An Introduction To Health Ethics' What Is Ethics?
An Introduction To Health Ethics' What Is Ethics?
An Introduction To Health Ethics' What Is Ethics?
What is Ethics?
Ethics is the study of how human beings treat each other and the natural environment; it is the
systematic examination of the attitudes and behaviors of people. Ethics is about carefully
studying the values that actually do guide our attitudes and behaviors in given contexts, and it is
about exploring what values ought to guide our attitudes and behaviors.
The terms bioethics and healthcare ethics sometimes are used interchangeably. Bioethics, born
out of the rapidly expanding technical environment of the 1900s, is a specific domain of ethics
focused on moral issues in the field of health care (see Box 2-1). During World War II President
Franklin D. Roosevelt assembled a committee to improve medical scientists' coordination in
addressing the medical needs of the military (Jonsen, 2000). As often happens with wartime
research and advancements, the work aimed at addressing military needs also affected civilian
sectors, such as the field of medicine.
Definitions of Ethics
The word ethics has Greek roots:
+ Ta ethika, referring to philosophical inquiry into good and evil
+ Ethos, meaning personal character
Purpose
The purpose of Ethics and the Healthcare Professional is to provide healthcare professionals
with information about ethics, ethical principles, and Codes of Ethics, and to explore the ethical
aspects of situations that healthcare professionals commonly encounter in practice.
Medical ethics. Known as the oldest phase of bioethical exploration is medical ethics which is a
fomulation of ethical norms for the conduct of health care professionals in the treatment of
patients (Pahl: 2; The Hippocratic Oath: 242). The physician-patient relationship is no different
from other human relationships in which duties and rights are involved. Respect for these rights
and acting by one's duties will be for the good of both the physician and the patient, whereas
any infraction thereof is detrimental to the relationship. Thus, codes of ethics were written by
and for physicians as early as the 3rd century B.C.
One of the oldest known formulations of medical ethics is the Hippocratic Oath, named after
Hippocrates (460-357 B.C.), who was recognized by many scholars as the Father of Medicine.
He was a native of Thessaly, Greece but practiced and taught medicine in Athens. A cursory
glance at the oath will reveal that it is a theocentric pledge made by the physician to both Apollo
and Asclepius, the father-and-son gods of medicine in Greek mythology. It underscores the
physician's all-out concern for the patient to be kept from harm and injustice. The physician
should not prescribe a fatal drug to anyone even if asked do so; nor should
the physician suggest that fatal drugs be taken (a clear reference to euthanasia during those
times). The oath rules out any form of abortifacient (another obvious reference to the practice of
abortion as early as 500 B.C.) and sexual relations between doctors and patients, be they male
or female, rich or poor, free or slaves. Likewise enshrined in the pledge is the moral significance
of confidentiality, otherwise known as medical secrecy. Fulfillment of the oath is believed to
bring about honor, fame, and joy in medical practice; while its transgression brings about
dishonor and infamy among all for every generation to come.
Research ethics. The second phase in the development of bioethical study is research ethics
in the biomedical fields (hence it is likewise called biomedical research) (Pahl). This refers to the
use of humans as experimental specimens., e.g.. prisoners, poor patients, childrern, and
fetuses. Undertakings along this line were surreptitiously perfomed on concentration camp
inmates in Germany during the dictatorial regime of Adolf Hitler -this period is also known as the
Third Reich (covering the years 1933 to 1945). The Nazi fascist was tremendously influenced by
Friedrich Nietzsche's philosophy of will to power (supposedly Hitler's favorite bedtime reading).
Nietzsche's superman concept as the culmination of the will to power inherent in every
individual strengthened Hitler's strong conviction that the German race is superior to others. He
agreed with the "superman” philosopher that real progress could be attained not by the
emancipation of the masses from poverty but by the cultivation of the superior race of humans.
And he thought the Germans could become the super race.
Public policy. This is the third stage in the development of bioethical inquiry. It accentuates the
participatory aspect of decision-making in a democratic set-up with regard to the formulation of
public policies for the benefit of all. This phase refers to the people's efforts or involvement in
formulating public guidelines for both clinical cases and biomedical research (Pahi: 3). This is
done by consulting the people through surveys, meetings, conferences, convocations about
their opinions and views on particular bioethical issues (e.g., human experimentation,
abortifacient contraceptives, allocation of scarce medical resources). Experts and authors from
various disciplines are asked to give their suggestions and recommendations. Public discussion
is encouraged and conducted in order to give everyone an opportunity to participate in the
consultative process.
Applied ethics does not only apply general moral concepts and principles, but also specifies
the particular situations in life in which they are valid and legitimate; hence it is also known as
special ethics. In an attempt to resolve specific moral problems, general ethical precepts are
applied (hence the name). Professional ethics is an applied type of ethics insofar as it deals with
certain moral precepts or rules by which persons behave and act in the exercise of their calling
or profession. Likewise, there is legal ethics for lawyers in the practice of law, a teachers' code
of ethics for educators, and nursing ethics, among others.
Traditionally, therefore, ethics may be divided into general and applied. General ethics refers to
all the diverse ethical formulations of general and universal concepts and principles which serve
as the foundation of morality (Bittle: 309). It raises the problem of moral norms and attempts to
formulate and defend a system of fundamental ethical perceptions that settle which acts are
good and which are evil. For every moral theory these ethical principles are presumed to be
valid (hence to be followed) for everyone. Consequently, inasmuch as general ethics deals
with the issue of the norm of morality, it is sometimes called normative
Ethical studies are based on reason, insofar as all proofs of ethical science must find their
source in the native power of reason alone. Ethics investigates the facts, analyzes them and
draws from them practical applications to particular actions. Ethics does not subscribe to, nor
will it rely on, so-called "divine revelation" for the final answers or resolutions of certain moral
issues. Divine revelation refers allegedly to certain know edge revealed by God to humans--
knowledge which we cannot fully understand, but which we have to accept as true because God
said so, and because we know that God can neither deceive us nor be deceived by us.
This makes ethics different from religion, for the latter subscribes to "divine revelation." Here lies
the disparity between two claims: The religionist contends that there can be no morality without
God, whereas the ethician maintains that morality remains possible even without God. This
means that one can still determine the goodness or badness of one's behavior even if one does
not believe in God. A non-believer can still be good. This apparently controversial, religious and
philosophical issue is a part of every Individual's continuous search for meaning.
Ethics deals only with human acts insofar as they are performed with intellectual deliberation
and freedom. Personal responsibility presupposes knowledge and volition. This explains why
the acts of irrational animals (e.g., cats, dogs, etc.) and insane persons are devoid of moral
significance; they are amoral beings performing nonmoral acts. Let us pursue this point further:
Is one to be held morally responsible for all one's acts? This leads to the distinction between
human acts and acts of man. (Aquinas 1947; Bittle 1950: 24-33). The former are those which
are done with knowledge and full consent of the will. One knows what one is doing and one
does it freely and willingly. The latter refers to those which are performed in the absence of
either or both of the two conditions (of a human act).
Types of Ethics
Descriptive Ethics
The aim of descriptive ethics is to depict and clarity moral opinions and practices, and to
explicitly articulate the concepts and assumptions implicit in these. For example, "What does
group X think about the morality of abortion?" is a question of descriptive ethics.
Nomative Ethics
Nomative cthics concerns making moral judgrments about what is right and wrong. good
and bad etc. It also involves developing action guides to direct ethical behaviour. For
example, "Is abortinga fetus ethically justifiable?" is a normative question.
Meta-Ethics
The discussion here is not about what particular people think ethics is or what ought or
ought not to be considered ethical. Rather, meta-ethics involves analyses of the language,
concepts, and methods of reasoning in health care. For example, "What does 'ethically
justifiable mean? is a meta-ethical question.
Preliminary
In this rapidly changing world, healthcare professionals face multiple changes involving
ethical dilemmas Ethical dilemma refers situations in which one's values conflict with that of
the other. These are situations in which two or more moral principles conflict with one another.
Ethical dilemmas occur when there is a difficult choice to be made between two or more
options, neither of which resolves the situation in a manner that is consistent with accepted
ethical guidelines. Ethical dilemma is a conflict between alternatives, where no matter what a
person does, some ethical principle wll be compromised.
3. Love "wills the neighbor's good" [desires the best for aur neighbors] whether we like
them or not
- Agape is in the business of loving the unlovable and we should always do the most
loving thing in any situation.
4. Love and justice are the same, for justice is love distributed, nothing else
- To act justy or fairly is precisely to act in love. Love is justice, justice is love.
5. Only the ends justify the means, nothing else
6. Love's decisions are made situationally, not prescriptively
- No decision can be taken before considering the situation.
Situation ethics was originally devised in a Christian context, but it can easily be applied in a
non-religious way. It is based on the general Christian norm of brotherly love, which is
expressed in different ways in different situations. In forming ethical system based an "love," this
is best expressed in the notion of love thy neighbor, which Jesus Christ
taught in the Gospels of the New Testament of the Bible. Although there is clothing of religion in
this type of ethics, it uses the religious term such as "agape" but it has nothing special to do with
theological faith. (Agape means absolute, universal, unchanging and unconditional love for all
people.) It is based on the golden rule "love your neighbor as you love your self" and altruism
which is putting other before yourself and showing agape towards everyone.
In the Bible story in Mark 3:1-6, Jesus healed a man with a withered hand in the Jewish temple,
an act which one would consider to demonstrate Jesus's love for all. However, the Pharisees
tell him off because he has performed this healing on the Sabbath day and the Jewish law says
that no one can work on the Sabbath. This act of Jesus is an attempt to show how acts can be
morally acceptable even if they go against the so-called moral laws. Jesus's act is morally
acceptable despite going against the Jewish law -because he acted to bring about the most
love.
2.4 Utilitarianism
Found in the writings of two English philosophers, Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832) and John
Stuart Mill (1806-1873), this ethical doctrine states that the rightness or wrongness of actions is
determined by the goodness and badness of their consequences. It claims that there is one and
only one moral principle-that is, the principle of utility formulated by Mill: "Actions are good
insofar as they tend to promote happiness, bad as they tend to produce unhappiness" (Pahl:
20-21; Mill 1961). How are we to determine, it may be asked, whether an action tends to
promote happiness or tends to produce pain? By means of its consequences or results rather
than by means of some features of the action itself. The utility or usefulness of an action is
happiness: An action is good (right) insofar as it produces the greatest happiness for the
greatest number of people; bad (wrong) insofar as it produces more harm than benefit for the
greatest number of individuals (Pahl 21-23; Albert and others 1984:219-238). Faced with a
moral decision, one should not just consider one's happiness or benefit, or the happiness of a
particular person or group of persons, but the overall balance of the greatest benefits for the
greatest number of people. It seems that the principle of equity is implied in the alternative
formulation: Equal benefits or happiness for the greatest number of individuals concerned.
The utility or usefulness of an action is determined by the extent to which it promotes happiness
rather than its reverse. No action seems to be either intrinsically right or intrinsically wrong; nor
does the goodness or badness of an act depend upon the motive, intention, or past action of the
doer. Consequences effects, results, and outcomes are most important. Bearing the principle in
mind, we should consider the possible effects of each action or moral decision. We ought to
choose the action (among many other possible ones) that produces the most benefits (comfort
or happiness) at the least cost of pain or unhappiness. Some unhappiness may possibly result
from the action we take, but what matters is the greatest possible balance of happiness over
unhappiness for all individuals affected. Physicians, for instance, should minimize the cost of
suffering of their patients. Whenever there is a choice between various but equally effective
methods of medical treatment, patients' benefits should be maximized and the costs and risks
minimized. To use an expensive method at the expense of the patient (i.e., for pecuniary
reasons) when an inexpensive one may be sufficient would be rightly regarded as an unethical
practice.
Happiness, for both Bentham and Mill, is an intrinsic good, or something good per se, good for
its own sake. By happiness is meant intended pleasure and the absence of pain; by
unhappiness, pain, the privation of pleasure. Whereas Bentham suggested a "calculus of pleas-
Bentham and Mill, bent on getting rid of any strain of individualism and subjectivism, gave an
alternative formulation of the utilitarian utility principle, known as the principle of the greatest.
Likewise, a doctor who performs his/her job out of the mere desire to do so, or inclines towards
it rather than something else, is not acting morally or doing a moral act. It is only when a doctor
recognizes the duty to cure a patient that he/she is genuinely a moral person, acting morally,
and doing a distinctively moral act. Duty in this context is that which an individual ought to do,
despite the inclination to do otherwise. Hence, doing one's duty is doing what one is obliged to
do. That is why duty is also known as obligation.
Kant maintains that one acts morally (1.e.. performs a moral act) if and only if one does
whatever one is obliged to do. But what is that act which an individual is obliged to do? It is one
that is performed or done from a sense of duty or obligation. Thus, what makes an act
moral is its being done out of duty as distinguished from acts done for other reasons. Anyone,
for example, who does something merely because one feels like doing it (e.g, out of inclination)
is not acting morally, is not a moral person, nor is he/she performing a moral act.
3.1.2 Categorical imperative. Kant's categorical imperative mandates an action without any
conditions whatsoever, and without regard to the consequences that such an action may yield
It is a command or maxim that joins a person to do such and such an act without qualification; it
thus lays down a universal rule which, if followed, will ensure that the person is acting from a
sense of duty. Therefore, such an act or moral decision is morally legitimate and just. A
categorical imperative is distinguished from a hypothetical imperative, which is a command with
a corresponding condition or limitation. It is a directive to the effect that if you wish to achieve
such and such an end, you must act in such and such a manner. Kant says that a hypothetical
imperative is concerned with prudential action, which is performed from a sense of prudence.
Another formulation is: (2) "Always act so as to treat humanity, either yourself or others, as an
end and never as only a means. This is Kant's principle of justice, which has important
consequences lor democracy. This is interpreted to mean that no individual should be
discriminated against before the law. It is another way of stating Confucius's Chung: "Do unto
others what you wish yourself," or as the Filipinos put it: "Gawin mo sa iyong kapwa ang nais
mong gawin nila sa iyo. " In your medical practice, for example, would you wish yourself to be
treated as efficiently and expediently as you should be treating a patient under your care? Or,
could you care less about how you should be treated by your own physician when you yourself
get sick? One can readily discern here the humane element of the golden rule as it is applied in
the medical context. Let's go back to Kant. Every individual must be counted as being of equal
value. Irrespective of one's gender, race, creed, social or financial status, no one should be
discriminated against. Everyone must be treated as equally as all others, be it in the legal or
moral realm of life. Rationality, in Kant's view, confers upon every person an intrinsic worth and
human dignity. very human being, therefore, because he/she is a rational creature, has an
inherent value and dignity which is not determined by one's profession, upbringing, or financial
capability: This explains why Kant holds that no one should be treated as only a means but
always as an end. In this light, seduction, abduction, exploitation, oppression, or kidnapping with
ransom are all acts whereby others are used as means for purely selfish ends, Rape is another
instance in which the victim is treated simply as a means for the sexual satisfaction of the rapist
be it a male or a female). And prostitution best exemplifies what Kant, in the second formulation
of the categorical imperative, means by treating ourselves as only a means rather as an end.
For a prostitute
Another formulation is: (2) "Always act so as to treat humanly, either yourself or others, as an
end and never as only a means." This is Kant's principle of justice, which has important
consequences for democracy. This is interpreted to mean that no individual should be
discriminated against before the law. It is another way of stating Confucius's Chung: "Do unto
others what you wish yourself," or as the Filipinos put it: "Gawin mo sa iyong kapwa ang nais
mong gawin nila sa iyo." In your medical practice, for example, would you wish yourself to be
treated as efficiently and expediently as you should be treating a patient under your care? Or,
could you care less about how....
Let's go back to Kant. Every individual must be counted as being of equal value. Irrespective of
one's gender, race, creed, social or financial status, no one should be discriminated against.
Everyone must be treated as equally as all others, be it in the legal or moral realm of life.
Rationality, in Kant's view, confers upon every person an intrinsic worth and human dignity.
Every human being, therefore, because he/she is a rational creature, has an inherent value and
dignity which is not determined by one's profession, upbringing, or financial capability: This
explains why Kant holds that no one should be treated as only a means but always as an end.
3.1.5 Autonomous, self-regulating will. Kant's concept of the will as autonomous and sell-
regulating has contributed a great deal to our understanding of autonomy as freedom of action
(Munson 1979). Autonomy means governing, regulating, restraining oneself, including one's
own choices or courses of action, in accord with moral principles which are one's own and which
are binding on everyone (i.e., universalizable). When we therefore say that an individual has
an autonomous, self-regulating will, we refer to his/her independence, self-reliance, and self-
contained capacity to make moral decisions by and for herself/himself. This means that the
reasons and justifications for one's decisions are one's own. To respect an autonomous agent,
therefore, is to recognize one's own considered value judgment, even if the latter is believed to
be mistaken or incorrect. To respect one's….
3.1.4 Two types of duties. Kant makes a distinction between two types of duties: the perfect
and imperfect (Munson 1979; Palht 31-32). The former is one which we must always observe,
irrespective of time and place or circumstances. That I should not harm or inflict injury upon
others is a perfect duty. The latter is one which we must observe only on some occasions. That
I should show love and compassion occasionally to others, based on my own choice, is an
imperfect duty. You will observe that the categorical imperative according to Kant, is the voice of
duty, the sense of oughtness; it is a priori in so far as it is derived from reason itself. This voice
of duty through the categorical imperative is the only thing in the calm of morals that is definite
in a relative and changing world.
Specifically for Kant, however, respecting autonomy is bound to his notion that every person
has worth and dignity, precisely because persons are ends in themselves and are capable of
making their own moral decisions. They are not to be treated merely as means. It goes
without saying then that to treat an individual merely as a means is an infraction of Kant's
concept of autonomy, because one is being treated in a way one does not want to be. Not to
respect an autonomous agent is either to reject that person's own judgment or to deny him the
freedom to choose and act on that judgment. For Kant, mutual respect for autonomy between
persons in moral relation is the basis of justice; its violation would be a form of injustice.
Third, an action is right and legitimate insofar as it satisfies the categorical imperative. Good
results never make an action morally right. The welfare of the great majority of people at large
may not justify the harm, deception, or injustice done or imposed upon an individual just
because he is poor, a criminal, or a handicapped person.
In the light of these problems, Ross has recognized that there are exceptions for every rule, and
in some situations the latter must be set aside. Absolute rules are often insensitive to the
consequences of an act; at times, not only are they in conflict with one another but they are also
so inflexible that they become irrelevant to ever-changing situations. "Always tell the truth." But
suppose the truth kills the patient, or at least hastens his death?
Sir David Ross (as his colleagues in the academe often call him) offers us two principles by
which to resolve cases of conflicting duties. First, act in accordance with the stronger, more
stringent or more severe prima facie duty. Second, act in accordance with the prima facie duty,
which has a greater balance of rightness over wrongness compared to other prima facie duties.
How am I to determine my actual duty in a given situation when there are conflicting prima facie
duties? If a terminally ill patient asks "Am I going to die?" I have a prima facie duty to tell him the
truth. But I also have a prima faci duty to give him comfort, peace of mind and to spare him from
needless suffering.
Ross holds that (a) one and only one of these two prima lacie duties is my actual duty; (b) I
know cach of them to be a prima lacie duty; and (c) I can have only an opinion (a personal
conviction or perception to the best of my knowledge) about which is "more of a duty" (more
crucial, more serious) and therefore my actual duty. So, if I can save a person from killing
himself by lying to him, then my prima facie duty to lie in order to save him is my actual duty; my
prima facie duty to lie is more stringent than my prima facie duty to tell him the truth and allow
him to kill himself.
Two conflicting duties. For Ross, we have to rely on our moral intuitions (hence, his view is
also known as intuitionism) as the ultimate guide in particular cases. What to do then in such a
situation would be: (1) Learn and discern the facts in the case; (2) Consider the possible
consequences of our actions; (3) Reflect on our prima facie duties; then (4) Decide on the best
course of action under the circumstances.
Ross has listed down seven types of prima facie duties: (1) duty of fidelity, (2) the duty of
reparation, (3) the duty of gratitude, (4) the duty of justice, (5) the duty of beneficence, (6) the
duty of self-improvement, and (7) the duty of non-maleficence (i.e., non-infliction
of harm). Duty of fidelity. We should be faith full to our duties, obligations, vows, or pledges; this
likewise refers to one's loyalty to a worthy cause, telling the truth as the situation demands it,
keeping actual and implicit promises, and not representing fiction as truth. Treachery, deception,
hypocrisy, trickery, double-dealing, insincerity, betrayal, lying, duplicity, cunning or craftiness are
infractions against the duty of fidelity.
Duty of reparation. A Filipino saying underscores the great significance of this duty: "Kung
nakagawa ka ng masama, gumawa ka naman g mabuti. " So we have a duty to make amends
lor injury that we have inflicted on others, This is an act of making amends, righting the wrongs
we have done to others. Asking for the other person's forgiveness is insufficient. We have to do
that person good to atone for our wrongdoing. It is casy to say "I am sorry," or "Please, forgive
me for what I've done." This duty lurther enjoins us to do good to make up for or repair the
damage done; hence it is also knownas the duty of compensation. You should not only say "I'm
really……. (Way sumpay)
Duty of gratitude. We have a duty to appreciate and recognize the services others have done
for us, which may be either a favor, kindness, good fortune, a great help., or saving one's life.
The cultural grip of one's duty of gratitude to one's parents among Fillpinos is very strong. In
fact, this is an essential element of their value system, their philosophy of life, by which they
gauge the rightness or wrongness of their moral decisions.
Duty of beneficence. This type of duty enjoins us not only to bring about what is good for
others but also to help them better their conditions with respect to virtue, intelligence, or comfort.
We should contribute in whatever small way we can to their health and well- being. Our duty to
confer benefits and to prevent and remove harm is important in biomedical and behavioral
contexts. Equally important is the duty to balance the good that our decision may yield against
the harm that may result from doing or not doing what we honestly believe to be beneficial to the
patient. In short, this duty requires the provision of benefits and balancing of benefits and harm
for all people concerned in a given circumstance.
Duty of nonmaleficence. Ross views "not injuring others" as synonymous with nonmaleficence
(Bcauchamp and Childress: 97-131). We ought to avoid inflicting evil, injury or harm upon others
as we would avoid doing so to ourselves. We ought to prevent evil or harm, which encompasses
pain, suffering, disability, and death. For instance, we have a duty not to push someone who
cannot swim into deep water. Culpable negligence, which includes the failure to guard against
risks of harm to others and to oneself, is an infraction of this duty. A physician who assumes the
treatment and care of a patient, yet lacks the qualifications of his profession, and does not
possess the skill, care, and diligence required for treating such a patient, would actually be
exposing this patient to danger.
3.3 Rawls's Theory of Justice
In his book entitled A Theory of Justice (1971), John Rawls, a noted Harvard philosopher, has
attempted a brilliant synthesis of the strengths of utilitarianism and of the deontological views of
Kant and Ross. While avoiding the apparent lack of justice in utilitarianism, he has built on both
Kant's and Ross's fundamental notion of the ultimate dignity of human beings his concept of
social morality, which serves as the basis of social justice.
3.3.1 Theory of justice. Every individual is inviolable. This inviolability, which is founded on
justice, is so sacrosanct that not even the general welfare of society can override and
supersede it (Rawls 1971; Albert and others: 364-381; Munson 1979; Pahl: 43- 48;
Beauchamps and Walters 1978:44-46). The greater good to be shared by all members, for
example, should not be used to justify the loss of freedom of others. Or the larger sum of
advantages which is Supposedly to be enjoyed by the many should not outweigh the sacrifices
or inconveniences to be imposed on a few. In other words, one may not exploit or oppress one
individual or a particular group of citizens in the name of modernism and industrial progress.
Another feature of Rawls's concept of justice is that an erroneous theory is tolerable in the
absence of a good one. As much as possible, when given two erroneous laws, one should
choose the better and the less erroneous one. An act of injustice, for instance, can be tolerated
if and only if it is necessary to avoid an even greater act of injustice. It must be borne in mind
though, that in the case of a tolerable erroneous theory it is the only one available at hand, so
reason dictates that it must be carried out for the sake of those who are supposedly benefited or
affected by it. It's like saying a wrong or an unjust law is better than no law at all. St. Thomas
Aquinas, in his political theory, seems .......
A third aspect of Rawls's concept of justice is: Individual liberties should be restricted in order to
maintain equality of opportunity. Liberties of equal citizenship are of paramount importance in a
Just society. Individual rights are not subject to political bargaining or compromise. Walang
palakasan. Hence, restrictions of individual liberties serve as safeguards against abuses and
misuses of one's freedom against others. Pagbibigayan ang kailangan. Walang lamangan.
Without constraints, some over-ambitious people may use their power, money, and influence
against their fellowmen. Restrictions, therefore, are intended not to destroy but to preserve
freedom; and amidst these restrictions, equality of opportunity among the citizens to develop
themselves will best be served.
3.3.2 Principles of justice. Rawls speaks ofa two-fold principle of justice: First, equal access
to the basic human rights and liberties (Pahl: 44-46). This principle defines and secures
equal liberties of citizenship. Our basic rights and liberties include the right to vote and to be
eligible for public office, freedom of speech and peaceable assembly, liberty of conscience,
freedom of thought, right of ownership (that is, freedom to hold property), and freedom from
arbitrary arrest and seizure as defined by the concept of the rule of law, and not of man. As it
appears, the first principle guarantees a system of equal rights and liberties for every citizen; it
prohibits the
bartering away of liberty for social or monetary considerations. No citizen, for example, may sell
his/her right to vote.
The second principle is: Fair cquality of opportunity and the equal distribution of socio-
economic inequalities. As much as the availability of resources will allow, everyone should be
given an opportunity for self-development or to receive medical treatment. This principle deals
more with the distribution of social goods and/ or medical resources than with liberty. Rawls
admits that some individuals are born more affluent than others, and they enjoy advantageous
social positions. Such socio-economic differences are neither just nor unjust per se. He
maintains, however, that in a just society, such differences are tolerable only when they can be
shown to benefit everyone, including those who have the fewest advantages.
3.3.3 Justice in human relations. Aware of the need for principles that bind and guide
individuals in making moral decisions, Rawls cites four.types of duties: (1) fairness in our
dealings with others, (2) fidelity, (3) respect for persons, and (4) beneficence. In addition,
he also mentions what he calls "natural duties": (1) the duty of justice, (2) the duty of helping
others in need or in jeopardy, (3) the duty not to harm or injure others, and (4) the duty to keep
our promises.
In Aquinas's view, the source of the moral law is reason it (Aquinas: 94; Pegis 1915; Aquinas
1923-1929). The latter directs towards the good as the goal of our action, and that good is
discoverable within our nature. In its operation, reason recognizes the basic principles "Do
good, avoid evil." He used the term synderesis to describe inherent capacity of every individual,
lettered or unlettered, to distinguish the good from the bad. This is the basis of Aquinas
argument that certain moral principles are objective and can be found in the nature of things
through reason and reflection.
3.4.1 Voice of right reason or voice of conscience. Interpreters of St. Thomas's moral
doctrine regard right reason or the voice of reason as the moral norm, insofar as an individual's
natural capacity to determine what is right from what is wrong (synderesis) is no less than the
manifestation of the moral law. In short, the moral law is the dictate of the voice of reason; and
this dictate is expressed in the moral principle "The good must be done, and evil, avoided"
(Aquinas: 94; Stumpf: 198-200; Reyes: 51-53). How are we to determine whether we are acting
rightly or wrongly? We know we are acting rightly if we heed or follow the voice of reason; we
know we are acting wrongly if we act against it. Other Thomists would view the voice of reason
as the voice of conscience.
3.4.2 Man's threefold natural inclination. What is theg ood? St. Thomas asserts that human
good is that which is suitable to or proper for human nature. Thus, whenever an act is suitable
to human nature as such (as being endowed with reason and free will), then it is good and it
must be done; whenever it is not proper for human nature, however, then it is evil and it must be
avoided. (You will notice how it is again related to the voice of reason, as mentioned earlier.) In
other words, how does one know that a particular act is or is not suitable to human nature as
such? By means of whether one is following and obeying the voice of reason (conscience) or
acting contrary to it. Hence, it is for this reason, too, that other Thomists human nature as the
proximate norm of morality.
In St. Thomas's view, the good is built into human nature, and it is that to which we are directed
by our natural inclinations as both physical and rational creatures (Munson 1979; Pahl: 50-51;
Stump: 198-199). We have three natural inclinations: (1) sell-preservation, (2) just dealings with
others, and (3) propagation of our species. We are naturally inclined to preserve our life. Self-
destruction, firstly, is unnatural as far as St. Thomas is concerned. This natural inclination urges
us to care for our health, not to kill ourselves or put ourselves in danger. Thus, any act that
violates this basic inclination is wrong; it contradicts human nature as the Creator intended to
be.
3.4.3 Three determinants of moral action. On St. Thomas's ethical principles, there are three
factors which determine the rightness or wrongness of a concrete individual human act: (1) the
object, (2) the circumstances, and (3) the end of the agent (Pegis 1945; Bittle: 83-90; Reyes:
149-151). For a given act to be truly morally good, it must be good in all its three elements. A
defect in any of these three determinants will make an act morally wrong.
The Object. That which the will intends directly and primarily is the object of the moral act; it
may be either a thing (for example, money) or an action (such as surgical operation). The very
act of operating on a patient for a particular disease, say, a tumor or cyst, is directly and
primarily intended by the physician. The circumstance and the end are also intended, but not as
directly and primarily as the object. Another example is the physician's act of injecting a drug
into an ailing patient in which case the act is primarily intended by the doctor. The physician
here is moved to action specifically and primarily by the object rather than by the circumstances
of the act or the end of the agent.
The Circumstances. There are conditions which, when superadded to the nature of the moral
act, will affect its morality. They are called the circumstances. "Will affect its morality" means
that a given circumstance or a set of circumstances will either mitigate or aggravate the
goodness or badness of a particular act; an act whose object is morally good may further be
judged as good because of some circumstance; likewise, an act whose object is morally wrong
may further be judged as wrong because of some circumstance. Let us examine the seven
circumstances cited by St. Thomas.
Who? This circumstance has something to do with the special quality, prestige, rank, or
excellence of the person involved in the moral act. It is morally bad to rape a woman but even
worse to rape one's own daughter. The worst is to rape one's own grand daughter.The act of a
physician who treats a hospital patient entrusted to him is morally good, but that of one who
extends medical assistance to an indigent unable to afford confinement is even better and more
commendable. To mistreat one's own patient is bad in itself, but to mistreat him, and take
advantage of his ignorance, is even worse.
What? This circumstance refers to the quantity or quality of the moral object. The very act of
surgical operation on a sick person who needs it is good in itself but to perform the act as
excellently as a skilled surgeon is capable of heightens the goodness of the said action. The
former may be done simply as a daily routinely function of a resident surgeon on duty, whereas
the latter is performed with a sense of service, dedication, and concern for the well-being of the
patient, irrespective of his socio-economic status in life. Let's consider
Where This circumstance denotes the place where the act Occurs, lt makes a big difference, for
example, when a doctor extends medica assistance to someone brought to the emergency
room for stab wounds, and when a doctor selflessly goes out of his way to take the wounded
victim to his clinic or to a nearby hospital. The former a perfunctory role, while the latter is the
act of a "Good Samaritan. lo abuse a patient maliciously is a corrupt medical practice, but to
assault her or him sexually in one's own clinic is even more heinous and outrageous. It likewise
makes a difference if an assassin kills his victim in a restaurant, or inside a church while mass is
being said.
By what means? This refers to the means used in carrying out the act. To take advantage of
one's weakness is bad enough; but to deceive and seduce someone in order to take advantage
of that person makes matters much worse. Let s take another example: To extend medical help
to an indigent patient is good; but to give him/her the money needed for his/her medication
makes the goodness of the act much greater. Carnapping, on the other hand, is in itself bad; but
to use the proceeds from the sale of the carnapped vehicle to hire an assassin to kill the car's
owner makes the act even more horrendous and inhuman.
Why? The end or purpose is considered as a Circumstance adlecting the goodness or badness
of the action, If the act itself is bad and is still carried out with a bad purpose, the said act
becomes much worse. To seduce a destitute girl is in itself bad; but to do so with the intenton of
making her one's querida or number two makes the act of seduction doubly, evil, so to speak.
On the other hand, helping this girl to finish a vocational course is in itself good; and doing so
with the intent of employing her later in one's garment factory, enabling her to help her own
family, makes the act even "more" legitimate and righteous.
How? This circumstance indicates the manner in which the action is done. When facing death
through starvation, for example, the famished or starving individual may take surplus goods
from the famis another in order to avoid death. In a case of extreme necessity, the another
ordinary right to private property no longer holds. Similarly, in the case of unjust aggression, it is
legitimate to kill the aggressor who unjustly attacks and attempts to kill another person. It makes
a difference whether a resident physician has been inadvertently remiss in his hospital duties
due to a hectic schedule or other unforeseen causes, or he has been advertently remiss in bad
faith due to personal indifference to his medical function. Has he committed an error in
When? This circumstance refers to the time clement involved in the performance of an action,
not only with regard to quantity but to quality as well. To commit rape under the cover of
darkness is even worse than when it is done in broad daylight. To abuse one's patient under
sedation is much worse than mere seduction. It makes a difference whether one commits a
crime in the church when the mass is being said or when there is no mass at all.
8.4.4 The double effect principle. The principle applies to a situation in which a good effect
and an evil effect will result from good cause (Pahl: 51-52; Bittle: 44-50; Reyes: 151-155;
Shannon 98/ 67). We may have a good action which will yield two effects, a good one and an
evil one, How are we to resolve this question According to the principle, under certain
conditions, some evil etfect voluntary in cause-may be permitted to occur The classic example
1.The action directly intended must be good in itscll, or at lcast morally indifferent. First of all, thc
moral action must be in tself good, otherwise it is evil at the very outset. In the case cited above,
the surgical operation on the woman's uterus is good per se because of the condition
mentioned. 2. The good effect must follow from the action at least as immediately as the evil
effect; or the evil effect may follow from the good effect. In other words, either both the good 3.
The foreseen evil effect may not be intended or approved. but merely permitted to occur In other
words, the killing of the unborn child must not be directly intended, but considered only as
indirectly intended and as the secondary effect of the operation. Ifit is directly intended, then it
becomes the direct and primary object of the operation, and hence it is evil. But Since it is only
indirectly intended, it becomes the secondary object of the operation, and hence it is morally
permissible. 4. There must be proportionate and sufficient reason for allowing the evil effect to
occur while performing the action at stake.
3.4.5 The principle of totality. An individual has the right to cut oft, mutilate, or remove any
defective or worn-out non-functioning part of his body; to dispose of his organs or to destroy l
their capacity to function "only insofar as the general well-being of the whole body requires it"
(Pahl: 52). Under natural law ethics, we have a natural obligation not only to preserve our lives,
but also to preserve the integrity of our bodies. Accordingly, a diseased organ may be
amputated or excised for the good of the whole organism. A gangrenous leg or arm or any other
organ that is beyond cure and threatens the whole organism may be mutilated to save the
person life. Healthy organs, however, may not be cut off, as this would weaken a person's
health. The principle of stewardship declares that human life comes from God, and no individual
is the master of his/her own body. Humans are only mere stewards or caretakers, with the
responsibility of protecting and cultivating spiritual and bodily functions. We are obliged to take
good care of ourselves, to maintain a sound mind and body, band to safeguard our dignity.
The principle of the inviolability of life states that life is God's and has been loaned to us;
hence, it is inviolable and sacred. It is only God who has complete control and dominion over
life; our duty is to take care of it until God takes it back from us. The principle of sexuality and
procreation underscores a twofold purpose of sexual union: (1) the procreation and nurturing of
children: band (2) the expression of loving union and companionship. Both purposes must be
achieved only within the conjugal bond. Human procreation requires responsible collaboration
on the part of the spouses with the fruitful love of God; the gift of human life must be actualized
in marriage through the specific and exclusive acts of husband and wife, in accordance with the
laws inscribed in their persons and in their union.
Our point of departure in this chapter is Mencius's concept of human-heartedness or the feeling
of helpfulness and commiseration. “All men," explains Mencius, "have a mind which cannot bear
to see the suffering of others.... If now men suddenly see a child about to fall into a well, they
will without exception experience a feeling of alarm and distress" (Fung Yu Lan: 69-70). What
Mencius is telling us here refers to what psychologists claim lies deep within the human psyche-
it is the desire to help others, the feeling of benevolence or good will, a sense of compassion
with the desire to help, to be of service, to give assistance whenever it is needed.
The biblical story of the Good Samaritan best exemplifies and supports this dimension of human
nature. For Mencius, this sense of helpfulness or human-heartedness consists in loving others.
We desire to help because we love others. Christians refer to this as a sense of charity,
kindness, or benevolence, which reflects what we earlier considered to be the principle of
benevolence and/or non-maleficence.
On the other hand, the principle of autonomy-otherwise known as the right of self-determination
—affirms that an individual is autonomous. Hence he has the right to act and decide by and for
himself. He can choose who he wishes to be, and take responsibility for such a choice. It seems
that respect for an individual's autonomy and right of self-determination presupposes
noninterference and nonintervention with his choice or plan of action and moral decision.
Generally speaking, however, paternalism involves some sort of interference with the
individual's freedom of action. This is the moral issue of paternalism
1.With regard to the recipient's welfare, paternalism may be either pure or impure (Childress
1982; Shannon 1987:13- 14,16). Pure paternalism justifies intervention into a life for the sole
welfare of that person. For example, a child is told by his parents to eat vegetables because it
good for his health. Impure paternalism, on the other hand justifies interference with another
person not only for that person's welfare but also for the welfare of another. Some argue, for
example, that the parent of a Jehovah's Witness should have a blood transfusion not only for
his/her own good but also for the good of his/her children (i.e., "alang alang man lamang sa
iyong mga anak na maiiwan kung ikaw ay mamamatay").
2. With regard to the recipient's defect and safety, paternalism may be either restricted or
extended. Restricted paternalism supports intervention which overrides an individual's action
because of some defect or weakness in that individual. One may prohibit a child from doing
something, for example, because of chronological or psychological incompetence (hence the
Filipino will say, "Anak, huwag mong gawin iyan, hindi mo pa kaya"). Extended paternalism, on
the contrary, is one in which an individual is restrained from doing something because it is too
risky or dangerous. For instance, riding motorcycles without wearing helmets is not encouraged
(i.e., it is unlawful) because of the imminent danger it incurs. Hence, the Filipino will say,
“Huwag kang magbibisikleta sa kalye, anak, mababangga ka ng mga sasakyan."
3. With regard to the promotion of good and prevention of harm, paternalism may be either
positive or negative. An example of the former is when a patient is forced into a rehabilitation
program to promote his/her own good; an example of the latter is when cigarettes or weapons
are taken away from an individual to prevent that individual from any harm or violence. (Hence,
the Filipino will say “Kaya dinala ka namin dito sa rehabilitation center, anak, para magamot at
pagkatapos ay magbagong buhay ka na sana" as an indication of positive paternalism and
“Itinapon ko na ang lahat ng iyong biniling sigarilyo sa hangarin kong hahaba pa ang iyong
buhay" as an indication of negative paternalism.)
4. With regard to the patient's sense of values, paternalism may be either soft or hard. In a soft
paternalistic act, the patient's values are used to justify the intervention with his possible action
or decision. An unconscious or comatose patient, for example, is usually detached from life-
support machinesbbecause he/she earlier signified such preference if ever he/shebwould be put
in such a situation. (Hence, a Filipino wouldbsay "Kapag ako'y nag-aagaw buhay na, huwag na
ninyo akong ikabit sa artificial respirator."
In hard paternalism, on the other hand, the patient'svalues are not the ones used to justify a
paternalistic act. For example, someone who supposedly knows what is good for a patient
directs the latter with regard to what is to be done, or directs someone else to do this for the
patient. Hence the Filipino physician would tell a patient, “Mas mabuti para sa iyo kung
magpaopera ka na ngayon,” or a husband would tell his wife's attendant physician: “Doc, mabuti
pa kaya'y gawin nang Caesarean ang panganganak ng misis ko."
5. With regard to the recipient of the benefit, paternalism may be either direct or indirect
(Childress: 14). In the case of the former, the individual who should receive the supposed
benefit is the one whose values are overridden or disregarded for his own good. The
motorcyclist, for example, who is forced by law to wear the helmet is the one who will benefit in
case of an accident. In the case of indirect paternalism, a particular individual will be benefited,
if one person is restrained from doing something. A good example is child abuse, in which
parents are restrained by law in some way to protect the child.
Considering Kant's concept of a person as a rational and autonomous agent, it seems that he
might be against paternalism. paternalistic act may be taken as an interference with an
individual's autonomy and sell-regulating will. It can be argued, however, that in the medical
context, Kant's position may become untenable if and when an individual lapses into
unconsciousness, in which case the attending physician must act in order to save the patient's
life as much as possible. For the physician to simply stand by and watch the unconscious
patient die without doing anything is somewhat contrary to the dictates of right reason. Moreover
it will be in keeping with
Kant's precept of not treating any person as a means but always as an end, if the attending
physician performs a paternalistic act for and on behalf of the unconscious patient.
Rawls's theory of social and political morality is compatible with state paternalism. Society
might decide to institute a set of medical practices and policies that would promote common
interests and general welfare. With regard to Ross's moral principles, on the other hand, each
person has a moral right to be treated as an autonomous agent who has to make decisions by
and for oneself. It is possible to imagine, however, certain circumstances in which intervention
or interference with an individual's autonomy would be legitimate. As an example, a person who
might be mentally Incompetent to make a decision would need paternalistic assistance.
Ulitarianism endorses paternalism insofar as state laws and policies are justified by the
principle of utility. Restricted individual liberty may promote the greatest benefits for the greatest
number For the utilitarian, individual freedom has no absolute value, it can be restrained or
restricted for the sake of the many.
28 Truth-telling
When a patient agrees to place himself under the care of a doctor by virtue of the fact that the
former consults the latter for medical care, the power of the physician over the patient cannot be
absolute; that is, the patient does not become a helpless slave or creature to the physician.
Thus, the physician-patient relationship involves the moral issue of truth-telling and
confidentiality Is it justifiable for a doctor to deceive his/her patient How much autonomy must
be given up by the patient? What are the limits of paternalism that can be legitimately exercised
by the doctor?
Two approaches to the truth-telling issue maybe cited: the person-centered and the
problem-centered. The former lends Importance to the patient as a person, while the latter
stresses the nature of the problem or the degree and severity of the patient's illness (Fletcher
1954). In other words, the person-oriented approach considers the patient as a person with a
problem, but not as a problem
Himself/herself. The patient is a person with feelings of hope and despair, with purpose and
defeat. As such, one has the right to know the nature of one's disease and the physician is
morally obligated to respect that right. The physician owes the patient the truth, just as the latter
owes the doctor skill and technical powers. Moreover, caring for a person is a moral relationship
in which the physician's attitude should be an utmost concern for the patient.
The problem-fomented approach, on the other hand, considers the patient's problem, illness,
or condition. The physician may not tell the truth when it is in the best interest of the patient;
after all the physician is fallible and makes mistakes. Thus, if only for the best interest of the
patient's failing or worsening condition, the physician may withhold the truth from the patient.
This approach is usually appealed to by those who endorse the legitimacy of the use of
placebos (Latin placebo, I shall please') in medical therapy. Patients who are seriously ill will
oftentimes show improvement when they are given placebos for treatment. This can happen
even when the medication is irrelevant to their condition.
Joseph Fletcher compares the twofold approach to truth-telling with what Martin Buber defines
as two types of relationship: the 1 it and the I-thou (Fletcher 1954). The "I-it" relationship
describes a person's relationship with things, objects, or "its"; hence, an it or man-object,
subject-object relationship, This kind of relationship is determined by our attitude to what is
other than Ourselves. My relationships with my books, cars, eyeglasses, shoes clothes, and
other possessions typify the "I-it" or subject-objectrelationship. Insofar as these things are my
possessions or personal
I-thou relationship, on the other hand, delineates our relationship with Other persons, like
ourselves, other subjects, 1's, thou's or you's; hence, "I-thou," or "I-I," subject-subject, person-
person relationships. Insofar as the other person is a fellow human being, a thou or someone
with integrity and a moral quality of his/her own, I cannot manipulate or use him/her without
degrading or dehumanizing him/her at the same time. For persons, like myself, are not things or
objects which are usable and manipulable by other persons.
In the medical context, the physician-patient relationship exemplifies an -thou" or person-
person relationship, inasmuch as both are persons, both are "I's." This type of relationship is a
moral experience because persons can respond, i.e., they are responsible; unlike things they
can say "yes" or "no"; they can make decisions. In short, they have sights, especially the right to
say "yes" or "no" in response to any course of action: the right to self-determination, the right to
be themselves, to choose to be a "you" rather than an "it." In FletcherS view, if a patient simply
becomes an object of medical treatment, who submits himself to a physician, without any
knowledge of his condition and its prognosis, that patient has ceased to be a "thou and has
become an "it." He is being used and manipulated as If he were a thing or object; he is no
longer accredited as a person, and hence is deprived of personal responsibility and moral
status.
(2) AS patients, We have entrusted to the physician any knowledge he has about Ourselves, so
the facts (i.e., his findings) are ours and not his-hence to deny them to us is to steal from us;
(3) The highest conception of the physician-patient relationship is a personalistic one which is
based on mutual confidence and respect for each other's rights; and
(4) To deny a patient pertinent knowledge about himself, especially in a life-and-death situation,
is to deprive him the ample time to prepare for his own death or to carry out responsibilities that
are based solely on his decisions or actions (Fletcher 1954; Pahl: 217-220).
9.8 Confidentiality
Confidentiality (from the Latin confidene 'to trust) refers here to medical or professional secrecy
in which certain information (1.e., secret finding) is committed to a physician in an official
capacity for the sake of medical assistance (Pahl: 220-221; Walters 1987: 169- 175). This is in
conjunction with one provision of the Hippocratic Oath: "Whatever I see or hear, professionally
or privately, which ought not to be divulged, I will keep secret and tell no one." The practical
function of confidentiality in a physician-patient relationship underscores the confidence and
trust that the patient has for the physician. With this feeling of confidence, the patient is not
reluctant but cooperative in giving personal information to the physician. The moral issue of
confidentiality arises if and when there is a conflict between individual interest (i.e., patient's
interest) and the interest of society (i.c., the common good). The physician is placed in the
middle of a conflict between the interest of the individual and the interest of society. Doctors, for
example, are required by law to reveal certain information about their patients. This legal
obligation enjoins them to report the names of patients who are carriers of communicable
diseases (e.g., AIDS, syphilis, T.B.) to health departments. If the physician acts to protect the
patient's trust, then he is acting contrary to law; if he acts in accordance with the law, he violates
the confidence of his patient. It is argued, however, that confidentiality is not absolute. Under
certain conditions, it is better to violate it than to preserve it. Confidentiality can be violated if it is
necessary to produce conditions which will bring about happiness and well-being. Let us
consider these instances: If someone's life is in great danger, then confidentiality loses its
binding power Or, if the testimony of a physician is nervous to help establish the innocence of
someone who is being tried for the crime he did not commit, then charity demands that the
innocent party be protected and the secret be divulged. Physicians, it must oe
Under the moral principles of situationism, one should consider the circumstances prevailing
in a particular situation. Whatever these circumstances are, however, one should make one's
decision in the name of agapeic love or concern for the welfare of the patient. Would it do the
patient more good than harm? Then, the expediency of the given situation should be one's
guide in making a decision.
The Moral Issue of Patients' Rights
Rights are necessary because every individual lives in a community of persons in relation. "No
man is an island," so the saying goes (Merton 1967: 9-17). Man is a being-with-others in the
world. For this reason, human life is more meaningful and worth living only in the presence and
help of others, in communion with others, and for the benefit of others. This holds true for all
kinds of human relationships, including physician-patient relationships. A patient, like the
physician, is an individual human being endowed with reason and freedom. As such, he/she
enjoys natural and inalienable rights, such as the right to life and the right to privacy, among
others.
Right to informed consent. The patient has the right to receive all necessary information
concerning diagnosis and treatment in order to be able to give consent based on his/her value
system, "Informed consent" refers to the knowledge or information about and the consent to a
particular form of medical treatment, before that treatment is administered. The information
should include the risks and advantages of any medical treatment that concerns the patient.
Right to informed decision. Information and understanding are necessary for genuine
deliberation. The patient cannot make a moral decision unless these two important elements are
present. "Informed decision" refers to the necessary information of and decision on a medical
treatment before the latter is carried out. The patient must be informed about the whole process
and must understand what this information pertains to so that an appropriate moral
decisionmcan be arrived at.
Right to informed choice. "Informed choice” refers to the necessary information a patient
should know about a medical treatment or experiment so that a moral choice can be made. The
patient has the right to be informed about all possible alternative courses of action to be taken,
together with the possible consequences. In reality, however, “informed consent, decision and
choice" go together in moral decision-making. As soon as the patient has been informed about
what the process involves and has understood it, he/ she will either consent to it or will not.
Whichever is the case, a decision is made, and whatever decision arrived at becomes the
patient's moral choice. In short, as the patient consents to undergo treatment, he/she decides
on it, as the patient makes a decision, he/she makes a choice between two or more alternatives.
Thus, the emphasis on informed consent" involves the information and agreement or
disagreement, consent or non-consent; "informed decision," the information and the decision
made; and informed choice," the information and the choice taken from among several
alternatives.
Right to refusal of treatment, In conjunction with the "Statement on a Patient's Bill of Rights"
presented by the American Hospital Association, the patient has the right to refuse treatment to
the extent permitted by law and to be informed of the medical consequences of his action"
(Beauchamp and Walters: 140; Beauchamp and Childress: 82-84). In many instances, a patient
may refuse medical treatment because their religious convictions prohibit them from doing so
(e.g., a patient who is a member of a particular set may refuse to undergo blood transfusion).
Many regard this right
2. Disclosure. This refers to the content of what a patient is told or informed about during the
consent negotiation. The patient must be informed and must understand the information
concerning medical treatment to be undertaken, so that a moral decision can be made. The
disclosure of the information must be conducted in such a way that the patient understands the
whole process and is aware of the possible outcomes of his/her moral choice. Should there be a
language barrier between the physician and the patient, an interpreter might be consulted to
communicate the pertinent information.
3. Comprehension. This refers to whether the information given has been understood. The
disclosure of information is not enough; equally important is the comprehension of that
information. If the patient does not understand what he/she has been told, then information has
not been relayed at all. Health care professionals have a professional language and so they are
expected to translate their jargon so that it will be intelligible to their patients. They must be
sensitive to their patients' needs.
4. Voluntariness. This means that consent must be voluntary. The patient must of his own free
will agree to become a research subject, as the case maybe. He/she must make a choice
without being unduly pressured by anyone else. Being free in making a decision means that the
patient owns the decision, that the decision is the patient's alone, that the patient has chosen
the option based on the information disclosed to him/her.
2. A patient in a moribund condition does not possess the necessary mental or emotional
stability to make an informed choice. A dying patient, or one who lapses into unconsciousness,
becomes mentally incompetent to make a decision. In such a situation, the attending physician
may perform a paternalistic act for the well-being of the patient.
3. Patients' rights are not absolute. Paternalistic concern limits the competent adult patient's
freedom of choice (e.g., refusal of treatment) for his/her own good in order to prevent harm from
befalling that patient. This precept is enshrined in the Hippocratic Oath: "I will apply dietetic
measures for the benefit of the sick according to my ability and judgment; I will keep them from
hain and injustice" (Beauchamp and Walters: 138).
In principle, the parents, immediate relatives, guardians, or next of kin should be informed when
the patient is comatose, blind or illiterate, underage or unable to understand the language of the
physician. In actual experience, however, the expediency of the situation may be such that the
physician, exerting a Solomon-like judgment, may not have time to consult the patient's next of
kin. In emergency situations, for instance, time is of the essence. An instant decision is a matter
of life and death. A physician's delayed action may be fatal to a particular patient
Utilitarianism's principle of utility requires health care professionals to design medical treatment
in a way that minimizes suffering and harm. As far as informed consent is concerned.
utilitarianism does not seem to require it. If more social good is to be gained by making patients
research subjects without receiving their consent, then it is morally legitimate.