Marginal Untility Theory - Retarded Acceptance - Kauder
Marginal Untility Theory - Retarded Acceptance - Kauder
Marginal Untility Theory - Retarded Acceptance - Kauder
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Oxford University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access
to The Quarterly Journal of Economics
This content downloaded from 211.145.57.214 on Wed, 01 Apr 2020 08:21:52 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
THE RETARDED ACCEPTANCE OF THE
MARGINAL UTILITY THEORY
By EMIL KAUDER
This content downloaded from 211.145.57.214 on Wed, 01 Apr 2020 08:21:52 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
MARGINAL UTILITY THEORY 565
Lottini Petty |
Davanzatti Locke Protestants
Montanari Adam Smith
Galiani > Catholics
Beccaria
Turgot
Condillac
This content downloaded from 211.145.57.214 on Wed, 01 Apr 2020 08:21:52 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
566 QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS
II
This content downloaded from 211.145.57.214 on Wed, 01 Apr 2020 08:21:52 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
MARGINAL UTILITY THEORY 567
This content downloaded from 211.145.57.214 on Wed, 01 Apr 2020 08:21:52 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
568 QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS
This content downloaded from 211.145.57.214 on Wed, 01 Apr 2020 08:21:52 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
MARGINAL UTILITY THEORY 569
This content downloaded from 211.145.57.214 on Wed, 01 Apr 2020 08:21:52 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
570 QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS
III
My theory has, however, an important limitation. The bela
acceptance of marginal utility in the nineteenth century cann
explained by the Aristotelian-Calvinistic dichotomy. Other con
tions prevailed. Economists in general no longer thought in acc
ance with their religious backgrounds. Only a dwindling minor
were influenced by religious convictions. To this small group b
longed Alfred Marshall, to whom Talcott Parsons has drawn
attention.9 The Evangelicalism of his dominating father left a st
imprint on the thinking of Alfred Marshall.' Evangelicalism w
Calvinistic revival movement which gained a foothold in m
Protestant churches of America and Great Britain during the n
teenth century. The Evangelicals demanded the consecratio
Christians to valuable and zealous action and the condemnation of
luxury.2
Marshall, as a mature personality, became an agnostic yet he
retained a deep feeling for religious values,3 and his welfare policy
was patterned after the moral postulates of Evangelicalism. "Work
in its best sense, the healthy energetic exercise of faculties is the aim
of life, is life itself," comfort is "a mere increase of artificial wants."4
Transferring this Calvinistic appreciation of activity for its own sake
and depreciation of comfort into economic theory produces a dilemma
which has been ably analyzed by Professor Parsons. On the one hand,
Marshall was one of the independent discoverers of marginal utility.
On the other hand, his glorification of labor attracted him to the cost
problem. The result was the unbalanced character of his price and
value theory. He failed to make fullest use of the marginal utility
theory,5 and he defended valiantly Ricardo's objective value theory.
9. In recent correspondence.
1. His father was "cast in the mould of the strictest Evangelicals." John M.
Keynes, "Alfred Marshall, 1842-1924," Memorials of Alfred Marshall, ed. A. C.
Pigou (London, 1925), p. 1.
2. About Evangelicalism: A Dictionary of English Church History, ed. S. L.
Ollard and Gordon Crosse (London, 1921), pp. 211, 215; Encyclopaedia of Religion
and Ethics, ed. James Hastings (New York, 1920), Vol. V, p. 602.
3. Memorials, op. cit., p. 7.
4. Quoted from Memorials and from Marshall's Principles in Talcott
Parsons, The Structure of Social Action (Glencoe, Ill., 1949), p. 141, n. 1, and p. 140.
Marshall's remark on his beloved chess game is typical of his Puritan abstinence
from luxury. "We are not at liberty to play chess games, or exercise ourselves
upon subtleties that lead nowhere. It is well for the young to enjoy the mere
pleasure of action, physical or intellectual. But the time presses; the responsi-
bility on us is heavy." Memorials, op. cit., p. 2.
5. It is worthy of note that Marshall presents the whole marginal utility
theory on two and one half pages in his Principles, a book dedicated mainly to
the explanation of price theory. Alfred Marshall, Principles of Economics (8th ed.;
London, 1930), pp. 92-94.
This content downloaded from 211.145.57.214 on Wed, 01 Apr 2020 08:21:52 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
MARGINAL UTILITY THEORY 571
This content downloaded from 211.145.57.214 on Wed, 01 Apr 2020 08:21:52 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
572 QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS
This content downloaded from 211.145.57.214 on Wed, 01 Apr 2020 08:21:52 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
MARGINAL UTILITY THEORY 573
IV
This content downloaded from 211.145.57.214 on Wed, 01 Apr 2020 08:21:52 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
574 QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS
This content downloaded from 211.145.57.214 on Wed, 01 Apr 2020 08:21:52 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
MARGINAL UTILITY THEORY 575
This content downloaded from 211.145.57.214 on Wed, 01 Apr 2020 08:21:52 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms