Correlativity of Rights and Duties by David Lyons
Correlativity of Rights and Duties by David Lyons
Correlativity of Rights and Duties by David Lyons
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Wiley is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Noûs
DAVID LYONS
CORNELL UNIVERSITY
45
vary substan
that all righ
common ele
"correlations
II
8 See Hart, op. cit., 178 and 181, and also his "Legal and Moral Obliga-
tion," in Essays in Moral Philosophy (ed. by Melden).
Court reviews such a law it finds it null and void, with no legal
effect.
Now it is easy to confuse this right with an area of free
choice protected by prohibitions against interference, for the latter
can be inferred from the former and standing conditions. If Congress
cannot restrict one's speech then it is not unlawful for one to speak
or remain silent; and since one is generally protected against inter-
ference (as I shall argue) others also have "obligations not to inter-
fere." But such Constitutional rights are not the same as these
protected areas of choice since we could lose the former and retain
the latter. To see this, imagine the First Amendment repealed: then
Congress would acquire the "power" to enact legally binding laws
restricting speech now unrestrictable. But Congress could have
this power without exercising it, and thus it could happen that
speech was no more restricted than it is right now and that one's
speaking and remaining silent were equally lawful and protected
against interference even though we could no longer truly say that
we have Constitutional rights of free speech.
These Constitutional rights exemplify what some jurists call
"immunities,"9 for to assert them is to say that protected areas of
speech cannot be taken away. Alvin's Constitutional right has a
conceptual correlative: but it is not an obligation; it is a legislative
"disability," the assertion of which says that Congress is not em-
powered to enact certain laws.
It may still be tempting to search for 'correlative" obliga-
tions here; but the candidates are implausible. The Constitutional
right of free speech is independent of, for example, the obligation
not to assault that was breached by those who silenced Alvin. Nor
does it correlate with obligations incumbent on Congress. There
may be some point in speaking of a Congressional "obligation"
not to (try to) exceed one's legislative powers or, more specifically,
not to restrict speech guaranteed free by the First Amendment. But
this "obligation" would be a queer one, for the members of Congress
are not subject to civil or criminal action against them if they
"breach" it by enacting unconstitutional laws. If they do this their
actions could be described as "illegal" or "unlawfurl only in the
sense of "invalid": it is not that they would break the law in so act-
ing, but rather that they would fail to make valid and binding
law.
rights do not logically correlate with those rights since others are,
in general, under such obligations even when one does not have a
right to act as he does.
Before considering some rebuttals, we should deal with the
possible inference in the other direction-from "active" rights to
protecting obligations-for this alleged entailment is all that is
sometimes meant by the equivocal term "correlativity." It must be
borne in mind, however, that if the inference works in this direction
alone, there is a significant disanalogy between such "active" rights
and Alvin's right to be paid.
From the fact that Alvin has a right to do X does it follow
that others are prohibited (in law or morals) from interfering with
his doing X? It should be obvious now why one may be tempted
to say yes-and also why at least some of the grounds for saying
yes are insufficient. Since others are prohibited in general from
(e.g.) assaulting, threatening, coercing and forcibly restraining
Alvin, they are prohibited from doing such things when they con-
stitute interference with the exercise of his rights. And thus counter-
examples to the alleged entailment between such "active" rights
and these "obligations not to interfere" will be impossible. It may
seem as if these obligations follow from, are "part" of or "correlate"
with Alvin's right. But once we see that these obligations apply
generally, whether or not Alvin acts within his rights, and that this
is what makes it seem as if they follow from Alvin's right, we should
no longer be tempted to say that they do follow.
Let this be granted. I shall consider two ways in which a
partisan of general correlativity might try to save that doctrine.
He might claim that, besides the ordinary obligations mentioned,
there are also extraordinary or special obligations that strictly
correlate with "active" rights. For the ways in which one might
interfere with Alvin's speaking are not, perhaps, exhausted by the
class of things the ordinary prohibitions cover; and some of this
surplus might be prohibited as well. Certain forms of verbal abuse
might be prohibited when used against a public speaker, for
example, but not otherwise. If so, the obligation imposed would
correlate with Alvin's right to speak publicly.
But this is not a promising line of defense, for it is a con-
tingent matter in the law, at least, whether any such special obliga-
tions are imposed; and so the existence of such obligations would
not be implied by (though they would imply) the right to speak
publicly. One might deny this if he were willing to say something
like (a) that any relevant change in the law (however minor)
changes the sense of the statement that Alvin "has a right to speak
publicly," or (b) that any such change destroys one right and
creates another in its place, though the two would be described
identically. But I see no reason to construe the case in such a way
except to defend at all costs a general doctrine of correlativity.
Furthermore, unless we suppose that the analysis of moral and legal
rights diverges at this point, any such special obligations in morals
are not implied by moral "active" rights either.
Another line of defense is given by the claim that there is a
general obligation not to interfere with another person, an obliga-
tion not exhausted by the ordinary prohibitions. For one is rarely
justified (in morals at least) in interfering with another's doing what
he has a right to do. But this suggestion too is covered by our
previous remarks. On the one hand, the existence of a general legal
obligation not to interfere is a contingent matter (it may protect
some forms of behavior and not others). And on the other hand,
I think it also true that one is rarely justified on moral grounds in
interfering with another whether or not he has a right to do what he
is doing-unless one is defending oneself or preventing substantial
hann to others.
III
Am I claiming, then, that it is not generally true that rights
"correlate" with duties or obligations-even in the minimal sense
of implying them? Well, yes and no. Our Constitutional right of
free speech does not correlate with duties in anything like the way
that Alvin's right correlates with Bernard's obligation. But given
certain assumptions there may be ways of deriving statements about
some obligation or other from the assertion of such a right. It
would be most misleading, however, to call the implication a case
of "correlativity" if that term is also used to characterize the very
tight, determinate relations between rights and duties exemplified
by our first example. I am not even prepared to grant that run-of-
the-mill "active" rights directly imply specific obligations not to
interfere. It seems correct and natural to say, for example, that
a motorist has a right to make a right, turn on a red light in
California which he does not have in New York State, in virtue of
the differences between the traffic laws of those two states, whereby
making a right turn on a red light is prohibited unless explicitly