The Thought of Ayn Al Quzat

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 19

Maisonneuve & Larose

Mysticism and the Linguistic Problem of Equivocation in the Thought of 'Ayn Al-Quḍāt
Hamadānī
Author(s): Toshihiko Izutsu
Source: Studia Islamica, No. 31 (1970), pp. 153-170
Published by: Maisonneuve & Larose
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1595070 .
Accessed: 22/07/2013 09:20

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

Maisonneuve & Larose is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Studia Islamica.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 143.207.2.50 on Mon, 22 Jul 2013 09:20:24 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ANDTHELINGUISTIC
MYSTICISM PROBLEM
IN THETHOUGHT
OF EQUIVOCATION OF
'AYNAL-QUDATHAMADANI

'Ayn al-Qudat Hamadani (1098-1131) stands out as a tragic


figure in the history of Islamic thought. Like his great pre-
decessor Mansuir al-Hallaj (857-922) for whose ana al-Haqq
(e I am the Absolute! ,) he never concealed his unreserved
admiration, 'Ayn al-Qudat provoked by his ((free ) thinking
implacable envy and hatred in the minds of the conservative
orthodox theologians and lawyers, and as a result was executed
as a heretic in his native town, Hamadan, at the age of 33, with
appalling cruelty by the hands of a Seljuqid vizier of Iraq. He
was a mystic of profound spiritual experiences, and at the same
time a thinker endowed with an unusually keen intellectual
power of analysis. On the ground of this happy combination
of mystical penetration and rational thinking, one can rightly
regard him as a precursor of the long Iranian tradition of
Hikmat philosophy to be inaugurated soon after his death by
Suhrawardi (1153-1191) and Ibn 'Arabi (1165-1240). The
present paper purports to analyze the very original semantic
aspect of the thought of this philosophic genius who has been up
to a short time ago unduly neglected by the orientalists ().

(1) The study is based on three of his major works that have been edited and
published in Tehran : (1) Zubdat al-.Iaqd'iq (Arabic) ed. 'Afif 'Oseyran, 1962;
(2) Tamhidat (Persian) ed. 'Afif 'Oseyr&n, 1962; (3) his < Epistles >. Ndme-hd-ye

This content downloaded from 143.207.2.50 on Mon, 22 Jul 2013 09:20:24 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
154 TOSHIHIKO IZUTSU

The basic principle underlying the whole structure of Hama-


dani's thought, reduced to the most elementary form, will be
found to consist in making a sharp distinction between knowing
the reality of a thing through an immediate personal experience
of it and knowing something about the thing. To know about
honey that it is sweet is one thing, to know by experience the
sweetness of honey another. The same distinction between
the two types of knowledge holds true at the higher level of
religious life. Thus to know something about God is completely
different from knowing Him by coming into direct contact with
the divine order of things.
'Ayn al-Qudat noticed this difference himself through a
personal, and we might say, existential experience. At first he
was making a most extensive study of theological works. But
the study of theology caused in his mind nothing but confusion,
bewilderment and despair. A spiritual crisis came. He could
only overcome it by the perusal of the works of Abi Hamid al-
Ghazali (1058-1111), to which he devoted four years. He did
not meet personally Ghazali, but under the latter's spiritual
guidance he went to the extreme limits of intellectual power and
almost went over them. Without being clearly conscious of
the fact, he was gradually stepping into the supra-intellectual
domain of Divine Mystery, when quite by chance he met the
brother of Abu Hamid the noted mystic master Ahmad al-
Ghazali (d. circa 1126). It was under Ahmad Ghazali's per-
sonal guidance that he went definitely beyond the boundaries
of rational thinking far into the divine world itself where human
reason and its logical function are reduced to utter powerless-
ness (1).
Man's stepping into the divine world is for Hamadani an
event of decisive importance consisting in the realization of a
new depth of consciousness in his interior. It implies man's

'Ayn al-Quddt-e Hamadani (Persian), ed. 'Afif 'Oseyran and 'Alinaqi Munzawi, 1969.
It is my pleasant duty to add that in the course of preparing this paper I have
profited much by valuable suggestions made by Professor Hermann Landolt of the
Institute of Islamic Studies, McGill Uhiversity.
(1) This whole process of spiritual development is described with a beautiful
touch of lyricism by 'Ayn al-Qudat himself in Zubdah, pp. 6-7.

This content downloaded from 143.207.2.50 on Mon, 22 Jul 2013 09:20:24 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
TOUGHT OF 'AYN AL-OUDiT HAMADiNI 155
existential transition to an entirely different plane of conscious-
ness from that of sensation and rational thinking. Hamad&ni
calls this event the e opening of the eye of spiritual vision >(1)
(infilah 'ayn al-basTrah), or <of the eye of gnostic cognition> (2)
('ayn al-ma'rifah). He refers to it also by saying: < a window is
opened in your interior toward the domain of the supra-sensible
order of things)>(rawzanah ila 'dlam al-malakat (s). Sometimes
it is described as the <appearance of light in the interior (4)
(zuhar nar fT al-bdtin). Ontologically, this subjective e light,
lightens up what he calls the ( domain beyond reason) (al-lawr
ward'a al-'aql) (5).
Not that Hamadani despises, or negates the value of, reason
and rational thinking (6). But man, according to him, does not
reach perfection unless he goes beyond the <domain of reason ,,
after having gone to the utmost limits of his rational power, into
the trans-rational dimension of things. The very structure of
the whole world of Being, in his conception, is such that the last
stage of the domain of empirical experiences is directly connected
with the first stage of the < domain beyond reason > (7).
After these preliminary remarks, we are now in a position to
discuss the nature of the specific problems raised by Hamadani
with regard to the semantic structure of human language. It
goes without saying that the words and their combinations which
are at our disposal are primarily so made that they might most
conveniently and suitably be used for the purposes of daily
communication. Our language is at its best when it is used to
express and describe our experiences in the empirical world
where the senses and reason fulfil their natural functions.
But even in this dimension it often happens that we get embar-

(1) Zubdah, p. 7, and passim.


(2) Ibid., p. 30.
(3) Ibid., p. 58.
(4) Ibid., p. 26.
(5) Ibid., p. 27, and passim. It is one of the technical expressions that appear
constantly in Hamadani's writings. It is also called the , domain (that comes)
after reason (al-tawr alladhl ba'da al-'aql).
(6) Cf. ibid., p. 10.
(7) Cf. ibid., p.35.

This content downloaded from 143.207.2.50 on Mon, 22 Jul 2013 09:20:24 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
156 TOSHIHIKO IZUTSU

rassed by the realization that there is a wide gap between what


we feel or know and what we can say. As Ludwig Wittgenstein
remarked (1): If someone knows how many feet high Mont Blanc
is and yet is not able to say it, we naturally are surprised; but
not so if someone knows how a clarinet sounds and yet is not able
to say it, for the knowledge of how a clarinet sounds is not a kind
of thing which can properly be described by an ordinary combin-
ation of words at our disposal. And of course the situation
grows far worse if, in addition to the empirical dimension of
human experience, we recognize the authenticity of the supra-
empirical dimension of spiritual or mystical awareness. The
Sufi, when he wishes at all to express himself verbally or des-
cribe his personal visions, must of necessity be faced with all the
linguistic problems that arise from the serious discrepancy bet-
ween what he knows and what he can actually (2) say.
What, then, will be the effective means the Sufi can have
recourse to in order to fill up this intrinsic deficiency of his
linguistic apparatus? Or, is there at all any? Symbolism will
perhaps be the first thing that one might think of. In fact
many mystic poets-or even mystic philosophers-in all ages
have created systems of symbols and taken refuge in them.
But it is not symbolism that Hamadani has recourse to.
Instead, he proposes that one should in such cases use words in
a multi-dimensional way which he designates as lashabuh, or
< equivocation >. And in fact, according to him, the majority
of the key-terms of religious philosophy in Islam must be inter-
preted by way of # equivocation >.
However, in order that we might be able to understand the
full meaning of a word used in an < equivocal > way-not to
speak of those cases in which we ourselves are using a word in
such manner- we have to have cultivated in ourselves an
extremely flexible and, as it were, mobile attitude with regard
to the semantic connection between a word and the meaning
which it is intended to indicate.

(1) Philosophical Investigations, 78, p. 36.


(2) Zubdah, pp. 88 (line 16-89.

This content downloaded from 143.207.2.50 on Mon, 22 Jul 2013 09:20:24 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
TOUGHT OF 'AYN AL-QUDiT HAMADANi 157
The most serious hindrance in the way of our understanding or
using words equivocally is the unduly great importance we ordi-
narily tend to attach to words in the word-meaning relationship.
This tendency is shown in its crudest form in the infantile use of
language (1). Childrenin fact cannot easily identify semantically
the word layth, for example, with asad simply because these
words happen to have two different external forms, although in
Arabic both mean one and the same thing < lion >. But the
grown-ups, too, often commit fundamentally the same kind of
mistake, albeit in a bit more sophisticated form.
The attitude to place undue emphasis on words as distin-
guished from meanings is ultimately reducible to the fact that
man naturally tends to believe that there is one-to-one corres-
pondence between a word and its meaning. In Hamadani's
view, nothing can be farther from the truth. The world of
meanings is something of an infinitely delicate, flexible and
flowing nature. It has no such rigid stability as corresponds
to the formal or material rigidity of words. This fact is easily
observable even in our daily use of the most ordinary words,
although normally it does not come up to the surface of clear
consciousness.
Take, for example, the Persian word nmm,((half >. The exact
meaning of the word varies in a delicate way according to wheth-
er or not quantity is made the point of reference. Let us say:
The major work of Abu HImid al-Ghazali consists of two parts;
the one half (nfm) deals with external properties of the body
while the other half (n(m) is concerned with the properties of
the mind. In such a case, the word < half , does not mean the
precise quantitative half of the book, because the division is here
made not in terms of quantity. Similarly, the same sentence
< Man is composed of two parts ) (Adami do chiz ast) indicates
two entirely different divisions if we mean thereby (1) ((namely,
head and body > and (2) ( namely, mind and body >(2). The
observation of this fact-which is by no means a difficult thing
to do-simply indicates that there is an undeniable discrepancy

(1) Epistle No. LX, ? 753, p. 452.


(2) Epistle No. LIII, ? 677, p. 405.

This content downloaded from 143.207.2.50 on Mon, 22 Jul 2013 09:20:24 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
158 TOSHIHIKO IZUTSU

between the world of words and the world of meanings. Unfortu-


nately, however, this semantic discrepancy is not so obvious on
levels of discourse higher than that of empirical experience.
Hamadani, be it remarked at this point, does not believe that
there is between a word and its meaning a strong, inner organic
tie. Quite the contrary, the semantic tie between them is, in
his view, something perfunctory, purely external, and in a
certain sense, even unreal. For there is no equal distribution of
weight between the two terms of the relationship. Only a very
precarious sort of equilibrium is maintained between them.
How can it be otherwise? The two, according to Hamadani
belong to different orders of being. The word belongs in the
world of material and sensible things (mulk), while the meaning
properly is of the world of immateriality (malakui). Compared
with the vast field of meaning that lies behind each word, the
latter is nothing more than an insignificant, tiny point. The
word is but a narrow gate through which the human mind steps
into a boundless domain of meaning. Moreover, the meaning
is something that has, so to speak, its own life. It has no fixity.
Quite independently of the word which indicates it, the meaning
develops as it were of its own accord with amazing flexibility in
accordance with the degree of depth of man's experience and
consciousness. The meaning with such characteristics is poured
into the ready-made mould of a word. By simply observing
from outside the word thus employed, one could hardly judge
the width and depth of the meaning that is intended to be
conveyed by it. This is particularly true when the meaning
that has been poured into the mould of a word happens to be
backed by a profound mystical experience. When the meaning
is thus of a non-empirical nature, the use of a word in reference
to it necessarily goes to the extremity of equivocation (ghdyat
al-tashdbuh) (1).
In such cases, in order to gain an exact insight into the mean-
ing indicated, one has to take a very delicate attitude towards
the indicating word. For one is here required to use the given
word as a springboard by which to dive into the depth of the

(1) Zubdah, p. 4.

This content downloaded from 143.207.2.50 on Mon, 22 Jul 2013 09:20:24 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
TOUGHT OF 'AYN AL-QUDAT HAMAAnINi 159
meaning. As long as one remains trying to understand the
meaningfrom the word,one can never hope to obtainit. Rather
at the very first and the slightest touch with the word, one must
leave it there and go directly into the domain of meaning(1).
But in orderto understandthe real significanceof this idea, we
must first elucidate the structure of equivocation accordingto
what Hamadanisays about it.
, Equivocation> or ( equivocality > (tashabuh) normally im-
plies uncertainty,indeterminationand ambiguousnessin the use
of a word. The ultimate source of these negative propertiesis
polysemy, a semantic phenomenonin which a word happens to
have in its basic structure a number of differentmeanings. If,
for instance, the Arabicword 'ayn is used without any clarifying
context, or within an insufficientlyclear context, one is said to
be using the word equivocally. For 'ayn can mean such widely
divergent things as <eye >),< spring)>(source of water), e essence ),
<(gold piece ), (uterine brother ), etc.
The kind of equivocation Hamadani is thinking of is com-
pletely differentfromthis type of polysemy. For the divergent
meaningsthat are connectedwith a word like 'ayn stand in one
and the same dimension. It is, we might say, a case of horizon-
tal polysemy, while what Hamadaniis concernedwith may be
characterizedas vertical polysemy. The latter is the multi-
dimensionalstructureof meaning based upon the multi-dinen-
sional use of the word.
Thus the equivocation as conceived by Hamadani refers to
those cases in which one and the same word-or one and the
same expression-happens to be used significantly and at the
sametime at two or more than two differentslevels of discourse.
Thereare conceivablemany such levels of discourse,but Hama-
dani is interested principally in two of them: [A] the level of
rational thinking, and [B] the level of the <(domainbeyond
reason>)to which referencehas earlierbeen made.
The level [A] is linguisticallyno other than a linear extension
of the ordinaryuse of languagein the daily, empiricaldimension

(1) Ibid., p. 58.

This content downloaded from 143.207.2.50 on Mon, 22 Jul 2013 09:20:24 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
160 TOSHIHIKO IZUTSU

of human experience. In the particular context which is our


immediate concern, the [A] level refers primarily to the lin-
guistic expression of theological concepts and thinking. Just
to give an example in a preliminary way, the theologians often
speak of the <nearness , (qurb) and <remoteness > (bu'd) of
man from God. Thus, for instance, those who do not believe
in God are said to be ( remote) from Him, while the believers
are said to be ( close > to, or < near God. As such, it is a per-
fectly significant use of the words. The concepts of ( nearness >
and ?remoteness)> in this context are but the result of the
theological elaboration of the <nearness> and <remoteness )>
respectively of the sensible things which we encounter in our
daily empirical experiences. Consequently, these two concepts
are at this level still understood basically in terms of the image
or idea of spatial distance.
However, the same words, qurb and bu'd, can be, and are in
fact often used by the mystics in describing the content of their
peculiar intuitions, whether religious or metaphysical. In such
a case, the words-according to the basic pattern of analysis
which we have here adopted-are being used at the [B] level.
The most important point to note concerning the [B] level, is that
the meaning which is actualized at this stage can never be reached
no matter how far one may extend the meaning that obtains at the
[A] level. This comes from the fact that the meanings of all
words at the [B] level are based on cognitive experiences that
are of a radically different nature from what is experienced in
the dimension of rational thinking, not to speak of in the dimen-
sion of daily life. For, as we have seen above, the meanings at
the [B] level are perceived only by the < eye of spiritual vision >
in the < domain beyond reason >. Thus, for example, qurb
? nearness ) at this level means for Hamadanl a certain supra-
sensible relationship that obtains between all existents and the
Source of existence, a very peculiar relationship, the structure
of which will be analyzed in detail later on. Suffice it to say at
this stage that ? nearness > here means the relationship of abso-
lute ontological equality which all things bear to God. Taking
the word ( distance > in an non-spatial sense, Hamadani often
speaks of all things standing at an absolutely equal distance from

This content downloaded from 143.207.2.50 on Mon, 22 Jul 2013 09:20:24 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
TOUGHT OF *AYN AL-QUDAT HAMADANi 161
God (1). Although Hamadani himself does not explicitly analyze
the meaning of xremoteness, at the [B] level, it is clear that,
since there is no spatial reference in this domain, ( remoteness )
turns out to be exactly of the same meaning as e nearness >,i.e. all
things being at the same (non-spatial) g distance > from God.
Although, in this way, the same word ((nearness) has two
entirely different meanings, we should not commit the mistake of
thinking that the meaning [A] and the meaning [B] have nothing
to do with each other. The relation between the meaning [A]
and the meaning [B] is not at all the same as the one which
obtains between, say, ((fountain ), < eye , ((gold >, ( essence >etc.
as possible meanings of the word 'ayh. For even at the [B]
level, qurb does maen ( nearness *. Only the ( nearness )) that
is actualized in the supra-sensible dimension is of a totally
different structure from the < nearness ) in the sensible or rational
dimension of experience. Otherwise expressed, the semantic
content of ( nearness ) changes from spatial to non-spatial in
accordance with the qualitative change that occurs in the human
consciousness. But this change does not affect the fact that
one and the same word is being used significantly and meaning-
fully at two different levels, [A] and [B].
The question is not: Which of the two meanings-[A] or [B]-
is genuine and real? (or which is figurative and metaphorical?)
For both are equally authentic and real, each in its peculiar
dimension, because each is backed by an authentic experience.
When I say, for example, < I see a flower ), my seeing has on the
empirical level an authentic meaning backed by an authentic
sense experience. Likewise, when I say, < The whole is bigger
than a part of it ), my statement has an authentic meaning at
the level of rational thinking (the [A] level). In the same way,
when Mansfir al-Hallaj says ana al-Haqq <I am the Absolute) (2),
his statement has an authentic meaning at the supra-sensible

(1) Ibid., pp. 77-78.


(2) For an analysis of the famous Hallajian statement, see Shakwd at-Gharib
(ed. 'Afif 'Oseyran, 1962, Tehran), p. 36, p. 62 (Arberry's English translation: A
Sufi Martyr, London, 1969, p. 36), and Tamhidat, ? 84, p. 62; ? 108, p. 77; ? 104,
p. 75.

12

This content downloaded from 143.207.2.50 on Mon, 22 Jul 2013 09:20:24 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
162 TOSHIHIKO IZUTSU

and supra-rational level of experience (the [B] level). The


only important point is that each of these three sentences must
be understood strictly in terms of the dimension to which it
properly belongs.
To have this kind of understanding, however, with regard to
words and sentences belonging to the [B] level is extremely
difficult, if not absolutely impossible. For ana al-Haqq (of
al-Hallaj), Subhdan( Glory to Me >(of Bastami) and the like are
all inspired utterances made by mystics of the highest spiritual
calibre when they happen to be in an unusual state of conscious-
ness-a state in which their rational power has broken down and
in which they have been ( annihilated in the illumination of
the overpowering Light of eternity ,>. ( Here there is no more
the subject of knowledge left; the act of knowing itself has been
annihilated; and everything has turned into the object of
knowledge (which is properly speaking no longer the object of
knowledge, since there is no subject to know it). It is in such a
state that this remaining point discloses itself in the plain of pure
and absolute Divinity (jabarut). Then what could Husayn
(al-Hallaj) say but ana al-Haqq! What could Bayazid (Bastami)
say but Subahdn >(1) It will be clear that in order that one
might be able to understand the meaning of such utterances
strictly in terms of the [B] level to which they belong, one has
to have passed through the same kind of mystical experience.
Consequently, for those who have no direct experiential
knowledge of the < domain beyond reason ), the use of words at
the [B] level-even if they theoretically admit the legitimacy
of such use of words-must necessarily appear as figurative (2).
Briefly stated, words used at the [B] level are for the majority
of men metaphors. The word nur <light >, for instance, is for
them simply a metaphor when God is called Light.

(1) Tamhldat, ? 84, p. 62. Cf. Epistle XLII, ? 560, p. 355, where the expression
<the plain of mulk > (i.e. empiriral dimension) is used instead of < the plain of
jabaruit ). Both expressions make good sense, because the mystical experience in
question belongs to the dimension of jabarut, but its linguistic expression is actual-
ized only in the empirical wolrld.
(2) Zubdah, p. 24 (11. 12-13).

This content downloaded from 143.207.2.50 on Mon, 22 Jul 2013 09:20:24 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
TOUGHT OF 'AYN AL-QUDAT HAMADANi 163
For those who have direct access to the ( domain beyond
reason >, however, it is rather the meaning at the [A] level (i.e.
nur in the sense of physical light) that is metaphorical. This
because the dimension of [B] is precisely the place where reality
is experienced in its original, absolute state. In this particular
context the [A] use of language is metaphorical, while the [B] use
is real (1).
As a typical example illustrating the semantic structure of
language at the [A] and [B] level, we shall now take up the word
'ilm (4knowledge >as it appears in the phrase , God's knowledge >,
about which Hamadani himself goes into considerable detail.
As in the foregoing, let [A] represent the theological and [B] the
supra-rational, or mystical level of understanding.
At the [A] level which is, as noted before, but a theological
extension of the ordinary use of language, < God knows some-
thing > is naturally understood on the analogy of <Man knows
something >. And within the confines of this understanding
various theological problems are raised and discussed by the
theologians under the' title of the < divine Attributes >>,for the
knowledge in this context is conceived as one of the Attributes
of God.
Since the meaning of a word as understood at the [A] level is
essentially and ultimately nothing other than a theoretic extens-
ion or elaboration of the empirical, pre-theological understanding
of the same word, so 'ilm <knowledge >, too, is naturally under-
stood on the analogy of what is usually understood by the word
in ordinary daily circumstances. Now in the ordinary, empi-
rical dimension, < knowledge > has a peculiar structure of its
own based on a two-term relation between the subject ('dlim the
( knower >) and the object (ma'lam the <known >). And what
is peculiar about this cognitive relationship consists in the fact
that the subject is passive and the object active. That is to
say, the subject of knowledge can play the role of a subject
when and only when there is something to be known. The
existence of the object precedes the existence of the subject qua
subject: (S -0) (2).

(1) Ibid., pp. 21-22.


(2) Epistle XXI, ? 270, pp. 176-177.

This content downloaded from 143.207.2.50 on Mon, 22 Jul 2013 09:20:24 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
164 TOSHIHIKO IZUTSU

This peculiar structure of empirical knowledge is transferred


consciously or unconsciously to the theological plane of thinking.
Thus the theological proposition ? God knows X ) would be
understood in the following sense: There is first X as a possible
object of divine knowledge, and the God comes to know it as it
really is. God does have an Attribute called < knowledge ?, but
it can exercise its function only when there are proper objects to
be known. The object, in short, acts upon, and determines,
the subject. Hence the notorious aporia concerning God's
knowledge of the particulars, i.e. the individual things and events
of the empirical world.
This aporia arises when, on the assumption that ( knowledge )
at all levels of experience maintains the above-mentioned basic
structure: (S -O), we ask the theological question whether God
knows the particulars. If we say Yes, we would thereby be
implying that God's knowledge is something contingent. For
the empirical world is by nature a domain of contingency. All
things are there constantly changing. No particular thing
remains exactly the same for two units of time. If God's
knowledge is to pursue the particular things as they go on
changing from moment to moment, it must also go on changing
from moment to moment. Moreover, in this world new things
incessantly come into being, and new states of affairs are
constantly occurring. According as God becomes aware of
them, new cognitive states would have to occur constantly in His
mind. But to admit this would be nothing other than admitting
the contingency of God's knowledge (1).
If, in order to escape this difficulty, we say No, we would
simply be saying that God is ignorant of certain things. Where
then would be the omniscience of God? Curiously enough, this
statement of God's ignorance, namely the proposition: ( The
knowledge of the Eternal does not comprehend the particulars
of the (empirical) world ) ('ilm-e azal be-juz'Tyad-e'alam muhil
nmst)(2) was precisely one of the statements for the sake of which
Hamadani was accused of heresy and unbelief.

(1) Zubdah, p. 22, p. 25.


(2) Epistle VIII, ? 219, p. 150.

This content downloaded from 143.207.2.50 on Mon, 22 Jul 2013 09:20:24 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
TOUGHT OF 'AYN AL-QUDAT HAMADANi 165

According to Hamadani, the above aporia itself arises simply


because the theologians understand the meaning of ( knowledge *
on the analogy of what is meant by the same word in the empi-
rical dimension of experience. This way of understanding
as
appears something quite natural in the light of what we have
said earlier about the semantic structure of the [A] level; name-
ly, that the use of language at this level is but a theological
extension of the empirical use of language. The theologians
are after all people who cannot break the magic spell of ordinary
language.
In order, however, to grasp the read semantic structure of
God's knowledge, one will have to push one's analysis further
beyond the confines of ordinary rational thinking into the inter-
mediary region (1) lying between the [A] level and [B] level.
More concretely stated, one will have to have recourse to a
peculiar type of thinking which is at once rational reasoning and
metaphysical intuition. This will be done in the following way.
A distinction must be made, first of all, between two kinds of
knowledge: (1) knowledge which presupposes, and is derived
from, the existence of the object to be known, and (2) knowledge
which is presupposed by, and from which is derived, the very
existence of the object known. Hamadani explains this dis-
tinction by an example taken from the domain of daily expe-
rience. ( My knowledge about this epistle (which I am now
sending to you) had been there in my mind before I actually
began writing it. And this knowledge of mine was the cause
of the existence of this epistle. If it were not for this knowledge,
the epistle would not have come into being. Your knowledge
of my epistle, on the contrary, is actualized only after the exist-
ence of my epistle. In this case it is my epistle that is the cause
of the existence of your knowledge >(2). The relation between

(1) 'Ayn al-Qudat himself does not speak of the < intermediary region >between
[A] and [B]. Theoretically he seems to be content with his distinction between
the two levels of discourse, so that according to his own description the analysis
here in question would seem to be made still within the confines of theological
thinking. But for the sake of clarity we had better, I think, consider it as some-
thing going beyond the [A] dimension.
(2) Epistle VIII, ? 220, pp. 150-151.

This content downloaded from 143.207.2.50 on Mon, 22 Jul 2013 09:20:24 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
166 TOSHIHIKO IZUTSU

God's knowledge and the particulars must be understood as of


the same structure as the relation which holds in this example
between < my knowledge # and < this epistle of mine >.
Thus through the basic distinction made between the two
kinds of knowledge, Hamadani's thought approaches the meta-
physical dimension of things. He concludes: ( The knowledge
of the Eternal is the very Source of existence (yanbi'-e wujid).
All existents, whether of the empirical world or of the supra-
empirical world, are to the infinite width of God's eternal know-
ledge just as one single letter (of one single word) appearing in
this epistle is to the width of my knowledge and ability >(1).
From this conclusion to the highest level of discourse (level
[B]) it is only a matter of one further step. But on the other
hand there is also noticeable a remarkable difference between the
[B] level and the preceding levels, whether [A] or the interme-
diary. For even at the intermediary stage which has just been
described and which is evidently very much of a metaphysical
or ontological nature, the word ( knowledge # still retains some-
thing of an epistemological connotation. There is, in other
words, in the use of the term ((knowledge > still some reference,
no matter how slight it may be, to the ordinary mental activity
of man by which he perceives and knows objective things.
As used at the [B] level, on the contrary, ( knowledge > carries
absolutely no epistemological connotation. Its meaning is
purely metaphysical. For God's (<knowledge ) here means
God's ma'lyah (lit. <<with-ness > or the absolute non-separation
of God from all things), and consequently the equidistance of
all things from their ultimate ontological Source. This is an
interesting point which needs to be elucidated in some detail,
because Hamadani himself declares that it is his original idea
and that nobody has ever expressed such a view on this pro-
blem (2).
It is a matter of common experience, he begins to argue, that
we constantly find things in the empirical world standing in
priority-posteriority relationship to each other. The appear-

(1) Epistle XIX, ? 251, p. 166.


(2) Epistle III, ? 22, p. 20.

This content downloaded from 143.207.2.50 on Mon, 22 Jul 2013 09:20:24 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
TOUGHT OF 'AYN AL-QUDAT HAMADANI 167
ance of the sunbeams, for example, comes after the rise of the
sun, the latter being the cause of the former. Likewise, the
movement of the pen with which I am now writing these words
follows the movement of my hand, which again follows the exist-
ence of myself as the writer.
The structure of the events of this kind, however, will appear
in a completely different light when looked at from the point of
view of the divine dimension. For in this perspective, both the
sun and its beams are found to be standing at an equal distance
from the Absolute. In a similar way, (1) the pen which is an
instrument by which I am writing, (2) the letters written by me
and (3) the writer (i.e. myself) stand on one single plane and at
equal distance from the Absolute. All this because we are now
in a metaphysical region where there is no temporal succession
(ful, lit. (length ?, vertical order), between things. All things
are here contemplated co-existing in a limitless, a-temporal
expanse ('ard, lit. ((breadth ,, horizontal order) of existence.
Hamadani criticizes Ibn Sina by saying that the latter has
confused the empirical dimension with the divine dimension
when he has established his proof of the existence of God on the
causal connections between things. A thing A, in order to
exist, must have something else, B, as its cause; B in its turn must
have its own cause C; C must have D, etc.... And at the very
extremity of the whole series of causes, A- - - B- - - C- -- D- --...
Ibn Sin5 believes to have found the Cause of all causes, God
the Absolute.
According to Hamadani this view is completely wrong. He
points out the crucial weakness of Ibn Sina's argument in the
following way (1). ( There are in this epistle of mine, for example,
ten thousand letters. Each letter comes into being (i.e. is
written) after another letter. And the second line comes after
the first line; the third line after the second; the fourth after the
third. Now suppose someone says: The tenth line comes into
being from the ninenth; the nineth from the eighth; the eighth
from the seventh, etc., and finally the third from the second, the

(1) Ibid., ? 23, p. 21.

This content downloaded from 143.207.2.50 on Mon, 22 Jul 2013 09:20:24 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
168 TOSHIHIKO IZUTSU

second from the first. Suppose further that at this point he


says: The first line itself has come into being from the will and
ability (to write) of the writer. This person evidently is taking
a wrong wiew of the matter, because he is seeking the position of
the writer in the vertical (i.e. temporal) evolvement of the
epistle, instead of in the horizontal (i.e. a-temporal) expanse of it.
Such a person will no doubt consider the distance of the first and
the second line from the will of the writer much shorter than
the distance of the eighth, nineth, or tenth line from his wil
to write ).
We have only to apply this kind of thinking to the above-
mentioned argument of Ibn Sina to realize that the mistake
committed by him consists precisely in that he is (unconsciously)
representing God as something temporal (zamanl). ( If he
had been in possession of a pure, uncontaminated view, he
would have seen no distance between God and any contingent
thing; he would have recognized the existential equidistance of
all things from Him. For the Absolute absolutely transcends
time. Witness how all the letters that are written on this sheet
of paper stand at an equal distance from the writer, if they are
considered from the viewpoint of the a-temporal existential
expanse, not from that of temporal succession > (1).
This existential equidistance of all things from God is the
semantic structure of the word 'ilm "knowledge" as it is used
at the [B] level of discourse in reference to the divine Attribute
which is indicated by the same word. There still remains one
more point to mention concerning the structure of " with-ness "
(God is with all things). It will be obvious that " with-ness "
implies the existence of a certain relation between the Absolute
and the empirical things. But it is a very peculiar kind of
relation. The peculiarity consists in the fact that this relation
has actuality only when looked at from the side of the Absolute,
but not from the side of the things. For the things in the
empirical world are in themselves sheer " nothing ", having no
reality of their own. The reality or existence that they seem to

(1) Ibid.

This content downloaded from 143.207.2.50 on Mon, 22 Jul 2013 09:20:24 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
TOUGHT OF 'AYN AL-QUDAT HAMADANI 169
have is derived from the very relation into which they enter by
the activity of the Absolute. (1)
Thus in terms of our ordinary use of the word " relation"
(nisbah), the relation which we are now taking about is no
relation at all. How could there be any relation when one of
the terms of relation is " nothing "? This is precisely what is
meant by Hamadani 'when he says: " Everything that exists in
this world has a relation to the width of the eternal Knowledge,
but this relation is so to speak the relation which a 'nothing'
(ld-shay') bears to a thing which is infinite" (2). But to say
so is tantamount to saying that " no existent thing has any
relation whatsoever to the width of the eternal Knowledge ". (3)
Therefore, we can rightly say: God is with the things, but we
cannot reverse the order and say: The things are with God. (4)
For there is absolutely nothing in the world that could stand
face to face with God. It is God that turns His Face (wajh) to
all things (5), and that is the real meaning of the statement that
God knows all things, The things themselves have no face to
turn toward God.
Since, however, it is impossible in normal circumstances to
think of, or to represent, a two-term relation with " nothing " as
one of its terms, we tend to imagine "nothing " as " something"
and posit between the two terms a bi-lateral relationship
(A<-B). Thus we often speak of the things standing in front
of God, turning their faces toward Him (muqdbalah). (6)
But, on the other hand, it is also true that the things do
possess a certain kind of reality which is derived from God's
turning His Face toward them. In this sense there is a bi-
lateral relationship between the things and God. And in this
perspective, each of the existents in the world is " existent "
(mawjud) and " non-existent " (ma'dum) at one and the same

(1) In the terminology of the later theosophers, this kind of relation is called
< illuminative relation > (idafah ishraqlyah).
(2) Zubdah, p. 21 (11. 17-18).
(3) Ibid., p. 25 (11. 15-16).
(4) Ibid., pp. 62-63, p. 76.
(5) Ibid., pp. 20, 26.
(6) Ibid., p. 23.

This content downloaded from 143.207.2.50 on Mon, 22 Jul 2013 09:20:24 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
170 TOSHIHIKOIZUTSU

time. It is this peculiar ontological situation that the word


" knowledge " (of God) indicates at the [B] level of discourse.
The phenomenon of equivocation as understood by Hamadani
consists in a multi-dimensional structure formed by two or
more meanings (as those of the word " knowledge " at the [A]
and [B] levels), which are different from each other in terms of
the depth of vision, being put together into one single semantic
entity.
Toshihiko IzuTsU
(Montreal and Tehran)

This content downloaded from 143.207.2.50 on Mon, 22 Jul 2013 09:20:24 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like