-Year Plans, designed to
turn Soviet Russia, independently of world revolution, into a socialist
society as quickly as possible.
Now, for the first time, positive content was given to the Marxist idea o f
the disappearance o f State and Law under socialism. It was thought that
Law, an instrument o f the class-dominated State, would be replaced by
Plan, the manifestation o f the will o f a class-less society. Through the Plan
all the characteristics o f the original Marxist dream would be realised.
Planning would eliminate exploitation; money would be transformed into
a mere unit o f account; private property and private right generally would be
swallowed up in collectivism; the family would disappear as a legal entity,
with husbands and wives bound only by ties o f affection and children owing
their allegiance and their upbringing to the whole society; crime would be
exceptional and would be treated as mental illness; the coercive machinery
o f the State would become superfluous. The Plan would give unity and
harmony to all relations. The Plan itself would differ from Law, since it
would be an instrument neither o f compulsion nor o f formality but simply
an expression o f rational foresight on the part o f the planners, with the whole
people participating and assenting spontaneously. Society would be regu
lated, administered— much as traffic at an intersection is regulated by traffic
lights and by rules o f the road; but in a society without class conflict there
would be few collisions and to deal with them it would be unnecessary to
have a system o f ‘justice*. Social-economic expediency would be the ultimate
criterion; disputes would be resolved on the spot.2
work out a coherent Marxist account of law. This, they knew, no one
had yet done properly. They wanted to show, as they thought Marx
showed, and as Soviet leaders had so far agreed (though Lenin had a
genius for ambiguity), that socialist law was a contradiction in terms.
Law, they held with Marx, was a reflection of economic antagonisms;
with the eradication of these antagonisms it would necessarily dis
appear. A Marxist theory of law, says Pashukanis, cannot claim to
seek the general concept of a proletarian law. ‘The dying out of the
categories of bourgeois law w ill. . . signify the dying out of law in
general: that is to say, the gradual disappearance of the juridic element
in human relations.’ 1 Pashukanis saw, however, that this view needed
far more support in the field of law than Marx, Engels and Lenin had
ever given it. He saw, above all, that it was necessary to show— as we
have seen Marx never showed— that bourgeois law is not merely in
fluenced and distorted by economic interests, but that its basic structure,
concepts and principles are the reflections of economic categories of
bourgeois society that make no sense without it. Pashukanis, in fact,
goes further and insists that law itself is essentially bourgeois, that it
rests on conceptions necessarily linked with commodity exchange, and
that law can therefore only attain its consummation in bourgeois
society. All law, Pashukanis argues, is private law. There can be no
true public law establishing the relationship between the State and
private individuals because the State is by its very nature above and
outside the law. Law is built on the contractual relationships required
in the process of exchanging commodities on a free market— its
corner-stone is the abstract individual of capitalist economic life, ‘the
right- and duty-bearing unit.’2 This contractual conception dominates
every sphere of law— tort, family and marriage law, labour law,
constitutional law (based on a ‘social contract’) and even criminal law,
in which Pashukanis sees the ius talionis giving way, after an inter
mediate stage of money composition, to the commercial idea that a
crime must be paid for ex post facto. With the overcoming of the
bourgeois abstraction of the individual, the abolition of commercial
relations and the establishment of the social interest and the social man,
the whole structure of law necessarily loses meaning and collapses.
1 Sochineniia ( Works), vol. IV, p. 740. Marx said later that Chemyshevskii’s
writings ‘brought true honour* to Russia (ME Soch., XIII, i, 354).
2 ‘Changing attitudes Toward the Individual*, in C. E. Black (ed): The Trans
formation o f Russian Society, pp. 606-25, at pp. 618-23 . 1 have relied on a number
of Dr. Kline*s interesting citations from works not easy to obtain in the West.
178
L A W A N D M O R A L I T Y IN S O V I E T S O C I E T Y
writes, gives only ‘a faint hint of that fusion of all human souls which
will be the inevitable result of the Communist order/1 Similarly, when
Bogdanov insists2 that Goethe did not produce Faust or Darwin the
theory of evolution, but that both men put the finishing touches to a
collective effort, there is more truth in this than Kline, say, is willing
to stress. Bogdanov has perceived, as Bazarov also perceived, some
thing of the mutually supporting character of artistic creation, love
and enquiry, the way in which they can ‘transcend’ the individual and
appropriate freely materials furnished by others. Recognising this how
ever, does not require us to minimise the role that any particular
person— Goethe or Darwin— might play in shaping the finished pro
duct of theory, whereas Bogdanov and Bazarov do patently wish to
minimise this role. The new society, Bazarov writes, will favour not
‘artists of disorderly individual searching, but artists in schools which
move by plan toward their goal.’ 3 Here we have more than the correct
recognition that free activities are mutually co-operative activities.
Here we have the reimposition of servility, the elevation of goals and
plans over the spontaneous workings of the free and creative life.
When Bogdanov and Bazarov turn to attack not Kant’s abstract will
but his elevation of man as an end, and themselves substitute other
ends, the servile character of their doctrine is finally confirmed. ‘The
free man not only regards his neighbour as a means; he demands that
his neighbour should see in him only a means . . . for the neighbour’s
own ends.’ 4 ‘The recognition of the ‘individual person’ as an absolute
principle has always been, and will always be, alien to the proletariat.’ 5
By 1920, the point of all this had become painfully evident. Leon
Trotsky, in his Terrorism i kommuniim (p. 61), repudiates scornfully
the ‘Kantian-clerical, vegetarian-Quaker chatter about the “ sanctity of
human life” .’ The doctrine that individuals are ends in themselves is a
metaphysical, bourgeois doctrine; the proletarian and the revolutionary
know that where necessary (for the Revolution) the individual is and
should be treated only as a means. The prominent party theorist
1 Na dva fronta (Toward Two Fronts), St. Petersburg, 1910, p. 140; Kline,
P*623*
2 Padenie velikogo fetishi^ma (The Fall o f the Great Fetishism), Moscow,
1910, p. 46; Kline, p. 623.
3 Op. cit., p. 164; Kline, p. 623.
4 Bazarov: ‘Avtoritarnaia metafifika i avtonomnaia lichnost* (‘Authoritarian
Metaphysics and the Autonomous Personality*), in Ocherki realisticheskogo
mirovo^reniia, p. 271; Kline, p. 623.
6 Bazarov: Na dva fronta, p. 141; ibid.
180
LAW AND MO R AL IT Y IN SOVI ET SOCIETY
A. B. Zalkind put the position bluntly five years later: ‘For the prole
tariat, human life does not have a metaphysical, self-sufficient value.
The proletariat recognises only the interests of the . . . revolution/1
and creative role to Soviet morality would have been to depart even
more dangerously from the Marxian slogan that ‘social being deter
mines social consciousness’ and that morality only reflects the material
life of man. Then, with Stalin’s Marxism and Questions o f Linguistics
(1950), the supreme authority himself opened the way for treating the
superstructure, including morality, as a vital and active force on the
path to Communism. Official encouragement was given to the creation
and propagation of the theory and norms of Communist morality. In
1951, a conference of Soviet and Czech philosophers agreed that the
teaching of Marxist ethics was inadequate and confused, that it was not
set out in logical terms and that it neglected moral theory before
Hobbes: a specialist course, such as M. I. Lifanov had outlined in
Voprosy Filosofii (no. 2, 1951), was badly needed. In the same year,
Sharia published his Concerning Some Questions o f Morality, in which
the active, creative role of consciousness was stressed even more
strongly than Stalin had stressed it:
Marxism-Leninism leaches that not only the building o f the new Communist
economy, but also the formation o f the new Communist consciousness o f
man is not self-propelled, not a process dictated by fate, but follows from
the many-sided, completely devoted educational work o f the Bolshevik
Party and the Soviet administration.
(Introduction, p. 3.)
Sharia, in his emphasis on conscious decision and limited free will, had
perhaps gone somewhat further than Soviet authorities were willing
to countenance; he has written nothing on ethics since. But the empha
sis on moral theory and propaganda continued. Shishkin, now the
doyen of Soviet moral philosophers, published his Foundations o f
Communist Morality in 1955 and the first reasonably serious work on
the history of ethical theory for many years, From the History o f
Ethical Doctrines, in 1959. At the same time, a conference of moral
philosophers and party, industrial, educational and Komsomol leaders
met in Leningrad under the auspices of the Soviet Academy of Sciences
and of the Ministry of Higher and Specialised Secondary Education to
discuss the role of ethics in Soviet life. It ended by formulating a draft
syllabus for ethical teaching in higher educational institutions and
publishing the papers presented before it.1 All of them stressed the
profoundly ethical nature of Communism and the need for the most
intensive moral education to overcome the vestiges of capitalism and
1 Voprosy marksistko-leninskoi etiki (<Questions o f Marxist-Leninist Ethics),
Moscow, i960.
182
L A W A N D M O R A L I T Y IN S O V I E T S O C I E T Y
reflect the economic conditions that give them birth, has finally led to
the extension of the ‘Popular Front’ ideology to the field of moral
philosophy. Soviet philosophers in recent years not only insist—
following Engels in Chapter IX of Anti-Diihring—that there has been
continuous progress in morality, but now emphasise that there are
certain basic moral conceptions applicable in all ages and that the ‘pro
gressive’ thinkers of all times have gone beyond the conditions of their
time to the morality of the future. Lenin, in The State and Revolution
(HM 759), speaks of the ‘elementary rules of social life’ which have
been taught in school books for generations and which Communists
will make into a social habit; Krushchev, as we have just seen, echoed
the phrase in his address to the XXIst Congress, where he called for the
‘voluntary observance of the fundamental rules of human communal
life’. To a Soviet philosopher, these are eminent and ‘safe’ authorities,
even if Engels (and Marx) were quite unequivocal in insisting that any
moral principles that had appeared ‘eternal’ did so only because they
expressed those forms of dependence common to all past societies. At
the same time, a new generation of specialists in the Soviet Union
tends naturally to become increasingly aware of the specific problems
and characters of a specialist’s field and to demand for it a certain
intellectual independence. Even so, only one Soviet philosopher— as
far as I know—has drawn the full logical implications of the Lenin-
Khruschev position. V. P. Tugarinov, of Leningrad University, has
been arguing since 1958 that in the various sciences we will find a part
determined by the categories of historical materialism, but also a part
based on the special categories of the science concerned— categories
which are applicable at all stages of historical development. Thus in
ethics, he argues in his 0 tsennostiakh {hi{ni i kultury (Concerning The
Values o f Life and Culture), there are ‘moments’ expressing what is
common to all humanity and ‘moments’ expressing class interest.
Tugarinov, of course, does not simply divide ethics into eternal
truths and disguised class interest; he portrays the relationship as an
intricate one, insists that abstract judgments expressing universal
ethical notions become subservient to class interest in the manner of
their application to concrete situations, and generally holds that
‘moments’ of a universal kind are stronger in aesthetics than ethics.
(Op. cit., pp. 2 3-4 .)
Even Tugarinov, however, promising as his position might appear,
is prevented from making any genuine contribution to ethical theory
by his uncritical acceptance of moral rules as normative rules and of
184
L A W A N D M O R A L I T Y IN S O V I E T S O C I E T Y
4. Socialist humanism:
(a) Socialist humanism—the highest type of humanism
(b) Respect for the worth of man and care of man
(c) Hatred for enemies and vigilance—an inescapable feature of socialist
humanism
5. The moral foundations of friendship, marriage and family:
(a) Society and personal life
(b) Friendship
(c) Marriage and family
6. The moral qualities and character traits of the fighter for Communism
187
7KLVSDJHLQWHQWLRQDOO\OHIWEODQN
Conclusions
7KLVSDJHLQWHQWLRQDOO\OHIWEODQN
Ethics and the
Foundations o f Marxism
of the human spirit, we have seen, was the foundation and driving
force of his intellectual and political development. The structure that
followed was high and broad. As it grew it disturbed the foundations,
but the basic thrust and design remained. The goal was the same. Man
would pass from the realm of conflict and dependence into the realm of
co-operation and freedom.
The concern with minimising conflict and maximising co-operation
in the abstract is no stranger to moral and political theory, and never
has been. It has not normally stemmed from the concern with freedom,
however. Liberty, as Croce has said, lives ‘a perilous and fighting life’;
the concern with minimising conflict of any kind, with making the
world safe for harmony, is more typical of the desires for security and
sufficiency, of the motives concerned to establish domination and seek
the shelter of submission. It is such movements, such concerns to
escape from the conflicts and dangers of history, that moral and political
philosophers have all too often been willing to serve. One of Marx’s
important contributions to ethics is his bringing out of the despotic
conceptions, and the resultant incoherence, underlying their work.
There is no harmony of discord with harmony, no way of binding man
into freedom. There can be no coherent principles of moral or political
obligation. The source of moral obligation, the legal and political
sovereign, cannot be exalted above the conflicts and divisions of his
tory. As long as movements and interests conflict, any attempt to bind
this conflict cannot be anything more than an attempted domination of
some of these movements and interests over the rest. If the community
of interest proclaimed by the sovereign were real, there would be no
191
CONCLUSIONS
they formulate social codes and political principles: codes and prin
ciples that nevertheless vary and conflict as movements vary and
conflict, which seek working arrangements and limits to conflict but
in no way presuppose that there is an ultimate working arrangement
or a final limit.
The main point is that any specific interest in adjustment as such is
not higher, but lower than specific interests. There are no ‘rational’
principles on which it can rest or base its supremacy. It does not
precede specific interests, but follows them. It is in general not creative
but parasitic. It is not above society, but part of it: it, too, is historical,
socially determined and partial. Its notion that it controls society
instead of being controlled by it is an illusion.
The illusion that policies, or moral and legal principles, are control
ling factors in society is one to which the moral and political theorist is
especially prone. The chief merit of Marx’s economic or materialist
interpretation of history, with all its confusions and difficulties, lies in
its exposure of this illusion. Causally, policies will be factors in any
given social situation and may affect the changes that take place in that
situation. But all the evidence shows that they are not controlling
factors in history: they do not precede and determine all historical
development. Above all, they are not the policies of ‘reason’ or ‘mor
ality’ or ‘society’; they are the policies of specific, existing movements,
the characters and social situation of which precede and determine
their aims. Normative ethical and political theory, as Marx realised, has
depended largely on obscuring this point: on treating ends, policies
and principles as ends, policies and principles in themselves. Once we
show that this is not so, that they are ends, policies and principles o f
specific and historical subjects, conflicting among themselves, the
normative pretensions of much moral and political theory are fatally
undermined. The vagueness and incoherence that break out in theories
of moral and political obligation stand revealed as inescapable results
of the illusion on which normative theories rest and not as the mere
consequences of an individual theorist’s incompetence. To this con
clusion Marx has shown us the way.
The belief that evil and the conflict of evils could be eradicated also
required a reductionist doctrine— a single course from which all evils
and all conflict sprang. That source, for the mature Marx, was private
property.1 In this, and in his allied definition of classes in terms of their
relation to property, he proved himself thoroughly the intellectual
child of the capitalism he criticised so unsparingly.
The most obvious failure of Marxism has lain in the incorrectness
of Marx’s predictions. In each case, this incorrectness has stemmed
from his over-estimation of the importance of private property. He
failed to see the gains which the working-class might make under
capitalism because he saw the worker’s divorce from property as a
divorce from all enterprise, control or political power. He failed to
1 Marx did see private property as following inescapably from the division of
labour. But he cannot coherently distinguish the division of labour from the
organisation of labour which will emerge under Communism except in terms of
the ownership of tools which the former allegedly implies. Hence I take
private property as fundamental in Marx’s analysis.
196
E T HI CS A N D THE F O U N D A T I O N S OF M A R XI S M
199
Bibliography of Works Cited
B. W O R K S R E L A T E D T O M A R X A N D M A R X IS M
Acton, H. B.: The Illusion o f the Epoch; Cohen Sc West, London, 1955.
Adams, H. P.: Karl Marx in His Earlier Writings; Allen Sc Unwin, London,
1940.
Barth, Hans: Wahrheit und Ideologies Manesse Verlag, Zurich, 1945.
Berman, Harold J.: Justice in Russia; Harvard U.P., 1950.
Black, C. E. (ed.): The Transformation o f Russian Society; Harvard U.P.,
i960.
Bums, Emile: (ed.): A Handbook o f Marxism; International Publishers,
New York, 1935.
Carr, E. H.: Karl M arx: A Study in Fanaticism; J. M. Dent Sc Sons, London,
I934*
Eastman, Max: Marx, Marxism and the Science o f Revolution; Allen Sc
Unwin, London, 1926.
Hazard, John et aL: Soviet Legal Philosophy; Harvard U.P., 1951.
Hilferding, Rudolf: Das Finamjapital; I. Brand, Wien, 1910.
Hook, Sidney: Towards the Understanding o f Karl Marx; Victor Gollancz,
London, 1933.
Kautsky, Karl: Ethics and the Materialist Conception o f History; Charles H.
Kerr Sc Co., Chicago, 1918.
Kelsen, Hans: The Communist Theory o f Law; Stevens Sc Sons, London,
I955‘
Lenin, V. I.: Sochineniia (4th Edition); Gospolitizdat, Moscow, 1948.
Lichtheim, George: Marxism: An Historical and Critical Study; Routledge
Sc Kegan Paul, London, 1961.
Lukacs, Georg: Geschichte und Klassenbewusstsein; Malik-Verlag Berlin,
I923‘
Marcuse, Herbert: Reason and Revolution: Hegel and the Rise o f Social
Theory; Routledge Sc Kegan Paul, London, 1955.
Mehring, Franz: Karl Marx: The Story o f His life, trans. Edward Fitzgerald;
Allen Sc Unwin, London, 1948.
Nicolaievsky, Boris and Manchen-Helfen, Otto: Karl Marx, Man and
Fighter, trans. Gwenda David and Eric Mosbacher, Methuen Sc Co.,
London, undated.
Popitz, Heinrich: Der entfremdete Mensch. Zeitkritik und Geschichtsphiloso-
phic desjungen Marx; Basle, 1953.
Popper, Karl: The Open Society and Its Enemies, vols. I and II; Routledge
Sc Kegan Paul, London, 1957.
Rosenberg, Arthur: A History o f Bolshevism from Marx to the First Five
Years Plan, trans. Ian F. D. Morrow; Oxford U.P., 1934.
Rubel, Maximilien: Pages Choisies pour une Ethique Socialiste; Librairie
Marcel Riviere et Cie, Paris, 1948.
201
B I B L I O G R A P H Y OF W O R K S C I T E D
C. OTHER WORKS
Chemyshevskii, N. G.: Sochineniia; Gos. Izdat. Khudozhestvennoi Litera-
tury, Moscow, I948f.
Feuerbach, Ludwig: The Essence of Christianity, trans. Marian Evans;
London, 1854.
Hare, R. M.: The Language of Morals; Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1952.
Hegel, G. F. W.: The Phenomenology of Mind, trans. J. J. B. Baillie; Swan
Sonnenschein, London, 1910.
Hegel, G. F. W.: The Philosophy of Right, trans. T. M. Knox; Clarendon
Press, Oxford, 1953.
Passmore, J. A.: Ralph Cudworth; Cambridge U.P., 1951.
Spinoza, B.: The Ethics, trans. R. H. M. Elwes; Tudor Publishing Co.,
New York, 1941.
Stevenson, C. L.: Ethics and Language\ Yale U.P., 1944.
Anderson, John: ‘Determinism and Ethics’, A .J.P .P ., vol. VI (1927).
Anderson, John: ‘Realism versus Relativism in Ethics’, A .J.P .P ., vol. XI
(i933)-
Anderson, John: ‘The Problem of Causality*, A .J.P .P ., vol. XVI (1938).
Anderson, John: ‘Art and Morality’, A .J.P .P ., vol. XIX (1941).
Anderson, John: ‘The Meaning of Good’, A .J.P .P ., vol. XX (1942).
Anderson, John: ‘Ethics and Advocacy’, A .J.P .P ., vol. XXII (1944).
Simpson, C. A.: ‘Old Testament Historiography’, Hibbert Journal, vol.
LVI (1958).
Urmson, J. O.: ‘On Grading*, in Logic and Language (Second Series), ed.
by A. G. N. Flew, Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1953.
203
Index
208