The Spirit of The Laws: What's Inside
The Spirit of The Laws: What's Inside
The Spirit of The Laws: What's Inside
Laws
Study Guide by Course Hero
a Main Ideas
j Book Basics
AUTHOR
Montesquieu
Three Systems of Government
YEAR PUBLISHED Montesquieu's (1689–1755) main project in The Spirit of the
1748 Laws is to weigh the benefits and drawbacks, along with the
special risks and opportunities, inherent in the world's many
GENRE systems of government. To accomplish this, he begins by
History, Philosophy dividing governments into three major categories: republic,
monarchy, and despotism. He does not pretend that these
AT A GLANCE
three models adequately describe every possible system of
Penned during the peak of the French Enlightenment (1700s, a
government; instead, he uses them as points of reference.
period where reason governed change in the areas of religion
Moreover, Montesquieu is aware of—and interested in—the
and politics), The Spirit of the Laws is one of the foundational
ways in which a nation transitions from one system to another.
works of modern Western political thought. Montesquieu
systematically distinguishes among different types of The term republic, as Montesquieu uses it, means any system
government and describes the laws appropriate to each. He in which the people—or a significant fraction of the
The Spirit of the Laws Study Guide Main Ideas 2
people—ultimately hold political power. Republics are further French and English was helped greatly by Montesquieu's use
divided into democracies, where the common people of it throughout The Spirit of the Laws.
collectively enjoy sovereignty, and aristocracies, where a select
few share power. Although he notes an example of direct
democracy in ancient Athens, he is more interested in Separation of Powers
representative democracies (the usual modern meaning of
democracy) in which elected officials represent their The Spirit of the Laws, though wide-ranging in the times and
constituents. The inclusion of aristocracies as a type of places it surveys, is neither neutral nor unbiased. Rather,
republic is a little unusual by present-day standards, since the Montesquieu uses his book's extensive tour of legal history to
word "aristocracy" now tends to be associated with hereditary support some specific ideas about how governments should
nobility common in a monarchy. Montesquieu, is less interested be run to benefit both their leaders and their citizens. One key
in whether a country has a king than in who really holds the principle is the separation of powers: the idea that different
reins of power. A nation with a figurehead monarch and a governmental responsibilities should be placed in the hands of
politically dominant nobility would be, by his reckoning, a type different people. Governments with an effective separation of
of republic. powers, he suggests, are resilient; governments that give too
free a rein to a single individual or group will quickly devolve
In both of the remaining systems, an individual serves as the
into tyranny.
head of government. In a monarchy this individual is subject to
the laws of the land. Montesquieu's prime example of such a At various points in the text Montesquieu gives slightly
system is England—and not his native France, as might be different enumerations of these powers and draws slightly
expected. In England, as in France, the monarch had once held different lines between them. Typically, however, he speaks of
near-absolute power, but after the English Civil War (1642–51, three powers: the judiciary, the executive, and the legislative.
fought between supporters of and opposition to the These correspond to the three branches of government in the
monarchy), Parliament was able to impose substantial United States (founded some three decades after The Spirit of
limitations on the monarch's power. Thus, in a sense, the the Laws was published) and in other modern representative
England of Montesquieu's day is more of a "hybrid" democracies. The resemblance is hardly a coincidence: the
government with both a legislative body (Parliament) and a framers of many modern democratic constitutions were
monarch. Again, the boundaries are not intended to be inspired, directly or indirectly, by Montesquieu.
absolute.
Montesquieu has no trouble coming up with instances in which
Despotic governments, in Montesquieu's view, are different poorly conceived separation of powers led to the ruin of a
from monarchies, in that the ruler is not subject to laws. Rather, government. "When legislative power is united with executive
his word is the law, and when he changes his mind about an power," he flatly declares in Book 11, "there is no liberty."
issue, the law changes too. As his main examples, Montesquieu Likewise, he says, several ancient Greek city-states created
names Japan, China at various points in its history, and the tyrants by giving their rulers both executive and judiciary
Ottoman Empire. (He typically refers to the latter simply as power while allocating only legislative power to the people.
"Turkey.") Montesquieu also points to some despotic qualities When there is no attempt to separate governmental powers,
in the rule of Louis XIV of France (1638–1715), the famous "Sun the situation is even worse: in a sense Montesquieu's quarrel
King" who embodied the principle of absolute monarchy. What with despotism—above and beyond mere moral disgust—is its
makes Louis XIV a despot, not a monarch in Montesquieu's lack of such separation of powers. The despot is, at the end of
sense, is his extreme consolidation of power and his lack of the day, the paramount maker, enforcer, and interpreter of the
subjection to his own laws. realm's laws. There can be no effective system of "checks and
balances" in such a regime.
The word despot comes from an ancient Greek term meaning,
literally, "an absolute ruler." By Montesquieu's time, however,
the word had acquired a strong negative connotation—it meant
not just an absolute ruler, but one who ruled in a cruel and
arbitrary manner. The popularization of the word in both
not mean they were carried out in the same way or served the
History Repeats Itself same administrative function.
d In Context
calls little explicit attention, is that history repeats itself. In
other words Montesquieu embraces the Enlightenment-era
ideal of learning as much as one can from history, not just as a
source of personal edification, but in order to avoid repeating
its mistakes. This belief guides Montesquieu in his selection of Law and Government in
examples to illustrate his points: often, Montesquieu will
juxtapose events from two regimes separated by hundreds or Ancient Rome
even thousands of years. He believes that where human
institutions are similar, history will follow the same broad The Spirit of the Laws is rich in allusions to the history of
pattern. various countries, both ancient and modern. No part of the
world gives Montesquieu more material for his ideas than
Much of The Spirit of the Laws is devoted to identifying the
Rome, which at different times was a monarchy, a republic, and
factors which drive or predict such repetition. In Part 4, Book
an empire.
22, for instance, Montesquieu asks why the Romans' attempts
to prevent usury (act of loaning money at a high rate of According to myth, Rome was founded as a kingdom by
interest) backfired. This question fascinates him because brothers Romulus and Remus in the mid-8th century BCE.
modern rulers, in their own quest to set financial policy, have Supposedly, Romulus killed his twin brother Remus and
sometimes placed similar restrictions on excessive interest. To became the first king of the city-state they had founded
understand why the Roman public ultimately rejected such together. Seven kings are said to have ruled, with the reign of
constraints is to understand the forces that will doom a similar the last, Tarquin, ending in 509 BCE. The Kingdom of Rome, to
program in the present. A key assumption here is that human the extent that descriptions of this state are history rather than
nature has changed little in the 2,000 years since the Roman legend, is generally described by modern historians as an
Republic. Then as now, people are fond of a quick fix, and absolute or near-absolute monarchy. Montesquieu, if he shared
politicians are happy to promise one to them. Then as now, this view, would have called it a despotic state. In The Spirit of
borrowers and lenders will find a way to do business, no matter the Laws, however, Montesquieu gives great emphasis to the
what the law says. early Roman Senate—which was, in fact, not nearly as powerful
as its successor in the republican and imperial eras. Because
The quest for historical parallels is one reason for
he treats the senate and its laws as a vital part of Rome's regal
Montesquieu's extensive reliance on ancient Rome as a source
era, he is inclined to see the Kingdom of Rome as a true
of examples. It also helps to explain his meticulous picking-
monarchy.
over of Roman, Frankish, and French legal customs at the very
end of The Spirit of the Law. However, Montesquieu does not The next major phase of Roman history was the republic,
believe—in fact, mocks other historians for believing—that the inaugurated in 509 BCE. Many of the laws to which
same broad system of government translates to the same Montesquieu refers are of republican vintage, but the most
specific legal practices. In the next-to-last book of his treatise, prominent is the Law of the Twelve Tables (451–450 BCE),
Montesquieu warns: "To carry back to distant centuries the established early in the republic's history. This document,
ideas of the century in which one lives is of all sources of error named for the 12 bronze tablets on which the laws were
the most fertile." In other words history can furnish an attentive engraved, was the first written legal code in Roman history.
reader with general patterns and with warning signs about the The exact nature of republican Roman government shifted
perennial threats faced by a regime—whether republican, somewhat over the centuries, but a pair of elected consuls
monarchical, or despotic. Assuming equivalence on a finer ruled except during military emergencies, when a dictator was
scale, however, is very foolish, at least to Montesquieu's way of chosen. The consuls were chosen from among the patricians,
thinking. The ancient Roman census and the medieval Frankish or upper class, whose ranks also included the senators—now
"census," for instance, may have the same name, but that does more influential than they ever were in the regal era. The
commoners, called plebeians, were effectively barred from Montesquieu is concerned with a later period, running roughly
government except through a small number of representatives, from the time of Louis IX (1214–70) to his own era. Louis was
called tribunes. In Montesquieu's scheme of government one of the Capetians, the dynasty that succeeded the
classifications the Roman Republic would be labeled an Carolingians in 987. Though he had many claims to fame—he
aristocracy. was canonized a saint in 1297—Montesquieu is mainly
interested in Louis's attempts to reform the legal code. Several
After the Civil War of 49–30 BCE, Rome formally became an aspects of the modern French system of justice were
empire as Julius Caesar's nephew Octavian (regnal name: introduced by Louis IX, such as the presumption of innocence
Augustus) took power in 27 BCE. By this point Rome had a ("innocent until proven guilty") in criminal defendants.
vast territorial extent, supported by an equally vast military and Montesquieu is critical, however, of Louis's willingness to
administrative complex. During the early imperial period, called personally judge court cases—a prerogative he says should
the principate, Roman emperors were nominally the principles, never be exercised by a monarch.
or "first citizens," of a continuing republic—though in practical
terms Rome was now a monarchy. The pretense was dropped After Louis IX the Capetians continued to rule until 1328. At
in the latter centuries of the Empire, known as the dominate, that point, a junior or "cadet" branch of the Capetian dynasty
because the emperor was the acknowledged dominus, or took over and ruled as the House of Valois (1328–1589). Their
master. history, again, is of interest to Montesquieu largely because it
coincides with the history of France's legal system. The
The fall of the Western Roman Empire, customarily dated to accession of the Valois monarchs depended on ancient Salic
the overthrow of Emperor Romulus Augustulus in 476 CE, left law—the law of the Frankish tribe which had first come to
much of Western Europe prone to conquest (or reconquest) by power under Clovis over 800 years before. In particular the
various Germanic tribes. The laws and customs of these tribes, first Valois monarch, Philip VI (1293–1350), based his claim on
mingled with those of the now-defunct empire, formed the the Salic principle that a woman could not succeed to the
basis for the legal codes of medieval France and its neighbors. throne. This belief barred Philip's main competitor (Edward III
Tracing this latter development is Montesquieu's express of England) from the throne and—more interestingly for
purpose in Part 6 of The Spirit of the Laws. In the East, Montesquieu—left historians and jurists with a centuries-long
meanwhile, imperial rule continued in the form of the Byzantine debate about the ongoing applicability of Salic law in France.
Empire, which lasted until 1453. Although hugely important to Readers of Shakespeare's histories may remember this same
European history, the Byzantine Empire occupies relatively law becoming a plot point in Henry V, where the English king
little space in Montesquieu's work, perhaps because its makes his own claim to the French throne.
territories never included France.
The Valois branch died out in 1589, and another junior branch,
the House of Bourbon, took over. This branch continued to rule
France in Montesquieu's Time right up to the French Revolution (1787–99, rebellion against
the monarchy and feudalism), some three decades after
France, from the Middle Ages to the 18th century, is Montesquieu's death. The most famous Bourbon monarch,
Montesquieu's other major frame of reference in The Spirit of perhaps the most famous French monarch of them all, is Louis
the Laws. In Part 6 of his treatise Montesquieu describes the XIV (1638–1715), who reigned from 1643 to 1715. Known as the
early medieval history of France, in which three successive Sun King, Louis was a strong believer in absolute monarchy
dynasties or "races" of kings progressively unified the region and, like the star of his own solar system, set about pulling all
into something like its modern form. Under Clovis I (c. 466–511) of the French government's institutions into his "orbit."
and his heirs, called the Merovingians, the Franks went from Montesquieu admires the cultural and political successes of
being a tribe with only local influence to exerting dominion over Louis XIV's reign but, because of his pursuit of absolute power,
most of France (then called Francia). The Merovingians were in cannot avoid seeing elements of despotism in the Sun King's
turn succeeded by the Carolingians, a dynasty whose most reign. Louis XV (1710–74), the great-grandson of Louis XIV, was
famous member is Charlemagne (c. 747–814). the sitting monarch throughout Montesquieu's adult life. The
Spirit of the Laws wisely reserves judgment, at least overtly,
In the main body of the work (Parts 1–5), however, about the wisdom or foolishness of Louis XV's style of
Reactions to The Spirit of the both the Federalists (in favor of ratification) and the Anti-
Federalists (who opposed it) quoted extensively from
h Key Figures
them. Some of these criticisms are repeated, albeit briefly, in
The Spirit of the Laws.
Full Key Figure List Childeric III (d. 755) was the last of the
Merovingian kings of France. His reign
Childeric III
ended in 751, when he was
sequestered in a monastery.
Key Figure Description
Hugh Capet (938–96) was the king of Louis IX of France, also called Saint
France from 987 until his death. He is Louis (1214–70), was the most popular
Hugh Capet the founder of the Capetian dynasty, Louis IX
of the Capetian monarchs and the king
which reached its height during the of France from 1226 until his death.
reign of Louis IX.
James Madison (1751–1836) was the Adam Smith (1723–90) was a Scottish
fourth president of the United States philosopher and economist. He was an
Adam Smith
(1809–17), one of the Founding enthusiastic proponent of The Spirit of
James Fathers, and one of the authors of the the Laws.
Madison Federalist Papers. He advocated for
separation of powers in government, a
principle he learned from The Spirit of Tarquin is the last of the seven kings
the Laws. of Rome. He ruled from 534 to 509
Tarquin
BCE. Some scholars doubt his
historicity.
Charles Martel (c. 688–741) was a
Frankish ruler who united the Frankish
Charles Martel kingdoms and stemmed the Muslim
invasion through Spain. His son was
Pippin III. k Plot Summary
Merovech (5th century) was the In early French and English editions The Spirit of the Laws was
grandfather of Clovis I. From his name
Merovech often divided into two volumes. The 1989 Cambridge edition,
derives Merovingian, the name of his
dynasty. used in this guide, divides the work instead into six parts. The
books within each part correspond to what a modern reader
Napoleon I (1769–1821) was emperor might think of as chapters; the chapters within each book vary
of France. He led France to territorial greatly in length but are sometimes less than half a page long.
Napoleon I
expansion and internal reforms after
the French Revolution (1787–99).
because the people themselves are in charge. This is true to "just" a monarchy, with no other relevant characteristics. He is
some degree of both a democracy and an aristocracy, but in a aware of the differences within each government type and,
democracy virtue is absolutely indispensable. In an aristocracy moreover, aware of the potential for a blurring of lines between
Montesquieu concedes, virtue is not "absolutely required," any two categories. In Book 8 Montesquieu will describe
because aristocratic structures have a greater power to political corruption as this kind of blurring, with a monarchy or
sustain themselves than do democracies. If the citizens of a a republic taking on despotism-like characteristics. It can help
democracy become corrupt and unvirtuous, the days of that to think of Montesquieu's categorization as a sort of gradient,
democracy are numbered. like the ones used to choose colors in a graphic-design
program. Some regimes are overwhelmingly monarchical, just
Monarchies, Montesquieu asserts, are driven by a different as the color of a stop sign is red, with no detectable trace of
principle: honor. In a monarchy the people compete for the blue or green. Some regimes are clearly republics and would
ruler's favor, and this competition is enlivened by placing a high be hard to mistake for anything else, just as the sky on a sunny
value on honor. Monarchical cultures often give their day is unmistakably blue. However, Montesquieu also
subjects—at least their more powerful subjects—a certain considers plenty of in-between states: monarchies with a
leeway to violate the law when obeying the law would violate a representative element, for example, or republics in the
code of honor. In a sense monarchies function by channeling process of succumbing to tyranny.
the selfishness and ambition of their subjects into services to
the state.
In despotic states, however, the ruler's power is too absolute Part 1, Books 4–5
to leave much room for virtue or honor. The subjects cannot be
expected to be virtuous, because they have neither a role
model in their ruler nor any expectation of being rewarded for Summary
virtue. They also cannot be honorable, since they do not have
the political freedom to act honorably and risk incurring the
despot's displeasure. Instead, the subjects of a despot are Book 4: That the Laws of Education
motivated by fear, the sole source of their obedience.
Should Be Relative to the Principles of
the Government
Analysis
In order to sustain a government, Montesquieu argues, it is
This short chapter acts as the fulcrum of Montesquieu's entire necessary to educate the people to share the government's
treatise. Almost all his recommendations in Parts 1 through 5, values. This means cultivating honor in the subjects of a
and many of his historical insights in Part 6, appear in terms of monarchy, virtue in the citizens of a republic, and fear in the
the three-part division of government he proposes here. At the servants of a despotic regime. To educate people in honorable
same time the idea of splitting governments up into just a behavior, he says, it is sufficient to expose them to examples
handful of categories can come across as simplistic. A student of honor in real life—for instance, at the court of a king or
of modern political science might object on the grounds that nobleman. Formal schooling is a secondary matter. In a
"democracy" alone is an endlessly diverse category, embracing despotic state, meanwhile, education is useless except as it
everything from ancient Greek direct democracy to the conditions the people to obey authorities unquestioningly. Only
present-day United States, with its bicameral legislature and in republics is "the full power of education," beginning at home
indirect presidential elections. Likewise, someone with a and continuing in formal institutions, essential to the
background in ancient history might take issue with a plan that government's project. As success stories in this respect,
assumes a clear distinction between monarchies and despotic Montesquieu points to the ancient Greek city-states of Sparta
regimes. (Lacedaemon) and Athens, both of which, despite their very
different cultures, successfully transmitted their values to
Montesquieu, however, is not proposing a hard-and-fast
successive generations. He concludes by recommending
categorization scheme in which a state is "just" a republic or
music as a pastime which can "soften" a people and prevent
them from becoming harsh or savage. in power, such as tampering with an established religion or
burdening the people with excessive taxes. "I'm not saying
despotism is a good thing," he seems to say, "but if you happen
Book 5: The Laws Given by the to be a despot, here are the main considerations in running
your country."
Legislator Should Be Relative to the
Principle of the Government Montesquieu's real feelings regarding the different systems of
government are not, however, hard to discern. His hatred of
Montesquieu now applies a similar logic to laws in general. In a despotism breaks through at intervals in outbursts of
republic, he says, laws should cultivate virtue not only in the incredulity or moral disgust, and in his refusal—ostensibly from
young but in the citizenry as a whole. By encouraging frugality, shock—to print the more sordid details of life in despotic
for instance, laws can keep citizens from growing greedy and regimes. His admiration for republican values is likewise clear
self-serving. Some ancient states, such as Sparta, aimed at this from the many favorable remarks he makes about England, the
by dividing up lands equally among the citizens. In modern Low Countries, and Switzerland. Each of these countries had
nations, Montesquieu concedes, it is easier to place limits on devised a system which put power, to a greater or lesser
wills, dowries, and other vehicles by which wealth changes extent, in the hands of the people and their representatives.
hands. Such restrictions are, he adds, less necessary in a
In his private and professional life, moreover, Montesquieu was
commercial republic, since people will naturally be frugal and
evidently proud or at least content to be part of a monarchical
hard-working where commerce is widely established. In an
society. Throughout The Spirit of the Laws he defends his own
aristocracy, however, it is necessary to keep the nobles from
advantages as necessary consequences of monarchy. The
joining large wealth to their already highly concentrated
hereditary nature of noble titles—Baron de La Brède, for
political influence. For this reason Montesquieu warns against
example—is, he says, a safeguard against those titles losing
allowing nobles to collect taxes.
their luster. The buying and selling of public offices, like the
In a monarchy honor is preserved by keeping titles and the presidency Montesquieu inherited from his uncle and later
lands that support them within a single family. A monarchy can sold, can likewise be justified by the specific political needs of
therefore thrive on inheritance customs that would ruin a monarchy. The market, though Montesquieu does not use this
republic. The laws of a monarchy should also provide a kind of exact word, is a better way of sorting out who is qualified to
counterweight to keep a ruler from acting too rashly. Finally, in perform each office than is an arbitrary choice made by a
a despotic state few laws are necessary—just enough to keep prince. Thus, a prince can dole out the offices as a type of
the people in their lane, so to speak. In fact, some practices are honor to the worthy, and those with the ingenuity and work
acceptable (politically speaking) under a despot, even though ethic to profit from those offices can buy them later.
they would be poisonous to a monarchy or republic. For Montesquieu readily admits that neither hereditary titles nor
instance, despots accept or even demand gifts from their the sale of public offices can be defended in a republic, which
subjects, but in other forms of government this is the crime of runs on different principles than a monarchy does.
bribery.
biases are less blinding concerning the issue of a woman's less by default. When those same principles have been
ruling a country. Giving credit where credit is due, he corrupted, even the best laws and institutions will be turned
acknowledges the successful reigns of both Russian empress into weapons of abuse. In a final chapter Montesquieu reviews
Catherine I (1684–1727) and Elizabeth I of England. contemporary writings on China and pronounces it, with its
vast territory and autocratic rulers, a despotic state.
Part 1, Book 8
Analysis
This book, unusually concise and abstract by Montesquieu's
Summary standards, almost speaks for itself. It should be noted,
however, that what Montesquieu calls "corruption" is a
different creature from the corruption complained of in modern
Book 8: On the Corruption of the government. To give just one example, venality (the buying and
Principles of the Three Governments selling of public offices) is illegal in many modern democracies.
Lobbying, though not usually against the law, is widely viewed
"The corruption of each government," Montesquieu asserts, with suspicion because of its potential to privilege powerful
"almost always begins with that of its principles." For a commercial interests over the will of the people. Neither one of
democracy this can occur in two major ways: either the spirit these, however, would make a government "corrupt" in
of equality is lost or a "spirit of extreme equality" takes hold, in Montesquieu's sense of the word. Modern politicians
which nobody can stand to be led or governed. Either way, the sometimes campaign on a promise to "drain the swamp," but
love of virtue—the "spring" driving any democracy—is lost, and Montesquieu cared more about stirring the swamp to keep it
democratic rule gives way to either oligarchy or tyranny. In an from growing stagnant.
aristocracy, too, corruption is complete when virtue is lost. This
happens when the nobles who rule the country no longer Far from confining its venality to gentlemen's agreements and
submit to the law. A hereditary nobility is, Montesquieu says, a backroom deals, early modern France had a well-established
virtual guarantee of such corruption because it allows the set of venal offices. In Montesquieu's time such offices
nobles to consolidate power at the expense of their own numbered over 50,000 by some counts; most, like
security. A republic of either kind, he adds, can generally retain Montesquieu's post in the Bordeaux appeals court, were
its integrity only when its territorial extent is small, since judicial in nature. The sale and purchase of these offices were
people's reliance on their homeland diminishes as the territory not only openly recognized but actually enshrined in French
grows large. law as a way for the crown to raise funds. Moreover, such
offices offered a prime working example of the monarchical
Monarchies, too, can become corrupt if the monarch gives in to culture of honor, since those who sought to buy them were
the urge to micromanage, rather than delegating significant often wealthy members of the merchant class hoping to be
portions of his power and authority to others. Honor, in ennobled. Above and beyond the revenue one might obtain as,
Montesquieu's view is the principle of a monarchy, and it is for instance, an appeals judge, public offices carried a kind of
impossible to sustain an honor-based culture when the awards "honor premium" that made them attractive to commoners.
and titles conferred by a prince have no relation to a person's
merit. Monarchies, he argues, are by nature inclined to be "of a Thus, from Montesquieu's point of view a monarchy did not risk
medium size": larger than republics but smaller than despotic becoming corrupt through mere venality. Indeed, he regarded
regimes. Those despotic governments, he goes on to say, do venality almost as a sign of health, since it meant the king was
not have to wait for their principles to be corrupted. Rather, taking an appropriately hands-off approach to the low- and
they are "corrupt by nature" and tend to fall apart all on their mid-level management of the realm. The presence of many
own unless some "accident of nature" holds them together. offices, whether inherited or sold, meant that power was
shared out among many hands, not concentrated despotically
When a state's principles remain uncorrupted, Montesquieu in the person of the ruler. Whose hands mattered less, as long
says, the government and laws will tend to be good more or as a culture of honor kept all of the players in open
Summary
Analysis
Book 9: On the Laws in Their Relation Montesquieu's doctrines of war and conquest represent an
with Defensive Force area in which he diverges sharply from 21st-century
sensibilities. Because his ideas were instrumental in the
Since republics are by their nature small, Montesquieu says, founding of modern democracies, it can be tempting to think of
they must band together into federations in order to defend Montesquieu as a sort of evangelist of political liberty. This is
themselves from invasion. Such alliances are, he argues, an exaggeration at best and, at worst, a distortion of the truth.
stable, because the members of the federation keep each In fact, Montesquieu takes it for granted that a country has the
other in check. Limitations need to be set, however, on the right to expand its territory at the expense of its neighbors—at
war- and treaty-making power of the federation members, lest least if those neighbors are threatening to do the same. It
the entire group be dragged into a conflict or bound by an would indeed have been very awkward for Montesquieu to
unwanted truce. Despotic states can provide for their defense speak out against wars of conquest, since the France of his
by leaving a perimeter of wasteland near their borders, day was built by such wars. Substantial territorial gains of this
whereas monarchies must build forts and recruit standing kind had been made under Louis XIV (1638–1715), the great-
armies. This is one reason that, as argued earlier, a monarchy grandfather and direct predecessor of the monarch who
should not have too great a territorial extent. If a country is too reigned as Montesquieu wrote.
big for an army to cross it in a few weeks at most, it is also too
big to defend against a sudden invasion. It is more important By the mid-18th century the right of conquest had a long
for a country to be larger and more powerful than its neighbors history not only in France but throughout Europe. Montesquieu,
("relative size") than it is for the country simply to grow as large aware of this history, cites examples from ancient Greece
as possible ("real size"). onward. Moreover, for over a century after Montesquieu's
death, territorial wars in Europe would continue to be fought
under the assumption "to the victor go the spoils." International
Book 10: On Laws in the Relation with law in the era of French emperor Napoleon I (1769–1821), for
instance, set bounds on what could be taken, but it did not
Offensive Force completely forbid one country from annexing or conquering
another. The right of conquest was only definitively abolished
Nations, Montesquieu argues, have the right to make war to
only in the wake of World War II (1939–45). The Nuremberg
protect themselves and can sometimes undertake wars of
Principles, the United Nations-authored rules for determining
aggression as a type of preemptive self-defense. When such a
what counts as a war crime, explicitly outlawed wars of
war results in conquest, a nation has the responsibility to
aggression as a "crime against peace." Interestingly, many of
preserve, not destroy, what it has conquered. Montesquieu
the other crimes codified in the Nuremberg
deplores the idea of slaughtering a conquered state's
Principles—including the infamous "crimes against
inhabitants, though he admits that sometimes it may be
humanity"—are ones against which Montesquieu speaks out in
necessary to reduce them to servitude for a time. When
these chapters.
republics conquer, they must quickly grant some political rights
to the conquered, or the double standard—a republic acting as
a monarchy—will breed resentment. As an example of how
conquests ought to be carried out, Montesquieu upholds the
condone slavery; he merely concedes that it is practiced more climate is considered. Many customs depend, for instance, on
successfully in certain climates than in others. In temperate whether a nation possesses land suitable for farming. The
and cold climates, prevalent in most of Europe, Montesquieu medieval Germans, living in a heavily forested part of the world,
deems slavery both "useless" and unnatural. If a country insists did not cultivate the land, and their laws were thus based more
on sanctioning slavery, he adds, care must be taken to regulate on kinship than on territory or property rights. Such peoples do
the exact nature of the relationship between slaves and not use money, Montesquieu says, but conduct their
masters. commerce by barter. They lack "even the idea of luxury" and
thus have no incentive to commit many of the nonviolent
crimes (e.g., fraud) widespread in sedentary cultures.
Book 16: How the Laws of Domestic
Slavery are Related to the Nature of the
Analysis
Climate
Montesquieu's persistence in tracing national characteristics
Montesquieu now moves to a discussion of women's back to climate may seem strange to a modern reader. In
household servitude in patriarchal cultures. Here, too, he particular, when compared to his other major theoretical
identifies a geographic pattern, since polygamy is more contributions—the three types of government (Part 1) and the
common in hot climates. Men in cold climates, meanwhile, are separation of powers (Part 2, Book 11)—the emphasis on
fond of drinking and behaving "intemperately," and legally- climate as a master key to understanding culture can come
mandated monogamy help rein in the chaos. Montesquieu across as embarrassingly simplistic. Although it is easy to
favors access to divorce in cultures where married women name examples of cultural norms predicated on climate (for
have some independence. The less liberty women enjoy, he instance, the Spanish siesta or the wearing of Bermuda
suggests, the less freedom a husband should have in divorcing shorts), an extrapolation such as Montesquieu attempts is
or repudiating his wife or wives. another story.
laws of the material world," Bonnet proclaimed; "you have hardly be called disinterested chroniclers. The Jesuits, who
discovered, sir, the laws of the intellectual world." arrived in Japan in 1549 only to find that the preaching of
Christianity was punishable by death, could not have received
a favorable first impression given that their whole purpose in
Part 3, Book 19 Japan was to preach Christianity. Their later writings, as of
their confreres in China (mission est. 1552), tend to draw a
close connection between the cruelty of autocratic rule and
Book 19: On the Laws in the Relation The hypothetical country mentioned in the final chapter,
with the Principles Forming the General though not named by Montesquieu, can be confidently
identified as England. Here, unlike in his writings about China,
Spirit, the Mores, and the Manners of a Montesquieu is working from considerable firsthand
experience. The publication of Montesquieu's Persian Letters
Nation
in 1721 had made him a literary celebrity and brought him into
Though not much longer than the other books of Part 3, this contact with several English courtiers, whom he proceeded to
book pivots away from the topic of climate and starts in on a visit on their home turf between 1729 and 1731. His remarks
new subject. Montesquieu now takes stock of the full range of about English art, society, and culture, though sometimes
social and cultural forces that hold a nation together, apart fancifully phrased, thus have the quality of firsthand
from its positive laws. The word "spirit" is Montesquieu's observation.
catchall term for such forces. Thus, the spirit of the imperial
Romans was too egalitarian for an overt monarchy but was
content with an emperor who proclaimed himself the "first Part 4, Books 20–21
citizen." Among the ancient Greek city-states, the Spartans
had a warlike spirit, while the Athenians were sophisticated
and fond of high culture. Summary
Much of the rest of the book consists of Montesquieu's
interpretation of the "spirits" of different cultures, including
Book 20: On the Laws in Their Relation
those of Spain, Japan, and China. In among these observations
is some practical advice: a prince "must reform by laws what is to Commerce, Considered in Its Nature
established by laws and change by manners what is
established by manners," never mixing the two. A law banning a
and Its Distinctions
people from wearing their traditional apparel, for instance, is
Montesquieu begins this book by calling upon the Muses, the
"tyrannical." The book closes by resuming the discussion of
Greek goddesses of art and poetry, to bless his work. He then
England from Part 2, Book 11 and showing how England's laws
remarks on the "spirit of commerce," a civilizing force that
are suited to the spirit of the country.
encourages peace among nations but competition among
individuals. Different types of government, he says, have their
own characteristic forms of commerce: monarchies tend to be
Analysis heavy importers of luxury goods, whereas republics tend to
engage in an "economic commerce" involving both imports and
Book 19 illustrates the profound difference between
exports.
Montesquieu's knowledge of East Asian cultures and his
knowledge of both ancient and contemporary Europe. Many of There are, Montesquieu acknowledges, many different types
the works cited on China and Japan are the writings of of laws and national policies concerning commerce. He
European missionaries—who, if not untrustworthy per se, can
considers it foolish for one country to prohibit trade with perspective. To be more specific, he is a proponent of the
another "without great reasons," but he admits that other types mercantilism—the tendency to promote trade as a matter of
of trade restrictions (tariffs, for instance, or export bans) can national policy—of his time. He names, and approves of, several
be useful. As a kind of tax, he says, import and export duties methods used by France, England, and other early modern
should not be farmed out to private tax collectors but should European states to regulate commerce, including the various
be collected by the government directly. Nobles and monarchs duties placed on imports and exports. In other words,
should not engage in commerce at all, since this would Montesquieu is not a believer in unfettered free trade: although
suppress the competition on which trade thrives. Some he sees commerce as beneficial in general, he also considers it
nations—those rich in necessities and poor in luxuries—would, wise and productive for countries to try and reap a larger
Montesquieu speculates, be better off if they shunned share of its benefits. To a greater extent than later
international trade. economists—notably Scottish philosopher and economist
Adam Smith (1723–90)—Montesquieu deems it possible for a
country to restrict traders' behavior without hindering
Book 21: On Laws in Their Relation to commerce overall.
Analysis Summary
The invocation to the Muses is a standard device of epic
poetry, appearing at the beginning of Homer's Odyssey and
Book 22: On Laws in Their Relation to
Virgil's Aeneid, among others. Thus, it's somewhat unusual to
encounter such an invocation in a nonfiction text on political the Use of Money
theory. By including such a gesture, Montesquieu may be
suggesting that he sees himself not only as a philosopher or a "Money," Montesquieu declares, "is a sign representing the
scholar, but also as an artist, a poet. He may also be reminding value of all commodities." Gold and silver are the most typical
readers that history is an art—with its own Muse, named materials used as money, but in some cases land can be
Clio—as well as a science. Whatever his precise intention may exchanged so freely that it forms a kind of currency in itself.
have been, Montesquieu's invocation provides a sort of rest Paper currency, increasingly common in Montesquieu's time, is
stop near the halfway point of his long work. also acknowledged. Montesquieu also draws a distinction
between real monies, meaning currency with a specified
In general Montesquieu writes from a pro-commerce content of precious metal, and ideal monies that merely
represent a certain amount of value. Although the fluctuations Montesquieu, he is wary of attempts to hamper international
in value of ideal monies are more obvious, Montesquieu notes trade or rig the game, so to speak, by manipulating currency
that real monies too can decline or rise in value as the supply values. It is a testament to Montesquieu's influence that,
of precious metals becomes ampler or more restricted. compared to some of his contemporaries, he said so little on
Fundamentally, gold and silver are commodities like anything economics yet achieved the reputation he did. An illustration of
else: they just happen to be more durable and convenient for this lasting legacy can be found in the work of the great 20th-
exchange. century British economist John Maynard Keynes (1883–1946),
who praised Montesquieu as "the real French equivalent of
Next, Montesquieu comments at length on the different Adam Smith ... the greatest of [France's] economists."
"operations" a nation can take with regard to its money supply.
The most fundamental such "operation" is debasement, in Montesquieu cites two major examples to show what happens
which the amount of precious metal in a given currency unit is when lending at interest is either restricted or forbidden. His
reduced but the currency's nominal value remains the same. first example comes from the "Mahommedan" (i.e., Islamic)
Modern nations, he says, don't gain as much as they think by nations, where lending at interest is banned outright. Usury,
debasing their currencies, because other countries quickly known as riba in sharia law, is forbidden in Islam, and this
become aware of changes in the content of, for instance, a prohibition takes the form of a complete ban on the charging
French livre coin. Instead, it is the bankers who profit, because of interest. Even today, countries with sharia-influenced legal
they have the resources to respond more quickly to changes in systems, such as Saudi Arabia, prohibit interest-bearing
coinage than an ordinary consumer or merchant can. financial instruments. An entire industry of "sharia-compliant
Montesquieu also cautions against the drafting of laws that finance" has arisen to fill the gap.
hinder international commerce, because these tend to deepen
a country's isolation. Montesquieu's other main example is the Roman Republic.
Here, he has access to much more thorough (and arguably
Finally, Montesquieu draws a distinction between interest in more accurate) knowledge through his extensive reading of
general and usury (excessive or illegal interest). The charging Roman historians. Thus, he can devote many more pages to
of some interest, Montesquieu says, must be permitted, or teasing out the republic's financial history. He tells mainly of
people will simply charge more to offset the risks of illegal the backfiring of policies designed to favor debtors or at least
lending. As a rule, he points out, nobody can be expected to to win their political support. These policies, to the extent they
lend money without some expectation of profit, which lenders were implemented, were popular because the credit structure
will seek either legally or illegally as their circumstances of Roman society was somewhat like that of modern countries.
require. To illustrate this, he tells of the rampant usury which There were many smaller debtors (think homeowners, car
arose in ancient Rome when lenders lost their trust in the owners, and credit-card holders) and a relatively few, relatively
republic's financial laws. wealthy creditors (today's big banks). The Romans, however,
pushed things too far—or so Montesquieu suggests. By making
it hard for creditors to reliably collect interest, he implies,
Analysis Roman legislators drove much of the republic's money-lending
activity underground.
As Montesquieu dips briefly into economics, he gives the
reader a sense of the fiscal issues then considered important
to Western European governments. Interestingly, Part 4, Book 23
Montesquieu's discussion anticipates—though loosely and
qualitatively—some of the conclusions reached by Adam Smith
in The Wealth of Nations (1776). That work is devoted wholly to
economics and thus naturally goes into much greater depth
Summary
than Montesquieu does here, but it echoes Montesquieu on
several points. Like Montesquieu, Smith takes great care to
explain to his readers that money is a commodity like anything
else and will obey the same laws of supply and demand. Like
Montesquieu now considers the role of the law in preventing Ancient legal history is a dry subject, and Montesquieu, though
either over- or underpopulation within a country. He cites the thorough, does not do much to liven it up. Those seeking a
examples of the ancient Greeks, who lived in small city-states more dramatic account of the laws, customs, and culture of
and wished to avoid overcrowding, and of the Romans, who early imperial Rome may be interested in Robert Graves's
were attempting to people a vast empire. In early imperial classic novel I, Claudius (1934). Written as a fictionalized
Rome, Montesquieu observes, there were many laws—some autobiography of Rome's fourth emperor, the book stays true
quite strict—encouraging marriage and childbearing. These to the broad historical facts while weaving a compelling
laws in effect rewarded a couple for each child they raised. narrative.
Later on, many of these laws were revoked, and the rise of
Christianity in Rome made celibacy culturally acceptable again.
Part 5, Books 24–25
Modern France, Montesquieu argues, is more like
underpopulated Rome than overpopulated Greece and should
fashion its laws accordingly. One option, he proposes, is to
ensure that everyone, even the poorest, has some land from
Summary
which to obtain a living and on which to raise a family. This is
preferable, in Montesquieu's view, to making the poor reliant on
a system of poorhouses that will only discourage them from
Book 24: On the Laws in Their Relation
seeking employment. to the Religion Established in Each
Country, Examined in Respect to Its
Analysis Practices and Within Itself
The laws Montesquieu cites here are most commonly The first book of Part 5 involves the established religion of a
associated with Augustus (63 BCE–14 CE), the first emperor of nation, meaning the religion practiced by most of its
Rome. There were relatively few laws regulating marriage in inhabitants. This is not necessarily the same thing as a state
the republic, which preceded the Empire, but Augustus greatly religion, which receives special legal status. Montesquieu
multiplied the marriage laws and made them much more explains that even a "false" religion (which for him means
detailed in scope. These Augustan social laws imposed tax anything but Christianity) can have political benefits, and he
penalties on unmarried adults, gave out prizes to couples who reminds readers that he is a political philosopher, not a
bore many children, and severely punished adultery. theologian. He rejects the argument that it is better to be an
atheist than an idolater and suggests some boundaries
Augustus quickly found, however, that his subjects were
between religious law (e.g., canon law) and the civil law of a
unwilling to tolerate such extensive meddling in their household
nation. In general, he says, religion is a better tool for
affairs. They found one stratagem after another to evade the
correcting the private morals of the people, and civil law should
marriage laws—including engagements and divorces
not intervene in this regard if it can be helped.
undertaken purely for tax purposes. Augustus responded by
attempting to make the laws even stricter, but by 9 BCE, it was
clear this moral crusade was a lost cause, and the laws were
Book 25: On the Laws in Their Relation
amended. Thus, what Montesquieu describes as the gradual
moral erosion of an empire was more like a short-lived, with the Establishment of the Religion of
aggressive reform followed by a return to business as usual.
Moreover, Augustus's own household was not exactly
compliant with the law's strict spirit. When the emperor's
of the Roman Laws on Inheritance is such a thing as taking simplicity too far. The laws should not
try to create a rigid uniformity in all things, but should account
This short book surveys the history of inheritance law in Rome for differences in class or custom.
from the beginning of the republic onward. Montesquieu walks
the reader through the complexities of inheritance—particularly
the limits on female inheritance—up through the early Roman Analysis
Empire and then briefly remarks on the relaxation of these
limits under later emperors. Almost as important as the laws In Books 27 and 28 Montesquieu breaks away from his earlier
themselves are the various strategies people adopted to skirt broad focus on legal theory and drills down into some very
the laws. Some refused to be counted in the census (which narrow historical questions. He investigates such issues as the
would mean having their estate assessed), and others specific legal tactics the Romans took to evade this or that law
"bequeathed" their estate to eligible friends who promised to on inheritance, or the differences in ritual combat between two
pass it along to the deceased's daughter. neighboring Germanic tribes. Such fine-scaled analysis is not
completely absent from Books 1 through 26, but here—and in
the final two books—it appears with a vengeance.
Book 28: On the Origin and Revolutions
A few guideposts will give some shape to the discussion. The
of the Civil Laws among the French evolution of Roman inheritance law in Book 27 begins with the
Law of the Twelve Tables (451–450 BCE), which was the first
Montesquieu next presents a much longer survey of the history systematic codification of Roman law. The next important
of French law, beginning with the early-medieval conflict change was the Voconian Law (Lex Voconica, 169 BCE), which
between the Roman Empire and various Germanic tribes in the set a precise upper limit on the amount women could inherit.
region. He describes a continually changing patchwork quilt of This law prompted the various evasive tactics which
small regimes, with the Salian Franks and their Salic law Montesquieu reviews in such detail. The social laws passed
gradually becoming a preeminent force. Remarkably, laws in under Augustus, sometimes so strict in their efforts to
early medieval France were often personal rather than encourage marriage, actually improved the inheritance
territorial: a Frank would be judged by Frankish law and a prospects for women—provided they raised a family. The Lex
Burgundian by Burgundian law, regardless of where they lived. Papia Poppaea (9 CE), which Montesquieu calls the "Papian
As the Salian Franks and their descendants consolidated Law," allowed women to inherit if they had at least three
power and France began to unify, a code of law emerged children. Most of the developments Montesquieu introduced in
which blended aspects of Roman and Germanic traditions. this book are elaborations of, or reactions to, the Voconian
Montesquieu considers some such traditions—e.g., trial by Law.
combat—to be barbaric, even as he admires the spirit of
independence conferred by France's Germanic legal heritage. In Book 28 it is much easier to miss the forest for the trees. Of
He closes by mentioning the "great period" of the early 15th all the different tribes Montesquieu names—Burgundians,
century, when French law was codified into something like its Goths, Visigoths, and so forth—the ones to really keep an eye
early modern form. on are the Franks, from whom France gets its modern name.
There were two principal tribes of Franks, called the Ripuarians
and the Salians. The latter, led by Clovis I (c. 466–511) and his
descendants, consolidated their rule across much of present-
day France between the 5th and 7th centuries. In doing so,
Book 31: The Theory of the Feudal Laws
they paved the way for Francia's (i.e., France's) emergence as
a major European power. Their law, known as the Salic law, among the Franks in Their Relation to
remained a shaping influence on France's legal culture for
the Revolutions of Their Monarchy
many centuries.
The drawbacks of living in a sophisticated legal culture are, for For a government to fall into despotism, however, is always a
Montesquieu, the price paid for a moderate government. A tragedy.
complex legal code is necessary in a republic or a monarchy,
where citizens (or subjects) have rights to defend and interests
to protect. In a despotic regime the laws can be simple "No word has received more
because there are, frankly, no real rights to protect. Later, in
Part 2, Book 13, he makes the same point about taxes: heavy different significations and has
taxation is accepted only by a populace who consider
struck minds in so many ways as
themselves free in other respects.
has liberty."
government." its laws are too restrictive. Montesquieu also considers the
opposite case: a nominally despotic regime where law or
custom gives the citizens a good deal of breathing room. His
— Montesquieu, Part 1, Book 8
overriding point here, repeated in various ways throughout the
treatise, is that political freedom must be carefully preserved
Beneath the three-part division of "republic, monarchy, by sound legislation, never taken for granted.
despotism," Montesquieu makes an even more fundamental
distinction between a moderate regime and a despotic one.
Though he writes for the subjects of a monarchy, he also finds "As mechanics has its frictions
many virtues to praise in republican governments, such as that
in the Netherlands. If a republic becomes a monarchy or vice which often change or check its
versa, he says, nothing of great importance is necessarily lost.
Here, Montesquieu indulges in the idea of politics as a science This statement both encapsulates and transcends
like physics. In some parts of the treatise this "mechanistic" Montesquieu's thinking about all the different laws, mores, and
view of politics can come across as simplistic, as when manners that shape a society. A wise legislator, he argues
Montesquieu cites climate as a universal influence on human throughout his treatise, will make laws that do not need to be
character. The allusion to "friction" is Montesquieu's way of broken often because they are well suited to the spirit of the
acknowledging the gap between the theories he generates populace. Even so, Montesquieu admits, cases will inevitably
and the real-world phenomena he observes. arise in which the letter of the law seems to contradict its spirit.
When this happens, it becomes necessary to consult a higher
law by asking what is best for the people.
"A free nation can have a liberator;
a subjugated nation can have only "The statutes of legislators regard
another oppressor." the society more than the citizen,
— Montesquieu, Part 3, Book 19 and the citizen more than the
man."
It's not enough, Montesquieu argues in this chapter, to change
the ruler or even the constitution of a country. Rather, he — Montesquieu, Part 6, Book 27
believes, freedom can take root only in a nation whose mores,
manners, religion, and even climate are hospitable to personal
Throughout The Spirit of the Laws Montesquieu calls for
liberty. A "free nation" in this sense is one that is deeply
moderation in lawmaking. He is particularly troubled by laws
predisposed to freedom, even if it temporarily suffers from an
that seem to ignore the natural feelings or inclinations of the
oppressive regime.
citizen. Such inflexibility—whether in laws concerning religion,
those addressing public morals, or those regulating
inheritance—is an imperfection, according to Montesquieu's
"Silver is the sign of values." way of thinking.
system will only burden the citizenry. A too lenient penal code
will fail to deter crime, but there is nothing to be gained from m Glossary
excessive cruelty, either. Montesquieu rejects any legal code in
which "excess" is seen as good. aristocracy system of government in which an elite group,
distinguished by wealth or ancestry, have control. Montesquieu
regards aristocracies as a type of republic.
"When one examines the records
body politic the people of a society, regarded as a group. The
of our history and our laws, it term is similar to "population" or "citizenry" but emphasizes the
political nature of the group.
seems that everything is a sea and
constitution set fundamental principles underlying a country's
that the sea lacks even shores."
laws. Most modern democracies embody these principles in a
written constitution, but a constitution can also be a set of
— Montesquieu, Part 6, Book 30 customs or traditions understood to be legally binding.
laws, and laws by history." executive power power to carry out (execute) the law, and in
some specific cases to override it. This power is held by the
as their ancestors. To resolve such issues, he says, it is international law. The law of nations governs the rights and
necessary to look at the overall history of the country in relationships of countries in both war and peace.
All material contained within this document/guide is protected by copyright law of the US and various other
jurisdictions and may not be reproduced or distributed without the express written consent. Contact Course Hero
with respect to reproduction or distribution. This document was downloaded from Coursehero.com on
09-09-2021 by 100000816543518.