10 1 1 739 4536
10 1 1 739 4536
10 1 1 739 4536
Case Histories in Business Ethics reflects upon, illustrates and extends the
role of case histories (summaries of real cases) and case studies (which may
be wholly or partly imaginary stories) in the teaching and studying of busi-
ness ethics.
This volume features contributions from Lord Borrie, Sir Adrian
Cadbury, Jon Entine and John Edmonds. It explores the role of case
histories in developing and generating argument in business ethics, and
shows that both better understanding and better practice in business ethics
require attention to ethical theory as well as to case histories.
Also addressed is the use of case histories in engaging the widest range
of student capacities, affective as well as cognitive, which directly affect
the development of character. The connections between virtue theory and
possible uses for case histories are also explained, as well as the potential
use of new ways of developing case studies, such as through the use of
information technologies, in the acquisition of virtues and transferable
skills.
Introduction 1
CHRIS MEGONE AND SIMON ROBINSON
PART I
Theoretical approaches to business ethics 7
1 Business dilemmas: ethical decision-making in business 9
S I R A D R I A N C A D B U RY
PART II
Topics and case histories 57
3 Shell, Greenpeace and Brent Spar: the politics of dialogue 59
JON ENTINE
PART III
The role of case histories in business ethics 159
10 The use of case histories in business ethics 161
CHRIS MEGONE
Index 175
Contributors
This book is derived in part from a lecture series held at the University of
Leeds in the autumn of 1995 under the auspices of the Centre for Business
and Professional Ethics. Lord (Gordon) Borrie, Sir Adrian Cadbury, John
Edmonds and Elaine Sternberg were amongst the contributors to that series
and we are most grateful to them, both for the original lectures, and for all
the work that they have done since to revise those lectures so as to bring
them up to date for publication now. We are also indebted to Elida Gibbs
plc, Barclays Bank plc and Yorkshire Electricity plc (as it then was) for the
sponsorship which enabled that very successful lecture series to go ahead.
In working on the Nestlé case we have been helped by David Smith at
the Council for Ethics and Economics in America, who has worked very
hard on developing the internet and CD-Rom versions of that case history.
We have been encouraged by several editors at Routledge (now part of
Taylor & Francis), including Stuart Hay, Michelle Gallagher and Gavin
Cullen. But we would especially like to thank Francesca Lumsden for her
energy in seeing the project to a close. Finally, we should like to thank our
families for their support, especially in the final stages of this work.
The authors and publishers would like to thank the following for
granting permission to reproduce material in this work:
The Biologist journal and Martin Angel for the reproduction of Angel,
Martin V. (1995) ‘Brent Spar: no hiding place’, Biologist 42(4) in Chapter 3.
Shell UK Limited for the reproduction of the Brent Spar Timeline in
Appendix 3 of Chapter 3.
Public Concern at Work for the reproduction of Chapter 4 and Chapter 5.
Chapter 4 is a revised version of a document originally published under
the title Whistleblowing to Combat Corruption, PAC/AFF/LMP (2000)1.
Copyright OECD, 2000.
Every effort has been made to contact copyright holders for their
permission to reprint material in this book. The publishers would be
grateful to hear from any copyright holder who is not here acknowledged
and will undertake to rectify any errors or omissions in future editions of
this book.
Chris Megone and Simon Robinson
Leeds, June 2001
Introduction
Chris Megone and Simon Robinson
In the last thirty years there has been a dramatic increase in the study both
of applied ethics quite generally, and of business ethics in particular.
Business ethics is certainly a branch of philosophy even if, as an inter-
disciplinary subject, it may also be seen as a branch of other disciplines
such as business studies or management. Thus this increase has brought a
different sort of student to the study of ethics, often students who are
studying ethics as a small part of a business or management course,
although there have also been some students, usually by far the minority,
who take business ethics courses as part of a philosophy degree. One result
of this growth in students of ethics from a different academic background
has been the introduction of different tools for the study of the subject. As
opposed to simply reading book-length studies of ethics, or learned arti-
cles, students have often been presented with case histories (accounts of
real cases) or case studies (which may be wholly or partly imaginary
stories) as a substantial component of their courses in business ethics.
(Hereafter, case histories alone will be referred to, for brevity.)
One main reason for this has been that students on a management or
business course have not always found it obvious that ethics should be a
required component in their studies. In response to this worry, it has been
thought that case histories can at least demonstrate the way in which
ethical concerns are so often integral to business decisions. At the same
time, the case history has also had a prominent role in other aspects of
business education, so it may have seemed natural to extend its use into
this new area. However, not a great deal of further thought has been given
to exactly how case histories are to play a role in business ethics curricula.
In particular two issues arise. First of all, many business students, once
satisfied that ethics has a role in business, are likely to see a course in
ethics as something that should help their practice, help them to reach
better decisions and conduct themselves better in the business context. So
one question is how, if at all, the use of case histories can contribute to the
achievement of that goal. Second, it is not entirely clear how the study of
ethics through case histories is supposed to be connected to the study
2 Chris Megone and Simon Robinson
been given to this ethical dimension and how the ethical virtues relate to
such decision-making. As indicated, the final chapter brings together
Aristotelian insights on the moral psychology of virtue and the nature of
virtue acquisition so as to explain how case histories can have a role here.
In sum the text will address both the more traditional question of the
relation between case histories and ethical theories, and that of a novel
way in which the study of business ethics can be affective and not merely
cognitive, and show how the use of case histories can be developed to link
these two aspects. The case histories in the text should serve as exemplars
for both cognitive and affective roles. The book also indicates how the
interactive opportunities offered by the CD-Rom and internet website
associated with cases like the Nestlé case may take this approach further.
Notes
1 One reason for finding it odd is that it was not a compartmentalization made
by the great Greek ethicists, Socrates, Plato and Aristotle.
2 Even if it is admitted that there are connections between the three branches of
ethics, a slightly weaker assumption might also be made: namely, that applied
ethics is simply derivative from, or dependent upon, the other branches, so that
students of these other branches can learn nothing from the study of applied
ethics itself. This would leave the challenge as one of having to show how the
study of case histories can have any bearing on the study of normative ethics or
metaethics.
3 E. Sternberg (2000) Just Business: Business Ethics in Action, 2nd edn, Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Part I
Theoretical approaches
to business ethics
Chapter 1
Business dilemmas
Ethical decision-making in business
Sir Adrian Cadbury
that is true!) But the very fact that governments felt that they had to inter-
vene in what was essentially a matter of how far a business should go in
buying business (a question to which we will return to a bit later on) – that
is, I think, something new. Such intervention raises the problem for
governments of trying to define limits on conduct, of settling what is
acceptable and what is not acceptable, in a world where transactions are
moving faster and becoming more complex all the time. It is very difficult
for them to keep up.
Fourth, there are issues raised by deregulation of the utilities, as well as
the increased public expectations of business, and growing media interest.
All of these have pushed the questions of conduct, both company and indi-
vidual, more to the fore. In the face of these levels of concern, there is, I
would suggest, a lack of general agreement as to what the rules of conduct
should be, both for companies and for individuals. On the individual side,
for example, life is very competitive and pay is related to winning. We may
possibly be seeing changing attitudes towards what is right and wrong in
this kind of area. Consider a well-known quote from Ivan Boesky, ‘Greed
is alright, I want you to know that. I think greed is healthy. You can be
greedy and feel good about yourself.’ The interesting thing about that
quote is perhaps not just that he said it, but that he said it at the
commencement address for UCLA, to all those bright new students coming
up to the university, prior to making their way in life. The message they
got was that. That does make one think.
Well, if these are the reasons that have brought corporate governance to
the fore, what should be the determinants of conduct? My object in this
chapter is to look at the ways in which we should set about making those
ethical choices. How are we to come to decisions in business in conditions,
if you like, of ethical uncertainty?
By virtue of being Chairman of the Committee on the Financial Aspects
of Corporate Governance for four years, I had the opportunity to become
involved in matters of corporate conduct, both at the national and the
company level, and both in this country and abroad (where there is very
great interest in these matters). In particular, as a committee we had the
task of drawing-up the Code of Best Practice which we addressed to the
boards of companies in this country and, in the first instance, to those
listed on the London Stock Exchange. One very proper question, therefore,
is how useful are such codes? Does the production of a code of best prac-
tice actually help boards in their task of directing and controlling
companies? And at the company level, what guidance can company codes
give to managers who are faced with decisions which require some degree
of ethical judgement?
The sort of company I always had in my mind was one widely spread
overseas, where the manager in some outpost in the Far East or in Africa
was faced on the spot with a decision which they had to take with nobody
Ethical decision-making in business 11
to turn to. What help were the sort of rules that we drew up within the
company going to be to such a person? Thus my interest lies really in the
interpretation of rules and their practical use as much as in the precise
nature of the rules themselves.
It is worth noting that the majority of business decisions do have an
ethical content. (Incidentally, there has always seemed to me a problem
over how you fit this subject of business ethics into a business course,
because there should not be a separate compartment for an ethics options
that you can take or disregard, treating it as quite unrelated to everything
else that is happening within the business course. It is really a thread which
runs through all the functions and all the aspects of a business. For
example, financial decisions might seem the most securely based on arith-
metic and rules. Yet financial decisions very often require you to make
some decision as between profit now and profit in the future, and to do
that you have to give some weighting to the interests involved here and
now, and to those in the future, so you end up with an ethical dimension
to the decision. So it seems to me that, at the end of the day, there are very
few business decisions which can be made on the basis of mathematics
alone.)
One kind of decision to which I will refer has to be made in situations
where there seem to be competing values, not cases where one course is
clearly right, the other wrong. You may decide to do the wrong thing.
That is entirely another matter, but in that case there need be no query in
your own mind as to which course is right and which course is wrong. The
difficulties come when in fact both courses seem right and we have to
decide which of them is going to prevail.
Another difficulty for decision-making arises from uncertainty as to
what the rules mean. We may have some rules, but we don’t actually know
how to interpret them in the particular case which confronts us. Another
problem may stem from conflicting orders. We are actually being asked to
do two conflicting things at the same time and we have to choose between
them. The final kind of problem I’ll address arises when there is a complex
decision to be made. I will come to a clear example of a complex decision
later on, where a number of interests are affected and you have the
problem of how you are going to decide which of those interests count
most and should therefore have the major say in the final decision.
This business of different shades of right and wrong takes me back to
my grandfather.1 He was deeply opposed to the Boer War and he bought
the only paper in this country which, at that stage, was promoting the
cause of peace and was against the war. He bought it to make sure that it
was able to continue its good work. After buying it, he discovered that a
great deal of the paper was taken up with racing tips and betting news and
this worried him because, in addition to being opposed to the Boer War, he
was actually opposed to gambling as well. So for a period he drastically
12 Sir Adrian Cadbury
cut this side of the paper’s activities. The results on the circulation were
disastrous and, no doubt to the enormous relief of those working on the
paper and I suppose to that of the readers, he decided in the end that to
promote a journal which was going to speak out against the Boer War was
actually more important than giving some mild support to gambling. So he
put the news back in and all went well.
Now, my question is, when we are faced with an ethical decision such
as one of those above, how do we set about resolving it? I should perhaps
at this point explain what I mean by ethics. I use the word to mean the
guidelines or rules of conduct by which we aim to live. To reiterate, then,
what should be the determinants of conduct?
Both companies and individuals work within frameworks. The
company framework is set by the law and by regulations, which are not
quite the same thing as the law, but which we have to abide by although
they are not necessarily statutory. Thus companies are subject to control
by the Board, and to the forces of shareholder opinion through the
General Meeting. There are also pressures from peer standards and public
opinion. In the case of individuals, obviously some of those determinants
just mentioned also apply, but there is also the personal code of the indi-
vidual concerned.
But who sets these rules and who enforces them? What we find is, if we
look at different countries, thinking on the corporate level now, that in
fact the frameworks are different in different countries. In Germany, for
example, the Board would have a greater degree of control over conduct
than it probably would have in the UK. In the US the law and regulation
would have a greater role to play than it does in the UK, and so on. So we
are all subject to certain rules, but the particular mix of those rules is
different and they change. They change as expectations change. Of course,
regulation is pretty straightforward. That is clear. What is less clear is how
what we come to regard as accepted standards of conduct are established
and maintained. So let’s look at codes.
There are really four levels of code. There are international codes,
national codes and company codes and, perhaps in between these, there
are trade or professional codes. International codes constitute an inter-
esting development and one that is relatively new. Recently there has been
an Inter-Faith Declaration, a code of ethics on international business for
Christians, Muslims and Jews.2 This is something at the international level
very much to be welcomed. There are others. There is a body called the
Caux Round Table. There are the Minnesota Principles set out by a group
in the United States entitled ‘Toward an Ethical Basis for Global Business’.
There is a relatively new organization called Transparency International
which states:
Ethical decision-making in business 13
So, there are certain guidelines being produced at the international level
that we can look towards. A second source of guidance is to be found at
the national level. The Code of Best Practice, which our committee
produced, is an obvious example.4 I mentioned that it was addressed to
UK companies, and we did indeed at the beginning of the report say that
we hoped that all companies, whatever their size, whether public or not,
would pay attention to the principles which we had set out there. But, in
the first instance, that code was addressed to listed public companies –
companies quoted on the stock exchange.
Third, it seems to me, there are the trade and professional codes. These
are obviously very important in the professions and have been there for a
long time. But there are others as well which are quite interesting. For
example, there is an advertising code under which Benneton had one of its
advertisements banned. We might not think of it as a professional code,
but it is still a code.
Then, fourth and finally, there are company codes, each company
drawing up its own particular code in different forms and, one hopes,
discussing it so as to ensure that it is not just a top–down process, but that
it does actually have some basis in the way people in the company think
and behave. The Cadbury committee Code of Best Practice was not specifi-
cally dealing with ethical matters, but nevertheless there was an ethical
content and, I felt, it was quite an achievement to get the committee to
agree on the significance of this point. We said it was important that all
employees should know what standards of conduct were expected of
them.5 We regarded it as good practice for boards of directors to draw up
Codes of Ethics or Statements of Business Practice and to publish them
both internally and externally.6 We stressed the principles of openness,
integrity and accountability. They go together. Openness on the part of
companies within the limits set by their competitive position is the basis
for the confidence which needs to exist between business and all those who
have a stake in its success. So company codes should reflect this.
Returning to the Cadbury code for a moment, one of the other points
we dealt with was the need for independent members of a board. We
defined what we meant by independence in this particular context and
what we were referring to was independence of judgement. We made this
suggestion in order to help boards resolve conflicts between the interests of
14 Sir Adrian Cadbury
the executive directors and the interests of the company. This led to a
misunderstanding, in my view, that somehow we were implying that
outside independent directors were more ethical than executive directors.
That was not the point. They can all be equally ethical. What we were
saying was that the outsider has less direct interest in the business, is more
disinterested, more objective. Thus on issues like take-overs, management
buy-outs, directors’ pay, top management succession – all things in which
the executive directors have an interest – then the outsiders have a particu-
larly valuable role to play. This is not a question of their personal virtue. It
is a question of their objectivity.
In general, the response to the Cadbury report was very encouraging
and two general points were established, quite apart from whether or not
companies followed our recommendations. First, public companies now
have to make a statement about their compliance with governance require-
ments and all have in fact to review the structure of their governance
processes, and that in itself seems salutary. I also believe that we have
helped to clarify responsibilities in an area where we found there was a
good deal of confusion, namely, that between directors and auditors.
So, codes are one determinant of conduct, but I suggested that a second
way in which standards of conduct were set was by peer pressure, and
this can be seen if you look at the UK financial sector which, as a conve-
nient shorthand, I will refer to as the City, although that is a
simplification. The City was an example in the past largely of self-
regulation, regulation through peer pressure. That regulation came about
by the wide acceptance of those who worked in the City of what might be
called the rules of the ‘Club’. Of course confidence has a special impor-
tance in the financial sector – it is very much the basis of business there,
not least because money can be made through breach of confidence, as
with insider trading. So membership of the Club involved acceptance of
the rules and code of the Club, and if individuals transgressed that code
there was a very effective form of punishment, which could well involve
exclusion from the Club, thus depriving them of their business. So there
are certain advantages to this club-type of approach to setting out rules of
conduct. First of all, the rules are known, certainly by the insiders, by
those to whom they apply. They are certain and that reduces the ground
for dilemmas. Second, such an approach is cheap, effective and adaptable.
One of the problems with any formal form of regulation is that it will
usually be behind the game. With self-regulation, the Club rules, the
moment that a new issue appears the Club can almost immediately
provide a rule to deal with it.
However, there is a danger to this approach, and that is that the rules
may be one-sided in that they are based on the interests of members of the
Club and not on the interests of those whom the Club is there to serve. I
said at the outset I would give an instance of nineteenth-century behaviour,
Ethical decision-making in business 15
and there is a very interesting case relevant here called the Steam Loop
affair. The Steam Loop was an invention which was designed to secure
savings for users of steam via economies of fuel, water and power. A
company was formed in 1890 to exploit it and Slaughter and May were
the solicitors, both to the company and to one of its promoters. Now the
promoters rigged the market for the issue of shares to ensure that they got
a successful launch – apparently in those days this was a regular occur-
rence. To get the new issue off to a good start, you created an artificial
premium on the opening transactions and that was what was done with
the Steam Loop shares. Unfortunately, though, the promoters then fell out
with each other and there was an argument about who in fact owned some
of the shares. So this whole performance was brought before a judge.
Slaughter and May did not really think anything of this, since it was
accepted as the normal system by which you launched new issues. So they
assumed there would be no problem in going before the law. As one of the
defendants declared: ‘you only have to ask anyone about new companies if
it [that is, creating a false premium] is not a necessity’. The judge, however,
took a remarkably different view, and what he said was:
Slaughter and May were shocked and thought the poor judge simply out
of touch with what went on in the City, so went to Appeal. It went to their
Lordships and their Lordships thunderingly upheld the judgement. And
William May later referred to the case as ‘a magnificent miscarriage of
justice’. Sadly, poor William actually went to his deathbed believing that
he had been very hardly done by.7
Now I think that case is interesting in a number of ways. First of all, it
shows a clash between two different sorts of rules. The rules of the Club in
this case clash with the rule of Law and, interestingly, this time it was the
rules of the Club which had actually got out of kilter with legal opinion as
to what was right. Of course, the rules of the Club are based on what is
acceptable to the members, to the insiders, not to those who are outsiders.
So, in this particular case, what was in effect happening was that, in order
to provide an efficient capital market for the flotation of shares, it was a
regular practice for those inside the market to rig it. This was of course
done to protect what they regarded as their interests – their own interests,
and also the interest of having an efficient capital market, outweighing the
fact that poor unfortunate outsiders not in the know paid over the odds
for the shares. It was that inability to see that there was a conflict of
16 Sir Adrian Cadbury
interest between the members of the Club and the world whom the Club
was there to serve that seems to me one of the problems about Club rules.
That limitation apart, this kind of approach, certainly within the City of
London, broke down for other reasons. It broke down because with the
Big Bang you had a very rapid expansion of numbers employed in this
particular field. The smaller finance houses had been run pretty much on a
partnership basis, with considerable personal influence lying with the part-
ners at the top who took people on, talked to them and discussed practice
with them. They in fact set the tone. When you had this rapid expansion
of numbers, that system of standards completely broke down and there
was nothing to put in its place. A second reason was that the boundaries
between different types of finance activity were swept away and with that
some of the Club rules went as well. Then, third, you had an influx of
newcomers who did not share the same attitudes, the same values, the
same aims and constraints as had applied previously. As I say, we are in a
much more competitive world where winning at all costs may be the
motto. A final reason was internationalization. Into that Club came banks
from very widely different backgrounds who didn’t share precisely the
same values. So the Club approach may have some good points, but it
does depend on there being a coherent group with shared values, and even
then such a coherent group can get out of touch with the wider commu-
nity.
Now I turn to specific examples of difficult managerial decisions, with a
view to examining the role of rules and codes in such decision-making. It
seems to me that the first of these dilemmas occurs when managers find
themselves under conflicting pressures arising from what we may perceive
as the role of business in society. The manager may be involved in cutting
costs in his particular business, and also being asked to ensure that the unit
he is responsible for continues to play its part in the community. He may
be having to get rid of staff and, at the same time, being told that he needs
to take up a certain number of trainees who are just leaving school or
college. So you get these pressures and, if one thinks in terms of rules, the
difficulty for the manager is to know exactly which rule to turn to. This
can be expressed in terms of responsibilities. For example, Tom Clarke
suggests three levels of responsibilities of business in society.8 The first
level is that of a company meeting its material obligations, to shareholders,
to employees, customers, suppliers, creditors, paying its taxes and meeting
its statutory duties. That level of responsibility of a company to society is
clear-cut, easily defined. The next level up from that suggests that a
company has an obligation to take account of the consequences of its
actions – for example: that it must be prepared to go beyond minimum
standards to ensure that it is making the most of its human resources; that
it is not damaging the environment; that it is actually assisting the environ-
ment, and so on. We then come to a third level of obligation, which is
Ethical decision-making in business 17
much less clearly defined. This refers to the responsibilities companies have
for the relationship between business and society in a wider sense. At this
level, the question arises as to how far a business has a responsibility for
maintaining the framework of the society of which it is a part and in
which it operates. That seems to me to be a difficult area. These supposed
levels of responsibility raise important but difficult questions for managers
in large businesses, managers who are unclear how to apply company
policy in the individual instances they are faced with. For example, should
they employ this disabled person or not? What help are the rules then?
And this sort of problem applies also to the small business. How far
should the owner/manager become involved in activities outside of just
running the shop? The latter is a problem the individual has to face alone.
In the former case, the company still leaves the judgement to be made by
the individual, but obviously the clearer we can make our statements of
company policy the easier it is for managers to make those decisions. The
responsibility here lies with boards of directors – the responsibility to set
policies in relation, for example, to recruitment, to redundancy, to the
company’s relationship with the community. But there is a danger here –
namely, that boards will make statements and rules on such matters, which
are duly minuted and passed down the line, and as far as the board is
concerned it will have done its job.
It will not have done so in two ways. First of all, there is a duty if you
set out policy, to follow it up and make sure that it is actually applied in
practice. Discrimination in employment may not happen very often at
board level but it certainly happens at the factory gate. So it is a job for the
board to follow this through and see whether their policy is actually oper-
ating. The second duty is to ensure that policies are backed up by the
system of rewards and discipline within the company, because the people
in the company know perfectly well what is going on in practice. So if in
fact it is the person who makes his or her budget who gets promoted,
whereas the person who has followed the apparent directive from the top
to do all kinds of other good things like training, is left where he is, every-
body draws their own conclusion. The rule may state that training is just
as important as profit, but if the ‘budget-meeter’ is promoted, and the
trainer is not, at the end of the day it is by the actions of the company that
the rules are judged.
One area where I think there are difficult managerial decisions to be
made is where a decision is required as to what to do in this kind of situa-
tion in relation to major policy issues. The difficulty is the possible conflict
between the obligations that arise at different levels. A second difficulty
has just been indicated, though it is in its own way more straightforward.
This is where there is confusion down the line as to whether a company
means what it says. I have a very good example here. It goes back a bit
18 Sir Adrian Cadbury
and concerns a court action involving the General Electric Company in the
United States. It has been reported as follows:
For the past eight years or so, General Electric had had a company
rule called Directive Policy 20.5, which read in part ‘no employee shall
enter into any understanding, agreement, plan or scheme, expressed or
implied, formal or informal, with any competitor with regard to
prices.’ … The trouble, at least during the period covered by the Court
action and apparently for a long time before that as well, was that
some people at General Electric, including some of those who regu-
larly signed 20.5, simply did not believe it was to be taken seriously.
They assumed that it was window dressing: that it was on the books
solely to provide legal protection for the company and for the higher
ups; that meeting illegally with competitors was recognized and
accepted as standard practice; and that often when a ranking executive
ordered a subordinate executive to comply with 20.5, he was actually
ordering him to violate it. Illogical as it might seem this last assump-
tion becomes comprehensible in the light of the fact that, for a time,
when some executives orally conveyed, or re-conveyed, the order, they
were apparently in the habit of accompanying it with an unmistakable
wink. … [Thus it was that when] asked by Senator Kefauver how long
he had been aware that orders issued in General Electric were some-
times accompanied by winks, Robert Paxton, an upper level G.E.
executive replied [as follows]. He had first observed the practice way
back in 1935 when his boss had given him an instruction along with a
wink or its equivalent, and that when sometime later the significance
of the gesture dawned on him, he had become so incensed that he had
with difficulty restrained himself from jeopardizing his career by
punching the boss in the nose. Paxton went on to say that his objec-
tion to the practice of winking had been so strong as to earn him a
reputation in the company for being an anti-wink man. But he for his
part had never winked.9
businesses will not get recruits of the quality they need. That will not only
be bad for business, it will be bad for society.
There is a final reason, which was highlighted by the Barings disaster.
The danger is that the failure of Barings will be seen as a failure of
controls. The answer to fraudulent or reckless trading will be thought to
lie in a tightening of controls. What went wrong was that the financial
controls were not tight enough, it will be said, so screw down the controls.
Some tightening of controls was clearly necessary in that case, and if there
is not a proper system of control in a business, or if people do not under-
stand the control system, then the business has to be at risk.
But we must recognise the limitations of the control approach. The
speed of information technology and the complexity of international trans-
actions require controls, but they have a supporting not a primary role.
You cannot keep pace with the gyrations of international currency markets
through control systems. The standards of honesty, integrity and prudence
of the people who are put in charge of dealings like those on the foreign
exchanges must be the primary safeguard. The Barings’ failure was more a
failure in selection, training and mentoring than anything else. Companies
need to recruit and train people in whom they have confidence and whom
they can trust. It is confidence and trust that are real safeguards against
fraud and disaster, and they can only be fostered and instilled on a sound
ethical base.
Notes
1 I also referred to this in ‘Ethical managers make their own rules’, Sir Adrian
Cadbury, Harvard Business Review, 1987, p. 69.
2 This was distributed as an inter-faith declaration entitled ‘A Code of Ethics on
International Business for Christians, Muslims and Jews’ in the mid-1990s.
3 Private communication from TI to the author.
4 Report of the Committee on the Financial Aspects of Corporate Governance,
London, 1992.
5 Ibid., section 4.29.
6 Ibid., section 3.2.
7 Laurie Dennet, Slaughter and May, A Century in the City, Cambridge: Granta
Editions, 1989, pp. 98ff.
8 Tom Clarke, private circular distributed at original lecture.
9 Reported in John Brooks, The Fate of Edsel and Other Adventures, London:
Victor Gollancz, 1964, pp. 146–8.
Chapter 2
As he goes on to observe, this raises the question whether right action can
be taught. As if in response to this, a slightly earlier Hastings Centre report
on the Teaching of Ethics in higher education includes the following claim:
One goal frequently proposed for courses in ethics is missing from our
list: that of changing student behaviour … We have concluded that
this is not an appropriate goal for a course in ethics.2
Sternberg is in a position to address this latter point more fully once she
has presented her substantive view of a proper understanding of business
ethics.
Central to this view is her claim that, ‘properly understood, business
ethics is about what business must do to be ethical. It is therefore impor-
tant to be clear about exactly what business is.’ It is this point that marks a
central Aristotelian aspect of her position. Sternberg describes her
approach as teleological, and in this connection she takes from Aristotle’s
work two main thoughts. First of all there is the idea that a definition of a
human activity should be given in terms of its purpose. As she says ‘One of
the most distinctive features of this approach is that it identifies and
explains human activities by reference to their ends/aims/goals/objectives/
purposes.’6 The reason this is important depends on a second Aristotelian
idea, namely, that we can assess the goodness of behaviour by reference to
the defining purpose of that activity. As she says, ‘Purposes are essential
for evaluating goodness. Because of their very different purposes, the
criteria of a good pillow are necessarily different from the criteria of a
26 Chris Megone
Having laid out the essence of her position, Sternberg is now able to claim
that
Having noted this connection between ethical conduct and good business,
she adds a caveat.
She then goes on to argue that if the ethical component of business decision-
making is not correctly addressed, which occurs when the principles of
business ethics are not properly understood or are ignored, then
There are many things to be said against this view, but the first is that
whatever else it may be, it cannot be an explanation of business. To
understand why, consider an enthusiastic environmentalist who, crit-
ical of the pollution and waste caused by the motorcar, endeavours to
remove from his own vehicle those properties that he finds most offen-
sive. Being a handy sort of chap, he reduces the cumbersome passenger
compartment to an open air slimline seat; he replaces the noisy engine
with a silent chain drive; he eschews expensive, polluting petrol in
favour of sustainable human energy. His contrivance is elegant and
efficient, and better than a motorcar for many purposes. But whatever
its merits, the one thing the new vehicle emphatically is not, is an
improved motorcar: it is not a motorcar at all. By stripping away the
essential features of a motorcar, the enthusiast has transformed what
was once a car into something else altogether; he has, in fact, re-
invented the bicycle.
In like fashion, an organization whose objective is anything but
maximising long-term owner value is not – cannot be – a business,
because it lacks the definitive feature of a business. What qualifies an
organization to be a business is just the objective of maximizing long-
term owner value; however valuable organizations seeking other ends
may be, they are not businesses but something else.
It may be objected that this is playing with words. But it is not.
What matters is not what the activity of maximizing long-term owner
value is called, but what it is. If people prefer to reserve the word
‘business’ for mixed-purpose commercial organizations and their
composite doings, so be it; maximizing long-term owner value will just
have to be given a different name. Whatever it is called, however, the
activity of maximizing long-term owner value is a vital part of modern
life, which needs both to be understood and to be conducted ethically.
And it is that indispensable activity which is the subject here.
So whatever stakeholder theorists are offering, it is not an improved
form of business. But perhaps it is something different and better, a
superior form of corporate governance, for instance. Unfortunately, it
is not that either: what stakeholder theory recommends does not even
make sense. However widely accepted it is, and however useful the
term ‘stakeholder’ may be as a collective name for those whom the
business needs to take into account in its deliberations, the stakeholder
approach is fatally, fundamentally, flawed.
32 Chris Megone
In a similar way, she argues, the ethical decision model is a valuable tool
for management.
But what does the Ethical Decision Model look like? Sternberg now argues
that the model she proposes, which is built on her analysis of the nature of
business, consists of five straightforward steps. She illustrates these steps
by applying the model to the issue of executive pay.
This leads Sternberg to the fifth and concluding step in her model: identi-
fying the right course of action for the business.
Once the relevant question and constraints have been identified, and
alternative proposals have been assessed, the ethical answer should be
clear. The business should choose that alternative which is likely to
contribute most to long-term owner value, so long as it satisfies
distributive justice and ordinary decency. If either of those conditions
is not met, then even if the proposal appears to maximize long-term
owner value, it should not be adopted. But equally, satisfying distribu-
tive justice and ordinary decency is not enough. The morally right
course of action for the business must satisfy all three conditions: it is
that which aims at maximizing long-term owner value while
respecting distributive justice and ordinary decency.
Typically, the hardest part of ethical decision-making is not
applying the principles of distributive justice and ordinary decency, but
determining which action will actually maximize long-term owner
value. But however difficult it may be to project outcomes, estimating
long-term owner value cannot be avoided: it is the core not just of
ethical decision-making, but of business as such.
Two Aristotelian approaches to business ethics 39
centre, we believe that if we put them in the advised conditions, and the
plant itself is not defective, then they will develop in certain characteristic
or normal ways, the ways good members of the kind develop. The same
sort of beliefs are still widely held with regard to animals and, finally, to
humans. It is widely accepted, for example, that there are norms (of an
evaluative kind) regarding the times at which humans should develop the
capacity to read, write and manage certain arithmetic calculations, as well
as regarding human physical development.
Aristotle’s view can be put in terms of potentials. Instead of thinking of
a member of a natural kind as a medium-sized object, an acorn, or a
sapling, say, one can think of it as a bundle of potentials. But out of all the
potentials to change that are in that bundle, there is a subset of changes
which a good member of the kind manifests, or actualizes. His further
claim is that these potentialities are the essential properties of the kind, the
potentialities that make an entity the kind of thing that it is. This is the
thing’s nature. So in the human case, human nature is that set of essential
potentialities which good members of the kind realize. When a human
being realizes those potentials he is realising his function or characteristic
activity. So, Aristotle suggests, just as what is good for an acorn, qua
acorn, is that which enables it to realize its essential potential, what
enables it to become a fully developed oak, so what is good for a human is
the realization of his essential potential.
Aristotle’s further suggestion, in this same short passage in NE I, 7, is
that human nature is constituted by the potential for a fully rational life.22
It is that (large) subset of potentialities, the set which is realized in the fully
rational life, that constitutes the human essence. On this view, then, the
human good, the eudaimon life, will be one in which an agent fully realizes
all those capacities which contribute to a maximally rational life. The
concept of rationality should not be understood narrowly here. For the
Aristotelian, rationality is not simply a matter of intellectual prowess. The
rational life takes in both practical and theoretical rationality. Desires and
emotions are subject to rational development as well as beliefs. Thus a
very complex set of potentials, including those for language, for imagina-
tion, for relationships with others, as well as for such things as drawing
conclusions from evidence or from premises, all these and more are part of
a fully rational life.
On the basis of this line of argument, therefore, Aristotle, reaches the
conclusion that the eudaimon life is the fully rational life. If, therefore, he
is to establish any connection between such a life and the life of ethical
virtue, or that of contemplation, he needs to show that the ethically
virtuous life is indeed fully rational. (For present purposes the life of
contemplation can be set to one side.) To understand his position it is
necessary to turn now to his discussion of ethical virtue.
Two Aristotelian approaches to business ethics 43
the agent’s desires are guided by reason in the sense, crudely, that their
strength matches the agent’s view of the value of their objective. The fully
rational agent will not have rogue desires motivating him to pursue objec-
tives of lesser worth, or value, than others he could pursue.
Finally, Aristotle notes that the rational principle, which determines the
mean (or appropriate) action, is the principle a man of practical wisdom
would use to guide his action. Once again a lot could be said here. For the
purposes of outlining the Aristotelian position it may be enough to say
that practical wisdom is an intellectual virtue. It is the intellectual virtue
that enables the agent to form the appropriate judgements as to what is, all
things considered, worth pursuing, and also to determine the appropriate
means to achieve that objective. However, since a rational agent’s desires
are for objectives that are desired because of the point which that agent
sees in them, this intellectual virtue also interacts with the virtuous agent’s
desires. A little more will be said about practical wisdom in the final
chapter of this book.
In sum then, on Aristotle’s account, virtue is a stable disposition of the
agent’s beliefs and desires, where the beliefs include a fully rational
conception of what is worth pursuing, and the desires are formed so as to
pursue just such an objective. The motivations, preferential choices and
actions of such an agent will thus lie in a mean, a mean which reflects
rationality in the sense just explained.
To reinforce the plausibility of this account, Aristotle goes on to argue
that it applies satisfactorily to those states of character most would
consider to be ethical virtues. For example, he argues that courage fits this
definition. It is a stable disposition of the mind which gives the agent a
tendency to choose and act courageously. It lies in a mean between
cowardice on the one hand and rashness on the other, and this can be
further explained in terms of the wayward beliefs and desires held by those
in these vicious states. Likewise temperance might be held to be a state of
character lying between self-indulgence and asceticism, generosity one that
lies between meanness and prodigality.
Rather than explore the details of this approach further, it is time to
consider its application to business ethics. What this complex account of
the nature of virtue has done thus far is to explain the relationship
between virtue and eudaimonia, and thus vindicate the belief that virtue
pays. Aristotle has shown that the ethically virtuous agent will be fully
rational and, thus, that the ethically virtuous life is (at least) a constituent
of the eudaimon life, since the eudaimon life is the fully rational life. This
is an important achievement methodologically, since establishing the truth
of this widely held connection serves, for Aristotle, to support the plausi-
bility of both the account of virtue and that of eudaimonia. The
establishment of the connection also has implications for the application of
the theory to business ethics.
Two Aristotelian approaches to business ethics 47
and fairness. And justice is the virtue which governs the allocation of
rewards and burdens in relation to the employee’s contribution to the
achievement of the goal of business. But other virtues may be relevant too.
A virtue such as courage may be required in negotiating a contract, or in
whistleblowing on injustice. Temperance (self-control) may also be
required of an employee to ensure he adopts a lifestyle that enables him to
contribute optimally to his work (for example an employee whose contri-
bution of physical effort to an enterprise is crucial for the success of the
whole). It may be a marginal issue whether this latter is considered a
matter of business ethics, or ethics conceived more broadly, but, as has
been indicated, within virtue ethics such sharp distinctions are not easily
made.
It is sometimes objected to a virtue account of the sort given that it is of
very little practical use.33 The advice to do that act which exercises the
relevant virtue in the circumstances leaves open the question which virtue
is relevant, and also what is required in order to exercise that virtue on this
occasion. But the Aristotelian theory does provide more resources. It gives
an account of the nature of specific virtues which indicates the kind of
considerations that one who has that virtue will attend to. It also gives an
account of what virtue is, and how it is acquired, which indicates that part
of acquiring the virtue of justice, say, will involve coming to have relevant
beliefs such that the agent can identify when it is in question. For example,
the child will learn that it is a matter of proportionate distribution and
start to learn the sorts of consideration that bear on appropriate propor-
tion (who made the cake, whose cake it is, who was invited to the party,
and the like).
Furthermore in NE IX, 2 Aristotle has a long discussion of rules in
connection with the topic of friendship. In this passage he does seem to
suggest both the possibility of discerning many general rules that govern
what is owed to different classes of people, and thus make more explicit
the nature of justice. He also appears to emphasize the importance of that
task. Having noted that it may be laborious, he adds ‘Yet we must not on
that account shrink from the task, but decide the question as best we
can.’34
Aristotle specifically denies that it is possible to produce precise guide-
lines in matters of conduct:
But this must be agreed upon beforehand, that the whole account of
matters of conduct must be given in outline, and not precisely …
matters concerned with conduct and questions of what is good for us
have no fixity, any more than matters of health. The general account
being of this nature, the account of particular cases is yet more lacking
in exactness.35
Two Aristotelian approaches to business ethics 49
There are two sorts of wealth getting, as I have said; one is a part of
household management, the other is retail trade: the former is neces-
sary and honourable, while that which consists in exchange is justly
censured: for it is unnatural.40
Once again it is only possible in the present context to be brief about the
ideas here.
Aristotle is distinguishing two possible types of commercial activity.
Both are concerned with the acquisition of wealth, but one has a limit and
the other does not. But he appears to be arguing that to undertake the
activity of business for the purpose of maximizing wealth, without limit, is
a mistake since it is contrary to what is needed for the proper development
of human nature. (This is what is meant by ‘unnatural’ here.) On the other
hand, it is perfectly compatible with such proper development (the devel-
opment of virtue) to sell goods and services for the purpose of acquiring
that quantity of wealth that is needed to lead a virtuous life. (This means
that when undertaking the activity of business the proper aim is not just to
sustain the business, but to produce what is required to allow those
engaging in the business the leisure for the virtuous life, and the where-
withal for such virtues as generosity.)
In other words, Aristotle presents an argument here which appears to
challenge Sternberg’s view that the proper purpose of business is to maxi-
mize long-term owner value by selling goods and services. The internal aim
or goal of business should be to seek to produce sufficient value for those
engaged in the activity, by selling goods and services, to enable those
people to lead a virtuous life. Since there is an ultimate end, eudaimonia,
to which other activities are subordinate, the internal goal or purpose,
when engaged in business activity, must be constrained by that ultimate
end.
One possible reply here might suggest that Aristotle’s remarks are not
concerned to show that the internal goal of business itself contains a limit,
but to point out that the time devoted to business activity must depend on
the role of such activity within a eudaimon life. On this view, when an
agent is engaged in business the internal aim for all the time he is so
engaged should be to maximize long-term owner value, but a proper
Two Aristotelian approaches to business ethics 51
Notes
1 James Allen, ‘The Use and Abuse of Humanistic Education’, in C.R.
Christensen and A.J. Hansen (eds) Teaching and the Case Method (Harvard
Business School, Boston, 1989), p. 51.
2 The Teaching of Ethics in Higher Education (The Hastings Centre, Hastings on
Hudson, New York, 1980).
3 Plato, Republic, 352 d1.
4 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, I, 3, 1095 a4.
5 This account draws directly on Sternberg’s contribution to the Leeds lecture
series. For contractual reasons the essence of this lecture has had to be
presented, with the author’s agreement, within the body of this chapter through
quotation by the editor rather than directly. All quotations from Sternberg are
from the Leeds lecture unless otherwise specified. A full account of Sternberg’s
position is available in her Just Business: Business Ethics in Action (2nd
edition, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2000; 1st edition: Little, Brown &
Co. London, 1994 Warner paperback 1995; ‘Introduction: What Makes This
Book Distinctive’ available online at http://ssrn.com).
6 E. Sternberg, Just Business: Business Ethics in Action (1st edition, Little Brown
& Company, London, 1994; subsequently ‘JB1’), p. 4.
7 E. Sternberg, JB1, p. 4.
8 This is the third Aristotelian aspect of Sternberg’s approach since she cites his
account of distributive justice, see E. Sternberg, JB1, p. 80.
9 For a much fuller discussion of stakeholder theory, and criticism of arguments
that supposedly support it, see Elaine Sternberg, The Stakeholder Concept: A
Mistaken Doctrine, The Foundation for Business Responsibilities, 1999; avail-
able online from the Social Sciences Research Network on http://ssrn.com.
10 Cf. ‘The Business Roundtable’, Corporate Governance and American Competi-
tiveness, March 1990, p. 13 (though they repudiated it in 1997); available from
The Business Roundtable, 200 Park Ave, NYC 10016.
11 It is only in the unlikely case that all the alternatives both satisfy distributive
justice and ordinary decency, and are projected to have equal effects on maxi-
mizing long-term owner value, that degrees of distributive justice or ordinary
decency might be taken into account.
12 I have presented the account put forward here in more detail in my
‘Aristotelian Ethics’ in Ruth Chadwick (ed.) The Encyclopaedia of Applied
Ethics (Academic Press of America, San Diego, 1997) Vol. 1, pp. 209–31.
13 It is still pertinent to investigate whether there is at least a common shape to a
life worth living. And it is still important to consider why we should be moral,
and whether the moral or virtuous life has any part in such a worthwhile life.
Thus it is still generally assumed that if an act can be shown to be unjust or
unfair it should not be undertaken; but the question ‘What’s the point of being
just?’ can still be raised. And if it cannot be satisfactorily answered, then it
54 Chris Megone
might at least seem questionable whether an act’s being just gives sufficient
reason for doing it, or an act’s being unjust rules out doing it.
14 In what follows I retain the Greek term eudaimonia. Whilst ‘happiness’ is often
given as a translation, modern readers need to be aware that the term may have
some misleading connotations, at least in so far as it is taken to connote a mere
feeling. If we think of the notion of true happiness, as contrasted with some
passing feeling, that might give a better sense of what Aristotle has in mind.
15 Aristotle, NE, I, 1 1094 a2. (All quotations from the Nichomachean Ethics in
this chapter are from Sir David Ross’s translation, Oxford University Press,
Oxford, 1925.) For example, when a rational agent eats an apple he does so
because of the good (or apparent good) he sees in doing so. This good might be
the apple’s flavour, or the health he will gain through eating it, to mention just
two possibilities.
16 Aristotle assumes that, at least provisionally, widely held views or the views of
wise predecessors can be supposed to have some truth in them. See, for
example, NE, VII, 1 1145 b2–7.
17 I use the term ethical virtue to pick out characteristics such as courage, justice,
temperance, which would normally be thought of as virtues nowadays, and
which are manifest in courageous, just, temperate (and so on) acts. Aristotle’s
term for virtue, arete, is applied to any human excellence, including intellectual
excellences, so that for him ethical virtues are a subset of all the virtues.
18 The arguments that follow are given in NE I, 5 1095 b17ff.
19 NE, 1, 7 1097 b27–30.
20 The interpretation of this passage is a disputed matter, and the account given
here, which takes his ethics to rest in a significant way on his metaphysics can
only be asserted, rather than fully defended, in the present context.
21 A fuller account of these ideas is given in C. Megone, ‘Aristotle on Essentialism
and natural kinds: Physics II:1’, in Revue de Philosophe Ancienne, (1987) Vol.
6, 2.
22 NE, I, 7 1098 a4ff.
23 NE, II, 6 1106 b36ff.
24 I understand by nature properties to be essential properties and take it that
essential properties are not merely necessary properties, but also properties that
play an explanatory role, but in the present context it is the fact that an actual-
ized virtue is not a necessary property that matters. See Megone, op. cit., fn. 21.
25 NE, II, 1 1103 a26–8.
26 NE, II, 1 1103 a36.
27 This and other features of Aristotle’s view have been well discussed in M.
Burnyeat, ‘Aristotle on learning to be good’, in A. Rorty (ed.) Essays on
Aristotle’s Ethics (University of California Press, Berkeley, 1980).
28 NE, II, 4 1105 b5–8.
29 See R. Nozick, The Nature of Rationality (Princeton University Press, New
Jersey, 1993), p. 19.
30 NE, II, 4 1105 a33–5. Aristotle need not think that all characters are
unchangeable, even if he is understood here as saying that a virtuous character
must be unchangeable, rather than simply settled. It may be that the fully
virtuous character would be one from which the virtuous agent would have no
inclination to change.
31 I am grateful to Roger Crisp for suggesting this way of explaining the doctrine.
32 As, indeed, Sternberg agrees: she states explicitly that the values involved in
business ethics apply to the whole of the moral life: there is no separate ‘busi-
ness ethic’.
Two Aristotelian approaches to business ethics 55
33 This is another large issue. For further discussion, see C. Megone, ‘Aristotelian
Ethics’, op. cit., pp. 228 ff.
34 NE, IX, 2 1165 a35–6. I owe this point to Roger Crisp.
35 NE, II, 2 1104 a1–5.
36 NE, I, 7 1097 b30.
37 Politics I, 1–3. Aristotle’s idea here is that the development of rationality
requires upbringing in a community. This idea requires a good deal of
unpacking, but it includes thoughts such as that language acquisition cannot be
achieved alone, and that the acquisition of virtue requires guided upbringing.
There are many ways in which the development of the capacities that
contribute to a fully rational life requires interaction with others.
38 Politics I, 8 1256 b26–30.
39 Politics I, 9 1257 b23–31.
40 Politics I, 10 1258 a39–b3.
41 Politics I, 9 1257 b25.
42 I am grateful to Elaine Sternberg for discussion of these matters. The points
made here may not be conclusive, and the relevant passages of Politics, book I,
are worthy of a paper-long treatment in themselves.
43 NE, IV, 1 1119 b24–9.
44 For some remarks on the importance of leisure, slightly contrasting in tone, see
NE, X, 7 and Politics II, 9 1269 a35, II, 11 1273 a35 ff.
45 NE, VII, 1 1145 a17ff. Aristotle’s classic discussion of acrasia follows in subse-
quent chapters of book VII.
46 I am most grateful to Roger Crisp, Simon Robinson, Nick Seel and Elaine
Sternberg for very helpful discussions of some of the material in this chapter.
Part II
There exist more than 6,500 offshore oil and gas installations around the
world, many of which provide a facility for tankers to load oil into their
holds. The North Sea is home to a majority of the world’s heavy deep-
water steel platforms. Of the approximately 600 rigs, operating in the
North Sea and North Atlantic, about fifty will reach the end of their useful
life by 2006. Because some of the equipment and the sludge contained
within could pose serious environmental consequences, plans to decommis-
sion these rigs raise ongoing and conflicting economic and environmental
concerns.
These issues came to a head in 1995 with Greenpeace’s guerrilla
campaign against Shell UK Limited and its attempt to sink Shell’s floating
storage buoy, the Brent Spar. Like the Exxon Valdez incident, it brought
into focus some of the imposing problems mankind faces as the world
population (and its tonnage of industrial by-products) continues to soar.
Given the media interest, the nature of the scientific controversies involved,
and the likelihood of future conflict, the Brent Spar incident has been cited
as a classic lesson in stakeholder management and the importance of
dialogue in crisis management. On close examination, however, the lessons
of Brent Spar are far less clear. Provocative questions remain about what
groups were legitimate stakeholders, what constitutes dialogue, and
whether dialogue is the appropriate management strategy when the ethical
divide remains so wide. This ambiguity is magnified by ongoing disputes
over the factual record of the Brent Spar incident. Competing factions
continue to spin the media record and the complicated scientific issues.
The only clear result is that the brouhaha has scarred the reputations of
many of those involved, including Shell, Greenpeace, the scientific commu-
nity, various European governments and the media. The controversy raises
archetypal issues often found in contemporary controversies that pit
corporations against social activists. Among them:
Background
The North Sea and North East Atlantic have been the site of significant
industrial activity since the 1960s. Just over 25 years ago, on 18 June
1975, UK North Sea oil was first brought to land after six years of explor-
ation and development. It was shipped from the small Argyll Field and
brought ashore by tanker to BP’s Isle of Grain refinery in Kent. Since
1975, over 2 billion tonnes of oil and 1,381 billion cubic metres of gas
have come ashore. Today, there are over 200 fields in production on the
UK Continental Shelf – and production is at record levels. In 1998, 132.6
million tonnes of oil and 95 billion cubic metres of gas were produced.
Shell built and in 1976 put online an offshore facility, the Brent Spar,
which stood between the coasts of Scotland and Norway in the Brent field
in the northern North Sea. Brent Spar was installed to allow early produc-
tion from the Brent field in advance of the pipeline to Sullom Voe,
Shetland Islands, Scotland, being installed and commissioned. But even
after the pipeline came into use, the Spar was retained as an alternative
offloading facility and as back-up to the pipeline in times of shutdown.
Brent Spar remained in full use for 15 years, finally ceasing operation in
1991. After the completion of an oil pipeline to the mainland at Sullom
Voe in the late 1970s, and after three years of operation, Shell put the Spar
storage buoy into standby status but maintained it in the event that prob-
lems developed with the pipeline. Over time, Shell (and the rest of the
hydrocarbon industry) concluded that the costs of such precautions
outweighed the benefits, although it had not yet resolved the best environ-
mental and economical way of handling redundant platforms.
The Brent Spar was unlike most other installations in the North Sea.
Under regulatory guidelines, all but the largest rigs were to be decommis-
sioned by being brought to shore and dismantled for reuse or recycling.
However, very large steel and concrete structures, such as the Brent Spar,
are considered difficult or even dangerous to remove. Like an iceberg,
most of the Spar’s bulk – six huge storage tanks – lay beneath the water’s
surface. As a result, these leviathans are handled on an individual basis,
although there remains a general presumption of total removal when
possible (some 80 per cent of structures are completely removed). (Note:
In July 1998, at the OSPAR Ministerial meeting in Portugal, the section of
the Convention governing the disposal of offshore installations was
reviewed and a new regulatory framework – Decision 98/3 – was instituted
which bans any disposal at sea of offshore structures.)
Shell, Greenpeace and Brent Spar 61
disposal option: tow the Spar from the North Sea to sink it in a deep water
channel in the North East Atlantic. Some scientists, such as Martin V.
Angel at the Southampton Oceanography Centre (UK), believed that the
criteria of evaluation did not address the right questions, since strong
emphasis was placed on the structural integrity of the seabed rather than
its direct environmental impact. This was an operating ‘ethic’ for hydro-
carbon companies who were far more fearful of causing a geological
disaster than an environmental one.
As it turned out, Shell and the government acted with little public
consultation or disclosure and did not solicit the opinions of critical
‘public interest’ groups that had been monitoring the decommission debate
for some years. Although Shell had historically demonstrated sensitivity to
environmental issues, it rejected liberal stakeholder theory canon that the
‘natural environment’ held status as a stakeholder in company operations
and fortunes. It also vociferously resisted the idea that public interest
groups, who were publicly hostile to the natural resource industry as a
matter of course, had a right to be involved in the review process.
Greenpeace, the world’s largest environmental lobby, had been
campaigning for years against ocean dumping of any kind. As a conse-
quence, Shell did not consider Greenpeace and other radical groups
representative stakeholders and, therefore, did not include their (unso-
licited) comments in the list of consultees, which was stipulated by the
then UK government.
Shell asked the British government to approve its plans in September
1992. After scrutiny by government scientists and following extensive
consultations, the UK’s Department of Trade and Industry (DTI), which
clearly saw Brent Spar as a test run for future decommissionings, endorsed
the plans in December 1994. Shell was issued with a deep-sea licence to
dispose the Brent Spar to a site 2,300 metres under the surface, about 240
kilometres north-west of the Hebrides on the North Feni Ridge.
Meanwhile, under the Oslo Convention, all other appropriate European
governments were notified and none objected. The UK government
announced its approval on 17 February 1995.
The announced support by the British government of Shell’s application
attracted little media interest until Greenpeace, accompanied by a number
of German and UK journalists, boarded the Spar for the first time on 30
April 1995. The occupation fired an immediate public debate pitting Shell
and the UK government against Greenpeace. The environmental group,
which had first become involved in an ocean dumping issue when its ship
Rainbow Warrior intercepted a radioactive waste dumping vessel in the
Atlantic in the summer of 1978, was on record as being opposed to any
ocean disposal as unethical. (Ironically, years ago, Greenpeace disposed of
the wreck of the Rainbow Warrior at sea to form an artificial reef for
marine wildlife.)
Shell, Greenpeace and Brent Spar 63
Greenpeace complained that its perspective had not been included in the
decision-making process – indeed the DTI refused to accept its written
protests. Shell defended its lack of consultation with Greenpeace on the
grounds that Greenpeace had definitely admitted that its goal was to
reverse the disposal choice, not to participate in risk–benefit environmental
and economic analysis. Greenpeace escalated its allegations, charging that
Spar was a ‘toxic time bomb’ of drilling mud, oil residues and radioactive
waste that could seriously damage the marine environment – an allegation
disputed by Shell and questioned by most independent scientists and
oceanographers. Greenpeace also asserted that allowing the use of the
ocean as a free repository would signal that it was acceptable for compa-
nies to pass on the externalities of its operations. Its proposed alternative:
onshore dismantling of Brent Spar.
The occupation
Greenpeace, noted for its confrontational tactics, sprung into action,
helped along by a Shell misstep. Because of a narrow weather window,
Shell chose to scuttle the Spar just before the Inter-ministerial meeting on
the North Sea. This handed Greenpeace, whose membership had gone into
decline, a golden opportunity for a high profile campaign. Greenpeace
invoked broad ethical principles as well as specific environmental objec-
tions in launching a vigorous international campaign against Shell and its
plan. Greenpeace initiated boycotts of Shell products in several European
countries. In Germany, for example, where Shell’s sales fell by between 20
and 30 per cent in the area around Hamburg during the crisis, protestors
threatened to damage 200 Shell sites. Fifty were subsequently damaged:
two firebombed and one raked with bullets.
Just before midday on 30 April 1995 activists, accompanied by a
number of journalists, occupied the rusting and deserted platform. The
audacity of the occupation, carried out at sea, attracted immediate media
attention. Greenpeace claimed an impending ecological disaster. Daily
postings on a special Internet website were enhanced after the second week
by satellite phone/fax/e-mail equipment that enabled the occupants to talk
directly to journalists. However, the main story did not break until 22 May
when, after a failed night-time attempt, police and security men began
evicting the activists under injunctions granted by Scottish courts.
Greenpeace began offering direct television feeds to broadcasters around
the world.
Shell evicted the protestors and began blasting high-powered cannons to
fend off reoccupation by Greenpeace. Videotaped by Greenpeace vessels
nearby, scenes of what appeared to be water cannons directed at
Greenpeace helicopters were flashed around the world, making headline
news. The drama was captured on video arranged by Greenpeace, and
64 Jon Entine
The controversy
Greenpeace’s decision to elevate its moral stance over scientific claims gave
it an initial tactical advantage in the court of public opinion. The news
media found the controversy difficult to manage. It did not yield to the
customary technique of instant verification used in news journalism, where
complex conflicts are frequently reduced to two opposing views with the
‘right answer’ arrived at by finding an ‘independent expert’. During much
of the crisis, large segments of the media presented the controversy as a
moral saga with ‘white hat’ Greenpeace environmentalists (forces of
caution) fighting ‘black hat’ Shell (new icon of multinational corporate
expediency) which was being secretly aided by Britain’s Conservative-led
government (symbol of governmental complicity). Shell’s appeal to science
and ‘rationality’ contrasted with Greenpeace’s ethical arguments and the
belief by many environmentalists that Shell had tried to engineer the most
financially advantageous, not the most environmentally responsible
disposal option.
That simplistic ethical paradigm held sway so long as the public
believed Greenpeace’s analysis of the toxic potential of the sludge still on
the rig. Greenpeace had dismissed Shell’s commissioned study which indi-
cated that some 53 tonnes of oil remained onboard. It publicized tests
from samples drawn by its guerrilla-occupiers that claimed there was more
than one hundred times as much – 5,550 tonnes. According to newspaper
accounts and Greenpeace press releases, it was further claimed that the rig
contained ‘14,500 tonnes of toxic rubbish’ and ‘over 100 tonnes of toxic
sludge’. Shell officials continued to insist that their figures were accurate,
which sparked widespread and well-publicized ridicule by activists.
But within a month of Shell’s surrender, public perceptions turned
abruptly when it became clear that Greenpeace had wildly exaggerated or
at least distorted (deliberately or innocently is still at issue) the potential
hazards of Shell’s disposal plans. The press first uncovered that
Greenpeace’s claim that marine life was threatened referred to a disposal
66 Jon Entine
option in shallow waters which Shell had explicitly rejected. In the most
damaging disclosure, several independent companies coordinated by Det
Norske Veritas undertook a new inventory examination. This comprehen-
sive study indicated that between 74 and 103 tonnes of oil remained on
the buoy, most of which could now be easily removed. That was very close
to the Shell estimate and far less than Greenpeace’s assertion that the buoy
contained 5,000 tonnes. Only 30 tonnes was low-level radioactive waste, a
level not considered dangerous and less than occurred naturally in areas
where there are granite rocks. The radioactivity originated in the stored oil
that was absorbed into the internal pipework. (Note: Another irony is that
bringing this radioactive lining ashore, as Greenpeace proposed, would
have been a violation of the UN convention against transferring contami-
nation from one environment to another.)
By late August, interviews with scientists and evidence uncovered
during the independent inspection revealed that the scuttling of the plat-
form was far less environmentally problematic than Greenpeace had
intimated. It turned out that Greenpeace took its sludge samples through
the top of the vent pipes on the uppermost deck, and not from the storage
tanks proper. These samples would have been predominantly oil that had
floated to the top of these pipes.
The media turned, particularly the more conservative press. ‘Minor
Mistake Which Tipped The Balance’, headlined the Daily Mail (6
September 1995). The Express ran a story entitled ‘Dark side of
Greenpeace do-gooders’ under the heading ‘D AILY E XPRESS – Asking The
Straight Questions’ (6 September 1995). Even the Guardian, which posi-
tioned itself as an ally of Greenpeace throughout the controversy, noted
almost apologetically that
• Sir John Vane, winner of a Nobel Prize for medicine, wrote ‘in the
clamour (made by Greenpeace) … the quiet, logical voice of science,
and of common sense … drowned. Reason said that the Brent Spar
should be buried. Emotion and irrationality have dictated otherwise’
(Daily Mail, 22 June 1995);
• University of London professors Euan Nisbet and Mary Fowler
suggested, ‘The environmental damage from the disposal of the Brent
Spar in (the Atlantic) would probably be minimal. … By concentrating
on and sensationalising relatively small problems, we risk making
poor judgments and neglecting more serious issues facing the environ-
ment’ (Nature, June 1995);
• Emeritus Professor Jack Pridham, also of the University of London,
claimed that the ‘toxic contents of this platform would have been a
biological pin-prick in this immense volume of water’ (letter to The
Times, 23 June 1995);
• Dr Martin Angel noted, ‘Every day more metal is pumped into the
oceans from volcanic vents of the seabed than is produced from mines
on land. The sea copes with this quite effectively. Brent Spar would
not have changed a thing’ (letter to the Observer, 2 June 1995);
• Aberdeen University professor, Alastair McIntyre, who was privy to
the AURIS research promoted by Greenpeace, opined that Greenpeace
had mistakenly claimed that onshore disposal was the preferable
70 Jon Entine
Although positioning itself as taking the ethical and scientific high road,
Greenpeace never made a persuasive case. Greenpeace did not provide
substantial risk–benefit analysis to support their view that land disposal
was the environmentally superior choice. All actions, and even inaction,
entail some degree of risk, some identifiable and some not. Greenpeace’s
campaign rested on a visceral belief that deep-sea disposal would disrupt
‘nature’ more than land decommissioning. By the time Shell officials had
authorized the burial of the Spar, the risks were widely documented (and
generally considered less severe than the land disposal option). It’s clear
that Shell did not flaunt the ‘precautionary principle.’
Initial media reports were far more sympathetic to Greenpeace than to
Shell. That may have reflected the lack of scientific sophistication of many
reporters, a general disdain for risk–benefit analysis, and a suspicion of
corporate greenwashing. Yet, in the months and years since the contro-
versy, numerous independent reports have reaffirmed Shell’s scientific
analysis that deep-sea disposal was environmentally and economically the
best disposal option. Greenpeace’s original claims, on which they justified
their guerrilla actions, appeared increasingly far-fetched. One of the most
authoritative independent analyses, by the National Environmental Re-
search Council (NERC 1996), was commissioned by the UK Department
of Trade and Industry. It concluded that despite the presence of ‘glaring
errors’ in Shell’s original BPEO, the global impact of the deep-sea disposal
of Spar would have been very small (Rice 1996a).
The NERC assessment stated, ‘In reaching decisions about disposal
options … factors including social, ethical, aesthetic, legal and economic
factors must be considered in addition to the scientific evidence.’ It exam-
ined a range of disposal options and their potential effects, negative and
positive, on the environment:
Deep-sea disposal
• Destruction of organisms through physical impact of the structure
and associated smothering by disturbed bottom sediments; and
72 Jon Entine
Conclusions/lessons
Nobody came out of the Brent Spar battle well. By any measure, Shell
sought an objective assessment of the various Brent Spar disposal options.
Yet it sought to keep its original scuttle plans secret. That can be seen as a
display of arrogance or a prudent decision, considering the absolute oppo-
sition by Greenpeace and (initially) sections of the media to the option that
the scientists suggested was scientifically and financially most responsible.
Greenpeace consistently made its moral opposition to deep-sea dumping
loud and clear. Yet it compromised its appeal to the moral high ground by
exaggerating the dangers posed by the ocean disposal of Brent Spar.
Moreover, it grounded its campaign on a radical interpretation of the
precautionary principle, which allowed it to justify a scientifically ques-
tionable claim of imminent danger.
Neither side had clean hands, which is usually the case when ethical
principles are so ambiguous. Greenpeace saw its reputation for integrity
eroded among the international press corps, although the UK government
and Shell faired worse with the general public. In 1996, Bob Worcester,
chairman of the polling firm MORI (Market & Opinion Research
International), in a paper ‘Business and the environment: in the aftermath
of Brent Spar and BSE’ concluded that ‘Greenpeace won the battle by ten
to one in the eyes of the British public’ but its ‘scientific methods were
flawed’. The UK government lost credibility and its ‘confidence [hubris?]
in its own infallibility’ was ‘unshared by the public’, while ‘Shell lost some
of its most precious asset, its reputation’. It was, Worcester concluded, ‘a
turning point in British attitudes to companies, to government and to envi-
ronmental groups’.
As a consequence of the backlash, British officials became far more
cautious in dealing with the decommissioning issue as they recalculated
trade-offs between industry and government and assessed the political
fallout. However, a major shift in policy did not occur until May 1997
when Britain elected a new Labour government, which declared in autumn
1997 that it would operate a presumption against ocean disposal.
Brent Spar was also a wake-up call to the press, which has traditionally
assumed as its default predilection that corporations lie and activists’
groups tell the truth. It underscores the reality that the media are never
impartial, although they can strive for reasonable disclosure of their own
biases and for basic fairness. They must become more vigilant and scep-
tical when it comes to choosing sources. Greenpeace had long boasted in
its publications of its skill in manipulating the media. At the Edinburgh
International Television Festival in August 1995, the BBC, ITN and
Channel 4 led reflections on the way the media had portrayed a one-sided
view of the Brent Spar debacle. As it turned out, Greenpeace had spent
more than $(US)500,000 for TV equipment to beam back the deep-sea
battle scene. David Lloyd of Channel 4 acknowledged that his news organ-
74 Jon Entine
ization had relied too much on Greenpeace news releases. ‘Greenpeace was
pulling us by the nose’, added an embarrassed Richard Sambrook, head of
newsgathering at the BBC. During the public brouhaha, the BBC had let its
enthusiasm for good pictures trump its responsibility for integrity by will-
ingly airing whatever exciting video beamed its way. In referring to
Greenpeace, Sambrook noted, ‘This particular David was not armed with
a slingshot so much as an AK-47’ (6 September 1995).
With the passage of time, certain journalists have engaged in what can
only be called historical revisionism. In one prominent example, New
Scientist gave Greenpeace UK executive director Peter Melchett two pages
of free advertising in the guise of an annual update to make the case that
Brent Spar was actually a ‘defining (positive) moment for the environmental
movement’. While admitting that ‘Greenpeace made mistakes too’,
Melchett excused its actions with the claim that this was only because ‘we
allowed ourselves to follow the agenda set by the [Department of Trade and
Industry], Shell and the media – too often getting into arguments about the
potential toxicity of the Spar’ (New Scientist, 23 December 1995). In other
words, Greenpeace erred in so far as it let the issue turn on the particulars
of this case rather than on the slippery slope argument that this dumping
would open the way to massive dumping and irreparable pollution.
Greenpeace’s actions during and since Brent Spar have emboldened
those who assert that pressure groups need to be held more accountable
and that exaggerating environmental hazards weakens the credibility of the
entire environmental movement. ‘Deep-sea disposal seemed the least
harmful option’, concluded Robert Sangeorge, a spokesman for the
Switzerland-based Worldwide Fund for Nature. Brent Spar ‘was a circus
and sideshow that distracted from the big environmental issues affecting
the world’ (Wall Street Journal, 7 July 1995). One overriding lesson of
Brent Spar is usually lost on both sides: beware of all spin-doctors, in suits
and even those dressed in green. Although government agencies and corpo-
rations have long charged that environmental activists exaggerate hazards,
engage in scare tactics and stoke media controversies through the use of
out-of-context anecdotes, rarely have the stakes been so high. In this media-
driven age, clever ‘green’ and ‘progressive’ companies and ‘public interest’
groups sometimes act like the old hard-line corporations they ridicule.
According to the common wisdom, Brent Spar radically altered corpo-
rate environmental management strategy. ‘Shell did everything by the
book’, wrote the environment-business magazine Tomorrow, ‘It’s just that
the Brent Spar changed the book.’ Shell postponed its annual Better Britain
environmental awards due to the ‘inappropriate’ atmosphere. The high-
profile Greenpeace campaign also had an effect on other major companies
who were struggling to balance increased financial demands from investors
with the public’s newly inflamed environmental concerns. In an effort to
help this process, the UK oil and gas industry recently set up the North Sea
Shell, Greenpeace and Brent Spar 75
Friedman concluded that businesses that act in the best interest of share-
holders maximize the benefits to all stakeholders. ‘There is one and only
one social responsibility of business – to use its resources and engage in
activities designed to increase its profits so long as it stays within the rules
of the game, which is to say, engages in open and free competition,
without deception or fraud’ (ibid.).
By traditional standards, Shell’s decision to commission risk/benefit
analysis of the various disposal options demonstrated that it took its social
responsibilities seriously. Shell officials believed they were carefully
weighing investor expectations and their stewardship responsibilities for
the environment. The key problem, according to more liberal stakeholder
theory, is that these ethical calculations were made by Shell officials alone
and only included other potential stakeholder perspectives at Shell’s
behest. Although the company sought input from a variety of sources that
it considered stakeholders, it acted with little public consultation and
certainly against the wishes of some environmental groups that, rightly or
wrongly, believed that they better represented the interests of the natural
environment.
The issue over who deserves a place at the negotiating table as legiti-
mate stakeholder (or stakeholder representatives, as Greenpeace saw itself)
haunted the Brent Spar controversy throughout. Dialogue can only work
when the participants are perceived as legitimate.
Publicly, Shell appeared to embrace the broader conception of stake-
holder responsibility, asserting that it would make ‘openness’ the
watchword for the future (BBC 1996). Heinz Rothermund, managing
director of Shell Exploration UK said the Spar had set a precedent in how
Shell treated the public. ‘Brent Spar will enter history as the symbol of our
failure to establish our position and connect in a meaningful way with a
wider audience’ (Scotsman, 16 April 1997). However, it is reasonable to
suspect that Shell’s post-crisis confessions of myopia and calls for dialogue
were more reactive and tactical than defining. Most corporations, Shell
included, have long recognized that they operate at a disadvantage in the
court of public opinion because of deep concerns about their motives,
which Greenpeace exploited. This incident made them more sensitive to
public opinion, which Shell believed was not always rational. ‘We hadn’t
taken into account hearts and emotions, you know, where people are
coming from, which is in part today’s debate’, noted Chris Fay, chairman
of Shell UK (BBC 1995).
In retrospect, the lessons appear ambiguous and contradictory. Dr
Angel, for one, has expressed his ‘enormous frustration’ at the lack of
sophistication displayed by all sides over the scientific issues, even by Shell
and the British government. Dr Angel writes:
Shell, Greenpeace and Brent Spar 77
One example of this was when we were trying to put some informa-
tion about biodiversity in the public domain. There had been a[n
erroneous] comment made in the media that disposal of the Spar off
Rosemary Bank would result in the extinction of several species. We
argued that while dumping the Spar would undoubtedly kill one or
two million worms, similar numbers would be killed by dumping the
waste in landfill. The problem was that Tim Eggar proceeded to put
out a statement in which he left out the ‘million’ [he wrote: ‘one or
two worms’] and proceeded to argue that the deep-sea is a low diver-
sity environment. We [Angel’s research group] were then pilloried for
this obvious untruth. Greenpeace showed a remarkable facility for
selective deafness.
(Angel 2001)
started what we call ‘the post-Brent Spar effect,’ he commented that same
summer. ‘Now we’re seeing that as soon as we announce a campaign,
companies back down. This happened most recently with Unilever. The
company said it would stop using products obtained by industrial fishing
in the North Sea before we could even launch our campaign actions. But
perhaps the most important lesson was the realization of what we can do
with market forces. It wasn’t Greenpeace’s strength that made Shell back
down; it was the consumer boycotts’ (Time International, 10 June 1996).
It is not clear whether dialogue would benefit the causes Greenpeace
has historically supported. As Paul Horsman, the Greenpeace leader of the
Brent Spar campaign said, ‘With the environmental movement, there’s a
sleeping giant that can be awakened very, very easily and very, very
quickly’ with such tactics (Wall Street Journal, 7 July 1995). It is arguable
that in the face of enormous corporate resources (Shell), and a less than
receptive government (UK Conservative Party), anything short of a shrill,
high-profile campaign in which violence was a threat would have resulted
in public debate. In other words, the anti-rational, emotive campaigns that
Greenpeace now claim they may eschew may yet remain its most effective
tactic considering the natural imbalance of power when public interest
groups square off against multinational corporations or conservative
governments.
Incident-driven development of international standards in a politically
charged atmosphere raises complicated business and ethical concerns. In
retrospect, managing public perception, rather than the need for more
dialogue and scientific rigour are the most important lessons from Brent
Spar. Brent Spar reaffirms that the simplistic distinction between ‘progres-
sive’ activist groups that purportedly fight for the little guy and so-called
‘evil’ corporations is a caricature that disguises a more textured reality.
Does this conclusion suggest that future conflicts are inevitable? Not
necessarily. There are encouraging, though limited, signs that dialogue
outside of the crisis framework that prevailed in Brent Spar might offer
some relief. As The Economist noted, the incident encouraged a ‘growing
universe’ of corporate behaviour to which ‘standards of correctness are
being applied’, so that ‘good firms will have to listen hard and explain
even harder’ (10 May 1997). Shell, like many companies during the
nineties that faced challenges about their environmental practices, estab-
lished a Social Accountability Team to review corporate practices.
Is this a sincere effort or strategic corporate greenwashing designed to
inoculate Shell against protests that are more virulent? Undoubtedly, it’s a
little of both. In the short term, Shell is determined to resuscitate its public
image. More than two years after the affair, in April 1998, Shell issued a
social accountability report, ‘Profits and Principles – Does There Have to
be a Choice?’ At Shell’s invitation, John Elkington prepared a ‘triple
bottom line’ analysis that was incorporated in the report assessing
80 Jon Entine
References
Angel, Martin V. (1995) ‘Brent Spar: no hiding place’, Biologist 42(4): 192.
—— (2001) E-mail exchange with author (May).
Bahree, Bhushan, Pope, Kyle and Sullivan, Allana, ‘Giant outsmarted: How Green-
peace sank Shell’s plan to dump big oil rig in Atlantic’, The Wall Street Journal,
7 July 1995, p. A1.
BBC (1995) ‘The Battle for Brent Spar’, BBC Public Eye, transmitted 2 September
1995.
BBC (1996) ‘Will Green Warriors Get a Say in the Boardroom?’, The Money
Programme, 24 March.
Bombace, G. (1989) ‘Artificial reefs in the Mediterranean Sea’, Bulletin of Marine
Science, 44(2): 1023–32.
82 Jon Entine
Bragdon, J.H. and Marlin, J.A.T. (1972) ‘Is pollution profitable?’, Risk Manage-
ment, 19(4): 9–18.
The Economist, ‘Shell man says sorry’, 10 May 1997.
—— ‘The non-governmental order: will NGOs democratise, or merely disrupt,
global governance?’, 11–17 December 1999: 18–19.
Elkington, J. (1997) ‘Laying the ghost of Brent Spar’, Resurgence, 3 September 1997.
Entine, Jon, (1994) ‘Shattered image: is the Body Shop too good to be true?’, Busi-
ness Ethics 8(5): 23–8.
—— (1995) ‘Rain-forest chic’, Toronto Globe & Mail Report on Business 12(4):
40–52.
Financial Times, ‘Greenpeace’s new head outlines the organisation’s strategy for
working with business’, 10 January 1996.
Fogler, H.R. and Nutt, F. (1975) ‘A note on social responsibility and stock valua-
tion’, Academy of Management Journal 18: 155–60.
Freeman, Edward and Reed, David L. (1983) ‘Stockholders and stakeholders: a
new perspective on corporate governance’, California Management Review
25(3): 88–106.
Friedman, Milton (1984) ‘Milton Friedman responds’, interview in Business and
Society 84(5).
Greenpeace Web Site: http://www.gre.ac.uk.
Guardian, ‘A Flotilla of Questions, 7 September 1995.
Jennings, Marianne and Entine, Jon (1998) ‘Business with a soul: a re-examination
of what counts in business ethics’, Hamline Journal of Public Law and Policy
20(1): 1–88.
Melchett, Peter (2001) ‘Green for danger’, New Scientist 148 (2009): 50–1.
National Environmental Research Council (1996) ‘Scientific Group on the Decom-
missioning of Offshore Structures: First Report’, April 1996, Swindon: NERC
(www.nerc.ac.uk).
Pearce, F. (1995a) ‘Breaking up is hard to do,’ New Scientist 146(1983): 14–15.
—— (1995b) ‘Storm warning over Brent Spar,’ New Scientist, 147(1992): 4.
Picken, G.B and McIntyre, A.D. (1989) ‘Rigs to reefs in the North Sea,’ Bulletin of
Marine Science 44(2): 782–8.
Rice, A. (1996a) ‘The beached buoy’, The Times, 31 May 1996: iv.
—— (1996b) ‘The lessons of Brent Spar,’ Endeavour, 20: 47–9.
Rockness, J., Schlachter, P. and Rockness, H.O. (1986) ‘Hazardous waste disposal,
corporate disclosure, and financial performance in the chemical industry’, in M.
Neimark (ed.) Advances in Public Interest Accounting, vol. 1, Greenwich, CT:
JAI Press, pp. 167–91.
Scotsman, ‘Brent Spar a gaffe says Shell chief’, 16 April 1997.
Spicer, B.H. (1978) ‘Market risk, accounting data, and companies’ pollution
control records,’ Journal of Business, Finance, and Accounting 5: 67–83.
Time International (1996) ‘The man who keeps the Echo Warriors in control’, 10
June: 147(24).
United Kingdom Oil and Gas Industry Association: http://www.ukooa.co.uk.
Wood, Graham (1996) ‘Guarding the corporate reputation: learning the ethical
lessons from ‘Brent Spar’, August 1996.
Shell, Greenpeace and Brent Spar 83
Actually, I think most countries in the EU think this is dirty and that it
should be stopped … [I]t is good that Greenpeace is around to ensure
these things do not go on secretly.
Ritt Bjerregaard, EU Commissioner for the Environment
There are many problems in the North Sea. Many of the platforms out
there are about to reach the time when they will have to be scrapped.
This has to be done in a safe manner and the only way this can be
done is on land.
Svend Auken, Danish Minister for Environment and Energy
Shell, Greenpeace and Brent Spar 85
(i) There has been no formal inventory of the Brent Spar’s contents, so
the environmental impacts could not possibly be properly assessed.
(ii) There is a lack of understanding of the deep sea environment, and it is
currently impossible to predict the effects of the proposed dumping on
deep sea ecosystems.
(iii) The documents which supported Shell’s licence application are highly
conjectural in nature. They contain numerous unsubstantiated
assumptions, minimal data and extrapolations from unnamed studies.
(iv) Dumping the Brent Spar would create a precedent for dumping other
contaminated structures in the sea and would undermine current inter-
national agreements. The environmental effects of further dumping
would be cumulative.
(v) Dismantling of the Brent Spar is technically feasible and offshore engi-
neering firms believe they can do it safely and effectively. The necessary
facilities are already routinely in use and decommissioning of many other
oil installations has already been carried out elsewhere in the world.
(vi) To protect the environment, the principle of minimising the generation
of wastes should be upheld and harmful materials always recycled,
treated or contained.
Greenpeace believes Shell UK were right in not dumping the Brent Spar.
This view is supported by most governments in Europe and a vast majority
of the public. There will always be scientific debate, but in the arena of
this debate the principle of precautionary action is applied and the benefit
of the doubt given to the environment.
86 Jon Entine
‘This report clearly shows that scientific opinion does not back Govern-
ment policy’, said Dr Helen Wallace of Greenpeace UK. Energy Minister
Mr Tim Eggar ‘should stop using science as an excuse to ignore public
concern about the environment’.
Greenpeace said today’s report gave a strong backing to the decision
made by the Oslo Paris Commission last year to agree a moratorium on
the disposal at sea of decommissioned offshore installations. The UK and
Norwegian governments have expressed reservations to the moratorium.
Appendix 2
Atlantic? The first point to make is that no matter what option is chosen
there will be deleterious effects. It is a question of choosing the lesser evil.
The quantity of heavy metals now left in Brent Spar after decommis-
sioning is probably less than that in any large ship. Since hydrothermal
vents expel heavy metals into the deep ocean in quantities that rival the
output of the world’s mining industry, many deep ocean inhabitants are
well adapted to cope with a metal-rich environment. The site chosen was
in 2000 m of water in a hollow, southwest of Rosemary Bank, through
which swirls one of the outflows of cold Norwegian Sea water. This
swirling flow would have rapidly dispersed any contaminants leaking from
the rig. This deep dense water takes at least 250 years to return back to the
surface, by which time the relatively small amounts of heavy metal would
have been stripped out by the sedimentary rain of material from the
surface and redeposited onto the bottom, and gradually incorporated into
the geological record.
It is most improbable that bio-accumulation within the food-web would
have been a problem. At depths of 2000 m the standing crop of organisms
is less than a fiftieth of those in shallow water. Consequently, there are no
potential living resources at such depths, and there are very few biological
pathways along which contaminants might move back up to the surface.
Similarly, the residual hydrocarbons pose no serious environmental
threat – hydrocarbons occur naturally in the deep ocean. Where there are
natural seeps, large communities of animals use them as a source of
organic material. Nor would the enhanced radioactivity in the stored drill
cuttings pose much of a risk. The radioactivity is at such a low level that
even on land it would pose no more radiological threat than living in a
granite building in Aberdeen.
There is less certainty about the persistent synthetic organic
compounds; we know so little about how they might move in deep ocean
communities. However, since the ultimate fate of all such materials is to
become incorporated into deep ocean sediments, discharging them at the
bottom of the deep ocean is likely to be a short-cut.
Questions of biodiversity are complex. The sediment faunas of macro-
and meio-benthos at 2000 m in the deep ocean appear to be as species rich
as some of the most diverse terrestrial habitats. We know that larger
species inhabiting the sea-floor have enormous geographical ranges, and it
seems reasonable to assume that the smaller organisms will be similarly
widely distributed. One habitat type that is in short supply in the deep
ocean is provided by hard surfaces, so in that sense the rig would have
enhanced the diversity of habitat.
The aspect that Shell was most concerned about was whether the rig
would trigger a mass wasting event when it landed on the bottom, and this
was one reason for their having selected a hollow in the sea-bed. In the
North Atlantic, the geological record contains evidence of repeated
90 Jon Entine
Ever since mankind started to cross the oceans in ships, the ocean bed has
been littered with his debris, ranging from sunken wrecks to clinker and
other rubbish. During the last World War, millions of tonnes of shipping
were sunk, each wreck representing a source of contamination comparable
to the Spar. Are the impacts of these tragedies yet another environmental
time-bomb ticking away, or are they serendipitous experiments that we can
use to evaluate the safety of deep ocean disposal? The deep ocean is poten-
tially a safe repository for many types of waste, so long as it is properly
managed, monitored and controlled. However, there is a general distrust in
the ability and willingness of Industry and Government adequately to
manage such disposal, and this will sway many into supporting the
Greenpeace view. Yet we cannot afford to discard the option of using the
deep ocean without full and proper environmental audit of the costs
entailed. Was this a victory for the environment? Personally, I doubt it, but
now that Pandora’s Box is open, how are we to close it?
Appendix 3
June 1976
Brent Spar installed in Brent Field, a unique design for oil storage and
tanker loading. Two of six tanks later damaged in operation. Structure
also later found to have been stressed during installation making major
difficulties in reversing procedure to raise from water.
September 1991
Brent Spar ceases operating.
1991–1993
Detailed decommissioning studies carried out by Shell and independent
external organizations and contractors to assess options. Two compared
in detail – horizontal onshore dismantling and deep-sea disposal with
deep sea emerging with six times lower safety risks, four times less cost
and minimal environmental impact.
1994
February
Independent Aberdeen University study (AURIS) endorses choice of
deep-sea disposal. Formal consultations with conservation bodies and
fishing interests. Draft Abandonment Plan submitted.
December
Shell submits final Abandonment Plan to UK Government Department
of Trade and Industry and receives approval.
1995
February
UK Government announces approval for deep-sea disposal and notifies
13 other contracting parties (12 nations and EC), signatories to the
Oslo Convention covering protection of the marine environment. No
objections raised within normal time limit. Shell announces deep-sea
disposal plan.
30 April
Greenpeace activists occupy Spar, wrongly alleging Spar is ‘a toxic time-
bomb’; ‘14,500 tonnes of toxic rubbish’; or contains ‘over 100 tonnes
of toxic sludge’. Over next months they say Spar will be ‘dumped in the
North Sea’ rather than disposed of at a carefully selected site in the deep
Atlantic and suggest ‘more than 400 oil rigs in the North Sea’ might
also be ‘dumped’. They say Spar contains 5,550 tonnes of oil.
92 Jon Entine
5 May
UK Government grants disposal licence to Shell UK.
9 May
German Ministry of the Environment protests against disposal plan.
13 May
Independent UK scientists begin stating support for deep-sea disposal
for Brent Spar.
23 May
Activists removed from Spar. Greenpeace calls for Shell boycott in
continental Europe.
8–9 June
Fourth North Sea Conference at Esbjerg, Denmark. Several European
countries now call for onshore disposal for all oil installations. UK and
Norway, the countries with the largest, heaviest, and most difficult
deep-water structures, argue for ‘case-by-case’.
11 June
Shell UK begins to tow Spar to deep Atlantic disposal site.
15–17 June
Public opinion in continental northern Europe strongly opposed.
Chancellor Kohl protests to UK Prime Minister John Major at G7 summit.
14–20 June
Protesters in Germany threaten to damage 200 Shell service stations. 50
are subsequently damaged, two fire-bombed and one raked with bullets.
20 June
Several continental northern European governments now indicate oppo-
sition. Shell UK decides to halt disposal plan in view of untenable
position caused by European political shifts, increased safety risks from
violence and need for more reasoned discussion.
Late June
UK scientific debate intensifies, with growing support for Shell approach
to environmental decision-making based on reason and sound science.
26–30 June
Eleven states call for a moratorium on sea disposal of decommissioned
offshore installations at meeting of Oslo and Paris Commissions.
Opposed by Britain and Norway.
7 July
Norway grants permission to moor Spar in Erfjord while Shell recon-
siders options.
12 July
Shell UK commissions independent Norwegian foundation Det Norske
Veritas (DNV) to conduct another audit of Spar’s contents and investi-
gate Greenpeace allegations.
Shell, Greenpeace and Brent Spar 93
12–18 July
UK Government makes clear that any new plan for which Shell UK
seeks approval, must be at least as good or better than deep-sea disposal
on the Best Practicable Environmental Option criteria.
26 August
UK television executives admit to lack of objectivity and balance in
coverage of the Spar story, and to using dramatic film footage from
Greenpeace which eclipsed the facts.
5 September
Greenpeace admits inaccurate claims that Spar contains 5,550 tonnes of
oil and apologises to Shell.
8 September
After a meeting between Dr Chris Fay, Chairman and Chief Executive
of Shell UK and Peter Melchett, Executive Director of Greenpeace UK,
Greenpeace says it recognizes that Shell UK must work within the legal
framework of UK Government policy and the BPEO.
11 September
UK scientists reiterate support for rational, science-based environmental
decisions at British Association for the Advancement of Science.
June–October
Shell receives more than 200 proposals for onshore disposal or re-use of
Spar.
11 October
Shell Expro outlines new ‘Way Forward’ to find a solution for Spar
disposal or re-use. Notice placed in the Official Journal of the European
Communities inviting expressions of interest from major contractors.
Their submissions, with the 200 unsolicited proposals, to be analysed to
produce a ‘Long List’ of 20 to 30 organizations then to be asked to
meet pre-qualification criteria.
18 October
Det Norske Veritas (DNV) presents results of its independent audit,
endorsing the thoroughness and professional competence with which
Shell and its consultants prepared the original Spar inventory. DNV
confirms that the amount of oil claimed by Greenpeace to be in the Spar
was ‘grossly overestimated’.
30 November
DNV further report no PCBs (polychlorinated biphenyls) on Brent Spar.
1996
22 March
Shell Expro launch original Brent Spar web site.
94 Jon Entine
22 May
‘Scientific Group on Decommissioning Offshore Structures’ report
published by the Natural Environment Research Council confirming
earlier Shell studies that environmental effects of deep-sea disposal of
Spar would have been very small and localized.
3 July
Shell announces ‘Long List’ – 21 leading contractors from eight nations
on the challenge to find the BPEO for Brent Spar. Competitors given
four weeks to develop outline concepts.
New structural analysis confirms that reversing Spar’s original instal-
lation procedure to raise it out of the sea for dismantling would be far
from straightforward.
Shell outlines how the new Spar Dialogue will help Shell identify a
solution by gathering a wide range of views and values.
31 July
Thirty outline proposals for Brent Spar disposal submitted by Long List
contractors.
15 August
Shell publishes Long List outline proposals.
1 November
First Brent Spar Dialogue Seminar in London – organised for Shell by
the Environment Council, an independent charity which helps different
interest groups work together to find common ground.
1997
13 January
Shell announces ‘Short List’ – six leading international contractors and
consortia to develop in detail 11 different ideas for re-using or scrap-
ping Spar.
Short List contractors given four months to complete studies and
make detailed commercial bids.
20 February
DNV commissioned to carry out independent evaluation of proposals
to ensure technical, safety and environmental aspects of each bid can be
compared on a like-for-like basis.
11 March
Brent Spar Dialogue Seminar in Denmark.
9 April
Short List contractors’ deadline extended by a month to beginning June.
14–18 April
Brent Spar and the Way Forward a major feature of the British Pavilion
at the Hanover Fair in Germany.
Shell, Greenpeace and Brent Spar 95
30 May
Brent Spar Dialogue Seminar in Rotterdam.
2 June
Six Short List contractors submit nine detailed proposals.
17 June
Shell publishes CD-Rom of proposals with computer animation, inter-
active maps and video sequences.
13 October
Shell announces Way Forward final stages and DNV publishes indepen-
dent findings together with contractors’ bid prices.
15–28 October
More Brent Spar Dialogue seminars in London, Copenhagen, Rotter-
dam and Hamburg.
November–January 1998
Shell carries out its final BPEO evaluation.
1998
29 January
Shell announces its choice of solution for Spar – a ‘one-off’ re-use as a
Norwegian Ro/Ro ferry quay.
Decommissioning Plan submitted to UK Government – the first step in
gaining approval.
26 August
UK Government announces its approval of Shell Exploration and
Production’s choice of solution.
25 November
Spar topsides are successfully removed.
1999
10 July
The project is effectively completed when cut and cleaned ring sections
of Spar’s hull are placed on the seabed at Mekjarvik to form the base of
a new quay. Taking into account expenditures related to the initial
aborted deep-sea disposal of the spar, the costs total close to $96
million.
1 September
Shell Expro hosts a feedback seminar in London for interested parties
and stakeholders providing details of Spar’s decommissioning.
Copyright Shell UK Limited, November 1998
Chapter 4
Whistleblowing
The new perspective
Gordon Borrie and Guy Dehn 1
Introduction
Whistleblowing is relevant to all organizations and all people, not just
those few who are corrupt or criminal. This is because every business and
every public body faces the risk of things going wrong or of unknowingly
harbouring a corrupt individual. Where such a risk arises, usually the first
people to realize or suspect the wrongdoing will be those who work in or
with the organization. Yet these people, who are best placed to sound the
alarm or blow the whistle, often fear they have most to lose if they do.
Unless culture, practice and the law indicate that it is safe and accepted
for them to raise a genuine concern about corruption or illegality, workers
will assume that they risk victimization, losing their job or damaging their
career. Firms and companies aware that a bribe has been solicited will fear
not only that they will lose the contract if they do not pay, but that if they
blow the whistle their future economic interests will be damaged and their
staff will be harassed.
In considering this issue, it may be helpful to bear in mind the approach
taken with a criminal who decides to testify in criminal proceedings
against his or her former accomplices or colleagues. The authorities in all
nation states value such collaborators and will often offer them protection
Whistleblowing: the new perspective 97
The dilemma
In practical terms, if someone is concerned about corruption or serious
wrongdoing in or by an organization, they have three options. These are
• to stay silent;
• to blow the whistle internally or with the responsible person;
• to blow the whistle outside to the authorities or the media;
Silence
Silence is the option of least risk both for the individual worker and for a
responsible firm which comes across corruption. It will be attractive for
98 Gordon Borrie and Guy Dehn
many reasons. The whistleblower will realize that his or her facts could be
mistaken or that there may be an innocent explanation. Where colleagues
or competitors are also aware of the suspect conduct but stay silent, the
whistleblower will wonder why he or she should speak out. In organiza-
tions where labour relations are adversarial, and in cultures where
corruption is common, the whistleblower is likely to assume that he or she
will be expected to prove that the corrupt practice is occurring, rather than
see those in authority investigate and deal with the matter. Even though he
or she has no control over it, the whistleblower may feel responsibility for
any action that may be taken against the wrongdoer. Finally, unless the
whistleblower believes there is a good chance that something will be done
to address the wrongdoing, it is almost inevitable that he or she will stay
silent.
Even if he or she thinks the alarm should be sounded, the whistleblower
will want to consider his or her private interests before taking action.
Without reassurance to the contrary, the whistleblower will fear reprisals –
be it harassment or dismissal. The whistleblower may also suspect (rightly
or wrongly) that the corruption involves, implicates or is condoned by
more senior people in or outside the organization, in which case he or she
will fear the matter will be covered up. Even where these obstacles are
overcome or reduced, the whistleblower will fear that he or she will be
labelled as disloyal by the generality of colleagues whose respect and trust
the whistleblower may want or need in future.
Time and again similar messages come out of official inquiries into major
scandals and disasters. They reveal that people who worked in or with the
organization had seen the problem but had either been too scared to sound
the alarm or had raised the matter in the wrong way or with the wrong
person. Quite apart from the tragic human costs and enormous financial
damage caused in these cases, they undermine public confidence not only
in the organization concerned but also in business and governments more
generally. These wider implications are serious. In a changing competitive
world, the very success of business, public bodies and new technologies
relies on public confidence in their openness and probity.
Whenever there is a scandal or major disaster that could have been
averted, there is pressure for new regulatory controls. Although these are
aimed at the reckless, they often impose burdens on responsible organiza-
tions in the sector, thereby damaging competition. Each disaster also calls
into question the mechanisms by which law and society oversee the
102 Gordon Borrie and Guy Dehn
conduct of private and public bodies. And each successive scandal renews
mistrust and scepticism about the role and work of governments and busi-
ness. The resignation of the European Commission in March 1999 is a
case in point. The Committee of Independent Experts remarked that the
facts demonstrated ‘the value of officials whose conscience persuades them
of the need to expose wrongdoings encountered in the course of their
duties. They also show how the reaction of superiors failed to live up to
legitimate expectations.’4
Winds of change
For all the above reasons there is growing acceptance of the case for a new
approach to whistleblowing. With the changing nature of employment,
globalization and the increased flow of information, there is also a recog-
nition that the traditional approach of trust and confidentiality in the
workplace cannot be relied upon to operate as it did through the twentieth
century. While trust and confidence is of critical importance in any
community or organization, to be effective it cannot be blind or unques-
tioning. Whistleblowing cultures which emphasize internal reporting are a
means by which the abuse of trust and confidence can be checked and by
which asymmetrical accountabilities of those within the workplace can be
understood and developed. If the organization is prepared to promote and
implement such a culture, any risk of it being hijacked by petty vendettas
will be minimized, if not removed.
This approach sees whistleblowing as a means to deter wrongdoing,
promote transparency and good governance, underpin self-regulation and
maintain public confidence. It is the approach which has been put on a
legislative footing in the UK and in South Africa in recent years.5 These
laws differ somewhat from the protection offered in the USA, which has
had whistleblowing legislation for over a century offering substantial
rewards to employees. While other provisions in the USA are rooted in the
concepts of freedom of expression, and those in Australia and New
Zealand are concerned with ethics in the public sector, these recent devel-
opments in the UK and South Africa address the issue of accountability
across all institutions.
Essentially, the new approach sees whistleblowing as a means to deliver
good management, to maintain public confidence and to promote organi-
zational accountability. These help everyone identify who is accountable
for what and to whom. While this has secured strong support from busi-
ness, unions and professional interests, it would be misleading to suggest
that the underlying principles are anything new. Based on ethical provi-
sions recognized by many religions, the principles were adopted and
developed into a balanced and practical approach in jurisprudence. Such
judge-made laws recognize both the public interest in maintaining confi-
dences and the particular circumstances where whistleblowing disclosures
Whistleblowing: the new perspective 105
outside can be justified. Like race and sex discrimination laws, the pre-
eminent aim of the UK initiatives has been to declare a change in culture.
The resulting legislation was commended by one of the most senior UK
judges for ‘so skilfully achieving the essential but delicate balance between
the public interest and the interest of employers’.6 It seeks to embed a
system where, in the words of independent experts called in by the
European Union, ‘the duty of loyalty and discretion should not become an
empty concept, but neither must it be used to install a conspiracy of
silence’.7 This UK approach has also been commended by both manage-
ment and labour interests at the OECD, who have recommended that it is
fed into the forthcoming revisions to the Anti-Bribery Convention.8
Notes
1 Gordon (now Lord) Borrie and Guy Dehn were, respectively, the founding
chairman and director of Public Concern at Work, an independent UK charity
which addresses ethics, accountability and whistleblowing. More information
about the charity’s activities (including details of the UK legislation and Third
Report, July 1997, p. 49) are available on its website at www.pcaw.co.uk.
2 UK Committee on Standards in Public Life, Second Report, May 1996, p. 22.
3 Asia Week, 19 November 1999, commented that Japanese culture deprecates
whistleblowing yet seems to condone the resignation or even suicide of top
executives when unchecked wrongdoing leads to major disaster.
4 The Committee of Independent Experts, Second Report, para. 7.6.9.
5 The Public Interest Disclosure Act, 1998, provides protection against reprisals
for good faith whistleblowing on wrongdoing. It directs the worker toward
seeking confidential advice and to blowing the whistle internally or with the
person responsible. Provided there is good evidence to support the concern, it
also protects (a) whistleblowing to designated authorities and (b) wider
whistleblowing where both the circumstances justify it (cover-up, victimization
or failure to address the matter) and the particular disclosure is reasonable
(having regard to the recipient of the disclosure, seriousness, risk, obligations
of confidence and the employer’s whistleblowing culture). The Protected
Disclosures Act, 2000, creates a similar regime in South Africa.
6 Lord Nolan, who had also chaired the Committee on Standards in Public Life.
7 See note 8, para 7.6.10. The European Commission’s proposals were published
in Feb 2000.
8 See OECD Labour/Management Programme – PAC/AFF/LMP(2000)1. This
chapter is a revised version of the discussion paper set out in that report, origi-
nally published under the title ‘Whistleblowing to combat corruption’,
PAC/AFF/LMP (2000)1, copyright OECD, 2000.
It can also be found at www.whistleblower.org/www/oecdreport.htm.
Chapter 5
David. She gave assurances that they would not be victimized and that
their careers would not suffer in any way. Bianca was unhappy with the
company’s responses, but she didn’t want to take things further. However,
Rick thought their attitude was unacceptable. He then wrote to Adrian
asking if the company would refund all of its customers who had been
overcharged. Adrian’s reply simply said that the company had taken
appropriate action and that it did not have to answer to Rick. Rick, who
estimates that the company has wrongly profited by about £1 million, has
told Bianca that they should warn the company that unless things are
sorted out they will go to the press.
Notes
1 This case history has been contributed by Public Concern at Work.
Chapter 6
Challenger flight 51-L was the tenth launch of the Challenger series, the
first launch from Cape Kennedy Launch Complex 39-B. Though this case
history focuses on the Challenger flight which ended tragically some 73
seconds into its flight on 28 January 1986, it is more to do with the whole
National Space Transportation System – the 24 launches prior to this one
and the ones scheduled after it. The Challenger was simply part of a
programme that summed up the technological capacity of the United
States. The programme as a whole was built on a series of myths, social,
technical and managerial, which sustained the national and political
interest and made management as well as politicians believe that over-
ambitious targets were feasible. In fact the whole programme remained
essentially experimental, with many threats to safety involved. Hence,
safety should have been at a premium. The safety programme, however,
was gradually eroded in the face of the many economic and political pres-
sures, and the management structure did not encourage managers or
engineers to state or press their concerns about safety. At various points
these concerns were expressed, but their implications were not taken seri-
ously by the management, and the critical issues were never addressed.
This case history will first outline the facts of the case. Then it will
examine the various points at which the whistle might have been blown,
drawing out the different perspectives of the people involved and also the
implications for the practice of whistleblowing. Finally, it will note the
conclusions of the Presidential Commission, with recommendations for a
more transparent management system which would encourage whistle-
blowing.
Challenger Flight 51-L 109
When the SRB was ignited the zinc chromate putty, which was above the
O-rings, was displaced. This had the effect of compressing the air between
the putty and the primary O-ring. The O-ring was then forced by the air
into the gap between tang and clevis. However, it was discovered that the
pressure then caused the walls of the cylinder to bulge slightly, which
caused a gap to open, increasing the risk of the gases escaping at the joint.
This was known as joint rotation.
In discussion with NASA, MTI set about altering the design so as to
increase the O-ring compression and thus decrease the joint rotation effect.
This led to three things: tightening the metal joints; increasing the O-ring
diameter and tightening its tolerance; and the use of shims, as noted above.
After the flight of the second Challenger mission (November 1981) a
further problem occurred. The O-rings were eroding during the flight, due
to the hot gases escaping past the putty. The solution was found in
providing different kinds of putty.
Of greater concern was a third problem, found in the shuttle flight 51-C
(24 January 1985). This flight was launched in extreme cold. Examination
of the SRB joints after this flight showed black soot and grease on the
outside of the casing, caused by the gas blowing through. This led to the
development of the Seal Erosion Task Team to study the compression and
reliability of the O-ring in low temperatures. In July of that year a new
design for the joint was being developed, and MTI ordered new steel
billets which would be used in the redesigning. The process of making
these billets was a long one and by 26 January 1986, the launch of the
Challenger 51-L, they were not ready.
As we shall see, other factors emerged in the discussion before the launch.
The launch
That night temperatures were even lower than forecast, at 8ºF. To keep the
water pipes on the launch pad from freezing, safety showers and fire hoses
were turned on. Some of this water accumulated, forming ice over the plat-
form. The ice inspection team feared that this might break away from the
platform and damage the heat-resistant tiles of the shuttle. A further
worrying and uncertain factor was the possibility of ice forming in the O-
ring grooves. The Challenger, the SRBs and the external fuel tank had all
been on the launch pad for 38 days, and, up to the freeze, seven inches of
Challenger Flight 51-L 113
rain had fallen. Nonetheless, the launch director decided to go ahead. Key
personnel, who did not know about the teleconference or the fears of the
MTI engineers, waived safety limitations on low temperatures.
When the launch came, the impact of ignition caused a shower of ice
from the platform. Some of this made contact with the left-hand SRB and
some was sucked into its nozzle. Shortly before lift-off, 0.678 seconds into
the flight, photographs clearly show a burst of grey smoke emerging from
the area of the aft field joint on the SRB, the area which faced the external
fuel tank. This already showed that there was ‘not complete sealing action
within the joint’.2 The putty which protected the O-rings had collapsed.
The cold had made it too stiff, allowing gases from the ignited solid fuel,
with temperatures of over 5,000ºF, to blow past both O-rings. Between
0.836 and 2.500 seconds into the flight there were eight more distinctive
bursts of smoke. The black colour and dense composition of the smoke
seemed to confirm that the grease joint insulation and O-rings were being
burned. Soon after the tower had been cleared the smoke stopped, indi-
cating that the oxides produced by the propellant had temporarily sealed
the field-joint gap before flames could escape.
At 37 seconds the Challenger was hit by the first of several high altitude
wind shears (winds of different speeds and directions close together which
lead to severe stress on aircraft). The steering mechanisms responded to
the buffeting, leading eventually to an increase in the SRB thrust. The first
small flame at the field joint was shown at 58.788 seconds, indicating a
breakdown of the temporary seal. At 59 seconds the most violent wind
shear of any shuttle mission was experienced. At 59.26 the small flame
grew into well-defined plumes and the breakdown of the seal was
confirmed when telemetry showed a pressure differential between chamber
pressures in the right- and left-hand SRBs. As the flame increased in size it
was deflected directly on to the external fuel tank. At 64.660 seconds the
colour and shape of the flame changed markedly, indicating that it was
mixing with hydrogen leaking from the tank.
Within 45 milliseconds a bright glow developed on the underside of the
Challenger itself. At 72.20 seconds the lower strut which linked the
Challenger’s SRB and the external fuel tank gave way and the right SRB
began to rotate around the upper strut. At 73.126 seconds, the after-dome
of the fuel tank gave way, releasing huge amounts of liquid hydrogen. The
subsequent forward thrust pushed the tank up into the lower part of the
liquid oxygen tank, leading to ‘structural failure’. At 73.137 there was an
explosive burn of hydrogen and oxygen that enveloped the Challenger.
The effect on the American nation was profound and the President
immediately ordered a commission, chaired by Senator Rogers, to investi-
gate the technical and other contributing causes of the accident, and to
make recommendations.
114 Simon Robinson
Analysis
Different managers and engineers at different points were presented with
key moments when the safety programme of the shuttle might have been
challenged:
The American taxpayer bet about $14 billion dollars on the shuttle.
NASA bet its reputation. The Air Force bet its reconnaissance capa-
bility. The astronauts bet their lives. We all took a chance. When John
Young and Robert Crippen climbed aboard the orbiter Columbia on
April 12, 1981 for the first shuttle launches, they took a bigger chance
than any astronaut before them. Never had Americans been asked to
go on a launch vehicle’s maiden voyage. Never had astronauts ridden
solid propellant rockets. Never had Americans depended on an engine
untested in flight.3
not clear or concise and failed to get critical information to the appro-
priate levels of management at NASA.
In this specific case, the weather-related problems, such as the ice
formation before the Challenger launch, were increasingly ignored, and
protocols about constraints to launch, or waivers of such constraints, were
not taken seriously. Whilst the ice on the platform was not thought to
contribute to the 51-L disaster itself, it could have compromised safety, not
least if the launch had been aborted before take-off, requiring the astro-
nauts to escape via the platform.
Once the problems with the O-rings emerged, the response was not well
documented or worked through. For instance, no significant trend analysis
was performed on the O-ring erosion and other joint problems. Five weeks
after the 51-L accident itself, the issues to do with the field joint were still
not properly documented in the reporting system at Marshall.
In fact, no one spoke out about the lack of attention to safety or the
erosion of the safety standards that were in place. The overriding pressure
to keep up with the shuttle programme dominated management thinking.
Another reason why there was no clear whistleblowing at this early stage
was the lack of transparency in management. As we shall see, no person or
group in the project was able to see the whole safety picture, even at the
top of management. A further reason, perhaps, was simply that no crises
had occurred, thus lulling the management into a sense of false safety. The
51-L disaster was the first real setback.
different offices. The last report sent by Boisjoly, highlighting the delays,
received no reply from management.
Boisjoly did many of the things recommended to whistleblowers. He
kept good records of his interaction with management, and was clear
about the possible consequences of ignoring the O-ring problem. He
ensured that all memos were circulated to his direct superiors. However, he
and his colleagues were not ready for the less than positive response from
management. When there was no feedback towards the end of the team’s
work they did not press the point or seek to clarify if their managers or
NASA had understood. This may have reflected a concern for their own
careers or a belief that the ultimate responsibility for dealing with the
erosion problem was not theirs but their superiors.
Underlying the work of the Seal Erosion Task Team and the problems
about delays was the more fundamental issue that the team was dealing
with a design fault and that such a fault should have led to the recommen-
dation that the shuttle programme be suspended until it was dealt with.
NASA engineers realized that there was a problem and for a time worked
with the task team. However, the problem was still defined in terms of the
need to speed up the delivery of the new design rather than as an essential
matter of safety. One of the difficulties was that the response of the NASA
engineers seemed to indicate that NASA had heard Boisjoly’s complaints.
In fact, the presence of the NASA engineers did not mean that the issues
were being communicated to NASA managers. Indeed, the essential matter
of safety remained unacknowledged by NASA management, who even
claimed to the Presidential Commission that they were not aware of the
problems.
In all of this the MTI engineers remained firmly within their own
system relying on their managers to communicate any problems to NASA.
This in itself may have led to unclear communication. At no point were
they encouraged by their organization either to go beyond their line
managers within MTI or to go outside to key personnel in NASA. Equally,
they had nowhere that they could go to discuss the implications of the
problem, or to discuss the engineering data and consider what other
evidence might be needed. For their part, there was no attempt by NASA
to see matters globally, or to check out thoroughly the nature of the
complaints that were emerging from the MTI engineers.
What more could the MTI engineers have done at this point? How
might the MTI management have best handled the material coming from
them? How could NASA have best kept itself better informed about this
aspect of the project safety?
The problem in the flow of information meant that the case which the
engineers had to make was never fully communicated, indeed was never
fully made, something which came to the fore in the teleconference itself.
Challenger Flight 51-L 117
The teleconference
All involved in the shuttle programme were aware of its high profile and
the consequent pressure to achieve targets. There was also economic pres-
sure, with some in the Reagan administration suggesting that turning the
operation over to an airline would make it more efficient. NASA had to
ensure that the programme was successful and also that it could pay for
itself. In turn, this put pressure on Rockwell (the firm responsible for the
development and maintenance of the shuttle itself) and on MTI. The result
was a strong incentive for managers to think and plan unrealistically. As
far back as 1982 NASA had begun a planned acceleration of the launch
schedule. An early plan looked to an eventual launch rate of one per week.
In 1985 this had been reduced to a projected annual rate of 24 by 1990.
Even this modified goal was over-ambitious, leading to difficulties,
including:
The shuttle flies with O-ring erosion and nothing happens, ‘Then it is
suggested that the risk is no longer so high for the next flights.’10
None of this was based on thoroughly researched evidence. On the
contrary, as the Presidential Commission found, prior to the accident
neither NASA, MTI managers nor engineers fully understood the mecha-
nism by which the field joint was sealed. The Commission also discovered
a massive discrepancy between the engineers’ and management’s view of
safety margins. Engineers estimated a shuttle failure rate of 1 in 100
launches. NASA management had figures of 1 in 100,000. When the
NASA figures were questioned by the Commission, the response of their
chief engineer was ‘We did not use them as a management tool. We knew
that the possibility of failure was always sitting there.’11 This leaves the
unanswered question as to how their figure was arrived at. As to the use of
such figures, it seems that they were submitted in response to a risk analysis
for the Department of Energy, the aim of which was to calculate the safety
of the use of small atomic reactors as power sources for deep-space probes,
which the shuttle could carry into space. The next mission of the
Challenger was scheduled to carry the Galileo probe, with 47.6 pounds of
plutonium-238.
The NASA figures were, in Feynman’s words, exaggerated ‘to the point
of fantasy’, and were part of a dynamic which led to a reversal of the usual
view of safety. NASA management even argued that the fact that a third of
the O-rings had been eroded and yet the shuttle had still flown, demon-
strated a ‘safety factor of three’. No one involved in the Commission could
understand what this phrase meant, given that erosion of a seal indicates a
diminution of safety by a third, not a safety margin of three.
This confusion was carried through into the teleconference. Though
there was a correlation between O-ring damage and low temperature
neither NASA nor MTI had carried out extensive tests in temperatures
below 53ºF. The engineers had not had the time or resources to prove
conclusively that it would be unsafe to fly the shuttle precisely because this
would have needed the shuttle programme to be suspended. Hence, NASA
and MTI were not fully prepared to evaluate the risks of the launch in
conditions more severe than they had experienced before. Boisjoly,
Thompson and McDonald could all have argued strongly, on the basis of
the initial correlation, that the flight should be delayed. But they did not
have a case tested at all temperatures.
The response of the NASA and Marshall managers and engineers to
Boisjoly’s presentation was fourfold. First, there was hostility, doubtless
because of a series of delays, and because of the pressure they were experi-
encing, not least in virtue of the State of the Union speech planned for that
day. Second, they questioned the engineers’ figures. NASA engineers ques-
tioned the temperature figures, believing that the original design
specification was for temperatures as low as 31ºF. The extent of confusion
Challenger Flight 51-L 119
was to emerge later when MTI argued that the temperature of 31ºF was
the limit for storage and not operation. Either way the actual temperature
at the time of launch was below this. Third, along the same lines, the
NASA managers focused on the lack of absolute evidence over safety, and
on the fact that previous O-rings had already been eroded by a third,
without compromising safety. Finally, it was later argued that the MTI
engineers were not unanimous in their findings.
Thus the MTI engineers found themselves suddenly having to prove
that the Challenger was unsafe to fly at low temperatures. As Lund in his
testimony to the Commission noted:
We have dealt with Marshall for a long time and have always been in
the position of defending our position to make sure that we were
ready to fly, and I guess I did not realize until after that meeting and
after several days that we had absolutely changed our position … And
so we got ourselves into the thought process, we were trying to find
some way to prove to them it wouldn’t work, and we were unable to
do that.12
So the MTI engineers had been sucked into a situation in which the discus-
sion was focusing purely on the feasibility of the launch and not upon the
issue of safety procedures per se. This meant that they had to defend their
judgement in a limited area with inadequate data, rather than approaching
management with a concern which would then have had to be investigated
and tested. Hence, there was no one to stand out for the principle of
‘safety first’, something all the more remarkable given that the American
Board for Engineering and Technology Code states that the ‘safety, health,
and welfare of the public shall be paramount’.13
This raises major questions about responsibility, which in turn point to
differences in the roles of engineers and management. Lund was both an
engineer and manager and when the manager Mason invited him to wear
his ‘management hat’ this implied very different responsibilities. Harris et
al. suggest that engineers are more traditionally concerned with risk–
benefit analysis and management with cost–benefit analysis.14 Mason
appears to have taken this further when he invited Lund to discount the
questions of risk raised by the MTI engineers, and to think primarily of
cost–benefit.
From the management perspective, another consideration might have
been the fact that MTI’s contract with NASA was up for renewal. The
Presidential Commission was more direct, concluding that MTI had
altered its original decision ‘to accommodate a major customer’.15
Whatever the final judgement on that point, it is clear that managers
and engineers had come to a critical point in decision-making without
reaching any agreement, not only on safety procedures but also on the
120 Simon Robinson
criteria of standards for safety in the first place. By being drawn into the
particular issue of the launch, the engineers allowed themselves to be
deflected from a defence of the key principle – above all do no harm.
Without a clear focus on that fundamental issue any attempt to blow the
whistle could have had little success.
Once this responsibility divide was crossed, the decision was taken
away from the engineers. Whose responsibility then was it to maintain
safety? What could the MTI engineers have done at the point where they
and MTI management were discussing the matter away from the telecon-
ference? Was their disagreement fully communicated to NASA? Is it
morally acceptable for an engineer or another employee to make a case
about safety and then pass the responsibility for outcome to the manage-
ment involved?
Notes
1 Cited in C. Harris, M. Pritchard and M. Rabins (1995) Engineering Ethics:
Concepts and Cases, New York: Wadsworth, p. 72.
2 Report of the Presidential Commission on the Space Shuttle Challenger
Accident (PCP) (1986), Washington, DC: US Government Printing Office, p. 3.
3 Cited in Martin, M. and Schinzinger, R. (1989) Ethics in Engineering, New
York: McGraw–Hill, p. 79.
4 Boisjoly, R. The Challenger Disaster (wysiwwyg://41/http://onlineethics.org/
moral/boisjoly/RB-intro.html).
5 Cited in Martin and Shinzinger (1989), op cit., p. 86.
6 Internal report 4 October 1985.
7 PCP, 14.
8 Ibid.
9 Cited in PCP, 12.
10 PCP, Appendix E 3.
11 Cited in Martin and Schinzinger (1989), op. cit., p. 83.
12 Cited in Harris et al. (1995), op. cit., pp. 285–6.
13 Robinson, S. and Dixon, R. (1997) ‘The professional engineer: virtues and
learning’, Science and Engineering Ethics 3(3): 340.
14 Harris et al. (1995), op. cit., pp. 274 ff.
15 PCP, 11.
16 Ibid.
17 Ibid.
Chapter 7
Global competition
In British industry, the received wisdom is that companies face intense
global competition and that only the best will survive. To be the best, a
company needs low costs; the ability to adapt very rapidly to change; and
a workforce which is highly flexible. In this environment, the theory goes,
high levels of job security are unthinkable and the labour market must be
deregulated so that managers have the ability to make whatever changes
are necessary to improve competitiveness. The disadvantage suffered by
employees is regretted but is essentially irrelevant; improved performance
within the terms of the system is the overriding objective.
Once the threat of global competition is accepted, low pay can be justi-
fied by reference to pressure from competitors in low-wage countries.
124 John Edmonds
Redundancies can be justified on the same basis. People with bad sickness
records must be eased out because companies cannot carry passengers.
Extensive training arrangements impose an unacceptable cost which
should be avoided. Equal opportunities cannot be taken too seriously
because, at various times during their working life, women are allegedly
more expensive to employ than men. And, of course, companies cannot
waste time consulting the workforce for fear that the lead time for making
a decision will lengthen to the point where the business will be paralysed.
The social consequences of these policies are undesirable. Britain has 4
million people being paid less than £5 an hour. Claims for unfair dismissal
have increased year by year. A third of British workers have received no
training whatsoever from their current employers. The gap between the
pay of women and men has scarcely narrowed in the past ten years. Even
the Labour government responds to this business agenda. Tony Blair tells
us that we need a lightly regulated labour market and Labour ministers
oppose the European Draft Directive guaranteeing information and
consultation rights to British workers.
From time to time, the unpleasant effects of this agenda can cause
managers some embarrassment. Then the hand-wringing begins.
Redundancies are ‘unfortunate’. Low pay is ‘regrettable’, but better than
having no job at all. Consultation arrangements are always ‘desirable’, but
should not be allowed to compromise management’s right to manage.
What managers rarely wish to discuss is the precise nature of this global
competition which is producing such unfortunate effects on fellow citizens.
There is no doubt that many parts of the manufacturing industry face
considerable competition from abroad. However, the manufacturing sector
employs less than 5 million people out of a workforce of over 28 million
people. Elsewhere, claims about the pressure of global competition seem
spurious. Employees of water companies were surprised, after privatiza-
tion, to be told that they were facing redundancies because of this global
competition. There was still only one pipe supplying the water and only
one set of reservoirs and only one sewerage system. When the arguments
were unravelled, we found that global competition was being used as
shorthand to describe the process whereby a company which does not
produce a particular return on capital will find that its share price is
pressed down to a level where the company will be taken over. Of course it
is a matter of public policy whether we allow our water utilities to be
taken over by other companies. Moreover, if a company is taken over, it is
also a matter of public policy whether we allow the terms and conditions
of workers in that utility to be worsened. The global competition argu-
ment has to be stretched very thin indeed before it reaches many
companies in the United Kingdom.
Pain and partnership 125
Choice
Throughout parts of the public sector a new kind of employment competi-
tiveness has actually been introduced by government decision. In the civil
service, where there is no obvious market and certainly no global competi-
tion, the Conservative government introduced a system called market
testing. In local authorities and the health service, the Conservatives intro-
duced the process of compulsory competitive tendering by which public
service work is packaged up and put out to tender. The Labour govern-
ment has modified these procedures, but has maintained a similar pressure
on the workforce. In place of compulsory competitive tendering, we now
have the ‘Best Value’ initiative. In place of market testing, we have value-
for-money examinations. In place of the Public Finance Initiative we have
Public–Private Partnerships. These are entirely artificial devices. They are
not introduced because competition is global. They are introduced because
government has decided that competition in the public sector is desirable
to improve efficiency. Stripped of the high-sounding rhetoric, these policies
are based on the value judgement that employees need to feel a certain
degree of insecurity if they are to perform at a level which is good for the
economy.
So what about the trading sector? Is the pain inevitable there or do
employers and governments have some discretion in the policies that they
adopt? Certainly many continental countries think so. Throughout the
European Union, workers have much greater protection than in Britain. In
Holland, for example, it is really difficult to employ someone on a tempo-
rary contract. In Germany, it is more difficult to sack people than it is in
Britain. In France, Germany and Italy, every worker has a much greater
right to be consulted about changes in the company than is the case in the
UK. Marks & Spencer reduce their workforce in Britain without great
difficulty, but their attempt to close their major store in Paris gets the
company into a legal tangle because the workforce has not been properly
consulted.
Some business leaders have argued that continental countries have not
faced up to the problems of global competition and that their economies
are suffering as a result. The evidence for this is sparse. Throughout
Northern Europe, production is significantly higher than in the UK and
living standards are noticeably better. Sometimes these advantages are
taken in terms of extra income and sometimes in extra leisure time. UK
employees have to work about 40 per cent longer to achieve the same
salary levels that are typically paid in France.
The British approach seems to be that commercial success can be
achieved on the basis of low wage rates. The full implications of this night-
marish policy are rarely revealed. In Bangladesh, the average weekly wage
of a textile worker is about £5 for 60 hours. In Haiti, the figure is about
£7 for 50 hours. Comparisons are more difficult with the People’s
126 John Edmonds
Republic of China, but it appears that wage rates are less than 10 per cent
of UK levels. So if we compete on wage levels with Bangladesh and Haiti
and China, we have to contemplate a society in Britain where disposable
income is reduced to a level which we have not seen for a hundred years.
In reality, the British response to global competition is neither inevitable
nor even rational. Other countries with different political ideologies have
taken different approaches. They have saved their workforce considerable
pain and do not seem to have suffered significant economic disadvantage.
So perhaps the best way of responding to global competition is not to say,
‘The competition is so severe that we must cut pay and conditions’.
Perhaps a more intelligent approach might be to say, ‘We have to make the
most of our advantages.’ Certainly, Western countries seem to find it easier
to compete if their people are highly skilled and if they use equipment
which is modern and effective.
Aspirations
A good place to start in developing a new policy is to talk to managers and
employees. When managers are asked what they want from their work-
force, they will normally use two words: commitment and flexibility.
However, if managers are asked what their employees want from manage-
ment, the managers are often thrown into confusion. Unfortunately,
British managers do not spend a great deal of time looking at things from
the viewpoint of their employees. Nevertheless, the evidence is readily
available.
Every three years, GMB uses MORI to survey people at work. MORI
asks, ‘What do you want from your employment?’ To prompt an answer, a
list of over twenty possible replies is given, including higher pay, a job to
be proud of, better fringe benefits, managerial respect, and so on. MORI
asks working people to pick out their top five aspirations in order of
importance. The results are always the same. Since the early 1980s, the top
two responses have been, ‘a job which is satisfying and interesting’ and
‘job security’. Then there is a large gap until we get to the third aspiration,
which is ‘a feeling of accomplishing something worthwhile at work’, and
then the fourth, which is more predictable – better pay.
GMB also surveys new members to discuss whether the two topmost
aspirations are being achieved. First, ‘Do you strongly agree that your
work is interesting and satisfying?’ Only one person in four replies, ‘Yes’.
Second, ‘Do you strongly believe that your job is secure?’ Only one person
in sixteen believes that their job is secure. The obvious conclusion is that
there is a massive gap between what people say they want from work and
what people are actually getting.
These results open up a productive line of thought. Perhaps the best way
for managers to get the commitment and loyalty which they require is for
Pain and partnership 127
managers to offer their employees the interesting work and job security
which the employees say they want. Trade unionists always think in terms
of negotiated agreements, but surely a deal by which managers and other
employees secure their topmost objectives is a more worthwhile way
forward than the pressure–pain model which we seem to operate at present.
A change of direction
Would this psychological deal lead to economic success? There are encour-
aging signs that it might. Some interesting research by Professor Michael
West at Aston Business School has demonstrated that the best way to fore-
cast whether a company will succeed or fail is to study how that company
treats its workforce. In Britain, we tend to believe that heavy investment in
new equipment, good design and effective marketing provides the key to
success. According to Professor West, these important contributors are
dwarfed by the importance of the people-treatment factor.2 Of course,
some of the indicators of good treatment also have direct economic bene-
fits. Providing training will make the workforce feel valued and will also
produce a direct improvement in productivity. Nevertheless, the results are
an interesting corrective to the views expressed by British company direc-
tors and British ministers throughout the last twenty years.
Interestingly, a change of direction would resolve some of the tensions
in the Labour government’s industrial relations policy. Two examples
stand out. First, the ‘Fairness at Work’ White Paper which led to the
Employment Relations Act was said to be based on the principle of part-
nership. However, in the introduction to the White Paper, Tony Blair was
keen to remind us all that the British labour market is the most lightly
regulated in Europe. The fiasco at Rover, the neglectful behaviour of Coats
Viyella and the arrogance of Corus have persuaded the Labour govern-
ment to deplore the British managers’ failure to consult their workers. Yet
the government has drawn back from the obvious solution of giving
British workers rights to information and consultation which are normal
elsewhere. Second, the introduction of the National Minimum Wage was
an obvious challenge to management’s right to compete on the basis of
wage rates, but the rhetoric of government ministers continues to suggest
that a rapid increase in the National Minimum Wage would damage
employment prospects in the UK. All governments want to ride a variety
of ideological horses, but increasingly the difference between the pain
approach and the partnership approach is requiring rhetorical skills which
are even beyond the accomplishment of Tony Blair.
A change of direction must start with a lead from government.
Government speeches should spend less time focusing on the flexibility of
the labour market and more on the obligation of employers to provide
work fit for the twenty-first century. An important symbol would be
128 John Edmonds
Training
In many ways, Britain’s attitude to training is the touchstone of industrial
policy. Training can develop and sustain satisfying work. Training is a very
good way of delivering the message to people that they are valued. And, of
course, training can substantially improve economic performance. At
present, Britain’s training record is appalling. The government’s Skills Task
Force reported in April 2000 that we suffer considerable deficiencies in
basic and generic skills, in craft training and particularly in mathematical
skills. The examples of inadequate performance are extensive. Twenty-
three per cent of the adult population in Britain have such serious literacy
problems that they cannot find the section on plumbing in the Yellow
Pages. Over a third of the British workforce are not qualified to NVQ
Level 2. In particular, Britain seems to distinguish itself from other indus-
trialized countries by the very large number of companies who provide no
training of any sort.
In order to change the culture of British workplaces, we have to lay an
obligation on employers to provide training for all employees. This obliga-
tion could be enforced by a training levy or by tax incentives and penalties
or by simply giving every worker an entitlement to a particular level of
training. In 1995, the CBI surveyed member companies to ask whether the
voluntary system of employee training in Britain was actually working.
Nearly half of CBI companies admitted that the voluntary system was not
producing adequate results. Unfortunately, there has been no CBI survey in
the last six years, but personal experience would suggest that the level of
dissatisfaction has grown. Nevertheless, CBI leaders continue to insist that
compulsory training is wrong and will only lead to bureaucracy and extra
costs. Inadequate training means damaged economic prospects and
blighted lives. A change of approach is urgently needed.
Most social issues in Britain seem to lead back to questions of class. The
curious assumption in Britain that wisdom in an organization resides
solely in senior management contrasts sharply with the outlook of
managers in Scandinavia, where management is by consent and where
Pain and partnership 129
Perceptions of failure
Finally, and most important of all, management should accept a change in
their priorities. In most companies, to cut the dividend is an admission of
failure. Indeed, it is so traumatic that it usually produces resignations
amongst senior managers. By contrast, reaching for the P45 and making
people redundant is often seen as an acceptable tactic to deflect criticism
from the City of London. Employees are not stupid. They understand that
within this value system they are less important than shareholders. If we
saw a change of priorities so that redundancy was regarded as manage-
ment failure, the commitment of people to their company could improve
dramatically. This is not just theory. There have been many examples in
Guinness, in Blue Circle Cement and elsewhere, of the way in which
employment relations are transformed once a guarantee of employment
security is put on the table. Flexibility becomes more possible because
people know they can contribute their ideas without threatening the
employment prospects for themselves and their colleagues. For managers
to accept that employees are the most important stakeholders in a business
will no doubt require a conversion of Pauline proportions, but it is the
essential requirement of long-term economic success.
My conclusion is that Britain has been fundamentally wrong about the
needs of a modern industrial economy. Many managers and politicians act
as if a deregulated economy with low pay and low levels of job security is
the only route to high economic performance. In fact, this approach is
producing great pain and demoralization. The analysis is economically
counter-productive because the pressure–pain model ensures that people
will not deliver their talent and will not produce of their best. Success in a
modern economy can only come by valuing people, motivating them and
training them effectively. They will contribute more enthusiastically if they
have a reasonable say in the development of their organization. The aim is
to produce a synthesis between modern management and human dignity.
Managers ought to take a more sensible view of the best interests of each
enterprise. Failure is guaranteed when the workforce regards itself as
130 John Edmonds
Notes
1 Milgram, Stanley (1974) Obedience to Authority: An Experimental View,
London: Tavistock.
2 West, Michael and Patterson, Malcolm (1999) ‘The workforce and produc-
tivity’, New Economy 6(March): 22–7.
3 Purcell, J. and Kessler, I. (1995) ‘Joint problem solving: does it work? An
Evaluation of ACAS Advisory Mediation’, Occasional Paper no. 55, London:
ACAS.
Chapter 8
Case history
The first John Lewis shop, a drapers, was set up in Oxford Street, London,
in 1864. In 1905 Lewis bought the Peter Jones store in Sloane Square, and
by 1914 his son Spedan was made owner and manager. It was at this point
that Spedan began to experiment with reform and the sharing of power.
He had three guiding principles:
concern for the inequality which existed between the employees and
the owners. When Lewis first joined the firm, the combined income of
its 300 employees was equal to that of the three owners. In the vein of
R.H. Tawney, he argued that too great an inequality was not only
inequitable but also damaging both to the rich and the less well off.2
• Employees should feel that they own the company, participating as far
as possible in decision-making.
• The company should be able to compete successfully in the market
place and attract the best in the profession into management. It was
clear to Lewis that this required two things. First, all employees should
feel that they were responsible for the success of the business and that
therefore any benefits which they accrued would be directly connected
to the standard of service. Second, aware of the failures in previous co-
operative approaches, he demanded tight commercial discipline.
The Partnership
John Lewis died in 1928 and in the following year Spedan formally moved
the firm into partnership, at the same time joining the Oxford Street store
with his Peter Jones enterprise. He sold his shares to the John Lewis
Partnership Trust Ltd, which controls the Partnership’s principal holding
company, John Lewis Partnership plc. From this, Lewis developed a
Constitution which was based on three elements: the Central Council; the
Central Board; and the Chairman.
The Chairman is also the Chief Executive Officer and is responsible for
maintaining profit and fulfilling the aims of the Constitution. The
Chairman has great power and can even name his successor. However, ulti-
mately the Central Council can dismiss the Chairman if he does not fulfil
his role in the terms of the Constitution. He is thus ultimately subordinate
to the Constitution.
Lewis was aware that over time, despite these checks and balances,
designed to keep the company focused on its organizational values and
principles, these principles could be eroded. Hence, he set down that two
directors should have as their only function the protection of the integrity
of the Partnership Principles. The first, the Chief Registrar, ensures that
the principles and democratic system are maintained. The second, the
Partners’ Counsellor acts as an ombudsman, receiving any complaints and
ensuring that the rights of Partners are fully respected. The Counsellor has
the function of ensuring that the Partnership is ‘influenced properly by
considerations of humanity’. Lewis saw these as dealing with the ‘critical
side’ of the firm as distinct from the executive. Each operational unit of the
Partnership has its own Counsellor and Registrar.
134 Simon Robinson
Profit: The Partnership aims to make sufficient profit from its trading
operations to sustain its commercial vitality, to finance its continued devel-
opment and to distribute a share of the profits each year to its members,
and to enable it to undertake other activities consistent with its ultimate
purpose.
Customers: The Partnership aims to deal honestly with its customers and
secure their loyalty and trust by providing outstanding choice, value and
service.
The community: The Partnership aims to obey the spirit as well as the
letter of the law and to contribute to the well-being of the communities
where it operates.
software and office products. Links with buy.com (USA) will be main-
tained.
Since 1971, employment has risen steadily and sales have grown at an
annual average of 6 per cent. In 2000, the sales for department stores were
over £1,997 million, and for supermarkets over £2,095 million, with a
turnover of over £4 billion, up by 10 per cent on the previous year.
Analysis
Although the writings of John Spedan Lewis tend to be discursive, they
reveal a passionate concern for both the well-being of his workforce and
right relationships with suppliers, customers and community. An account
of well-being can be summed up in the industrial psychology of R.H.
Tawney, and in particular in the work of contemporary psychologist P.
Warr. In what follows, I use Warr’s analysis of work, and the needs it
fulfils, to examine the JLP approach to its workforce.4
Warr argues from a psychological perspective that work is necessary for
the well-being of persons. He argues that there are basic human needs
fulfilled in work, and fulfilling these needs gives content to respect for the
workforce. The majority of these needs are fulfilled by JLP:
The Partnership was meant to enable people to feel that they might
be making a contribution of real value to the ceaseless experimenta-
tion that is necessary to human progress. It was meant for people
who need not only something to live by but also something to live
for.5
At the heart of this approach to managing the business and personnel there
is an emphasis on the need for a strong sense of responsibility amongst the
managers. This is seen in a ‘commitment to the organization and a concern
for the welfare of its members’. Whilst management style may differ
between different branches, there is a ‘general awareness that decisions
have to be defended on rational grounds’.6 Freedom to criticize is main-
tained throughout the organization and thus keeps management attention
focused on both the workforce, and the basis for any decision-making.
Equally, because each Partner is involved so deeply in the company,
there is a sense in which every employee feels responsibility for the whole
company. This leads to the reduction of psychological distance between
the different parts of the organization, something reinforced by the
communication of knowledge. That, in turn, tends to encourage the devel-
opment of proactive responsibility, responsibility more in the sense of a
John Lewis Partnership 137
civic virtue, as distinct from responsibility simply for a task.7 Hence, Lewis
stressed a sense of responsibility which should go ‘beyond the letter of the
law’, which he summed up in the idea of good citizenship applied to the
workplace.
As a whole this gives members a sense of identity and purpose. The
scope of this purpose is not simply confined to the production and sale of
goods, and maintaining the well-being of the workforce, but looks to the
higher purpose of contributing to and maintaining the well-being of the
wider community in a variety of ways. This is exemplified in a number of
different relationships:
many are still sceptical as to whether there are clear empirical connections
between this and the success of the company. Robert Oakeshott suggests
several pieces of evidence which do provide a connection. First, in the mid-
1990s absenteeism was running at the low rate of 3.5 per cent. Second, the
labour turnover is low – 7.1 per cent in 1984–5 compared to 30 per cent
in the retail sector as a whole.14 Third, there is anecdotal evidence that
‘stock shrinkage’, petty pilfering and so on, is low. These factors would
indicate a settled workforce.
Nonetheless, there remain major questions regarding the effectiveness of
the Partnership. As Flanders et al. note, the much-lauded industrial democ-
racy is not as remarkable as some would argue. Decisions still rest with the
CEO, who selects the deputy chairman as well as five other members of
the Central Board. The Communications Committees rarely influence
policy. Moreover, Flanders et al. argue that the strong stress on the basic
principles, virtually unchanged since the Partnership began, smacks of
paternalism.15 Though acceptance of the underlying ideology is not a crite-
rion for job selection, workers do have to work within this value system.
Moreover, the company does not accept unions and may sound harsh at
points. Regulation 186 of the Constitution, for instance, notes that if a
Partner has been absent, for whatever reason, for three separate times in a
period of six months the Registrar should refer this to the Staff Manager
to determine if there is need for medical consultation, or ‘consideration of
his continued membership of the Partnership’. Is this paternalism or
reasonable discipline born of mutual accountability?
The other questions are about how far this kind of system could be
replicated outside the retail sector, and to what extent the success of this
project is dependent on freedom from external investors. How far, also, is
the system ultimately dependent upon the underlying principles and an
acceptance of them? The Registrar and Counsellor, for instance, are not
there simply as ethical consultants to help members work through ethical
problems. Their task is driven by the ideology of the company and is to
ensure that its principles are applied in the areas of human resources and
decision-making.
This leads to a fundamental question championed by Friedman and
Sternberg as to whether such principles should be imposed upon a
company. They would not argue against the Lewis approach per se but
rather that no such approach should be imposed on another company.
The JLP case, however, invites a more fundamental question about a
business’s awareness of the humanity of the workforce and the develop-
ment of systems that will enable that awareness to remain in place. If this
is fundamental, as Edmonds suggests, then how can it be applied in
different contexts? How might the ‘critical’ and reflective side of a
company be developed and the human needs of the workforce be attended
to? How might the learning dimension be introduced and how might it
140 Simon Robinson
relate to the success of the business?16 As West and Patterson note, if the
rallying call, ‘People are our most important asset’, is not to be just a
management platitude then these issues have to be addressed in practice.17
Notes
1 Zygmunt Bauman develops this theme in Modernity and the Holocaust (1989),
Polity: London, and Postmodern Ethics (1995) Oxford: Blackwell.
2 R.H. Tawney (1930) Equality, London: Allen & Unwin.
3 J. Lewis (1948) Partnership for All, London: Kerr-Cross.
4 P. Warr (1987) Work, Unemployment and Mental Health, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
5 J. S. Lewis (1948) Partnership for All, London: Kerr-Cross.
6 A. Flanders, R. Pomeranz and J. Woodward (1968) Experiment in Industrial
Democracy, London: Faber & Faber.
7 C. Harris, M. Pritchard and M. Robins (1995) Engineering Ethics: Concepts
and Cases, New York: Wadsworth.
8 R. Solomons (1992) Ethics and Excellence, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
9 R. Higginson (1996) Transforming Leadership, London: SPCK.
10 A. Flanders et al., op. cit., p. 184.
11 P. Hawkins (1991) ‘The spiritual dimension of the learning organization’,
Management Education and Development 22(3): 172–87.
12 K. Bradley and S. Estrin (1986) ‘The Success Story of the John Lewis
Partnership: A Study of Comparative Performance’, London: Partnership
Research.
13 R. Oakeshott (2000) Jobs and Fairness, Norwich: Michael Russell, p. 225.
14 Oakeshott, op. cit., p. 226.
15 Flanders et al., op. cit., p. 193.
16 Unipart, for instance, have developed an in-house university which is integral
to its business. Employees pass through this every day and courses apply
directly to their work, increasing their efficiency and developing greater control
and confidence. See J. Kinghorn (1999) ‘U Turn at UNIPART’, Knowledge
Directions, Fall: 6–17.
17 M. West and M. Patterson (1999) ‘The workforce and productivity’, New
Economy 6(March): 22–7.
Chapter 9
The so-called ‘Nestlé Case’ has been ongoing since the 1960s. The case
focuses on the work of multinational corporations (MNCs), and in partic-
ular Nestlé, and how they market their products in the Third World. Key
issues which emerge are:
Babyfood booklets: All the companies produced booklets that gave advice
for pre- and post-natal care. They used pictures to show correct feeding
methods and made a variety of recommendations for ‘mixed feeding’,
including the use of a bottle where there was insufficient or poor quality
breast milk. All of this gave the impression of informed and careful advice,
while at the same time managing to extol the quality of their own product.
The booklets were careful not to denigrate breastfeeding, but some early
versions did not actually mention it.
Nestlé and international marketing 143
Milk banks: In addition, milk banks were set up in some areas to sell
formula at reduced prices to poor mothers, at a discount of between 33
per cent and 40 per cent.
adamant, for instance, that the Jelliffe thesis was focusing on a single issue
without taking account of many other social and economic factors that
accounted for the figures on morbidity and mortality.
Nonetheless the Code was passed, was accepted by Nestlé, and formed
the basis of marketing practice. The Code directives included:
anti-trust laws. To reveal company policy and practice could lead to viola-
tion of those laws.
Meanwhile, a new activist coalition was formed, the Interagency Group
on Breastfeeding Monitoring (IGBM). This claimed independence from the
many different activist groups but had overlapping membership with
many. Without fully consulting the formula industry, IGBM issued a size-
able document called The Code Handbook. This sought to provide the
definitive approach to interpreting the Code and even provided a model
law for countries to adopt. The pressure from this organization, supported
by UNICEF, then led to a document called Cracking the Code (1997). The
document aimed to present independent research into the controversy. In
the event, Nestlé and the researchers could not agree over the methodology
employed or conclusions. The report asserted that companies were system-
atically violating the Code and that the whole marketing policy should be
altered. Nestlé responded with detailed questioning of methodology, and
noted that, even if the methodology were accepted, the report included few
details of Nestlé transgressing the code. Once more then, common under-
standing, even about data collection, proved to be elusive.
UNICEF continued with its policy of not talking with the formula
industry, and even extended this to criticizing the International Paediatric
Association for its discussions with the industry. In 1997, Carol Bellamy
did meet with the new Nestlé CEO Peter Brabeck. Despite hope for a
continued and open dialogue, Bellamy declined further contact.
will be the opinion formers of the future. Second, academic support would
lend credibility to Nestlé’s arguments.
Even this approach has had its problems. Denied the chance to set out
their case in the Oxford students’ newspaper, Nestlé UK decided to place
an advertisement in the local free paper. One of several claims in this was
that ‘even before the WHO International Code for Marketing Breast Milk
Substitutes was introduced in 1981, Nestlé marketed infant formula ethi-
cally and responsibly, and has done ever since’. The response from Baby
Milk Action was to take these claims to the Advertising Standards
Authority. Here was an arbitrator who might be able to judge the case.
In the event the ASA ruled against the adverts on the basis that they
contained implications that could not be easily substantiated. The response
of Baby Milk Action was to claim that the ruling finally showed that
Nestlé were unethical.5
Of course, the ASA was not saying that Nestlé was unethical. It was
simply making a ruling on the narrow claims that were in the advertise-
ment. The implication of the ruling was that if the advertisement had been
reframed then it might have been permitted. Moreover, the ASA were
clearly uneasy about having to make judgements on matters of ethics.
So the Nestlé case continues. At critical points it raises major questions
as to how Nestlé might best have handled the issues, and beyond this
further questions about the different ethical views that might be applied to
the case.
Analysis
This case history illustrates the very different ethical positions which can
be taken to marketing in the Third World. For Nestlé this has led to major
changes in marketing strategies. With each major challenge to their ethi-
cal reputation, Nestlé developed a response which moved to a different
ethical position. These positions are summed up by Sethi and Post in an
analysis of a previous case which concerned the whole formula industry.
They name the positions as follows: social obligation; social responsibility;
and social responsiveness.6 As each of these approaches is outlined in turn
this will raise questions about what other options there might have been
both for Nestlé and for others involved in the case.
Social obligation
The initial ethical standard of Nestlé in the Third World was one of social
obligation, summed up as ‘reasonable responsibility’. It determined first to
operate within the law of the countries involved, and second, to ensure
product safety. For Nestlé this included commitment to research both the
need for breast milk substitute and the quality of the formula. It also
150 Simon Robinson
accepted the need for truthful marketing: advertising should not make
claims for a product which are inaccurate or misleading. Finally, it was
concerned to identify and answer the consumers’ needs.
In all this, Nestlé believed themselves to be perfectly ethical, precisely
because they did not believe that they had any responsibility beyond the
manufacture and proper marketing of the goods. As such they viewed the
whole project from the perspective that the Third World is part of a global
free market where there is great competition from other formula compa-
nies, and within which the company was only obliged to fulfil the legal
and economic criteria governing its operation. This position is close to
Sternberg’s view noted in chapter 2.
The case, however, raises questions about that view when applied to
corporate behaviour in the developing countries. First of all, this view led
to myopia in the Nestlé approach involving:
accepted that there might be second-order impacts from the sale of its
goods. The impacts were on the babies who were not part of the
company–consumer relationship, yet might in the end have died partly
because of the sale of the formula. In accepting such a second-order impact
the company was not accepting full responsibility for the death of the
babies, but was accepting that it shared in responsibility for possible nega-
tive impact on the babies.
This concept of the shared or mutual responsibility of different stake-
holders is what led to the WHO Code. In many respects, the WHO Code
sums up a particular view of stakeholding in business ethics. The term
stakeholder can mean anything from a group or person who has a finan-
cial stake in the business to the inclusive view of anyone who affects or is
affected by the business in question.9 The WHO Code embodies a view of
stakeholding somewhere between the two. It was able to identify stake-
holders who shared a particular concern for the well-being of newborn
babies in the Third World. The stakeholders in this sense included: the
formula industry; national governments; local health services; NGOs such
as UNICEF and WHO. The shared concern was not focused on the busi-
ness, but rather on the consumers and the wider effects of marketing.
Moreover, this view of stakeholder theory was not about balancing
competing interests so much as sharing responsibility. This meant deter-
mining together what the different responsibilities of the stakeholders were
to the mothers and babies. Responsibility was roughly apportioned along
these lines:
The Code itself provided the criteria for good practice, and alongside this,
acting as arbitrator, there was the Muskie Commission. For a time this
provided the means whereby any allegations of Code-breaking could be
discovered and dealt with. However, the Code had its problems:
formula be written in the local language may be hard to fulfil if, for
instance, it is not clear what the local language is.10
• The monitoring of the Code was down to the national government
involved. This was difficult when some did not see this as a priority
and others had significant but occasionally conflicting legislation. In
India, for example, two different laws, brought into force in 1993, laid
down different conditions about wording and language. Nestlé filed a
petition to the High Court in October 1995, not to contest either law
but to clarify the position. The complexity of the case made it difficult
to determine the truth. Evidence from patients, health workers and
health establishments, and local NGOs often conflicted. As a result,
suspicions often re-emerged about the integrity of witnesses.
• The implementation of the Code had at its heart major ambiguities for
the formula industry. The sales force on the ground was in danger of
receiving ambiguous messages – the importance of increasing sales of
the product, but also the importance of encouraging the potential
consumer to use a different ‘product’. It was not surprising that local
sales forces might have found this hard to deal with.
• The Muskie Commission had its critics amongst the NGOs but did at
least provide a mechanism for receiving allegations about the breaking
of the Code and attempting to ensure that they were dealt with. Nestlé
allowed this group to disband in the 1990s and did not attempt to
replace it. In effect this produced a power vacuum with the return to
polarization and both ‘sides’ insisting that they had the support of
independent groups.
Social responsiveness
Faced by the most recent attacks of the NGOs, Nestlé began to change its
ethical position from that of social obligation to one of social responsive-
ness. This involves a more proactive approach, which seeks to anticipate
and prevent ethical problems from arising. Nestlé, for instance, proactively
stopped the provision of free milk supplies in some forty countries, other
than when it is provided under the direction of the local health services. It
put more money into research on breastfeeding and offered to increase
collaboration with the other stakeholders. Despite this, Nestlé’s response
has, at times, been ambiguous. It is clear that its practices have changed
radically, particularly when compared to those of the 1960s. It is equally
clear that its commitment to dialogue is genuine. However, in its dealings
with the ASA, Nestlé appeared to be claiming that it had always worked
according to the social responsibility model. This, in turn, was interpreted
as an attempt to gain the moral high ground. In terms of tactics in the
debate, this simply encouraged the return of the old polarized dynamic.
Attempts to increase dialogue and collaboration with UNICEF initially
Nestlé and international marketing 155
Such principles are important for several reasons. First, they suggest the
possibility of pursuing at one and the same time several different purposes,
including profit and concern for well-being and justice. Second, they set
out a moral minimum in working in other countries.14 Third, they provide
a basis for trust.
In the light of such principles, the problems posed by AIDs may well
cause the different parties in this case history to begin to explore very
different ways of operating. Are there ways, for instance, of achieving co-
operation with UNICEF without having to violate anti-trust laws? This
would mean serious examination of how closer cooperation with the
formula companies could be achieved.
Those who argue against stakeholder theory might suggest that no clear
limit to stakeholders and their influence can be drawn. Thus this kind of
approach threatens to lead to a significant diminution in the autonomy of
companies and thence possibly to the complete transformation of the free
market. However, this case might be taken to show that the capacity to
make effective decisions in international business is dependent upon
working with different groups with very different ethical views. The
autonomy of the company can only be understood in that context.15
156 Simon Robinson
Conclusions
This case has highlighted a number of different ethical positions that can
be held in relation to international marketing, ranging from social obliga-
tion to social responsiveness. Considering the case from these perspectives
provides a way of testing basic theories about stakeholding and the social
responsibility of business. At the same time, the case could be seen as
showing the practical difficulties which emerge in attempting to resolve
complex ethical issues and the need to work at communication and collab-
oration.
Underlying all this is the fundamental question as to whether Nestlé
should have responded in the way it did. Should the company have taken
the initial challenge from the NGOs so seriously? Should an MNC be
responsible for the actions of its customers? Is it not more important to
simply respect the autonomy of the customer, and not to pursue avenues
that are the responsibility of local health services? It could be argued that
the global campaign to ensure universal breastfeeding is more than simply
a matter of providing information. It could be interpreted as aggressive
and paternalistic in that it does not respect the autonomy of the consumer,
the mother. Indeed it assumes that the mother is incapable of deciding for
herself.16 However, this is not an argument for avoiding the social respon-
siveness model. On the contrary, autonomy is a complex notion which
depends in practice on the person developing the skills and virtues of decision-
making. It is hard to develop these without dialogue and collaboration.
The mother, for instance, needs to know the facts, options, constraints and
underlying objectives of formula milk in order to make a choice about its
use. The key question then is who should be enabling the mother to make
that choice? This case might suggest that, in a situation where many of the
stakeholders are powerless or are not convinced where their responsibility
lies, such responsibility has to be shared. The work of the formula industry
in research for, and in support of, health services, for instance, can enable
those services to fulfil their responsibilities. The work of NGOs could
enable national governments to fulfil their responsibilities in relation to the
WHO Code. Would this view of stakeholding as collaboration fit into
Sternberg’s position or would it demand that there be recognition of
shared purpose to begin with, so moving into more of a virtue ethics posi-
tion? How might Nestlé begin to develop such a virtue ethics approach?
Finally, two further points might be suggested as worth considering in
this case history. First, Nestlé cannot avoid the debate. Ethical reputation
is of paramount importance to a multinational corporation. Second,
without dialogue and collaboration the ground for ethical debate is lost:
data are eroded; values and principles are distorted; and the range of
possible options is diminished.
Nestlé and international marketing 157
Notes
1 H. Nestlé, (1869) Memorial on the Nutrition of Infants, Vevey: Loertscher,
p. 1.
2 D.B. Jelliffe (1971)‘Commerciogenic Malnutrition? Time for a Dialogue’, Food
Technology 15: 55–6.
3 D.B. Jelliffe (1971) op. cit.
4 New York Times, 26 July 26 1998, cited in L. Newton case study (1999).
5 Marketing Week, 4 February 1999.
6 S. Sethi and J. Post (1989) ‘Public consequences of private action: the
marketing of infant formula in less developed countries’, in P. Iannone (ed.)
Contemporary Moral Controversy in Business, Oxford: Oxford University
Press, pp. 474–87.
7 M. Novak (1993) ‘Eight arguments about the morality of the marketplace’, in
J. Davies, God and the Marketplace, London: IEA.
8 De George notes that debates about justice are a key feature in international
business ethics, see R. De George (1999) ‘International business ethics’, in R.
Frederick (ed.) A Companion to Business Ethics, Oxford: Blackwell, pp.
233–42.
9 E. Sternberg (1970) ‘Stakeholder theory: the defective state it’s in’, in W.
Hutton, Stakeholding and Its Critics, London: IEA, pp. 70–85.
10 S. Robinson (1994) ‘Modern business ethics and prophecy’, Crucible
Oct.–Dec.: 189–203.
11 Baby Food Action Network (1994) Breaking the Rules 1994, London: IBFAN.
12 UNICEF (1997) Cracking the Code, London: IGBM.
13 L. Newton (1999) ‘Corporate codes from Borg Warner to the Caux Principles’,
in R. Frederick (ed.) A Companion to Business Ethics, Oxford: Blackwell, pp.
374–85.
14 T. Donaldson (1989) The Ethics of International Business, New York: Oxford
University Press.
15 A quite separate area which could be explored within a complex case history of
this sort is that of whistleblowing in MNCs. If it is part of the responsibility of
the formula industry to monitor its own practice, how can it ensure that prac-
tice is sufficiently transparent to be monitored across so many fields of
operation? Moreover, how can a positive climate for whistleblowing be devel-
oped when an increase in sales seems to be the highest priority?
16 L. Newton (1998) The Controversy over the Marketing of Breast Milk
Substitutes, Columbus, OH: Council for Ethics and Economics 2(I): 7 (www.i-
case.com).
Appendix I
between the case histories presented in part II and the analyses offered
both there and in the first part. And it will thereby point to a way of
comparing analyses of key ethical issues arising in particular areas of busi-
ness with the quite general theories outlined in the first part. As has just
been indicated, it will also show the relation between a particular ethical
theory and an understanding of the value of case histories.
from a given theory apply to the case history provided, and a grasp of
what those principles then mean in the specific context given. This, then,
will lead to a better understanding of the theory within which these princi-
ples operate, and thus a better basis for comparing that theory with rivals.
But a second feature of such a comparison will be to compare what the
case history comes to from the point of view of distinct theoretical
approaches. If the theoretical approaches are genuinely distinct they will
identify distinct considerations as salient when it comes to considering
what was ethically permissible or required at different stages in a case
history. If a theory requires that a business agent maximize long-term
owner value within the bounds of distributive justice and ordinary
decency, then the analysis of any case history in those terms requires that
at any particular stage in the case the agent consider the effects of possible
actions on owner value. On the other hand if a theory requires that the
agent be accountable to stakeholders, then any decision within a case
understood from that perspective needs to be assessed solely in terms of
obligations to relevant stakeholders.
One effect of reading a case history in the light of an ethical theory may
be to indicate that the history lacks certain information which, from the
point of view of the theory in question, is needed for appropriate decision-
making. That need not undermine the value of the case, as an important
skill in actual decision-making will be identifying whether the information
already available is what is needed to make an appropriate decision. (Of
course, time considerations may sometimes require the agent to proceed on
the basis of what is known to be insufficient information.)
The third feature involved in using case studies for the comparison of
theories is the assessment of the theories in terms both of what they pick
out as salient, and in terms of the practical prescriptions that appear to
follow from them. The factors identified as salient, and the practical
prescriptions following from them according to the theory, will normally
need to be assessed in relation to the case user’s pre-theoretical convic-
tions. (These are the beliefs (if any) that the case user holds about the case
before attempting to examine it from any theoretical perspective.) For
example, an application of stakeholder theory to a particular case history
would identify which stakeholders an agent owed obligations to in specific
circumstances. This then raises the question whether that approach to the
notion of obligation coheres with pre-theoretical beliefs about obligations
in that particular case, or indeed with the pre-existing notion of obligation
itself. Is it plausible that the decision-maker really does owe obligations to
all those apparently picked out by stakeholder theory? If not, then this
may either tell against the theory or, if the theory seems to cohere with
many ordinary beliefs but conflict with a few, this may lead the user to
reconsider some of the pre-theoretical beliefs.
To take a second example, one might consider what a utilitarian theory
164 Chris Megone
For present purposes, then, Aristotle’s key point here is that practical
wisdom about what to do in a particular circumstance requires some intel-
lectual capacity (a perception distinct from sense-perception) to appreciate
the nature of that particular situation.
These ideas can be further understood in connection with one of his
remarks on the imprecision of ethics already alluded to:
But up to what point and to what extent a man must deviate [from
goodness] before he becomes blameworthy it is not easy to determine
by reasoning, any more than anything else that is perceived by the
senses; such things depend on particular facts, and the decision rests
with perception.7
desirable if there were further resources for facilitating its acquisition other
than real experience. Obviously actual experience will continue to play a
role in the acquisition of the capacity, but such further resources would
make it possible to achieve at least some of the development without
moral wrongdoing. To explore this possibility it is necessary now to indi-
cate how exactly experience does lead to the acquisition of such
intellectual perception, perception of the sort that enables the agent to
make correct ethical judgements
The role of experience here can be explained by reference to Aristotle’s
remarks on the role of habituation, or practice, in the acquisition of virtue,
outlined in chapter 2. ‘Men become builders by building … so too we
become just by doing just acts.’11 As was explained, part of Aristotle’s
point is that habituation or practice has a cognitive role. At first a child
will have to be guided towards just acts. It will do the right act because
told to do so by a parent or teacher. At that point the child only believes
that the act is just because told so by someone he trusts. This is purely
‘external’ knowledge. In time the child comes to see that the just act has a
point, and then further to see that it has a point as just. At this further
stage the child has some grasp of the concept of justice, and relates the
point it sees in the action to this embryonic conception of justice. Then the
child is internalizing the knowledge. This internalization can only be
achieved through experience. This process is what is involved in the acqui-
sition of nous, or intellectual perception.
To see that a just act, a certain sharing of a cake, for example, has a
point the child must appreciate what features are relevant to that cake’s
being shared, who made it, to whom it belongs, who was invited to the
party, and so on. In doing this, the child is recognizing salient features of
the situation. But the child must also appreciate the relevance of these
features, that these are features that need to be attended to in dividing up
the cake. This is acknowledging these features. In doing these things the
child is starting to acquire nous. And Aristotle’s claim is that these achieve-
ments can only come through experience.
But why does Aristotle emphasize the need for long experience? Here
the point about the particularity of action is relevant. A concept like justice
is complex. A child has to internalize not just the relevance of these
features in this cake situation, and in time that these are concerns of
justice. The child also has to internalize that other similar considerations
are also concerns of justice, though found in other situations. The child
has to see that, say, the hard work and intelligence that are relevant to the
appraisal of homework are comparable with the features of justice in the
cake sharing, to see that this feature here is (comparable with) that feature
there. Developing a capacity to perceive considerations of justice in all the
variety of situations where it might arise requires long experience.
Furthermore, in addition to appreciating that a consideration is relevant,
Case history use in business ethics 169
that it has a point, the child also has to internalize the relative weighting of
different considerations. Again Aristotle might plausibly hold that such
internalization requires experience of how different considerations weigh
against one another in different circumstances. This requires both, again,
comparing this situation with previous like circumstances, and appreciating
the novelty of the new situation. Thus, too, determining the right thing to
do in the light of this weighting, and perhaps also seeing that it is right,
that it accords with some ill-formed conception of what is right overall,
may also be aspects of intellectual perception that require experience.
Of necessity, then, this internalized knowledge is not something that can
be acquired without actually being in relevant situations, having experi-
ence. Of necessity also, given the huge variety of circumstances that can be
encountered, this is knowledge that can only be acquired with long experi-
ence.12 The capacity for the intellectual perception to make judgements as
to what virtue requires, comes with this knowledge. For it is a capacity
which involves appreciating the considerations that are salient, in a partic-
ular situation, from the point of view of a relevant virtue, and weighing
them appropriately. Its acquisition, therefore, requires long experience (a
breadth and variety of relevant experiences).
Given this outline of the role of experience in the acquisition of nous, it
is now possible to see that case histories may be able to make a contribu-
tion to that process, and thus, too, that actual experience may not be the
only resource that can enable such an acquisition. One way to use a case
history is as a presentation of experience to the student. In the business
context, it can present the student with novel experiences, situations he has
never in fact experienced. Furthermore, a case history such as the
Challenger, or the Nestlé case, can present the reader with a variety of
possible perspectives on the same situation, a range of ways of experi-
encing it.
Clearly, like any literature, a case history is a ‘quasi-experience’. For the
agent to have something like the experience of a real situation, he needs to
be engaged in the situation. This may require imagination. But it is
certainly possible for a case history to engage readers and to enable them
to have the experience of appreciating the salient points of the situation,
and weighing them; and also, as just noted, to differ from life in allowing
the agent to internalize how the situation is experienced from a range of
situations, not just his own. This allows the agent to appreciate that
different features might seem salient from different perspectives, broad-
ening his previous experience in still another way.
This use of case histories has a number of implications. First of all, as
has been seen, the acquisition of nous is a long process and initially the
process must be guided by someone external to the agent who already has
it, or at least has a much more developed capacity, for example, a parent.
Without such guidance the child cannot appreciate that a situation is to be
170 Chris Megone
thought of as a matter of justice (for example) at all. The child may also
require guidance, at first, as to what it is about the situation that is a
matter of justice (‘it’s her Easter egg too!’). Thus, in order to use a case
history for the further development of nous, a student must already have
gone beyond the initial stage in the development of nous, and no longer
require such guidance, or at least not require it to the same extent. (This
cannot be taken for granted, because it is not simply a matter of achieving
a certain age; as Aristotle remarks, some remain childlike.13) The agent
who can use case histories for the further development of nous, must
already have, from past (guided) experience, sufficient grasp of salient
features in relevant circumstances, and an embryonic conception of the
concepts of the virtues to which they relate. These are prerequisites that
will enable him to make intelligible comparisons with that past experience
in appreciating the novel experiences he faces in the case history.
Second, case histories can vary considerably in length and depth. At one
end of the spectrum are fairly short case histories like the Rick and Bianca
case presented in this book. At the other is the Nestlé case history to be
found here and in much more detail on CD-Rom and the Internet. There
are reasons why the Nestlé case, as it stands, will be more suited to the
kind of use currently being discussed. The case needs to be presented with
considerable detail so that the student is in a position to discriminate what
is salient. The case also needs to engage the student’s imagination if it is to
have the quasi-experiential character required for the student to internalize
knowledge. Obviously apart from the depth and detail, the engagement of
the reader can be affected by the quality of the writing. Some case histories
are written in more engaging styles than others.
Even though it lacks the depth and detail of longer case histories, it
might be suggested that a brief history like the Rick and Bianca case could
be used as the basis for a role play in which students imaginatively develop
the case. Just as the engagement of the imagination is important if longer
case histories are to give students the necessary quasi-experience, so here,
when successful, such creative imagination will help in the student’s expe-
riencing the situation from a participant’s perspective. Used in that sort of
way, therefore, such a case history could also contribute to the acquisition
of nous.
All these factors, then, bear on the extent to which a case history actu-
ally serves to develop the student’s nous. For the sorts of reasons just
given, brief case histories like the Rick and Bianca case may need to be
used in a particular way, or else they will be more suited to the theoretical
uses that I outlined first. The main point here, however, is that case histo-
ries can, in principle, serve in the acquisition of nous, the intellectual
perception that is crucial to phronesis or practical wisdom. Enormously
developed and rich cases like those of Nestlé or Brent Spar or Challenger
can clearly serve this purpose.
Case history use in business ethics 171
made plausible by considering the effect that a fictional story can have in
that regard.14
In sum, a case history can affect the motivational force of a student’s
desires if the student comes to sympathize imaginatively with a personality,
or perhaps even with an abstract perspective in the case. The effect may be
to reinforce an already existing desire, which is perhaps most plausible
since that may itself have some causative effect on the agent’s sympathy.
However, the quasi-experience might even be sufficient to give motiva-
tional strength to a novel desire. In the latter case, the student would not
only come to see the point of some activity for the first time, but also
acquire, also for the first time, a corresponding feeling of motivation.
Imagine, for example, that a student comes to feel justified anger (justified
as he sees it, at least) that the Challenger was allowed to launch. He might
never have been in a situation like any of the engineers in that case but
now, for the first time, feel motivated to do something about safety impli-
cations if and when in relevantly similar circumstances.
Conclusion
Case histories can be used in a number of roles in ethical education. They
can have a theoretical role, and can be used to enhance a student’s under-
standing of a theory. But they can also be used in a way which will affect
the character development of the student. Thus, if the Aristotelian account
of moral psychology is broadly correct, and if case histories can teach busi-
ness ethics (or applied ethics quite generally), then it is foolish to think that
courses in business ethics (or applied ethics quite generally) cannot or
should not affect a student’s behaviour.
Notes
1 The term ‘behaviour’, here and throughout, is meant in its sense of conduct,
not simply physical movement.
2 One other way in which case histories can be used will not be analyzed here, so
it will be mentioned only to be put to one side. It is often suggested that, when
teaching applied ethics to students with no general background in philosophy,
it is useful to begin with case histories since beginning with actual historical
practice brings ethics closer to where the students are. Roughly speaking, the
thought here must be that such students are free of any ethical theory, and that
for such students the case can work as a stimulus, or introduction, to ethical
thought. Whether a student capable of studying ethics really can be entirely
free of ethical theory, and thus exactly what role the case history thus used has
in the development of ethical thought, will be left aside here. There are further
complex methodological issues as to the study of ethics here, on which
Aristotelian ethical theory for one has something to say. See, for example, my
‘Aristotelian Ethics’ in R. Chadwick (ed.), The Encyclopaedia of Applied Ethics
(Academic Press of America, San Diego, CA, 1997) vol. 1, pp. 212–13.
3 NE, V, 3–4, 1131 a10–1132 b14.
174 Chris Megone
4 Aristotle’s main discussion in NE is in Book VI, esp. chs 5–9 and 12–13. In
what follows I am also indebted to M. Nussbaum, The Fragility of Goodness,
(Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1986) pp. 298–306, though my
concern here is not with the relevance of rules to Aristotle’s understanding of
practical wisdom, which is Nussbaum’s focus there.
5 NE, VI, 8 1142 a23–9, in Nussbaum’s translation, op. cit., p. 305.
6 NE, II, 2 1104 a2–10.
7 NE, II, 9 1109 b20–23.
8 M. Nussbaum, op.cit., pp. 302–4.
9 M. Nussbaum, op. cit., p. 305. As noted, Nussbaum presents this view in the
context of arguing that Aristotle is a moral particularist. Whether that is right
or not, this account gives some flavour of the nature of nous, intellectual
perception.
10 NE, VI, 8 1142 a12–16. Nussbaum, op. cit., p. 306, also notes a similar
passage at NE, VI,11 1143 a25–b14.
11 NE, II, 1 1103 a36.
12 The variety of circumstances that can be encountered, and of considerations of
importance in those circumstances, is one of the main reasons why ethics is
such a hard subject.
13 NE, I, 3 1095 a6. Such childlikeness will be a reflection of bad upbringing,
lack of good guidance.
14 This is not to say that a case history need only be used like a work of literature.
There may be other ways in which it may be used in teaching, as was suggested
with reference to the Rick and Bianca case, for example. It is only to make
plausible the fact that it can affect the force of an agent’s motivations.
Index
Benetton 13 Burnyeat, M. 43
Big Bang (City) 16 business ethics, study of 1–5, 11,
Bingham Inquiry 101 161–74; applying theories to case
Biologist 88–90 histories 163; understanding theories
Bjerregaard, Ritt 84 162–3, 164; using case studies for
blackmail 100 comparison of theories 163–4; see
Blair, Tony 124, 127 also Aristotelian virtue theory; case
Blue Circle Cement 129 histories; ethics; Sternberg, E.
boards 12; independent members buy.com 134–5
13–14; of John Lewis 133; policy
setting and enforcing 17 Cadbury, Sir Adrian 3, 24, 154, 155
Bode, Thilo 78–9 Cadbury Limited 9
Body Shop 81 Cadbury Report see Code of Best
Boer War 11–12 Practice
Boesky, Ivan 10 Cape Kennedy Launch Complex 39-B
Boisjoly, Roger 111, 112, 115–16, 118 108
Bophal 9 case histories 1–5, 161–74; and
Borden 142 acquisition of phronesis and nous
Borrie, Gordon 24 165–71; and acquisition of virtuous
BP 60 motivation (link with desire) 171–3;
Brabeck, Peter 148 and behavioural change 164–5;
Breaking the Rules 1994 153 imaginative engagement with 172–3;
breastfeeding 142–3, 144, 146, 147, quality of the writing 170, 172;
148, 156; and AIDS 148; research theoretical purpose 162–4; varied
into 154 length and depth 170, 172
Brent Spar controversy 59–95; Caux Round Table Principles 12, 155
chronological sequence of events CBI (Confederation of British Industry)
91–5; cost of decommissioning 67; 128
decommissioning decision and lack CD-Roms 3, 5
of consultation 60–3; dialogue issue Challenger Flight 51-C 110
75–81; effect on industry 74–5; Challenger Flight 51-L disaster 108–22;
Greenpeace news releases 84–7; as case history 173; confusion over
Greenpeace occupies rig 63–5, 84; temperature specifications 112,
Greenpeace’s exaggeration of oil 118–19; design problems of solid
volume and radioactivity 65–7; rocket booster (SRB) 109–10, 111;
public opinion 73, 76, 77, 79–80; inadequacy of lines of commun-
recycling and re-use possibilities 72; ication 120–1; initial launch delays
re-use as Ro/Ro ferry quay 67; risks 110–11; launch and causes of
of land disposal 68, 70; role of explosion 112–13; possible last-
media 63–4, 65–6, 67, 73–4, 77; minute actions during countdown
scientific and ethical arguments 120–1; pre-launch teleconference
68–72, 87, 88–90; Shell’s efforts to 111–12; Presidential Commission on
restore reputation 67; Shell’s reversal 108, 116, 117–18, 119, 120, 121;
of decision 65; social accountability problems of bureaucracy 115–16;
analysis 79–80; types of reasons for hurried launch 110–11;
contaminants present 68; see also safety programme 114–15; Seal
Greenpeace; oil rigs, Erosion Task Team 110, 111, 112,
decommissioning of; Shell UK 115–16, 118, 119–20
Limited Channel 4 73
bribery: problem of defining 18–19; charity 29–30, 137
whistleblowing and 97, 100, 102–3, China, People’s Republic of 125–6
104, 105 Church 145, 147; see also religion
Index 177
against 146, 147; role of dialogue Lewis and 138; NASA and 121;
156; social responsibility approach Nestlé and 147; Shell and 73, 76, 78
151–4; social responsiveness ‘ordinary decency’ 26, 35–8
approach 154–5; sues ADW 145; organic food 137
tries to enlist academic support Oslo and Paris Commission 67, 87
148–9; tries to improve PR 145, Oslo Convention 62
146; and UNICEF 147–8; WHO OSPAR 60, 70
code accepted by 146, 147; see also Oxford University 149
infant formula milk substitute
Nestlé, Henri 142 Pagan, Rafael 146
Nestlé Coordination Center for paternalism 139
Nutrition 146, 147, 154 pay: executive 34–5, 37–8; ‘going rate’
Nestlé Infant Formula Audit 37–8; low 123–4, 125–6, 129;
Commission (Muskie Commission) statutory limits 36, 127
146, 147, 152, 153, 154 peer pressure see self-regulation
Nestlé UK 149 Peter Jones 131, 132, 133
New Internationalist 145, 150 Pettersson, Pelle 84
New Scientist 74 pharmaceutical industry 49, 142
New Zealand 104 phronesis (practical wisdom) 46,
Newton, Lisa 3 165–71
NGOs (non-governmental phronimos 43, 165
organizations) 145, 151, 152, 153, Plato 23, 40
156; accountability 154 Politics (Aristotle) 49
Nicomachean Ethics (Aristotle) 23, 40, Polly Peck 28
41–2, 43, 48, 49, 162, 165–9 practice (habituation) 43–5, 52–3, 168,
Nisbet, Euan 69 171–2
normative ethics 2 Presidential Commission on the
Challenger Disaster 108, 116,
North Feni Ridge 62
117–18, 119, 120, 121
North Sea 59, 60; industrial fishing 79;
pressure groups 74
see also Brent Spar controversy
Pridham, Jack 69
North Sea Decommissioning Group 75
private sector: as initiator of good
Norway: and Brent Spar 65, 67, 68, 70, practice 99
75; Det Norske Veritas 66 problem-solving: by consensus 129
nous 166, 167, 168, 169–71, 172 professional codes 13
Nussbaum, M. 167, 174 profit-sharing 136
NVQs (National Vocational ‘Profits and Principles – Does There
Qualifications) 128 Have to be a Choice’ (Shell) 79–80
prohairesis 43, 44–5
Oakeshott, Robert 139 ‘Public consequences of private action’
obligation 163, 164 (Sethi and Post) 149
Observer 69 Public Finance Initiative 125
OECD (Organization for Economic Public Interest Disclosure Act (UK,
Cooperation and Development) 105 1998) 105
oil rigs, decommissioning of 59; Brent public opinion: and Brent Spar
Spar as test run 62; Labour controversy 73, 76, 77, 79–80
government’s policy on 73; Public–Private Partnerships 125
moratorium on seabed disposal 67, public services 128; tendering for 125
70, 87; oil and gas industry sets up Purcell and Kessler 129
discussion group 74–5; regulations purpose of business 25–7, 47, 49–52
60; see also Brent Spar controversy
openness 13, 19–20, 101, 104; John radioactivity 66, 68
182 Index