(Walter Kasper) The God of Jesus Christ (B-Ok - Xyz) PDF
(Walter Kasper) The God of Jesus Christ (B-Ok - Xyz) PDF
(Walter Kasper) The God of Jesus Christ (B-Ok - Xyz) PDF
JESUS CHRIST
Walter Kasper
Translated
by
Matthew J. O'Connell
Preface IX
PART ONE
The God-Question Today
God as a Problem 3
1. The traditional formulation of the problem 3
2. The formulation of the problem today 7
3. The theological formulation of the problem 12
PART TWO
The Message about the God of Jesus Christ
PART THREE
The Trinitarian Mystery of God
Tiib;l!gel!,
Feast of Mal/hel<! the Apostle. 1982
PART ONE
Therefore before we ask 'Does God exist?' and before we answer 'God
exists' or claim 'God does not exist" we must know what is at issue when
we use the ambiguous word 'God'. Unless we have a clear concept of God
or at least some preunderstanding we cannot answer the questions just
asked, and any answers given are bound to be empty formulas.
The question, then, is this: how can we arrive at such a preliminary
concept of God? How are we to set about theologizing? We certainly
cannot begin with a proof of God that supposedly has no presuppositions.
Anyone who undertakes a proof of God must already have some idea of
what he wants to prove; any meaningful question supposes some pre-
understanding of what the questioning is meant to ascertain; so too a
proof of God presupposes a provisional concept of God. The principle
may be formulated universally: there is no such thing as presupposi-
tionless thinking. All human knowing occurs through the medium of
language, which always provides us with pre-existent symbols and
schemata for interpreting reality. For this reason, the only way to begin
theology is by inquiring what the religions and the theological tradition
have understood by 'God'. We must investigate the history of talk about
God and thus make clear to ourselves the problem that resides in the word
'God'.
We may begin with one of the great mosters of theology, Thomas Aquinas
(1225-1274). At the start of his theological SlImma he immediately gives
a number of descriptions of what 'all' mean when they speak of God: God
is the ultimate, ungrounded Ground of all reality that sustains and moves
everything; God is the supreme Good in which all finite goods participate
and which is the ground of all these goods; God is the ultimate End that
directs and orders all things.' For these reasons Anselm of Canterbury
(1033-1109), the father of medieval Scholasticism, defined God as id quo
maillS cogitari Iteqllit, 'that than which nothing greater can be thought",
and indeed that which is greater than anything that can be thought.- This
definition is not simply a superlative; it is not saying that God is 'the
greatest thing that can be thought'. If this were the case, God would simply
God as a Problem 5
be the highest possible realization of the human person. God is, rather, a
comparative that can never be matched: he who is always greater and
fuller; hewho amid all likeness is always more unlike, always other, always
more mysterious.
The definition which Luther gives in his Grosser Katechislllus is quite
different in character. It is utterly unphilosophical and expresses, rather,
the existential importance of the understanding of God: 'What does it
mean to have a God, or: What is God? A God is that from which we should
expect every good and to whom we should have recourse in every distress.'
'That ... to which you attach your heart and on which you rely is in fact
your God." The necessary (notwendige) being of the scholastic definition
has become for Luther the one who 'turns afflictions around' (der Not-
welldende), who supports and sustains human beings in the distresses of
life, the one who is absolutely trustworthy and on whom human beings
can base their lives. There is no doubt that Luther has effectively brought
into play basic motifs of biblical faith in God.
Various modern definitions a!tempt to combine the abstract philosoph-
ical and the concrete existential dimensions. According to P. Tillich, God
is 'what concerns us ultimately'.ID According to R. Bultmann, he is 'the
reality determining all else' .11 G. Ebeling calls God 'the mystery of reality', 12
and K. Rahner speaks of him as 'the holy mystery' which is the term and
origin of man and which 'is present in loving freedom' as 'that which is
nameless and which is not at our disposal, and at whose complete disposal
we exist'.1l
Despite differences in their details all these definitions make one point
clear: the word 'God' is not intended to answer one question among many
others. For the tradition, God is not a reality alongside or above the rest
of reality. He is not an object of questioning and understanding in the way
that other objects are. God is not a given in the way that human beings
and things are given. He is rather the answer to the question that is
contained in all questions; he is the answer to the question that is contained
in the very existence of the human person and the world." God is an
answer that includes and transcends all other answers.
The all-inclusive and all-transcending answer given in the word 'God'
corresponds exactly to the basic situation of the human person. Man is
unlike any other living thing in that he is the one being that is not adapted
by sure instinct and therefore unquestioningly to a particular environment.
On the contrary, he is the being who is open to the world, as the
anthropologists like to say." He does not live in an unforced harmony
with himself and his environment; he himself must shape both himself and
his environment. He is pregiven to himself but also given to himself as a
6 The God-Questioll Today
task to be carried out. He therefore has the power to ask questions, and
he is constantly asking them. This ability to ask questions is the source of
man's greatness; it is the ground of his transcendence, that is, his being
insofar as it reaches above and beyond everything else, and it is the ground
of his freedom as well. But his ability to ask questions is also the source of
his wretchedness. He is the only being who can be bored, the only one who
can be discontented and unhappy. Man, thus open to the world in its
entirety, finds fulfillment only if he finds an answer to the meaning of his
own existence and to the existence of reality as such.
The religious tradition is convinced that the reality expressed in the word
God provides this answer. According to this tradition, therefore, God is not
just one reality alongside all the others; he is the reality that comprehends,
grounds and determines all other realities, the unconditional in all that is
conditioned, man's all in all. To put it differently: the God-question is not
a categorical but a transcendental question, in the twofold sense of a
question that includes all that is (transcendental, therefore, in the sense the
term has in the Scholastic doctrine of the transcendentals) and a question
that has to do with the condition for the possibility of all other questions
and answers (transcendental, therefore, in the sense this term has in modern
transcendental philosophy).
Because God is the question in all questions, he himself can be placed in
question. Even classical theology did not develop in a sterile atmosphere
in which there were no contradictions or in an idyllic world falsely assumed
to be sound and good.,n In his theological Summa Thomas Aquinas
introduces his article on the question 'Does God exist?' by stating the two
objections which arc still fundamental even today. He cites evil in the world
as an argument against the affirmation of a God who is infinitely good,
and the possibility of explaining the world in a purely immanent way 'if it
be supposed that God docs not exist'." Thomas thus anticipates the
modern explanation of reality 'even if there were no God'.
But in Thomas' discussions with the pagans (the gentiles), and especially
with Islam, it was not only the existence of God but also the identity of
God (who is God?) that was disputed. Otherwise he would not have had
to write an entire Summa call Ira gemiles. Even for a medieval thinker like
Thomas, then, God is not something self·evident, and talk about God is
anything but a peaceful exercise of poetic contemplation. Given the
characterof reality as we have it, faith in God has always been a questioning
and a seeking faith. Human beings have always had to say: 'I believe: help
my unbelief!' (Mark 9.24). For this reason, in the classical tradition faith
was always a fides quaerells illtellectltm, a faith in search of understanding.
In this formula we have the classical definition oftheology or accountable
God as a Problem 7
speech about God. Following Augustine, Anselm of Canterbury defines
theology as fides qllaerells illtel/ectllm," faith in search of understanding.
According to this definition neither the asking nor the understanding is
extrinsic to faith. Faith itself is understood as a faith that questions and
understands. Faith is an act of the human person (even though from
another standpoint it is also an act of sheer grace in which God enlightens
man); faith exists only in the medium of human hearing, understanding,
assenting and also questioning. Theology therefore prolongs and develops
a movement that arises within faith and from faith. In the proper sense of
the phrase, theology is a science of faith. The special character of theology
as a science consists in the fact that it prolongs, in a methodical and
systematic way, the quest for understanding that is inherent in faith, focuses
this quest on the problems that arise in each situation, and seeks to satisfy
it with the tools made available by the thinking of a given age."
The conclusion we may draw from this brief survey is that modern
secularization has various roots. Having been made possible by Christ-
ianity, it sprang into existence as a reaction, in the name of freedom, against
an absolutist image of God. It is inseparable from modern subjectivity,
which grounds its autonomy not theonomously but in terms of immanence
and even by way of a critique of religion, and therefore also makes its own
the humanism of antiquity. Thus many and partially contradictory motifs
explain the rise of modern autonomous culture, which is dearly distingui-
shed by its immanentiS! orientation from the medieval world-picture that
had been formed by Augustine and was transcendent in its orientation. In
this secularized world God become increasingly supernuous as a hypothesis
for explaining phenomena within the world; he loses his function in regard
to the world. We must live in the world 'as though there were no God'.
Thus faith in God becomes increasingly emptied of its perceptual and
experiential elements and increasingly unreal; God himself becomes increa-
singly unreal. When all is said and done, the statement 'God is dead' could
serve as a plausible interpretation of the modern sense of life and reality.
It is not possible, of course, to expunge the reality of God and expect
that everything else will go on as before. In the history of the human race
the word 'God' stands for the ultimate ground and ultimate goal of man
and his world. When God drops out of the picture, the world becomes
GDd as a PrDblem 11
without ground and without goal and everything threatens to become
meaningless. For a thing has meaning only when it stands in a larger
context that is inherently meaningful. Then, once the meaning of the whole
has been lost and once the reality of God as that which ordains, governs
and supports the whole has been removed, every individual reality also
becomes ultimately meaningless. Everything descends into an abyss of
nothingness. In other words, as J. Paul, Jacobi, l-lovalis, Fichte, Schelling
and Hegel already saw, nihilism stands at the term of this development.
Nietzsche was one of the few who had the courage to face up to the nihilistic
consequences of atheism. In The Gay Scie//Ce he follows his message of the
death of God with some questions:
What were we doing when we unchained this earth from its sun? Whither
is it moving now? Whither are we moving? Are we not plunging
continually? Backward, sideward, forward, in all directions? Is there
still any up or down? Are we not straying as through an infinite nothing?
Do we not feel the breath of empty space? Has it not become colder? Is
not night continually closing in on us?'·
A person who believes in God as the realiry that determines all else cannot
acquiesce in the bourgeois separation between a secular public sphere nnd a
private sphere in which alone religion is given a place. We can only agree
eagerly with the new political theology insofar as it calls attenrion to this
baneful separation and bids us relate God to public life as the trurh abour man
and human social life. On the other hand, insofar as this rheology turns the
political dimension into a programmatic foundation and the all-inclusive
framework and horizon of its arguments, it is to be no less decisively rejected.
Even in inner·worldly terms! the political is not the quintessence of reality nOf,
consequently, the framework within which the freedom of the person is to be
discussed. The person is indeed social by narure and dependent for its concrete
fulfillment on a social order marked by freedom, bur it also has inherent rights
over against society and is even in its turn the ground or origin, the supporting
base, and the goal of all social institutions." The point of departure for our
argument is therefore not society as such bur the human being who as person
has a social dimension, but also transcends this in the direction of a real Whole
which hear she always possess only in a pre·apprehension (Vorgriff) bur never
God as a Problem 15
in a concept (Begriff) and to which he or she is always on the way as one who
seeks, asks, hopes and dares.
Talk of God as the reality that includes and determines everything, as the
ground and goal of everything, and as id qltO IIwilts cogitari lIeqllit, is to
be understood as the answer to the question, inseparable from the human
being as a person, regarding the whole of reality; moreover, it is only in
relation to the most comprehensive of all questions that talk about God
can become articulate. Metaphysics is the name given to the science which
enquires not about individual beings or realms of being but about being
as such and as a whole.4' Talk about God presupposes the metaphysical
question about being and at the same time keeps this question alive. In our
present situation, therefore, theology as talk about God also acts as
protector and defender of philosophy as the question about being as such.
'The Christian is the person who by virtue of his faith is compelled to
philosophize.'44 This does not imply a choice of one particular philosophy,
as, for example, Aristotelian philosophy and metaphysics; it does, however,
imply an option for a philosophy that in opposition to every narrowing
and obscuring' of the human horizon keeps open the question about the
meaning of the whole and precisely in this way serves the humanness of
humanity. For it is the removal of these limits as well as human openness,
transcending reality as given, that sets us free from all reality as given and
endows us with freedom and dignity within the existing and any future
social order.
H talk about God transcends any and every inner-wordly sphere,
including the political, then to preserve the transcendence of God is also
to preserve the transcendence of the human person and therefore the
freedom and inalienable rights of humanity.4' For the sake, then, of both
God and man 'the return to the sacred' is our essential task today.4'ln view
of the many reductionist theological programs now in existence it is
unfortunately not a redundancy to say that, especially today, a theological
theology is the need of the hour and the only appropriate answer to modern
atheism.
II
Atheism in the strict sense of the word came into existence only in the
modern age. Even the word atheism seems to have entered common use
only around the end of the sixteenth and beginning of the seventeenth
centuries.' The content of the concept may not be derived simply from an
analysis of the two components of the word itself (theism .nd alph.
privative or the negating particle). It would be both a narrowing and an
unwarranted extension of the idea if we were to understand by 'atheism'
simply a denial of (monotheistic) theism and therefore to regard even
pantheism as a form of atheism. Only that view should be regarded as
atheistic which denies any and every divine or absolute that is not simply
identical with man and with the world of our empirical experience and
with its immanent principles. Atheism, therefore, rejects any and every
claim that God or the divine exists. This means that there can be and are
not only various forms of the idea of God but also various forms of atheism.
Given this concept of atheism, it can be said that no primitive people is
unqualifiedly atheistic, since among all primitive peoples there is some kind
of an idea or a worship of a divine realiry. Even the high religions of Asia
that do not .cknowledge a personal absolute (Buddhism, Taoism) are not
atheistic, as is often mistakenly claimed. By reason of its conception of the
world as numinous, classical antiquity likewise did not have any atheists
in the sense described above. From the second century be on we do indeed
find lists of names of atheoi, but the term refers to people who disregarded
the gods of the state and their public veneration, not to people who simply
denied everything divine. 2 1t was in this limited sense that even Christians
were subsequently execrated and persecuted as atheoi. Justin comments:
The Denial of God ill Modern Atheism 17
'We admit that as far as all such false gods are concerned we are atheists.
but we are not atheists when it comes to the true God." It is therefore a
kind of fraudulent labelling to make the 'accusation of atheism' against
the early Christians the basis for a contemporary Christian atheism.
Atheism in the proper sense. which denies everything divine. became
possible only in the modern age. It presupposes Christianity and to that
extent is a post-Christian phenomenon. 4 The biblical faith in creation had
broken with the numinous conception of the world that was current in
antiquity and had effected a denuminization of reality by distinguishing
clearly and unambiguously between God the creator and the world as his
creation. In so doing. the Bible thought of the world in wordly terms and
God in divine terms and of the two as qualitatively distinct in infinite
degree. Only when God had been conceived as radically God was it possible
also to deny him in a radical way. Only when the transcendence of
God had been taken seriously did it become possible to experience the
immanence of the world, and only after the world had been 3Cknowledged
simply as world could it become the object of objectifying scientific study
and technical transformation. The way was being prepared for this kind
of autonomous understanding of the world as early as the twelfth and
thirteenth centuries. Albertus Magnus and Thomas Aquinas were the most
outstanding representatives of this movement. But the autonomy of the
world. based as it was on the idea of creation. remained part of a total
context that was theonomous; in fact. the autonomy itself was given a
theonomous justification.' On the other hand, the very emancipation of
autonomy from its theonomous context and reference and thus the
presupposition for the rise of modern atheism had theological causes.
These were provided by late medieval nominalism. Nominalism carried
the idea of God's omnipotence and freedom to an extreme. turning him
into an absolutist deity who acts in an arbitrary manner. The rebellion
against this God who does not liberate human freedom but oppresses it.
this God who might well command even what is untrue and unjust. was
an act of human self-assertion.
The reaction is especially clear in Descartes (1596-1650). He is
tormented by the thought of a genius maligmls, an evil spirit. 'very powerful
and very tricky" who 'bends all his efforts' to deceive him. Atlast Descartes
discovers an unshakable foundation on which to base knowledge of the
truth. In triumphant tones he declares: 'Let him deceive me as much as he
will. he can never make me be nothing as long as 1 think that I am
something,'· Descartes expresses his new insight in the formula: Cogito
ergo SIIIIl ('I think, hence 1 am').' The 'hence' does not point to the
conclusion of a syllogism, but is simply a way of expressing an insight
18 The God-Questio/l Today
given in the very act of thinking: 'I am a thinking being." In thus starting
with the ego cogital/5, with the subject who grasps himself as subject.
Descartes provided an Archimedean fulcrum for the entire modern age
that followed; subjectivity was to become the modern mode of thought
and intellectual attitude. Kant described this as a Copernican revolution.'
But subjectivity should not be confused with subjectivism, although this is
a mistake constantly made. Subjectivism, which abolutizes the subject's
limited position and private interests, is a particularist point of view;
modern subjectivity, on the other hand, is a universalist mode of thought,
a new approach to the whole of reality.
In a special way, modern subjectivity has consequences for the God-
question. Descartes and all the great thinkers of the modern age down to
the nineteenth century were anything but atheists. In fact, in his third and
fifth meditations Descartes falls back on traditional arguments for the
existence of God (the proof that concludes from effect to cause, and the
proof that starts with the concept of God). But for Descartes knowledge
of God occurs in the medium of human subjectivity. In contrast to the
nominalist exaggeration of theonomy autonomy here becomes the norm
of judgment. The idea of God is admitted as the ground and means of
human autonomy. In this approach, God ultimately becomes a factor in
the self-fulfillment of man, although Descartes himself does not yet draw
this conclusion. III
This new baSIC ani tude which was cscablishcd by Descartes was henceforth
given the name 'autonomy'," Antiquity and the Middle Ages knew this idea
only as a political catesory; amonomy meant the freedom to lave according to
onc's own laws, that is, political sclf·dctermination. The concept acquired a
bro:.tdcr meaning in the context of the confessional or religious wars of the
sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. Unity, freedom and peace could no longer
be defended on theonomous grounds; recourse had to be had to natural law,
which binds everyone and alone is evident to all, and in terms of which
autonomy can be granted to the religious dissenter. Thus the modern doctrine
of natural law was formulated by J. Bodin and H. Grotius, under the influence
of Stoic idea!!!. This teaching identifics lex uaturae with lex dlVina, but
grounds it no longer thconomously but autonomously with the help of human
understanding 'cven if there were no God'. 1l The autonomy of Jaw Icads to the
autonomy of morality. WhIle in antiquity and the Middle Ages law, custom
and morality formed in large measure an inextricably interwoven complex,
morality was forced to become conscious of itself now that the state and law
had achieved emancipa~ion. The result was an autonomous morality based on
interior conviction. 1.1 It was owing to Kant that this morality was given its
philosophical justification. His starting point is the dignity of the human person
The Denial of God in Modem Atheism 19
who can never be made a means to an end but 4exisrs as an end in himself' ,14
This autonomy has its basis in freedom, which 'can be efficient, independently
of foreign causes determining ir',lS Freedom can therefore only be its own law.
But the autonomy enjoyed by freedom is not to be identified with caprice; it
had its norm in the freedom of the individual himself as well as in the freedom
of everyone else. For this rcason Kant's categorical imperative runs as follows:
41 am never to act otherwise than so that I could also will that my maxim
should become a universal law.''' This principle is only seemingly a formal
onc, for in fact it bases morality on the dignity of the human person; it grounds
an interpersonal (not an individualistic) ethics in a perspective which embraces
the entire human race.
The emancipation of law and morality from the theological contexts that
had given them their foundations meant a new situation for religion. If religion
is no longer the necessary presupposition of order, law and morals in society,
then it inevitably becomes a private affair. Once the various secular spheres
had been freed of their theonomous connections, religion became increasingly
a matter of the interior life. It became a matter of subjective piety, a religion
of the heart, with the way being paved by pietism and the various revivalist
movements.!Hegei recognized that this withdrawal of religion into the subjecti-
vity leads, on the one hand, to a flattening of reality and, on the other, to an
emptying of religion itself. The world becomes godless, God worldless and -
in the strict sense of the word - objectless. The consequences are atheism and It
nihilism. 17
Modern thought has laid the foundations for various forms of atheism.
The word 'atheism' is applied to very diverse phenomena that are classified
in quite different ways in philosophical and theological literature.'" Funda-
mentally, however, atheistic systems may be reduced to two basic types,
corresponding to the two possible understandings of autonomy in the
modern age. There is, first, the autonomy of nature and the secular
spheres (culture, science, art, the economy, politics, and so on), for the
understanding and functioning of which there is increasingly less need
of the God-hypothesis (naturalistic, materialistic, scientistic, methodical
atheism or agnosticism). There is, second, the autonomy of the subject,
whose dignity and freedom militate against the acceptance of an omnipo-
tent God (the humanistic atheism of freedom and the political atheism of
liberation). To be distinguished from these are the forms of atheism that
spring from protest against the wickedness and evil in the world. From an
existential point of view wickedness and evil are far more decisive for many
people than are theoretical and ideological denials of God. I shall discuss
this third kind of atheism in c'lnnection with the question of theodicy
rather than here. "
It would, of course, be absurd to focus attention here solely on the
20 The God-Qllestion Today
systematic philosophical approaches to atheism andon the major ideologies
of the modern age. 2• These, after all, suppose that basic atheistic attitudes
are already seen as plausible. To describe this state of affairs K. Rahner
has coined the phrase 'troubled atheism'; by this he means the experience
of being crushed by a secularized world, the feeling of no longer being able
to make the divine real to oneself, the experience of the silence of God, and
the fear of the emptiness and meaninglessness of the world. 2I Atheism thus
becomes a plausible interpretation of modern secularization. At the same
time, troubled atheists, who are frightened by the absence of God and
whose hearts are restless, are a pastoral windfall.
In addition, there is an atheism characterized by indifference: a complete
unconcern with religious questions, an atheism that, either seemingly or
really, is all too much at peace and takes itself for granted, an atheism that
represses, no longer raises, or even disparages the great questions asked by
the religions. Nietzsche has drawn a sarcastic picture of this 'last man'.
The last man only blinks when the great questions are raised (Zarathustra
is speaking in this passage):
'What is love? What is creation? What is longing? What is a star?'
thus asks the last man, and he blinks.
The earth has become small, and on it hops the last man, who makes
everything small. His race is as ineradicable as the Aea-beetle; the last
man lives longest.
'We have invented happiness,' say the last men, and they blink .. .
One still works, for work is a form of entertainment. But one is careful
lest the entertainment be too harrowing. One no longer becomes rich or
poor: both require tOO much exertion. Who still wants to rule? Who
obey? Both require too much exertion.
No shepherd and one herd! Everybody wants the same, everybody is
the same: whoever feels different goes voluntarily into a madhouse. 22
What Nietzsche has done here is, 01 course, to anticipate the consequences
of modern atheism. Despite all the humanistic impulses at work in modern
atheism, the death of God leads ultimately to the death of man."
The trial of Galileo, which ended in 1633 with a condemnation 01 his teaching,
The DCllial of God ill Modem Atheism 21
was, more than any other incident, of prororypical and epochal significancc"!-~
As everyone knows, in developing the discoveries made by Copernicus and
Kepler, Galileo was led to reject the ancient geocentric picture of the world
that is presupposed in the Bible. He advocated the thesis that the sun docs not
circle the earth but rather the earth circles the sun. The Roman Inquisition on
the other hand defended an outdated picture of the world and an unhistorical
interpretation of the Bible (in this respect, by the way, it was in agreement with
the Reformers). It must be said, however, that there have been few historical
events in which the historical reality has been so unrelated to (he historical
influence it exerted as in the Galileo case, which quickly became a myth. For
the issue at the time was nor only a claim to the autonomy of the natural
sciences, a claim which was quite legitimate from the standpoint of modern
theology. The issue was also Galileo's claim that it is for the natural sciences
to interpret what the Bible says about creation or, in other words, the claim,
in the name of natural science, to determine the scope of theological statements.
Both sides went beyond their competency, even allowing for the fact that the
Inquisition would have been satisfied if Galileo had presented his thesis as a
hypothesis - which is precisely what it is by modern standards. The conflict
that marked the Galileo case was unfortunately not an isolated phenomenon.
Similar conflicts arose, especially in the nineteenth century, in connection with
the disputes over Charles Darwin's theory of evolution; these conflicts have
lasted well into our own century, as the debate over Teilhard de Chardin
shows. The result was one of the greatest catastrophes in the history of the
church: the schism between natural science and theology and even between
the church and modern culture..!" For the modern natural sciences are the hard
core of modernity.:!7The modern economy and technology which these sciences
made possible provided the foundations for the bourgeois culture in which the
modern philosophy of subjectivity could develop and in which the modern
immanentist outlook of which I have already spoken could spread abroad.
Conversely, the natural sciences have their roots in the modern identification
of the human person as subject, for only then could nature become the object
of scientific observation and technical mastery. Consequently, if any new talk
about God is to be serious and to be taken seriously, it must prove itself by the
hard standard of the scientific understanding of reality.
In the Middle Ages nature was an image and symbol of God. In Nikolaus
Copernicus and especially in Johannes Kepler such a symbolic view of the
cosmos is still present in the background. In his Mysterimn cosmographicum
and his Harmonices mlludi (World Harmony), Kepler's aim is to capture the
creative thought of God himself. As for Copernicus, although his rejection of
the old geocentric world-picture expels man from his position at the centre of
the cosmos, he keeps man as the spiritual centre and reference point of the
universe; man is no longer by his physical nature the centre of the world, but
he becomes this centre actively and spiritually by his own efforts." The age
had now dawned in which the dominam vision was of a world which man
22 The God-Questioll Today
creOles for himself scientifically, artistically and philosophically. Central
position had given way to central function. For this reason Kant was justified
in seeing himself as the one who had completed the Copernican revolution.
In Galileo and Newton this revolutionary new mode of though! bears fruit
in il method proper to the natural scicnces.!oJ The laws of nature are nor simply
rcad off. in a purely objectivist way, from nature itself, bur emerge rather from
the interaction of hypothesis and experience. The natural scientist compels
nature, as it were, to give answers to questions which he puts to it. Bur as early
as Newton the danger arises of confusing this way by which knowledge of
nature IS gamed with the way of nature itself; of turning the laws enunciated
by the natural sciences into iron laws of n:afure itself; and of converting the
method of the natural sciences into a new metaphysics. The danger becomes
,cute in the mechanistic approach to the world which Newton developed. In
this approach n;J{urc is treated like a gigantic clockwork that operates in
accordance with minutely determined patterns.
Initially there was a widespread conviction th>t faith and knowledge were
reconcilable. The work of G. W. Leibniz (1646-1716), one of the last
univer,,1 scholars, w" representative of the attempt to find a new
synthesis of faith and knowledge. But the more the scientists discovered the
regul,!ities of nature, the more they were forced to eliminate God from
the world. They needed him now only at the periphery and to fill up lacun"
in hum,n knowledge (for example, in the c"e of Newton, to correct the
deflections in the orbits of the planets). In the course of such withdmwal
skirmishes God was increasingly pushed off (0 the periphery of the world
and into the hereafter. On the other hand, scientists were more and more
convinced that the world is infinite. Did this mean th>t in the final analysis
divine predications must be made of the world itself? that God and world
were in fact one? As a result of these developments two possible but
contrary ways emerged of defining a new relationship between God and
the world: pantheism and deism. Atheism is, by comparison, only a
relatively late product of this development.
Pantheism") means that in his being and nature God is one with the
whole (pall) of reality. The concept occurs only in modern times. Factors
inclining to pantheism are to be found, however, in all religious cultures,
especially in the Asiatic high religions but also in the ancient Stoa, in
Neoplatonism and even in the Middle Ages (Amalric of Bena, David of
Dinant). But the formation of a pantheistic system is a modern
phenomenon.
Early on, Jacobi objected to this pantheistic identification of God and the
world as being atheistic, since it dissolves God in nature and nature in
God.'· The debate over whether or not Spinozism is a concealed, though
refined, form of atheism lasted into the nineteenth century.,17 It is no less
possible, of course, to agree with Hegel that Spinozism is a form of
acosmism, since according to Spinoza the world is simply a disposition
and mode of the one divine substance and not something substantial in
itself.,1H Pantheism is thus a profoundly ambiguous system.
The characteristic religious philosophy of the Enlightenment was not,
however, pantheism but deism." It started in seventeenth-eighteenth
century England (Lord Herbert of Cherbury, T. Hobbes, J. Toland, J.
Locke, M. Tindal, A. Collins, and others), became the religious philosophy
to which the French Enlightenment gave its allegiance (P. Bayle, Voltaire,
D. Diderot, and others), and finally gained entrance into Germany (H. S.
Reimarus, and others).
~.J-
.I"-l~
The De/lia/ of God in Modern Atheism 27
desire for happiness can be fulfilled only if the desire is in harmony with
external nature; but this harmony between spirit or freedom and nature can
in turn only be ensured by absolute Spirit and absolute Freedom, that is, by
God. Only if God is presupposed, then, can human freedom 'turn out well'.
Kant needs God for the sake of man's happiness. God is no longer important
'in himself' but only in his significance 'for us'.
In thinkers after Kant, in Fichte and Schelling, for example, the idea of
human autonomy is again the focus of intense interest. The young Schelling,
in his Philosophische Briefe iiber Dogmatismus lind Krit;zismus (Philosophical
Letters on Dogmatism and Criticism) already comes quite close toa postulatory
atheism. He seems to regard human freedom as incompatible with the idea of
an objective God." The conflicts are already evident here which will become
acute in the atheism controversy started by Fichte in 1798. In an article entitled
'Concerning the Foundation of Our Belief in the Divine Government of the
World','o Fichte identified God with the moral order of the world; God is thus
the means and mediation of freedom, but he himself is not free. Fichte denied
that God is personal, because he was afraid that this would introduce limitation
and finiteness into God. sl What he was trying to say in this misleading manner
was that God should not bethoughtof as exisringafterthe mannerof substance,
for the concept of substance is derivable from the sensible world and (in Kant,
for example) is in the service of human happiness. In Fichte's eyes, such a God
would be an idol and not the true God. For him, the true God belongs to the
moral sphere, that is, to the dimension of freedom. From this point of view
Fichte is close to the late philosophy of Schelling, who repeatedly tries to think
of God not as a means of freedom but as absolute freedom in himself."
Hegel in particular grasped the situation and emphasized atheism as the
current flowing in the depths of modern thought. He made his point by referring
on several occasions to the hymn in the Lutheran hymnal, 'God Himself is
dead'." The way was prepared for him here by Pascal and by Jean Paul's
address of the dead Christ from out of the universe. Hegel called the sentence
'God himself is dead' an expression of the culture of his age, as 'the feeling
upon which the religion of more recent times rests'. With the help of his idea
of the 'speculative Good Friday', that is, of the reconciliation of God and death
with the help of the idea of absolute freedom that recovers itself in its contrary,
he sought to overcome this situation. God must be thought of as a living God,
as kenotic freedom, as love that empties itself out in its opposite, namely death,
and is thus able to abrogate death.
Despite the sublimiry of the ideas involved, Hegel's effort to eliminate
atheism dialectically was marked by ambiguity. This is why immediately after
Hegel's death (1831) his disciples split up into a right wing and a left wing.
While the Right Hegelians, especially P. Marheineke, sought to interpret Hegel
in terms of orr hod ox theism, the Left Hegclians soon charged him with atheism.
Typical here was B. Bauer's book Die Posa/Ille des Jiil1gstel1 Gerichts iiber
Hegel dell Atheisten WId Alllichristell (1841; The Trumpet of the Last
28 The God-Question Today
Judgment sounded over Hegel the Atheist and Antichrist). According to Bauer,
Hegel acknowledges only the universal World-Spirit that becomes conscious
of itself in man. Naive disciples like Strauss (says Bauer) have regarded this
simply as pantheism; but in fact it is the most deliberate atheism, that puts
self-consciousness in the place of God." A. Ruge called Hegel a 'messiah of
atheism' and a 4Robespierre of theology'.55 We may leave aside here the
question of the true interpretation of Hegel. The only important point in this
context is the fact that as far as its historical influence was concerned, Hegel's
philosophy turned into the atheism that has shaped our situation down to the
present time. 56
It was the publication of the Paris Manuscripts in 1932 that led to a discussion
of the original Marxism of Marx himself as distinct from the orthodox
doctrinaire and totalitarian Marxism found in the ideology of the Communist
party and state. The debate led to various anthropological and humanistic
interpretations of Marx (Lukacs, Korsch, Gramsci, Schaff, Kolakowski,
Machovec, Bloch, Same, Garaudy, Lefebvre, Merleau-Ponty and others),
which were rejected as revisionist by orthodox Marxism. These new interpreta-
tions introduced the idea of a democratic Marxism as well as new possibilities
of dialogue with Christianity. The 'Frankfurt School' (M. Horkheimer, T. W.
Adorno and others) sought to present Marxism as a continuation of modern
enlightenment and to revitalize it as a philosophy of history that has a practical
purpose U. Habermas). The structuralist interpretation of Marx offered by L.
Althusser, on the other hand, insists on the very opposite: that is not the
individual human being but the totality of relations that is the subject of
history. More recent interpretations are once again contending that totalitarian
traits are to be found not only in Marxism but in the thinking of K. Marx
The Dellial of God ill ModeTII Atheism 33
himself, so that rhe internal development of Marxism is ro be considered not
a degeneration but a more or less consistent evolution (A. Glucksmann; C.
Jambet; G. Lardreau; B. H. Levy). From rhe theological standpoint, rhe most
important question in the interpretation of Mux is whether atheism and (he
criticism of religion are essential to Marxism or simply historically conditioned
and, as such, accidental.
This concrete economic and political view of man has consequences for the
new humanism which Marx is seeking, Whereas Fcuerbach was bent on
unmasking Hegel's pantheism as a form of atheism, Marx wants 'the world's
becoming philosophical' in Hegel to be replaced by 'philosophy's becoming
wordly'.91 Hegel reconciled philosophy and the world only in thoughr, nO! in
reality; philosophy made perfecr now stands in contrast ro a world rhar is
perverse. Marx wanrs ro fulfill and rhus cancel our philosophy; he wanrs ro
rurn rheory into pracrice. 'The philosophers have only il!te~preted rhe world
in various ways; the point is, to change it,''12 According to Marx, therefore,
rhe chief defecr of marerialism up ro now, including rhe marerialism of
Feuerbach, is rhar it has grasped realiry only as an objecr of perception and
not subjectively as human activity and practice. '1.\ Marx thus moves beyond the
previous mechanistic materialism and replaces it with a historical materialism.
The larrer makes irs own rhe modern idea of subjecrivity and is rhus able ro see
irself as rhe rrue heir of rhe Enlighrenment and idealism. Marx's marerialism
is thus at the same time a humanism, according to which man is the supreme
being for man. '14 But since there is also the question of the concrete person,
this humanism is also a naturalism, that is, the realization of a human world.
34 The God-Questioll Today
This realization in turn presupposes rhatrhc products of work, being mediations
between man and the world, belong tD all in common. For this reason the
elimination of private property, or communism, is true humanism.'1s In the
final analysis Marx's aim is a radical and universal emancipation, that is, the
complete restoration of man, 'a restoration of the human world and of human
relationships to malt himself. 96 The need, therefore, is 'to overthrow all those
conditions in which man is an abased, enslaved, abandoned, contemptible
being','J7
Nietzsche clothes his own answer to the question of aim in various metaphors.
The most important of these is his talk of the Superman in Thus Spoke
42 The God-Question Today
Zarat/JUstra. The figure of the Superman makes its appearance when the death
of God has become a reality. 'Dead are all gods: now we want the Superman
to Iive.'J60 But what is this Superman? For Nietzsche he is 'the meaning of the
earth'lnl and the meaning of man. 16Z For 'man is something that shall be
overcome'; 'What is great in man is that he is a bridge and not an end: what
Ciln be loved in man is that he is an overture and a going under.'163 Superman
is the man who has overcome all the former alienations. He is therefore not
an other-worldly man, but rather remains '(aith(ull to the earth' and does not
believe in other-worldly hopes.'" He also breaks in pieces the 'tables of
values';lnS he is not one of 'the despisers of the body';Hi6 he rejects the old
virtues and lives 'beyond good and evil', He is the man who is at one with
himself, who has overcome all tension and division between being and meaning;
he is the man who has himself become God and replaced the vanished and
slain God. Only in order to become God could man kill God.'" 'J(there were
gods, how could I endure not to be a god!'If>H
Nietzsche explains the way to Superman by means of another image: the
metaphor of the three metamorphoses, or 'how the spirit becomes a camel;
and the camel, a lion; and the lion, finally, a child'. The camel humbles itself;
it submits co higher values. The lion seeks freedom; he is an image of the man
who wants to win happiness and fulfillment for himself in and by hi, own
freedom. But as for the child: 'The child is innocence and forgetting, a new
beginning, a game, a !telf-propelled wheel, a first movement, a sacred "Yes". 'If>,)
Yes-saying brings redemption from transitory time. The creative will says:
'But thus I will ir.' ''. 'Was that life? .. Well then! Once more!' '' '
In the third part of Thus Spoke Zarat/lIIstra Nietzsche logically extends rhe
idea of Superman to an 'abysmal thought': the idea of eternal recurrence. I- "!
He means by this the presence of eternity in every instant: 'In every Now, being
begins; round every Here rolls the sphere There. The center is everywhere.
Bent is the path of eternity.'l 71 Nietzsche gives expression co this insight in the
image of the great Noon.' " 'The world is deep, I Deeper than day had been
aware. I Deep is its woe; I Joy - deeper yet than agony: / Woe implores: God!
I But ioy wants all eternity -/ Wants deep, wants deep eternity.'l 1.i Instead of
accepting the negation oftife, Nietzsche wants co break through 'to a Dionysian
affirmation of the world as it is, without subtraction, exception, or selection'. I16
He wants to understand the previously denied aspects of existence as not only
necessary but desirable and to accept the eternal recurrence of all things. His
formula for this is 'alllor (ati lIove of fate],.' '''
This doctrine of the eternal recurrence of the same is undoubtedly meant to
contradict the historical and eschatological world view of Christianity, and
this dissolution of all contrarieties and oppositions. represents a rejection of
the very foundations of Western metaphysics. It is possible to see in it a critical
revival of mythical religiosity, which would show that even Nietzsche was not
really finished with the God-question and that instead it returns in a new form
in his writings. Nietzsche is not alone in thus having recourse (0 myth. Before
The Denial of God in Modern Atheism 43
him Gorres, Schelling and Holderlin had already called for a new mythology.
In his poem Die Gotter Griechenlands [The Gods of Greece] Schiller grieves
over a world that has lost its soul, and summons back the ancient world in
which 'everything was a footprint of God'. '" Even more filled with a sense of
urgency, if this be possible, are Holderlin 's elegies, his grief at the disappearance
of the gods, and his call for and even expectations of their return. 'Close is the
God and difficult to grasp. But where danger threatens, redemption is also at
hand.'''' Later on, Stephan George and Rilke (in the form of the angel in the
Dllino Elegies) point in a similar direction. In Thomas Mann and, though
differently, in Giinther Grass we again come upon the fascination with myth.
No onc, of course, has dared to gaze so deeply as Martin Heidegger into (he
abyss of nothingness that is the present world with its technological image of
reality, while at the same time joining H61derlin and Nietzsche in looking for
a new revelation of being. 1110
Nietzsche himself asks: 'Is not just this godlike that there are gods but no
GOcl?,11I1 Even in his late notes we find the question: 4How many new gods are
still possible?' He answers: 'I should not doubt that there are many kinds of
gods."" Therefore: 'We believe in Olympus - and no/ in the "Crucified",''']
This longing finds its clearest expression in the well-known 'Dionysus Dithy-
ramb': 'Oh, come back, I My unknown god! My pain! My last-happiness!'''4
However these verses are to be interpreted, Nietzsche was preoccupied with
the God-question until the very end, and he supplies the reason: '. fear we are
not getting rid of God because we still believe in grammar.'''' We are caught
in the snares of grammar, which is 'the metaphysics of the people';IK6 due
to it, nothing hitherto has as direct a power of persuasion as the error
regarding being: 'Every word, every sentence we utter speaks in irs favour.'Ul 1
Is ir even possible, rhen, ro express Nierzsche's conceprion? Is ir possible [0
think it?
Recent theology has often sought to follow this path as a way out of the crisis.
Undoubtedly the Nietzsche to whom appeal is made in this context is a carefully
selected Nietzsche.'" In addition, the questions of principle which Nietzsche
raises are by no means answered in such short-cur adaptions. Nicczsche's
remarks do, however, supply a stimulus which it will be worth accepting in a
critical way. But if absolute love is to be the answer on which there is agreement
in principle, then man can never be this absolute love; he can only allow it to
be bestowed on him.
This brings us back once again to the basic question involved in the modern
idea of autonomy: can the concept of a radical human autonomy in the
sense of a pure self-mediation ever succeed? Or must not a successful
human identity rather be only a freedom that is given to man from another?
Being from man's own resources - or being that is received? Can autonomy
find an other than theonomous foundation? And how can theonomy be so
conceived that it does not signify heteronomy, but rather both grounds
autonomy and brings it to fulfillment? The word 'love' already points to
the answer given by theology. For love means a union which does not
absorb the other but sets him free to be himself and thus brings him to
fulfillment. The response which theology gives to a modern atheism that
appeals to human autonomy is, then, the following: greater union with
God means greater and more fulfilled freedom for humanity.
In order that it may give its answer to modern atheism in a reasoned
way, theology is challenged to a basic self-definition and self-criticism. In
dosing this chapter, therefore, let me once again call to mind the funda-
mental question raised by modern atheism. The fundamental question is
not the one that arises when the confession of faith 'God exists', is met by
the conttaty assertion:. 'God does not exist,' so that theology is forced to
ask: 'Does God exist?' The confession of faith has never asserted the
existence of God in an abstract way; it has always spoken instead of the
one God shows himself as creator of heaven and earth and as Father of
our Lord Jesus Christ. Neither has modern atheism in its reflective forms
ever simply asserted the non-existence of God; it has, rather, denied a very
particular God who acts as opptessor toward humanity, and life, and this
in order that it might then ascribe the divine attributes to humanity.
The fundamental question that lies behind this historical process was
already brought out into the open by Fichte during the atheism controversy
46 The God-Qllestioll Today
(the Atheism"sstreit). The question is whether and to what extent we can
speak of God at all in terms of being and existence, or whether we can only
assign predicates based on action.'" Classical theology concluded from
God's action to his being and said, for example, that because God shows
himself good to me, God is good. It thus understood God as a substance
to which certain predicates could be applied. Modern philosophy criticized
this approach. Fichte'" and later Feuerbach'9S were of the opinion that
when such statements about being in the sense of substance are used of
God, he is being thought of as a being who exists in space and time and
is thus objectified and rendered finite. The answers given by modern
philosophy itself are admilledly ambiguous, to say the least. The Fichte of
the atheism controversy gives the impression that he applies the divine
predicates to the moral order, somewhat as Spinoza applies them to nature
and as myth does to the cosmos. Feuerbach for his part applies them to
humanity, and Marx to society. The later Fichte and the later Schelling
wanted to avoid these atheistic consequences by speaking of God not as a
substance but as a subject (in the modern sense of the term); that is, by
thinking of God within the horizon of freedom. They thought therefore
that they could overcome modern atheism on the very ground where it had
arisen: on the ground of the modern philosophy of subjectivity when this
is thought through to the end.
The fundamental question raised by modern atheism is thus the question
of the meaning or meaninglessness of sentences such 35 'God exists' or
'God does not exist'. It is the question of the condition for the possibility
of existential (existe/ttia/) statements as made about God. This clarification
is necessary because the word 'is' is profoundly ambiguous. At first glance
it seems to assert an identity. If this is the case, then it is possible to convert
the New Testament statement that God is love, exchange subject and
predicate, and say: Love is God; that is, where love occurs, there God is
and there something divine occurs. Now this statement may be quite
legitimate from a Christian point of view, but it can also be interpreted
atheistically unless an explanation is given of who the subject of this love
is, or how human and divine subjects are related to one another in the
loving. Thus, in the mailer of the God-question modern philosophy
ultimately confronts us with the problem of whether and how the question
of being, or the question of the meaning of being, can be asked anew within
the modern philosophy of subjectivity. It is the merit of Nietzsche and of
Martin Heidegger's interpretation of Nietzsche to have posed the problem
in this radical manner.
III
The Predicament of Theology in the Face of Atheism
Scholasticism provided some further explana tions that are important especially
for present-day discussion. In particular, in his Proslogion Anselm of Canter-
bury, the father of medieval Scholasticism, develops the thought of Augustine
and explains that God cannot rationally be thought of as non-existent.' Anselm
thus prepares the way for the Thomist theory according to which God is
implicitly known in every act of knowing. s This means that there can be no
such thing as absolute atheism and that the athiest who (for example) makes
matter ultimate and therefore absolute does know of God in a manner which
under some conditions may be hidden from him, although he gives an erroneous
interpretation of this knowledge. Nonetheless, with Heb. 11.6 Thomas main-
tains as necessary for salvation a faith that is not simply implicit but explicit/·
He gives two reasons for this view. On the one hand, even what we are able
to know of God by our natural powers cannot be known easily and without
admixture of error by all. On the other hand, human beings can by their natural
powers know the existence of God, but knowledge of God as man's salvation
is beyond the natural powers of man to obtain. Consequently an explicit faith
in response to revelation is necessary if man is to be saved. Here Thomas
presupposes, of course, that the message of God as man's salvation is known
to all human beings. If then (says Thomas) there is a human being who lives
in the primeval forest or among wild beasts and has not heard this message,
God will certainly convey to him by an interior enlightenment the revelation
of what is necessary for salvation, or else he will send the person an evangelist. 7
It is possible that at a later stage, in his theological Summa, Thomas moved
beyond this emergency solution, which really requires a miracle. He says that
every adult human being who is capable of the full use of reason must renect
on himself and on the meaning and goal of his life and, with tho help of grace,
has the power to turn to God as meaning and fulfillment or, in other words,
as man's salvation. II It would follow from this that anyone is saved who in his
conscience directs himself toward ulrimace values, insofar as he is capable of
recognizing these in his concrete situation.
Ii
for the possibility of finite knowledge. According to Rahner- and entirely
in the spirit of Thomas Aquinas - in this pre-apprehension (Vorgrif{) of
being as the condition for the possibility of knowledge of beings the reality
,
of God is always already affirmed ..!1 The unthematic experience of God
thus occurs with transcendental necessity in every spiritual act, even in the
act of denying God. This thesis is of radical importance in coming to grips
with atheism. There arc four possibilities:.12
(a) The person interprets his transcendental relatedness categorically as
theism and accepts this by a free decision.
(b) The person interprets his transcendental relatedness categorically as
theism, but denies God by a free decision . This represents the conventional
idea of culpable practical and theoretical atheism.
(e) The person accepts his transcendental relatedness but interprets this
with the aid of an erroneous concept of God, which he rejects, or else
reaches no concept of God at all. This is inculpable atheism, which at
bottom is an anonymous theism.
The Predicamelll of Theology ill the Face of Atheism 53
(d) The person violates his conscience and denies even the transcendental
relatedness, and then goes on to reject both correct and erroneous concepts
of God, or else he reaches no concept of God at all. This is culpable atheism;
as long as the person remains in this attitude, he has no possibility of being
saved.
Rahner's theory, which on the whole is entirely in the line of Scholastic
tradition, represents a tremendous advance because it makes it possible
for the first time to reflect on the inherent possibilities in the phenomenon
of atheism and to do so in theological terms, instead of immediately
rejecting it as alien and even absurd. This theory makes a dialogue possible
for the first time, since dialogue by its nature presupposes a common basis.
Nonetheless questions remain that have to do with Rahner's central idea
of a necessary affirmation of God. If this idea is presupposed, is any real
atheism still possible, that is, an atheism which is not a veiled anonymous
theism? For, according 10 the theory, every individual, whether or not he
realizes it, whether or not he wills ir, must with transcendental necessity
direct his life to an absolute. The only questions remaining are whether
this absolute is God or an idol and, should the case arise, whether or not
the decision against God and for an idol is culpable. In a sense, then, it can
be said that Rahner's theory of atheism is the antitype of the atheistic
theory of religion. H The laner theory interprets theism atheistically as a
projection of man, while Rahner interprets atheism theistically as a false
interpretation of man and his transcendence.
Rahner thus remains within the framework provided by classical meta·
physics as well as within that provided by the modern point of departure.
His merit is to have shown that there is no opposition between classical
thinking in the line of Thomas Aquinas and modern transcendental
thought. On the other hand, as the entire modern development has made
clear, it is highly ambiguous to claim God as the interpretation of human
transcendence, for there is the danger either of no longer being able 10
preserve fully the transcendence of God or - as is rather the danger in
Rahner - of turning this transcendence into an ineffable mystery in which
man exists but which he must rather be silent about than speak of. Today,
at the end of modern times (R. Guardini), at the end of modernity (A.
Gehlen) and at the end of modern consciousness (R. Spaemann), when we
have become clear on the limits of these starting points, this position is no
longer adequate as an answer to modern atheism.
All ,he thcologil..'al approaches to :ttllL'isl11 that I h;\ve thus far disclIssed arc
challenged by politic;}1 rhcology'iO and hy the qucstions it raises in thl' form
of thl' thl'olngy of libl'ratioll.;1 Thesl' two theologiL's promote a new kind
56 The God-Qllestioll Today
of theology which is conceived of not primarily as a renection on faith but
as a reflection on the practice of faith. They regard even modern atheism
as primarily a practical and political problem that can be resolved only
through a new practice. Their concern is thus with a new acceptance and
new definition of the theory-practice relationship, which past theology has
neglected. This theology has undoubtedly performed a service by reacting
against the tendencies to privatization that arc found in transcendental
and in dialogical theology and by calling attention to the practical and
political dimension of theology in general and of modern atheism in
particular. Political theology and the theology of liberation have thus
intensified our awareness of certain problems. The insight that the modern
privatization of religion has produced modern atheism leads these theol-
ogies to the programmatic statement of a post-bourgeois religion and
theology that will not uncritically accept into theology the modern subject
which is the result of the modern age and its process of privatization. I! Put
concretely, the antithesis is: theology of the people. 53 The people, or the
base of the pyramid as the case may be, is here not only the goal and
addressee of theology but its subject and the place where ir is carried on.
The struggle about God becomes a struggle for the right of all to be free
subjects before God."The new God-talk is thus possible only in the context
of a liberating practice.
Political theology in fact calls our attention to aspects which are short-
changed in the theologies of the modern age which take as their point of
departure the subject or the I-Thou relationship. The only question is
whether it in turn does not fall victim to possibly even more deleterious
simplifications. I have already pointed out that society and therefore the
political dimension is not the only dimension, and certainly not the most
inclusive one, or the one in which alone the God-question can appropriately
be raised. 55 And in fact, with the passage of time, political theology has
substantially broadened its approach, by maintaining that religion must
be at once political and mysticaL'· But atheism calls in question the
very condition for the possibility of mysticism, insofar as mysticism is
understood in the traditional theistic sense. This question can be tackled
under the rubric of 'practice' only if practice is understood strictly in the
sense given it by modern philosophy: the practice of freedom; in other
words, only if one accepts the despised modern philosophy of freedom and
then, within the horizon of freedom, raises anew the metaphysical question
of the meaning of freedom within reality as a whole.
The attempt to ground faith in God purely in itself and to. take a radical
position of faith as the starting point for a debate with modern atheism
brings us to a final model of theological encounter with atheism; it is a
model that may be described as dialectical. The dialogical model looks to
the natural-theology tradition for a common basis of understanding that
allows faith in God and atheism to comprehend and discuss each other
and thus enter into a dialogue. The dialectical model, on the other hand,
challenges the existence of this common basis. It acknowledges no positive
connection between the two, but only a connection in the form of a
58 The God-Questioll Today
contradiction. This is the direction in which a large part of contemporary
Protestant theology has moved in its exchanges with modern atheism.
This attempt is to be secn in its most authentic form in the notes which D.
Bonhocffer jotted down during his imprisonment by the Nazis." We find in
them an outline of a rcligionl<ss Christianity. Even though Bonhoeffer's
concept of religion is not (hat of Barth, the two are nonetheless in agreement
that at least today and in the time to come the religious presupposition is
lacking in our society which has become irrcligious.7.2 But the Christian need
not bemoan this turn of events, since It brings us to '." true recognition of our
situation before God'. The God of Jesus Christ allows himself to be expelled
from the world through the cross ; he is helpless and weak in the world, and
only under these conditions does he abide with us and hdp us. Therefore
'before God and with God we live without God'. The atheistic situation makes
it possible to sec the God of the Bible 'who WinS power and space in the world
by his weakness' .' " 'The world that has come of age is more godless, and
perhaps for that very reason ncarer to God than the world before its coming
of agc.'~"Bonhocfrcr thus takes:1 renewed theology of the cross as rhe starting
point for his answer to modern atheism.
It was not until the 1960s, when the situation had completely changed since
his time, that Bonhocffer began [0 exert an extensive, although unfortunately
often quite superficial, influence. In German theology his influence showed
itself first in the radical wing of the Bultmann school, where H. Braun extended
Bultmann's program of demythologization 10 the understanding of God that
is presupposed in the New Tc>tamenr, and interpreted God in existential terms
"' 'the ground of my drifting', 'the ground of the security I find in my fellow
man and of the obligation Ihavcto him', '3 certain kind of human fcllowship',1.5
60 The God-Questioll Today
In like manner, D. SolIe looks for a way of believing atheistically in God."
'God happens in what happens between human beings';77 faith is '3 certain
kind of living' ,711 '3 certain way of being there',1'1 an 'existential movement'.IIO
By means of this Christian atheism SolIe attempts to reach a position beyond
theism and atheism, although in the process she oversimplifies both by taking
them to be objectivizing positions. 1I1 In the final analysis, her position, like that
of Braun, leads to exactly what Feuerbach wanted, and is indistinguishable
from a pure humanism,1Il
In non-German theology there was a direct connection between K. Barth,
D. Bonhoeffer and, to some extent, Hegel, on the one hand, and, on the other,
the 'death of God' theology" that caused so much shaking of heads within and
especially outside theological circles. 'Death of God' actually had a variety of
meanings: from the death of God in modern secularized culture (G. Vahanian),
in language (P. van Buren), in the silence of God (W. Hamilton), all the way
to the extreme kenosis-theologies according to which God in Jesus Christ died
on the scene of world history (T. J. J. Altizer). These ideas were popularized
in the book HOliest to God by the Anglican bishop J. A. T. Robinson; this
book, though it was an undigested mixture full of over-simplifications,
nonetheless gave expression to what many people were vaguely feeling. 1I4 It
soon became clear, of course, that this theological fad was self·contradictory.
For if God is dead then so is theology - a fate that has since befallen at least
the Death-of-God theology. This current of thought has not really grappled
with modern atheism, but has simply capitulated to it and thus surrendered
any chance of arguing on mhcr than an atheistic basis. All that was left was a
theological verbal facade with nothing theological behind it.
The first new serious attempt has come inJ. Moltmann's The Crucified God.
Following closely in the footsteps of Barth and Bonhoeffer, Moltmann take,
as his starting point 'the cross of Christ as the foundation and criticism of
Christian theology'." This approach thus excludes natural theology which,
in Moltmann's view, ignores the cross and attempts to argue back from
experienced reality to its absolute ground in God, reaching in the process the
theistic notion of a God who is incapable of suffering.1I1> The rejection of this
theistic God justifies our speaking of a 'Christian atheism'.II':' Moltmann's
epistemological starting point is not analogy but dialectic."" That is, God is
known here in terms of his opposite, and godlessness is in a sense the
presupposition for knowing God. In other words, if we start with the death of
God on the cross and really take this seriously, then atheism is integrated into
the reality of God and, at the same time, is therein negated, preserved and
transcended. On the cross God has anticipated atheism, made it his own, and
blunted it. Atheism and theism alike have been negated and transcended by
the cross. 'With a trinitarian theology of the cross faith escapes the dispute
between and the alternative of theism and atheism.'"':! The conclusion, to be
sure, that Moltmann draws from all this is that God is, in an almost Hegelian
manner, entangled in the history of human sin, so that God's existence in and
The Predicament of Theology iI/ the Face of Atheism 61
for himself (the immanent Trinity) can no longer be distinguished from the
history of God's suffering in the world. At this point, a radical approach 'from
above' in terms of the theology of revelation and of the cross is dialectically
converted by Moltmann into a conception of God that no longer adequately
distinguishes God from the world and is almost mythological and tragic in
character. The dialectic with which Mailman" starred turns into an identity.
The extremes touch.
The question that has to be asked'· of the dialectic theology which K. Barth
inaugurated is whether the transcendence of God and his word can be
preserved otherwise than by 1I0t making man and his positive or negative
answer a phase in the word and action of God; for if man and his answer
are given such a role, the next easy step is to make God a phase of man. It
is necessary, in other words, to understand the human person as a partner
who has been brought on the scene by God and established as free, that is,
as a relatively independent partner whom God, in revealing himself,
presupposes as one capable of hearing and understanding his word
(poeelltia obocdielltialis, obediential potency) . The correspondence at the
level of faith (allalogia fidei, analogy of faith) thus presupposes, on its own
behalf, a correspondence at the level of creaturehood (allalogia elltis,
analogy of being). This second correspondence does not function as a
pregiven, independent framework for revelation, restricting the scope of
the latter and turning it into a special application of a pre-given general
principle; it is, rather a presupposition for revelation, and a presupposition
which revelation itself requires if it is to be possible. It exists for the sake
of revelation and formulates the pure potentialiry of the creature for God,
utterly beyond any active power of its own."
Barth's position is not the only onc that serves contemporary Protestant
theology as a basis for coming to grips with atheism. The Lutheran position
is also brought to bear on the discussion, especially in the writings of G.
Ebeling" and E. Jungel." Luther agrees with Barth that true knowledge
of God is to be had only through faith. 'For the two go together: faith and
God! Anyone who tries to find God apart from faith finds only the devil.
But it is faith that gives shape to both: God and idols. "" When faith and
God arc connected in such a close way. Fcuerbach's suspicion of a
projection seems to make itself felt with special intensity. Luther's position
is by its innermost nature exposed to the temptation of atheism. 10 1
Objectively, of course, it is worlds removed from atheism. For while Luther
says: 'That to which you attach and surrender your heart is really your
God,''''' Feuerbach's principle is: 'His heart is his god.' ''''
The question, of course, is how this fundamental difference can be not only
asserted hut also made clear to the unbeliever or, in words, how what is
believed can be made universally intelligible and thus its rationality be proved.
At this point rhe Lutheran position differs from the Barthian in that the former
claims a correlation not only between God and faith, but also between faith
or word and situation.l o4 In the word 'God' and in the word of God it is not
only God who makes himsclfknown; light is also shed on the situation of man.
In fact, the word 'God' and the word of God look to the basic situation of man
as a word situation; they lay hold of man in his Iinguisticality.1U5 The word
'God' shows us 'that man in his linguisticality is not master of himself. He lives
from the power of a word that is not his own, and at the same time he thirsts
after the power of a word that likewise cannot be his own.' lUll God is thus the
mystery of reality .IO~ But because of his linguisticality man gains knowledge
of this mystery only in and through the word; only in the word does the truth
about God and man come to light. Only the word of God makes it known that
man is always one who is already being approached by God. For this reason,
before the word comes to him man cannot know God as the mystery of reality;
on the other hand, the word 'God' and the word of God arc verified in the
being of man and the world - 'verified' in the sense of verum facere, 'make
true' and bring to the truth. 1011
The contest with atheism is thus a contest for the world and man. But the
contest is not waged - as it is in natural theology and to some extent also
and especially when the relation between faith in God and modern atheism
The Predicamellt of Theology ill the Face of Atheism 63
is conceived as dialogical- on the ground of a shared neutral base, namely
a natural power of knowing God that precedes both faith and unbelief.
Faith is not a particular case under an overarching universal category (on
this poine Luther's criticism is in agreement with Banh's},IU,* The starting
point is the reality of faith, which encounters the reality of unbelief as
man's factual simarian ilnd seeks to convince man in this situation of
his losmess and lack of truth. The starting point is God's promise, the
prollllssio of the word of revelation, to which faith responds but which
unbelief opposes. Luther's thinking moves not in the framework of natural
and supernatural knowledge of God but in the framework of law and
gospel. ""
The thesis that true knowledge of God is to be had only through faith in the
word of God has for a consequence thar we c:m never speak of God \\,hile
prescinding from man, but only of God for me and for us, or of God in his
rdation to man. 111 If we abstract from thiS relation and speak abstractly of
God's being in itself, we are in d:lngcr of turning God into an object and thus
:,rripping him of his divinity, One acts as an atheist by 3S~crtlOg the existence
of God no·k'Ss than by denying it.'" The old ontology of substance must
therefore be replac<d by relational thinking. The following principle is valid:
'The idea of God without rhe world is a pure hm it nQtlon which gives expression
to the truth that when God and world arc taken together the absolute primacy
of God emerges. 'I L1 For the rcst, it remains true that DeliS supra liDS, nibil ad
liDS, God is beyond us and no business of our5. 114 \Virh this, the classical
distinction between the being of God thought of as at rest and the same being
thought of as active is eliminated. From the inSIght that we may not speak of
God's being while prescinding from his activity I[ follows that 'God's being is
in becoming'.'"
At thIS pomt we arc dangerously close to Hegel's h'ghly ambiguous position
that God cannot exist without the wor1d. ll t> The dialectical definition of the
relation between £3ith and unbelief is thus in danger, even in Lurher's version
of it, of turning IOto an identific:1tIon of the two, so that it is no longer possible
to distinguish between the (wo in :1 rationally argued way, hut instead the
distinction must be arbitrarily asscncd. Neither In the old ontology ofsubslancc
nor in the rciational theology developed out of Luther does the danger of
atheism seem to be eliminated in principle.
It is interesting, to be surc, tha.t Luther a.nd Thoma.s a.rc not only threatened
by the sa.me danger but a.lso a.stonishingly close in their positive a.ssertions. As
everyone knows, according to Thoma.s we ca." know better wha.t God is not
than what he is. Less well known is the fact that for Thomas the same holds
trUC of fa.ith. Even through rcvcla.tion we do not know what God iSj wc arc
united to him quasi ignoto, a.s ro one unknown to us. Through revebrion we
gain knowledge only of more and greater works of his.ll~ There is no denying
64 The Cod-Ql/estiO// Today
that this thesis of Thomas is at odds with the many passages in which he makes
statements about the being of God. Nonetheless, the passage to which I have
referred shows that there is no mutual opposition between the metaphysically
based theology of Thomas and a relational theology of lutheran extraction.
We are dealing father with two complementary schemes and approaches which
intend to say materially the same thing but which also have limits and dangers,
so that each needs to be criticized and supplemented by the other. On this
fundamental question, which is a matter of life or death for both, they can
fulfill their common task only in conjunction with each other and not in
opposition [Q each other.
For many people today the Christian message about God has become a
foreign language they are unable to understand or grasp. In fact, in the
context of modern experience the questions asked in this message and the
answers given seem to have become meaningless. This loss of the basic
presuppositions needed for understanding affects in our day not only
peripheral and borderline truths but even the terms that are central to the
Christian proclamation (God, sin, redemption, grace). The real issue today
is no longer primarily this or that truth but the very abiliry to believe. We
have to a large extent lost the dimension of faith, which is the dimension
of mystery. Theologically, therefore, we are forced back to the rudiments
of understanding; our capacity for experience has become in good measure
limited to what can be grasped by the senses, to what can be counted and
produced. As a result, in our secularized sociery dogmatic theology is
compelled, more than in the past, to reflect on the presuppositions o(
understanding that are proper to it. This reflection on the presuppositions
(or the understanding of faith is known as natural theology. '
The present situation of nawraltheology is admittedly a quite paradox-
ical one. For in the measure that the call has been increasingly sounded in
present-day theology for a discussion of the presuppositions of understan-
ding, natural theology has failed into disrepute. Natural theology has
become as it were the neuralgic point in contemporary theology (E. Jiingel).
The Bible does not as yet contain any reflection on the presuppositions
for the understanding of faith. To that extent there is no natural theology
in the Bible. On the other hand, the Bible practises natural theology to a
surprising degree. For the life mirrored in the Bible goes on in a world that
is religious to the core; the Bible can therefore, in a still utterly unreflective
66 The God-Questioll Today
way, have recourse not only to religious ideas and experience but also to
universal human, every-day experiences and from these derive images for
use in religious statements. We see this process at work on the opening
pages of the Bible, in the two accounts of creation. These take very ancient
religious ideas of the human race (ideas which we today describe as
mythical) and interpret them in a new and critical way in the light of the
experience of faith. The creation psalms in particular show how the devout
ofthe Old Testament derive from wordly reality a knowledge of the power
and glory of God (d. Pss. 8; 19; 29; 104; 148). Only the fool says in his
heart: There is no God (Ps. 14.1). In the late period of the Old Testament
this 'natural' knowledge of God is already being expressed in didactic
form: 'All men who were ignorant of God were foolish by nature ... For
from the greatness and beauty of created things comes a corresponding
perception of their Creator' (Wisdom 13.1-5).
In the New Testament, Jesus' practice of speaking in parables is highly
significant. In the parables of Jesus the world as it presents itself to human
beings in their everyday experience becomes an image of the reign of God.
All the processes in nature and history are capable of serving in this context
as images of eschatological salvation. Jesus takes the everyday experiences
of human beings as his starting point and uses them as a mirror in which
to make his message intelligible. Conversely, however, these same everyday
experiences often have a new and unexpected light thrown on them by the
parables of Jesus (contrast parables). Through the parables of God's reign
the world at last acquires its definitive meaning. When Jesus speaks in
parables he turns the world into a parable of the reign of God.
The New Testament shows parabolic language being used in varying
measures. The link with wordly experience shows up with greatest immed-
iacy in Luke's Acts of the Apostles. According to Acts Paul appeals in his
missionary discourses not only to the Old Testament but also to the
religious experiences of the pagans: to the testimony God has given to
himself in nature and history (Acts 14.16f.; 17.22-28).
In the letters of Paul the reference to 'natural' experience and knowledge
does not take this direct and positive form but rather a critical and
dialectical form. Paul does indeed speak of God being known from created
reality (Rom 1.19f.), and especially from conscience (Rom. 2.14f.). But he
also says that while the pagans knew God they did not acknowledge him
as God, but refused to honour him and transferred to creatures the homage
due to him alone. In so doing, their hearts were hardened and their minds
darkened. They have no excuse for their godlessness and corruption (Rom.
1.20). When Paul thus makes the pagans responsible for their unbelief, he
indirectly recognizes the possibility and actuality of the pagans' knowledge
Experiellce of God alld Kllowledge of God 67
of God. It is possible here to speak of contact amid contradiction. In other
words: it is not legitimate to make Paul's theology of the cross simply a
contradiction of the concern at work in natural theology. For although
Paul emphasizes the foolishness of the cross (I Cor. 1-2), he would also
rather speak five words with his mind than stammer ten thousand words
in an ecstatic tongue (I Cor 14.19); in fact, he wants to take all thinking
captive for Christ (II Cor 10.5).
The situation is again different to Johannine theology. John accepts the
questions of human beings with regard to bread Uohn 6), light Uohn 8),
and way, truth and life Uohn 14), in order then to proclaim Jesus Christ
as the definitive answer to these questions. He starts therefore with the
assumption that the lives of human beings are inspired by the quest for
salvation and that in this way men and women have a preunderstanding
of salvation. On the other hand, it is only through Jesus Christ that
definitive clarity comes on what light, life and truth are. Just as an answer
is intelligible only in the light of the question being asked, so conversely
the answer throws a definitive light on the meaning of the question. John's
proclamation of Jesus Christ as the incarnate Word proved to be especially
momentous Uohn 1.1-14), for it meant the acceptance of a concept which
Philo, a Jewish philosopher of religion, had already used as a way of
mediating between Old Testament faith and Hellenistic thought. Behind
John's application of Logos to Jesus stands the conviction that the Logos
at work in creation is no other than the Logos who in the fullness of time
became a human being in Jesus Christ. In similar fashion, the theology of
later ages drew Stoic, Platonic and finally also Aristotelian concepts into
the service of the faith. The purpose in so doing was to give expression to
the fact that the Logos who holds sway in a seminal and traceable manner
in all reality (logos spermatikos) has manifested himself fully in Jesus
Christ.'
In summary we may say that while the Bible does not expressly reflect
on the natural presuppositions of faith, it does in fact appeal to these
presuppositions to a quite notable extent and in manifold ways. In the
background of this unreflective yet extensively practised natural theology
there is a convinction that is basic to both the Old and the New Testament:
the conviction that the order of creation and the order of salvation fit
together. The Bible understands the revelation given in the course of
salvation history as being a prophetic interpretation of reality. Conse-
quently, faith, as understood in the Bible, is not a blind venture, not an
irrational feeling, not an uncalculated option and certainly not a sacri{icillm
illtellecllls (sacrifice of the understanding). Rather, faith can and must give
a rational account of itself. According to the New Testament, believers are
68 The God-Qllestion Today
called upon to explain to all men the reasons for the hope which they have
(I Peter 3.15).
The Bible is nor concerned with the nature of things, that is, with what things
are by reason of the origin peculiar to each of them (natura from nasci, 'to be
born') but only with what man and the world are by reason of their origin in
God. The Bible thus looks upon reality not as nature (physis) but as creature
(ktisis). Reality as created is, on the one hand, wholly dependent on God and,
on the other, infinitely different from him; moreover, insofar as it is entirely
distinct from him even while being dependent on him, it enjoys a relative
independence over against him. Because of this relative independence the Bible
has no hesitation about speaking of a nature that has been given to man by
God himself and that inspires him (el. Rom. 1.26; 21.4; I Cor. 11.14). This
relative independence also makes it possible for human beings to [Urn against
God and in this way to corrupt their own natures (el. Rom. I. ISH.). Now they
are by nature children of wrath (el. Eph. 2.3), but because they owe their entire
being to God, they remain, even as sinners, wholly related to God. Precisely as
sinners, they arc, in their corrupt state, a question to themselves, a question
which they themselves cannot answer. The Bible thus expounds the being of
world and man in the form of an extremely tension·filled history of relations
between God and human beings. But despite all the vicissitudes that mark this
history, there is something that abides and retains its identity and that, even
though profoundly distorted by sin, cannot be radically negated or cancelled
out. At the same rime, however, this abiding nature is henceforth drawn into
the dynamic movement of the historical dealings between God and man, a
history of which Greek philosophy could have had no knowledge. In the Bible,
therefore, nature is not the basis for an order of being which is independent of
grace; it is rather the term which expresses a relatively independent meaningful
structure within the ordpr of grace.
This integration of natural theology into the history of salvation is to be
found in all the great theologians of the classical tradition: Augustine, Anselm
of Canterbury, Bonaventure, Thomas Aquinas. The dynami~ movement of
salvation history into which the concept of nature has been incorporated finds
expression especially in the axiom mentioned earlier: 'Grace presupposes
nature and completes it.' The axiom makes it clear that nature exists entirely
for the sake of grace; it is the extrinsic presupposition of grace, just as,
conversely, grace is the intrinsic presupposition of nature, that for the sake of
which nature exists. Nature is therefore not an independent, self·enclosed and
self·completing or fulfilling realm. It is dynamically ordered beyond itself to a
fulfillment which it cannot bestow upon itself but rather achieves through
grace alone. Only through grace does nature attain to its own full de(ermina·
74 The God-Question Today
tion. When it closes itself to grace through sin it becomes contradictory to
itself and is deeply perverted.
A twofold order, one of nature and one of grace, is at most suggested as a
possibiliry in the classical tradition; the idea has been developed only in the
modern age. This momentous development was set in motion by the heresy of
Baius, a theologian at Louvain in the sixteenth century. Baius taught that
nature is not only ordered co grace bur even has a right to grace. As a way of
maintaining the gratuitousness of grace the theologians of the Baroque and
NeD-scholastic periods constructed the idea of a pure nature (natllra pllra).n
This was originally intended simply as an auxiliary construct, a conceptual
hyporhesis, enabling theologians to grasp (he gratuitousness of gracc. Bur it
led in turn to the development of a twofold order of natural and supernatural
theology. This elaboration of something initially proposed simply as a concep-
tual possibility is intelligible only in the light of the indirect inOuence exercised
by a new understanding of natural theology that developed in the modern
Enlightenment.
2. Experience of God
As far as the God-question is concerned, we arc being forced back today
to the rudiments of understanding. Consequently, when we speak of a
natural knowledge of God, there can be no question simply of abstract
proofs of God. Such proofs are meaningful and intelligible only if they
have a basis in experience and represent an affort to penetrate more deeply
into this experience and defend it against intellectual challenges. Like all
knowledge, the knowledge of God requires a basis in experience. But what
is experience? To what extent is it possible to speak at all of an experience
of God?"'o
The them~ of faith and experience is an extremely difficult and perplexing
one. This is due not least to the fact that both the concept of experience
and the concept of faith arc many-levelled and ambiguous. Experience
may mean: personal experience of life, and the methodically disciplined
experience of the modern experimental sciences; everyday experience in
the secularized world of our day, and devotional experience and the
experience of faith all the way up to mystical experience; practical
experience, especially that gained in political practice, and experience
taken over and imported from the experimental sciences. It is clear that
these distinct concepts of experience, to which others might be added,
point in very different and to some extent contradictory directions. When
someone appeals to experience, he has not yet said anything clear and
unequivocal; he has called attention to a problem, but he has not answered
any questions.
The concept of faith likewise has a number of meanings. In theological
parlance faith may mean the act of faith (fides qua credilllr, the [act of]
faith by which one believes) but also the content of faith (fides quae
creditur, the faith-contents which arc believed). In the first case, to ask
about the relation between faith and experience is to ask how the act of
trust, self-surrender and obedience toward the impenetrable mystery which
in religious language we call God can be reconciled with our sober,
enlightened, rational experience of the world. In the second case, the
relation between faith and experience has to do with the problem of how
certain contents of faith can be reconciled with our modern world-picture
80 The God-Qllestioll Today
and especially with the results of the modern experimental sciences. The
two problems cannot be wholly separated, but they must nonetheless be
carefully distinguished.
It is not only the concepts of experience and faith but also the relation
between faith and experience that can be defined in very different ways.
At the present time two opposed positions call for particular discussion.
The first and traditional formulation of the relation says: faith comes from
hearing (Rom. 10.17) and has for its criterion not our present experience
of reality but the authoritatively proclaimed gospel message which is
transmitted through the church. The second and basically modernistic
definition of the relation says: faith is an expression of religious experience,
and the traditional confessions of faith must be measured by their ability
to express our changed modern experience or at least 10 make this
experience possible. Both positions have something true 10 say, but both
are also one-sided.
True though it is that the Christian faith has for its norm the faith
delivered once and for all Uude 3), it is also true 10 say that we encounter
this faith in a quite limited hislOrical experiential tradition and that this
tradition is no longer directly ours but must be appropriated via our own
experience. This fact points 10 the truth in the second position. The latter,
however, overlooks the fact that experience never begins at point zero but
is historically mediated. Above all, it overlooks the fact that not the word
of God as such but the hislOrical form in which it is transmitted 10 us (and
it comes 10 us only in a historical form) needs 10 be criticized, tested
and sounded more fully. Our always limited and historically changing
experience cannot and may not be the criterion for what is 10 be accepted
as the word of God; rather, the word of God is meant to, and must, make
known 10 us whattrueexperience is as compared with illusory appearances.
The word of God proves itself 10 be true by opening up new experience 10
us, experience which proves its worth by other experiences.
Finally, the point must be made that faith is not only related 10 an
experiential reality which antecedes it, but also has experience which is
proper 10 it. This aspect finds expression particularly in the biblical
understanding of knowledge (Yadli) which is never acquired with the mind
alone but is mediated through the whole of existence and through the
existential centre, the heart of man. This experience which is proper 10
faith has been known especially by the mystics, for 10 them mysticism is
cognito Dei experimentalis (an experiential knowledge of God)."
It follows from all this that the relation between faith and experience
can only be described as a relation of critical correlation. The resultant
hermeneutical circle between the transmission of faith and the experience
Experiellce of God alld Kllow/edge of God 81
of faith cannot be eliminated. The decisive point, of course, is that within
this circle primacy belongs to the message; this means that we may never
absolutize our present experience and that our experience is rather always
a historically open experience that is and must be open to new experience.
The question, then, is this. Where is faith to find its correlative in present-
day experience of reality?
Our present situation is characterized by a far-reaching loss of religious
experience. If, then, we are to make such experience at all accessible again,
we must take as our point of departure a general understanding of
experience and then show how the dimension of religious experience opens
up 'in, with and under' everyday human experience. This very attempt is
still difficult enough, since, as I already said, the concept of experience is
extremely complex and multi-leveled; it is one of the most difficult and
obscure concepts in all philosophy.
In our everyday linguistic usage we speak of an experienced person,
meaning that he is one who knows people and things not simply by hearsay
or from books but repeated direct dealings with them; one, therefore, who
combines knowledge and ability. The German word for 'to experience',
er{ahrell, is derived from {ahre>t, which means ' to journey'. An experienced
man is thus a 'travelled' man, who does not know the world only by
hearsay but has rather been out in the midst of it and has shared the life,
sufferings and activities of other human beings. The Romance languages
take a different approach to the idea. They speak of cxpericlltia (the Latin
word behind the Romance words). The expert is the periflls, the man who
through experimentation, trial and error, and confirmation has as it were
piled up insights within his own person.
This everyday linguistic usage shows that experience may not be reduced
to an objectivist understanding of experience, such as is often attributed
to the so-called experimental sciences. Experience is not only what we can
establish and test by experiment and then reduce to the simplest kind
of factual descriptions. Such a narrowly empiricist understanding of
experience has in fact now been rejected even by the experimental sciences.
Down to the present, no science, not even the natural sciences, has
succeeded in convincingly reducing all knowledge to purely empirical data.
The very development of modern physics, especially quantum physics, has
shown that we never know reality in itself but always and only through
human images, models and concepts. We never experience reality in itself;
we always experience it as something that has a specific meaning for
US; objective experience and interpretation of experience can never be
completely separated. In any case, an absolutization of what is experiment-
ally ascertainable would be a contradictory claim, since the thesis that
82 The God-Qllestion Today
the empirically ascertainable is alone real is itself not an empirically
ascertainable assertion. Anti-metaphysical positivism is, paradoxically, a
metaphysics of the positive. Consequently it is not a valid objection against
belief in God to observe that God is not empirically observable; for there
is no conceivable empirical method that could show that God is. The God
who is is not a given. But there is also no conceivoble empirical method
that could ever prove the non-existence of God.
The critique of a one-sidedly objectivist concept of experience should
not, of course, lead to a reduction of religious experience to the opposite,
that is, to subjective experience (£rfebnis ) or even to subjective moods.
Every expenence doubtless takes place in the medium of human subjecti-
vity, calling forth therein an echoanda reflex response. Religiousexperience
affects the human person to the depths and in all the fibres of the being; it
sets humming all the chords of existence. One cannot encounter God and
remain a distant spectator, for God lays total claim to the person. In the
language of the Bible: the experience of God takes place in the heart, that
is, in the core or centre of the human person. But the primary clement in
the person's being subjectively touched is that he or she comes in contact
with and is even overwhelmed by a reality not himselfor herself. TIllS holds
even for religIOUS experience. Significantly, it is precisely the great mystics
who arc mOSt critical and reserved toward inward personal experiences.
The hunger for religious experiences can be very unreligious and self-
centred. If, then, the person wants to encounter God and not simply himself
or herself he or she must not seck such experiences for their own sake.
Were we to reduce the experience of God to pcrsonallife·expcriencc, we
would confine ourselves to the realm of the subjective, of non-commitmentj
the suspicion of projection would then immediately arise.
The twofold limitation on the concept of experience brings us to a
positive definition of the essence of experience. Experience is not (0 be
reduced to something purely objective or to something purely subjective. It
includes both clements: objective contact and subjective feeling. Experience
arises from the interplay of objective reality and subjective intercourse with
the milieu and our times. Experience is inseparably a being affected by
reality and an interpretation of this contact through words, images,
symbols and concepts. It thus has a dialectical structure; that is, it is
historical, for 'history' means the reciprocal interaction of the person and
the world.
The historicity of experience has, in turn, several aspects. It means, to
begin with, that experience never takes place at an isolated point of
time through the here-and-now digestion of momentary perceptions.
Experiential knowledge emerges, rather, from repeated and increasingly
Experience of God and Knowledge of God 83
proficient intercourse with reality. It comes into existence by the fact that
certain impressions and the interpretation made of them are repeatedly
confirmed. Experience thus requires a familiarity and practice in dealing
with things and persons, a mastering of patterns of action. This is why
Aristotle connects experience with memory.·ll But the memory of which
he speaks is not simply the individual memory of each person; it is also
the collective memory that is recorded especially in the language of
a community. Language is the precipitate of the experience of many
generations. This means that experiences are always likewise the we-
experience of a community, a people, a race or class. These various
human communities arc characterized by a common remembrance of basic
experiences that are constantly revived through the retelling of myths,
sagas, legends, anecdotes and other stories. In other words, experiences
are communicated through narrative.
This last statement points to a second aspect of the historicity of our
experience. Through the mediation of language not only do former
experiences come alive again today; language and the experience 'stored
up' in it also help to interpret our prescnt experience and pass it on to a
future generation. Experience thus exists, at any given time, in a tcnsion
between remembrance of past experience, the experience of the moment,
and the transmission of this experience in the hope that the future will
preserve and confirm it. In other words: experience is a constantly renewed
and never finished learning process. It is 'experience of life' in the proper
sense of the phrase. The experienced person is not one who has a definitive
answer for everything but the person who realizes that experience can
never be complete, is opcn to new experience on the basis of past experience,
knows how to experience, and understands how to undergo new experi-
ences and correlate them in a productive way with past experience.
This historical tension between past, present and future experience has
a twofold critical significance. First, the remembrance of past experience
has a critical significance. For there are not only memories that shed light
on the past but also dangerous memories in which unfulfilled hopes or
experience of profound suffering are revived and present their claims. As
a result, the delusive coherence of a personal universe now taken for
granted can be suddenly destroyed and a new world opened up. Conse-
quently, nothing would be more foolish and uncritical than to absolutize
present and possibly very impoverished experiences and make them the
sale criterion for judging past experiences by applying the simplistic
saying: That no longer says anything to us today.' On the contrary, the
remembrance of great past experiences can provide an impulse toward the
future and render us capable today of new and more profound experiences.
84 The God-Questioll Today
On the other hand, there can evidently be no question of simply
integrating new experiences into old experiential patterns. We undergo
truly fundamental experiences only when we experience the stubborn
resistance of reality to the model of thought and action which we have
cultivated up to now; when we experience something surprisingly new
which alters our previous views, thwarts our plans, opens up new perspec-
tives to us and forces us to advance in new directions. The capacity for
experience is always linked to a readiness to change our minds and
be converted. The experiences that arc fruitful are not our everyday
experiences but rather those contrasting experiences that challenge us to
il decision. In other words: experiences 3rc dis-illusioning, in the positive
sense of the term; they dissolve previous illusions and delusive coherences
and thus reveal the truth about our previous experience.
The understanding of experience as historical, as I have thus farpresented
it, leads to a final point. It is this: the historical dialectic between past,
present and future experiences shows that we not only have immediate
and direct experiences but also experiences of our cxpcrienccs 11 or indirect
experiences. These indirect experiences represent the beginning of reflec-
tion. The reflection is not yet of a conceptual kind but consists rather in
the fact that 'in, with and under' our immediate experience a deeper
experience takes place.
This experience of our experience is in the final analysis an experience
of the finiteness and incompleteness of our experience; it is thus an
experience of suffering. From Aeschylus onward Greek literature repeated
the play on the words patbos and lIIatbos: experiential learning (Illatbos )
through suffering (patbos). Nietzsche prOVides a clear formulation of this
idea: 'As deeply as a man sees into life, he also sees into suffering.''' 'It
almost determines the order of rank bolU profoundly human beings can
suffer.''' From this it follows that the widespread expulsion of suffering
from public life by hiding it behind a mask of youthfulness, vitality and
health leads to an alarming shallowness and impoverishment of our
experience and a declining sensitivity to 'the sigh of the oppressed creature'
(Karl Marx). No one has experienced humanity to the full unless he or she
has experienced its finiteness and suffering. But then experience becomes
a way leading into an open immensity, into a mystery that is ever greater
and never (0 be completely plumbed.
I may sum up by saying that our experience of our experience is in the
final analysis an experience of the finiteness and mysteriousness of our
experience. At this point we have reached the religious dimension of
experience. Religious experience is an indirect, not a direct type of
expcriencc; it is an experience which we have 4in, with and under' our
Experimce of God and Know/edge of God 85
other experiences. It is therefore not just one experience alongside other
experiences, but rather the basic experience present in our other experi-
ences; it is an experience that presides over and gives a pervasive tone to
all other experience. For this reason, K. Rahner and J. B. Lotz speak of
transcendental experience." At first hearing, this description sounds
like a contradiction. For the term 'transcendental' applies to a type of
consideration that is concerned with the conditions that precede and make
possible any and all experience. It is impossible, or so it seems, for an
experience to be its own condition; experiential knowledge cannot grasp
the conditions that precede any and all experience. But the paradoxical
character of the concept simply reflects the paradoxical character of the
reality. For on the one hand it is transcendentality that makes experience
possible to begin with; on the other hand, this transcendentality is itself
historically contingent as far as its concrete form is concerned, and to this
extent it can be the content of a special experience at the level of horizontal
disclosure. In religious experience there is revealed to us, via other
experiences, the ultimate, all-inclusive, sheltering horizon of human experi-
ence, namely, the dimension of that mystery out of which all experience
emerges and to which all experience points.
Having pointed out the dimension of religious experience, 1 must now
turn to the reality of religious experience itself. Religious experience would
be simply a general, vague mood, were there no individual experiences
to which the religious dimension became 'manifest'. In Anglo-Saxon
philosophy, 'disclosure situation' has become the accepted term for such
experiences." What is meant are individual experiences in which more
than just this individual experience is revealed to us: 'suddenly' the whole
of our experience is clarified; the overall coherence of our experience, and
the mystery that holds sway in it, become the subject of experience 'in,
with and under' 3 concrete experience.
Such disclosure situations can take many forms: a situation of joy, for
example, in which we feel a blissful delight and in which the world, and
our own life, seems infinitely rich, beautiful and lovable; or a situation of
sorrow, in which the world no longer makes sense to us and the question
of 'Why?' forces itself ineluctably upon us; or a situation of anxiety, in
which firm ground suddenly vanishes from beneath our feet, the world
reels, and the utter unfathomableness of it all is made clear to us; or a
situation of consolation, in which we feci supported, embraced and
protected; or a situation of love and fidelity coming to us from our fellows,
when we are unconditionally accepted and affirmed, and are ourselves so
taken by the lovableness and beauty of another that everything about us
seems transformed and even under a spell; or a situation of appalling
--
1=--=-=--= ===- ~ _ ~
.=- """". -
= MP
-.. _
Ancient philosophy prepared the way for the theological use of analogy as a
linguistic form. On foundations laid by Parmenides and Heraclitus" Plato first
introduced the concept of analogy into philosophy. He regards analogy as the
most beautiful of all bonds/·II as what binds reality together, mediates between
all things, and creates unity and coherence. This cenere assigns the extremes
their place and links them together. Analogy here is thus a structural principle
of the universe. For Aristotle, [00, the ana/agon (the proportional) is a meso",
an intermediate;6\! this is especially important to him philosophically when he
comes 10 describe the unity (which embraces the various genera) of all reality
insofar as it is being. 70 This unity cannot be strictly defined, because every
definition presupposes a genus and a specific difference, whereas when there
is question of being, there is no conceivable specific difference that is not itself
somehow being. Being can therefore only be ascribed proportionately, that is,
analogously, to ,he various spheres of being. 7I It is possible to speak of being
96 The God-Question Today
only in relation to the one and in terms of the one.7.! Analogy, like metaphor,
proves to be an indirect discourse that points beyond itself.
Wisdom 13.5 already makes it clear how fundamental a role analogy plays
in speech about God, for we are told there that we can gain knowledge of
God from the world by analogy (ana/ogos) because the order and beauty
of the world point beyond the world. Of course, the ancient philosophers
were already aware that the statements which we can make about God or
the divine in this process are of a more negative character. 7.1 Properly
speaking, we can say of God or the divine only what it is not: incorporeal,
invisible, infinite, and so on. But these negative statements have a positive
meaning. They point not to a nothing but to that which is beyond being
and unity and cannot be grasped in concepts" and before which the mind
that secks conceptual knowledge can only stand silent and still." The
fathers of the church took over this the%gia negativa and applied it even
more radically. Dionysius the Pseudo-Areopagite (so called because he was
wrongly identified with the disciple who attached himself to Paul on the
Areopagus) already gives classical expression to the idea: 'In dealing with
the divine, negations (apophaseis) are true, affirmations (kataphaseis)
inadequate.'7. The ultimate possibility for thought in this area is thus a
realization that we do not know, a docta ignorantia (learned ignorance).77
These insights ultimately found their way into the confession of faith of
the Fourth Lateran Council (1215): 'For no similarity can be asserted
between creature and creature unless an even greater dissimilarity is
included.''' Here the self-enclosed philosophical doctrine of analogy,
which sought to bring all oppositions into unity through a mean, was
forced open in the direction of God, dynamically oriented beyond itself,
and directed towards an Ever-Greater. The theological doctrine of analogy
when thus understood does not serve as the basis for a closed cosmological
or ontological continuity, but on the contrary is a principle of ever greater
openness. It directs us toward the ever greater mystery and as such does
not supply the basis for a natural theology in the sense of a doctrine of
God with a purely rational content, but is rather the grammar of faith."
If we look more closely at the theological doctrine of analogy, we find
that it contains three phases or three interconnected steps.'· The via
affirmationis (way of affirmation) takes as its starting point the positive
connection between the finite and the infinite, as this emerges from crearion;
it knows God from his effects in the world. The via negationis (way of
negation) denies the finite mode inherent in our statements and in the
embodiment of all perfections in the finite realm. The via em;,/elltiae (way
of eminence), finally, says that these finite perfections belong to God in a
Experience of God and Knowledge of God 97
higher degree, in a more sublime manner, and, in fact, in a simply all-
surpassing way (eminenter). By following these steps we come to know
more what God is not than what he is; we come to know that we cannot
know him. Nonetheless we do know that we do not know. Ours is not an
unqualified ignorantia but a docta ignorantia, an informed ignorance or
conscious not-knowing. This does not mean, as Hegel thought, that our
statements tail off into indeterminancy. Rather, we may say with Hegel
that the via negation is presupposes the via affirmation is; the negation is
not total but limited, denying only the finite mode of the posit;ve perfection
and not the perfection itself; the via eminentiae in turn negates the negation
and to that extent posits something higher. It expresses the positive meaning
of the negation. We are dealing therefore with a coherent process of
mediation that in the end does not close in on itself but is entirely open."
4. Knowledge of God
In our present-day world of science and technology the basic question of
natural theology, which is the problem of responsible talk about God, will
be answered, in the final analysis, not in terms of religious experience and
religious language but in the light of reason. Without 'the exertion of the
concept' experience and language become empty (Hegel). The question,
then, is this: is faith in God intellectually honest and responsible or is faith
in God possible only through the mind's abandonment of itself (sacrificillm
intellectlls)? What is the relation between faith in God and human
knowledge? Can we know or even prove God in a purely natural way?"
Let me get into the subject by asking first of all: what docs it mean to
100 The God-Questioll Today
know? Knowledge evidently includes far more than proof. Knowledge is
a many-leveled vital process of the entire person; it is not a matter simply
of conceptual abstraction but has a personal dimension and, above all,
always presupposes experience. But knowledge differs from experience in
that it is not only in contact with reality but also knows that it is in
contact." While direct experience involves only an absorption in its object
.nd subjective interiorization of this object, knowledge is entirely present
to the other but in that very act .Iso entirely present to itself. It is reflective,
that is, it turns back from the object to itself .nd becomes conscious of
itself. Knowledge thus presupposes a relative independence from wh.t is
known; it is immediately linked to freedom. In knowledge we ore one with
things .nd human beings, but in such. way th.t at the same time we
dist.nce ourselves from them .nd distinguish them.s objects from ourselves
as subjects.
In agreement with Aristotle I may describe the difference between
experience and knowledge in this \V.y. Knowledge .sks not only wh.t is
but also why it is; it also inquires into the grounds of this knowledge-
including knowledge of and talk .bout God." To that extent knowing
.Iso includes supplying orguments and proving. We must realize,ofcourse,
th.t proof is an analogous concept which derives its specific meaning from
the object of the proof in each instance." Common to all forms of proof
is the fact that there is a process of subst.ntiarion that can be repeated
by people generally. But proofs take different forms: the proof of a
m.thematician, the proof of • n.tural scientist who proceeds by exper-
iment, the proof of a lawyer, a historian, a literary researcher, Or the proof
of a doctor when he di.gnoses .n illness. It is not surprising, therefore,
th.t. proof of God's existence must be of. different kind from. proof in
mathem.tics or the n.!Ur.1 sciences. The 'proofs of God's existence' reach
beyond the dimension of the physic. I .nd of the purely ration. I into the
metaphysic. I world .nd the realm of the infinite, which by its very noture
c.n no longer be conceived and comprehended in finite definitions. If we
were to attempt to prove God as though he were just like any other being,
.nd to reach him through calculation and est.blish his f.ctu.lity after the
manner of the scientist who objectifies .nd keeps his own dist.nce, then,
for from knowing him, we would profoundly foil to know him. Therefore
we should not expect more from the proofs of God's existence than.
well-founded invit.tion to faith. If freedom and knowledge are .Iw.ys
interconnected, then it can be said of the knowledge of God that it is in a
special w.y possible only in freedom. The proofs of God's existence 're
therefore. re.son.ble appeal to human freedom .nd an account rendered
of the intellectu.1 honesty of f.ith in God.
Experience of God and Knowledge of God 101
(aJ The cosmological argllmellt
The cosmological argument is probably the oldest of the proofs for God's
existence. Its point of departure is the reality of the cosmos with its order
and beauty, but also its mobility, frailty and contingency. Starting with
experience of these aspects of the world, the argument inquires into the
ultimate ground of the world; to this ground if finally gives the name 'God',
which is derived from the language of religion.
The cosmological argument has been in use since practically the begin-
ning of Western thought. The early Greek natural philosophers already
argue back from the cosmos and its order to the ground of these. The
fathers of the church take over this approach at a very early point in church
history.·7 The argument is given its classical form in the East in the three
ways of John Damascene" and in the West in the five ways of Thomas
Aquinas." Thomas takes as his starting point various aspects of the world
of our experience (movement, causality, contingency, degrees of being,
purposefulness). He then inquires into the cause of these phenomena. In
this search for a cause it is not possible to engage in an infinite regress in
its entirety as a series, no less than in its individual members since the series
of causes is itself contingent and therefore requires an explanatory ground.
There must therefore be a first cause that is not to be understood simply
as the first member in a series of causes, but that grounds this series in its
entirety and cannot itself have its ground in a higher cause. It must therefore
be understood as self-subsistent, complete being, as that fullness of being
which we call God. Even Kant, who subjected this proof to a searching
critique, is of the opinion that it has an abiding importance. In Kant's view
the arguments are not indeed compelling, but they do impose on the mind,
so that even in the future attention will have to be paid to this proof. In
particular, the so called teleological argument from purposefulness will
always have to be mentioned with respect. It is 'the oldest, the clearest, and
that most in conformity with the common reason of humanity'.IO.
As a matter of fact, even among present-day natural scientists arguments
are to be found that resemble the cosmological argument, especially as this
talies the form of the teleological proof. The natural scientist sees a
marvellous order everywhere in nature. Admittedly, we know today that
natural laws are laws formulated by man and that they have only a very
high degree of probabiliry; on the other hand, we also know that we can
rely on these laws, for without such reliance technology, for example,
would be impossible. There must therefore be something in the realiry of
nature itself that corresponds to the designs worked out by the human
mind in the natural sciences; nature must be controlled by a rational order
102 The God-Questioll Today
that cannot originate in man but only from a mind that embraces reality
in its entirety. This consideration leads prominent natural scientists (0 a
kind of new Platonism. They see in reality the embodiment of intellectual
ideas which we cre:ltively reconstruct in our natural laws. Thus nature,
precisely as known by the natural sciences, makes it possible to accept the
existence of God. This acceptance can, of course, take many forms. The
argument just explained still leaves the way open for pantheism or
panentheism (A. Einstein), for the acceptance of a personal God (W.
Heisenberg) or for a Neoplatonic th.o/ogia /tega/iva (c. F. v. Weizsiicker).
But whatever the more specific interpretation of the relation between God
and world, these various positions are in agreement that God alone can
ground the scientific intelligibility of reality.
Nowadays it is philosophy rather than the natural sciences that chal-
lenges the proofs of God's existence. It was Kant that dealt them a first
blow from which they have still not entirely recovered. Yet the more serious
challenge to them comes today from nihilism rather than from Kant. For
this reason, for us the starring point for the proofs of God's existence can
no longer be simply an inquiry into the ground of the order in the world.
For it is not only the "what' but the "that" of reality that calls for an
explanation. The basic philosophical question is: why is there anything at
all instead of nothing?'O' With this dimension of the question Thomas
deals rather in his third way, the proof from contingency.'" For the
contingency of reality means its radical problematicalness. Everything that
is was not at one time and will at some point cease (0 bej even morc,
everything that is could also not be. Everything that is is therefore suspended
over the abyss of non· being; it is inclined tow3rd nothingness and controlled
through and through by nothingness. This nothing is not a minimally
structured, perhaps ever so weak and shadowy reality; nothing is nothing.
It is a pure concept of the understanding which we use in order to bring
out the problematical characterofbeing.lt is with this radical problematical
character that we must begin.
If we do start here, we notice something remarkable; it is precisely when
we take the possibility of not-being as our horizon that we realize the
positive character of being. Despite its vanity, being does not fall prey to
nothingness; rather, the wonder of being reveals itself to us precisely in the
face of nothingness. Precisely when confronted with the non·evidentiality
of reality we experience its reliability, solidity and beauty. Thus being
reveals a power within it that resists nothingness. This may be stated
formally in the classical principle of contradiction: insofar as it is, what is
cannot not be. Thomas says the same thing in a more substantive way:
nothing is so contingent that it does not contain within itself some element
Experience of God and Know/edge of God 103
of necessity. This element of the unconditioned in the conditioned is not
first brought home to us by a complicated proof; it is grasped unrhematically
in every knowledge of the conditioned, since it is only in the light of the
necessary that we know the conditioned as conditioned. When thus
understood, the cosmological argument is in the final analysis simply
reflecting this primordial knowledge; it is an explanation of the astonish-
ment felt at the wonder of being. IOJ
In its radical form, the proof from contingency, the cosmological
argument, thus brings us into the presence of the marvellous fact that being
is, even though (to use a paradox) non-being could exist. We are therefore
confronted with a pure 'that', the 'what' of which we are unable to grasp.IO'
We are dealing here with a limit-concept of the mind, for we grasp
something of which we can say only that we do not grasp it. We know
what it is not but not what it is. In this idea the mind that seeks to conceive
and explain reaches beyond itself. We are confronted with a groundless
ground that lies beyond our explanatory thinking. Precisely when we deal
with the ultimate ground we must put aside our explanatory thinking and
trust ourselves to the absolutely Groundless. And that which is an abyss
for our thinking is also an abyss for our conduct and our striving for
security. Man faced with groundlessness, with the abyss, is overcome by
anxiety. There is nothing to which he can hold tight in the abyss of Dasein.
He can only trust himself to the groundless Ground. When finite values
that have been absolutized collapse, when the idols fall, only God, the
Absolute, can give life stability and meaning. A conversion of mind and
conduct is needed, and only through such a conversion is knowledge of
God possible. Such a conversion does not disclose to liS God's being in
itself, but it does allow us to grasp reality in a new way as an image and
likeness of the mystery of God and thus to understand it as meaningful.
Even in its incomprehensibility, the knowledge of God is authenticated by
the fact that it makes the world and its order intelligible and thus proves
its authenticity by means of the phenomena of reality. This is due not least
to the fact that the acknowledgment of God means a demythologization
and de-ideologization of all the finite realities that have been turned into
absolutes. Man thus becomes free over against the world; he need not
become the slave of anything or anyone. The acknowledgment that God
alone is God makes it possible to be human in a human way. At this point
the cosmological argument leads into the anthropological argument.
104 The God.Questioll Today
The writers of antiquity already saw that in the spiritual nature of man there
is a presentiment and tacit presupposition that something divine exists. These
~iters ~ointed especially to (he ph,5nomenon of conscience as a testimo~
God. T e fathers of the churcti look up this nOlion and spoke of an idea of
God that is innate in the human person. lOS Terwllian even speaks of the witness
given by the a"ima 1Iaturaliter christiana (the soul that is by its nature
Christian).I06 Above all others, however, it was Augustine who T'inted:!:1
way inward and taught men (0 look for God in the heart that [Jr1 e ss u til
It n s 1m. IS own spirit man n strut regarding which he can, in
prinCiple, have no doubt. For, long before Descartes. Augustine says: 'Si eni",
(aI/or slim' (If I am deceived then I exist).'·' He finds it impossible 10 interpret
this truth as being anything but an enlightenment from God. 'Therefore we
cannot know God except by going beyond ourselves within ourselves. 'uw The
same arguments are to be found in Thomas Aquinas. According to him, in
every act of knowledge of a finite entity we apprehend infinite being, for it is
only in the light of the infinite that we can know the finite as finite. Thus in
every act of knowledge we implicitly know God. '''' In like manner our willing
strives beyond all that is finite.
In this process there cannot be an infinite regress; there must therefore be a
final goal. We are free in the face of finite goods only because we strive toward
the absolute good. All of our striving is implicitly a striving toward God; he is
loved along with everything else we love. In Scholasticism these arguments
admittedly take second place to the cosmological argument; only in the modern
age do they move into the foreground. In his third Meditation Descartes takes
3S his point of departure the idea of God that is given in human consciousness;
he cannot find the ground for this in the finite human mind itself but only in
the reality of God.'" The idea of God is of fundamental importance to
Descartes especially because he can ensure the certainty of our knowledge of
the external world only through the idea of God who embraces both man and
world. As Descartes needs God as guarantee of knowledge, so Kant needs him
as a postulate of freedom. For freedom can find the blessedness It seeks only it-
there IS a pfe-establishs d harmony bet'. cea ftccdoJii aad hJmre. Bu( (hiS In
tum-irpOsslble only If both IIJCUie and freedom are embraced by (he all-
inclusive freedom of God.'"
It was owing to the Belgian Jesuit J. Marechal that the modern approach
through subjectivity was accepted into Catholic theology. ' " Marochal
Experience of God and Knowledge of God 105
influenced K. Rahner, J. B. Lon, M. Muller, B. Welte, J. Moller, E. Coreth,
W. Kern and others. J. H. Newman had already independently pointed out the
presence in the human conscience of a real apprehension of God. II " In the
following remarks I shall adopt the approach of the Marechal school, but with
H. Frings I shall take freedom as my starting point rather than consciousness." 1
I
and the tntimte. Only because it is open to the infinite can .t lie free in
relation to the finite. For this reason there is no intra-wordly encounter
that can bring human freedom its proper fulfillment. The person can reach
fulfillment only through encounter with a freedom that is unconditioned
not only in its formal claims but also in its material possession of the good.
Only in encounter with absolute freedom can the person reach inner peace
and inner fulfillment. In every other exercise of freedom there is a hopeful
but always unsatisfied pre-apprehension of the complete realization of i
freedom. This pre-apprehension of complete fulfillment makes possible,
and supplies the light and strength for, every free act. The idea of an utterly
fulfilted-.@d all-fulfilling..@solute freed.omls th,!!s a n~dea;-it-is-a
transcen,ie.m al conditton for the possibility of freedom .
1
But is there a realicy that corresponds to this idea? As in the case of the
cosmological argument, so here we arc confronted with a limit·definition.
For the encounter with absolute freedom is outside the conditions of our
present mode of existence. If possible at all, it is possible only in death . It
would therefore be possible to speak of God only in a pre-apprehension
of 'eternal life' and the 'vision of God'. In our present life we must be
s;!.t· with fragmentary antici atio lsi! not, therd5re, enough for us
to settle for grasptng t e absolute in ever-new symbols that constantly
elude us? According to a view that is widespread today it is better to be
modest and renounce any absolute determination of meaning. But is human
freedom adequately grounded by means of an indeterminately infinite
horizon, or must it derive its ultimate grounding from a determinately
infinite goal? Only this much can be said by way of answer: if there is to
b an absolute fulfillment of . an this re uires absolute
reedom as tlon. The question then is: is there then to be an absolute
fulfi ment of meaning? (t was Christianity thatlirought into1he world
-Such an absol utefiilfillmentof meantng. In the final analysis this fulfillment
stanas or fallsmaependence on a decIsIon in which freedom decides about
itself and its own meaning. Only in fteedom can the meaning of freedom
be decided. This means, hmvever, that God as ~erfect freedom Whid!.f
brings our freedom to fulfillment cannot he d"morutrated to ar1fQne-.fFOm~
outside unless that person Intenorly opens himself to thjsuuth. The person
106 The God-Qllestion Today
must be ready to anticipate death and to surrender himself in order to gain
himself. The anthropological argument can only explicitate the alrernatives
on which a decision must be made. It can, in addition, show that the choice
of God is meaningful and even the more meaningful of the alternatives.
When all is said and done the anthropological argument boils down to
Pascal's 'wager': 'If you win you win everything, if you lose you lose
nothing. '116
The anthropological argument h.s. decisive advantage over the cosmo-
logical argument: it points not to a necessary aLsolute being, a supreme
Good, and so on, but to perfect freedom. Freedom is something the human
person can recognize only if it discloses and reveals itself in history. For
this reason, what we encounter in the anthropological argument is not an
abstr.ct God but the living God of history. Thus the anthropological
argument leads us to the proof of God's existence from the philosophy of
history.
More than any other, it was J. S. Drey, the father of the C.tholic Tiibingen
school, who, in critical and creative di:llogue with German idealism, developed
the idea of God in the perspective of universal history. I!!) In contemporary
Protestant theology W. Pannenberg has expounded a theology in the light of
universal history; in his work he h3rks back to Hegel but also depends on
Dilthcy, Heidcgger and Gadamer,lZI In its Marxist or Nco-marxist form,
Hegel's philosophy of history has exerted a wide influence on political theology
and liberation theology.1Z.! For Hegel's idealist interpretation of history,
according to which it is spirit that determines history, became problematical
to the post-idealist thinkers (the laterSchelJing, Feuerbach, Marx. Kicrkcgaard,
Experiellce of God alld Kllowledge of God 107
etc.). They acknowledged the facticity of teality as both incapable of being
detived from spirit and as nonetheless a given that cannot be ignored. K. Marx
believed that idealism should be turned upside down and that history should
be derived from changing socia-economic conditions. According co Marx,
mediation between humanity and world is through practice and more spec-
ifically through work, in which humanity shapes the world but at the same
time is determined by the world, 12J until finally humanity is entirely reconciled
to the world in the communist kingdom of freedom. '"
The Scholastic tradition, to which I attach myself here, intends to move
beyond the one sidedness of both idealism and materialism and sees itself as a
realism Of, in many cases, more specifically 3n ideal-realism.I!S It acknowledges
subject and object, spirit and mattcr, intellectual knowledge and sense experi-
ence as each having a relative independence, and thus does not simply derive
anyone of them from the others. However 1 realism, being an ideal-realism,
does see spirit as the more comprehensive reality. For in the act of intellectual
knowledge and in free practice human beings appropriate reality for them-
selves. On the one hand, this appropriation is of such a kind that in this very
act of becoming one with the world spirit sees itself as a relatively independent
entity, while at the same time acknowledging the rdative independence of
material reality. On the other hand, this relative unity and relative penetration
of matter by spirit presupposes that matter is not unqualifiedly spirit-less bur
rather has a structure that makes it analogous to spirit. w , If matter did not
'somehow' have a spiritual character and if it were not ordered to spirit, we
would be unable to discern laws of nature which are more than human
projections. The very knowledge of nature, and especially the sciences of
narure, presuppose that spirit embraces both subject and object, establishing
each of them in relative independence. This interconnection is revealed and
realized in the historical intercourse of man and world. Consequently, a
historical vision of the world signifies that reality is not simply something
objectively pregiven, but rather that the subject plays a parr in the constitution
of the world, just as the subject in its turn is mediated through the world. Thus
reality is constituted in a dialectical interplay of world and humanity.ll'
It was J. H. Newman especially who worked out this proof from probabili-
ties.I5H Newman is panicularly interested in knowledge of the concrete.
Abstract conclusions are of no real help in this area; at both ends they are as
it were suspended in the air: on the side of the first principles which they must
in every instance presuppose, and on the side of the results achieved, which
never reach down to concrete reality. When we deal with concrete knowledge,
the only possible way to proceed is through a cumulus of probabilities which,
taken together, lead to certainty. Such a procedure admittedly requires a
certain intuition, an instinct, a discernment, a power of Judgment; Newman
himself speaks of an illative sense, which acts as a light illumining our concrete
deductions. In this respect he is at onc also with the Neoplaconic and
Augustinian doctrine of knowledge, which speaks of an illumination. Pascal
speaks in a comparable way of the knowledge of the heart: 'The heart has irs
reasons of which reason knows nothing. '1$9 As examples of this kind of concrete
reasoning process Newman cites the archeologist, who from individual finds
reconstructs an entire world with its cultural life, or the lawyer who from clues
reconstructs the course of a crime, or the doctor who from particular symptoms
of illness forms a comprehensive diagnosis. In each case a degree of brilliance
and originality is required. Put more generally and in the terms I have been
using, this means: only in the light of pre-apprehension of unconditioned
meaning can we grasp the connections of meaning in the reality of our
experience.
The option for meaning that is made in faith in God proves itself adequate
to our experience of reality by virtue of the fact that since it is a pre-
apprehension of irreducible mystety, it cannot claim to be a complete
explanation of reality and all its phenomena. On the contrary, the option
for meaning that is present in faith is supremely critical of any total
explanation of the world. This option brings with ir a decided capacity for
being critical of ideologies, because ir points beyond all absolutizarions of
finite values - possessions, power, pleasure, honour, or nation, race or
class to an ever greater freedom, and thus constantly makes us frce and
keeps history open·ended. It has not only an affirmative function bur a
critical one as well. The credibility of the faith is thus shown precisely in
Experience of God and Knowledge of God 115
the fact that it has no need of suppressing any kind of experience of reality.
It has no need of putting on ideological blinders and of reducing the many-
leveled and ambiguous whole of reality to a single dimension, be this the
dimension of the positivist or the spiritualist, the pessimist or the optimist.
Faith can do justice to both the greatness and the wretchedness of man.
It is not possible apodictically to demonstrate the validity of this outlook
to anyone; it is possible, however, to bear witness to it with good arguments.
It becomes evident only to one who is ready to enter into it and change his
views; one who, in Augustine's terms, purifies his heart and, in the language
of the Bible, contemplates reality with the eyes of the heart. This means
that in faith man finds the meaning of his existence, provided that he makes
a personal commitment to faith. Faith itself rejects the philistine view that
truth and goodness will 'prevail' 'by their own power' and without a
commitment of the person. Faith is the noble and courageous decision to
accept the risks life entails and in the process to risk life itself.
Faith in God is the foundational and primordial act of the spirit. Faith
engages neither the mind alone nor the will alone, but the whole person.
Knowing and willing are thus parts of a single act of faith; in faith the two
meld into an inner unity. For this reason, faith in God is neither a purely
intellectual belief-faith nor a purely volitional decision-faith nor a matter
simply of feeling. It is an act of the whole person, an act in which alone the
person reaches fully human stature.
With this recapitulatory thesis we have reached the goal of our reflections
on the problem of natural theology. The question with which we began
was the question of the human accountability of faith in God and in his
revelation. The result of our reflections is this: man is the being who in the
experiences of his life, in his speaking and in his knowing, pre-apprehends
the absolute mystery of an unconditioned, perfect freedom. It is this
believing and hoping pre-apprehension that sets the mark of freedom on
his knowing and acting in this world. Consequently he is in quest of signs
in which the absolute mystery of an unconditioned freedom addresses him
and communicates itself to him. He is the being who lives in the presence
of the infinite mystery and who waits and hopes for the free self-revelation
of this mystery. He goes in search of signs and words in which God reveals
himself to him.
v
Knowledge of God in Faith
The result of all that has been said so far can be summed up thus: the divine
mystery is manifest in the midst of our world. We can encounter it in nature
which, being God's creature, points to its creator; in the mystery which
becomes visible within man himself; and in history which is vitalized by a
hope that looks for more than history. The mystery of man, of his world
and of history points beyond itself. To this first thesis we must, of course,
add a second: in the mystery of man and his world God is also hidden. We
can grasp the 'that' of this mystery, but its 'what' is concealed from us. As
a result the mystery remains indeterminate for pure thought and is
susceptible of varying interpretations. There are indeed arguments which
explain this mystery as an existent, holy mystery that is distinct from the
world. But a final clarity in this area is not possible to isolated thought.
We cannot penetrate the nature of the mystery, because all the similarity
that marks our statements about it is accompanied by an ever greater
dissimiliarity. The inner nature of this divine mystery is therefore hidden
from us, inaccessible, a closed book. As finite beings, all of our living,
thinking and acting is always already being done in the light of a pre-
apprehension of the infinite; but this 'infinite' is only a pre-apprehension
and not a concept; it is a limit-concept which we are unable to turn into a
concept. Our thinking is always struck dumb in its presence. If the infinite
is to be accessible to us, it must disclose and make itself known to us; it
must reveal itself. For this reason revelations are an essential parr of all
religions.!
At all times and in all religions human beings have looked for traces and
signs that would help them grope after the mystery of God. The word
"revelation' serves as a categorical expression forthosc worldly experiences,
Kltow/edge of God i/l Faith 117
areas of experience and aspects of experience in which man sees signals,
signs and symbols in which the inexpressible divine mystery is disclosing
itself to him. Revelation is therefore first of all an indirect experience, that
is, 3" experience 'in, with and under' other experiences in which God or
the divine makes its appearance (theophany) or makes his will known
(divination). Among such experiences are astonishing - i.e., wonder-
awakening - experiences in nature (storms,lightning, thunder, gales, sun,
etc.), in inter-personal encounter (especially the fascination of man and
woman for one another), in history (victories and defeats, the establishment
of cities and states, etc.); also cultural events, dreams and the interpretations
of dreams, the drawing of lots as oracles, the ordeal (understood as a
'judgment of God'), and so on. Ecstatic phenomena such as auditions and
visions playa role no less than do tradition, reAection, meditation and
contemplations.
These experiences are accessible to people generally and can nowadays
be scientifically 'explained', at least in principle, by psychology, for
example, or sociology. But for the religious man something more takes
place in, with and under these worldly experiences; he sees them as signs
and symbols of the divine mystery revealing itself. For religious man a new
horizon and all-embracing coherence makes itself known in and under
these worldly experiences which are available to everyone; for him a light
is turned on, as it were, in which the whole of reality is seen in a new way.
In the terminology of contemporary linguistic philosophy we may speak
of disclosure situations in which a particular event opens up a total meaning
and a total context.' We must therefore distinguish between the categorical
concept of revelation (revelations) in the sense of individual revelatory
events and the transcendental concept of revelation, that is, that supra-
categorical occurrence in which the mystery that holds sway in and above
all realiry discloses itself.' In this second sense of the word, revelation is
not a given but something that gives itself; not a fact, but an occurrence (a
verbal noun). And since this occurrence is the basis of religious faith, it
cannot in turn be justified. One 'has' it only insofar as one accepts to be
involved in it and opens oneself to it, and therefore in an act of religious
faith (these two words being understood here in a provisionally very broad
and general way).
Faith in this broad sense is not a categorical belief in certain suprarational
truths; rather it is the fundamental choice whereby the person opens
himself to this dimension of divine mystery and, in terms of it, understands
and encounters life, world, man and history. Religious faith does not have
its existence, therefore, at the level of a regional and categorical act; it is
neither an act of understanding alone nor willing alone nor feeling alone.
118 The God-Question Today
Religious faith exists at the level of a decision regarding life, a decision that
embraces the whole person and all his acts. It is a kind of primordial choice,
a fundamental option, a decision in behalf of a certain understanding of
reality as a whole, together with a decision to adopt a specific practical
attitude to this reality. As a responsible human act the decision is a response
to revelation; the person knows himself to be invited, challenged and
supported by this revelation. His decision is an act of primordial trust,
understood as an act of self-giving.
Biblical revelation freely acknowledges the existence of such revelatory
events outside the 'official' salvation history of the Old and New Test-
aments. The Bible tells us in various passages of 'saintly pagans' who are
witnesses to the living God: Abel, Enoch, Melchizedek, Job, and others.
After all, God 'desires all men to be saved and to come to the knowledge
of the truth' (I Tim. 2.4). For this reason the Second Vatican Council
teaches:
Throughout history even to the present day, there is found among
different peoples a certain awareness of a hidden power, which lies
behind the course of nature and the events of human life. At times there
is present even a recognition of a supreme being, or still more of a Father
... The Catholic Church rejects nothing of what is true and holy in these
religions. She has a high regard for the manner of life and conduct, the
precepts and doctrines which, although differing in many ways from her
own teaching, nevertheless often reflect a ray of that truth which
enlightens all men.'
The meaning of this general histoty of God's revelation is first made known
to us when we reach the history of special revelation, that is, the history of
revelation as set down in the Old and New Testaments. For in the general
history of revelation the picture of God remains ambiguous. Alongside
noble insights is often to be seen the grimacing of the demonic. A further
consideration is that God does not will to approach man solely as an
individual, independently of his reciprocal ties with others, but also wills
to reveal himself to man as a social and historical being. His will is to
gather human beings into a people and ro make this people the light of the
nations (lsa. 42.6).'
The theological concept of revelation is admittedly a very obscure one
and extremely hard to pin down.' The usual procedure is to start with
individual revelations or truths of revelation; by 'truths of revelation' is
meant individual truths which are not accessible to the unaided human
mind and which God, through his messengers of revelation, authoritatively
sets before human beings for their belief. This authoritarian understanding
Kllowledge of God ill Faith 119
of revelation, which is modelled on the phenomena of information and
instruction, by its nature comes into inevitable conflict with the responsible
use of human rcoson and human freedom. It is therefore significant that
more recent theology usually replaces this authoritarian understanding of
revelation with another that is based on the model of communication. In
this new context theologians speak not of revelations in the plural but of
revelation in the singular, with revelation understood not as a revelation
of objective facts but as a self-revelation of a person. What God reveals is
first and foremost not something but himself and his saving will for
humanity. In revealing himself and his mystery, he also reveals to humanity
themselves and their own mystery. Revelation is thus the determination of
the indeterminately open mystery of humaniry and its world and history.
The theological tradition was fully aware of the mysteriousness of God. From
the beginning it taught that God is invisible (invisibilis), incomprehensible
(incomprehensibilis) and ineffable (ineffabilis),23 It was obliged to defend this
teaching especially against the Eunomians, in the context of the disturbances
caused by Arius. The Eunomians claimed the possibility of an exhaustive,
adequate and comprehensive knowledge of God even in the present life. In
opposition, the fathers - especially Basil, Gregory of Nazianzus, Gregory of
Nyssa and Chrysostom - developed the doctrine of the incomprehensibility of
God." John Damascene sums up the teaching of the Greek fathers in a lapidary
statement: 'The divine nature is ineffable and incomprehensible.''' All the
great theologians of the West- Augustine, Anselm of Canterbury 1 Bonaventure,
Thomas Aquinas, Duns Scotus and, not least, Nicholas of Cusa - bear
unanimous witness that the supreme knowledge of God is (0 know that he is
unknowable. A docta ignorantia (Nicholas of Cusa) is the most that is possible
for us human beings. 26 These insights have also become part of the church's
official teaching. An avowal of the Deus invisibilis occurs even in the early
professions of faith; the confession of DeliS incomprehensibilis is to be found
above all in the Fourth Lateran Council (1215)27 and the First Vatican Council
(1869-70)."
It is admittedly striking that the theological tradition says almost nothing of
the hiddenness of God and prefers to speak of his incomprehensibility. From
the viewpoint simply of terminology there is a shift of accent here as compared
with the Bible. The tradition usually meditated on the mystery of God nor in
terms of the history of salvation and revelation but in epistemological and
metaphysical terms, seeing it as the mystery of the infinite being of God which
is beyond the reach of finite human knowledge. Such an approach did not
bring out the full depth of the biblical teaching on the hiddenness of God. In
modern times, moreover, a concept of knowledge became prevalent in which
knowing was understood as grasping or conceiving, thoroughly penetrating
KIJDIIAedge of God ill Faith 127
and even controlling. This rationalistic ideal of knowledge led to the disinte-
gration of the theological category of mystery in Enlightenment theology. In
their efforts to counter this trend, theologians developed a concept of mystery
that focused negatively on the non-conceivable and supra-rational. Mystery
was now an impassable boundary for knowledge, rather than the ultimate
overflowing fulfillment of all knowing. This led to an understanding of mystery
that was narrowly anti-rationalistic: a mystery in the strict sense (mystcrill1t1
stricte diettlm) is a truth which is absolutely inaccessible to human reason; if
we are to know it, revelation must not only set the mind in motion (so that we
might subsequently gain insight), but it, together with faith, remains the sole
abiding basis of our knowledge.
In this understanding of mystery there is a twofold narrowing of vision. 1.
The concept of mystery is defined in a purely negative way in relation to human
re::lson. The fact is overlooked that the human mind ilS such is so consciruted
that it reaches beyond itself into an impenetrable mystery. There is also a
failure to see thar the revelation which makes this mystery known as mystery
is for this very reason man's salvation. In this positive understanding of it, the
mystery of God is nor a mystery for the mind but a mystery of salvation. 2.
The concept of mystery, because it is thus negatively defined by contrast with
categorical knowledge, itself falls indirectly under the control of that ideal of
knowledge. Theologians taking this approach no longer speak of the one
mystery of God but of many mysteries (mysteria). No longer are the saving
events and the reality of salvation in their totality a mystery, but only
'the higher and nobler part of ir [Christianity), (Trinity, incarnation, grace,
rranssubstantiation, etc.}.l'l The incomprehensibility of God becomes one
divine attribute alongside others and therefore no longer even an attribute that
systematically determines and grounds the whole. In short: the mystery of God
is itself conceived categorically as one of the mysteries.
The Christian confession of faith begins with the sentence: '( believe in
God, the Father almighty." This statement sums up in a valid and binding
way the essential message of Jesus: the coming of the reign of God and
specifically of the God whom Jesus called 'my Father' and whom he taught
us to invoke as 'our Father'. At the same time, the indeterminate and
ambiguous concept 'God' is specified and interpreted by the concept
'Father'.
This interpretation, it must be admitted, hardly makes the God-question
any simpler for us today. On the contrary, the statement, so central to the
New Testament, that God is the Father of Jesus Christ and the Father of
us all, has today become difficult for many to understand and assimilate.
This observation is all the more momentous since 'father' is a primordial
word in the history of cultures and religions. In the course of history down
to the present, 'father' in this context has been understood as meaning far
more than simply ' begetter'. The father is the creative source and at the
same time the protector and nourisher of life. One's life depends on one's
father, but at the same time the father makes this life something independent
and accepts it as such. Thus the father represents the binding order of life.
He represents power and authority as well as gift, goodness, solicitude and
aid. After along prior history this picture of the father has become uncertain
to us today.' M. Horkheimer observes that there are no fathers any more,
if by 'father' you understand what society has for centuries understood by
it." In continuity with S. Freud, A. Mitscherlich speaks of a society without
fathers.' The question that arises here is an obvious one: if the experience
of a human father is lacking or if the experience is even a primarily negative
134 The Message about the God of Jesus Christ
one, how is it possible to have a positive relationship to God as Father?
How will we be able to proclaim and confess God as the Father almighty?
The background of this 'collapse of the father' (H. Tellenbach) contains
many and varied elements. From a sociological standpoint we might take
as our starting point the termination of the patriarchal form of society by
our modern industrial society that is based on exchange. When everything
is based on an exchange of services of equal value, and when everything is
geared to independence, promotion, progress, emancipation and self-
fulfillment, there is no longer any place for authority and rank, certainly
not for the authority of the ancient and the primitive. Like society at large,
the structure and culture of the family, and with these the authority of the
father, have been caught up in a process of revolutionary transformation
and even of dissolution. The problem here is not only the protest against
and rejection of the father, but the father's own renunciation of responsible
fatherhood and of any binding and responsible authority.
S. Freud analysed the problem from the standpoint of depth psychology'
and A. Mitscherlich has carried the analysis further while adding the
viewpoint of social psychology. Freud explains the ambivalent attitude to
the father as a father-complex and more specifically as an Oedipus complex.
According to Freud, this is at the heart of all neuroses. For the rebellion
against the father and the murder of the father led to a struggle of all
against all, to a chaos that begot anxiety, and to a reign of terror. As a
result, human beings embark on a search for the lost father, and endeavor
to give new life to the ideal of fatherhood. According to Freud, it is
Christian doctrine that most clearly bears witness to the primal guilty act.
Christ sacrifices his own life and thus frees the multitude of his brothers
and sisters from original sin. But in the very act by which he offers to the
Father the greatest possible atonement, he also reaches the fulfillment of
his own wishes against the Father. He himself becomes a god alongside
and even in place of the Father. The religion of the Son eliminates the
religion of the Father. These theses of Freud are more than questionable
from the historical point of view. From a psychological point of view,
however, they do make intelligible the difficulties many people have with
God as Father. They explain the God-complex (Richter)' or, to put it more
strongly, the way people suffer from God, as impressively described by,
for example, T. Moser in his book 'Poisoning by God'.' Finally, these ideas
make understandable the paradox involved in the death-of-God theology,
which boils down to the slogan: God is dead, and Jesus Christ is his only
Son. Here we have an extreme theology of the Son that has radically freed
itself from the Father-God.
The broad connections thus established by sociology and depth psycho-
God, the Father Almighty 135
logy also provide the context for the modern women's liberation movement
and its accompanying feminist theology.' The protest against the patriar-
chal form of society and against the selting of man above woman leads the
movement and the theology 10 criticize the idea of a Father-God, since
they see in this the sacralization of the patriarchal relationship and the
ideological exaltation of male superiority and of the repression of both
women and womanly values. This criticism need not lead, as it does in M.
Daly,' 10 a post-Christian religion of the mother goddesses; it may instead
lead, as it does in R. Ruether, to an emphasizing of the prophetic criticism
that has for its point of departure the biblical understanding of God as
Father. 10 This prophetic criticism is based on the idea that God is the Father
of all human beings and that he alone is truly the Father (Matt. 23.9). If
this is so, then there must be no oppression of one human being by another,
since all of them are brothers and sisters. Of course, they are brothers and
sisters only so long as they have God as their common Father. Viewed in
this light, feminist theology is a challenge 10 reflect more profoundly and
more critically on the idea of father and gain a new grasp of its meaning.
The sociological and psychological approaches already bring us 10 the
threshold of the radically metaphysical dimension of the father problem.
The problem must be underslOod, in the final analysis, against the back-
ground of the modern philosophy of emancipation, of which the emancip-
ation of women is but one aspect, though an important and typical one."
Emancipation in the sense of liberation from all imposed dependencies is
a watchword that applies to the whole modern age and its experience of
reality; it is also a fundamental his tori co-philosophical category that helps
characterize the modern processes of enlightenment and liberation." For
while emancipation in Roman law meant the graciously granted liberation
of slaves or the release of the adult son from his father's authority, it has
come 10 mean in the modern age the autonomous self-liberation of the
human person or social groups (peasants, citizens, proletarians, Jews,
Blacks, women, colonial territories, etc.) from intellectual, legal, social or
political tutelage, from discrimination, or from a domination perceived as
unjust. The extent 10 which at the end of the modern age emancipation
has become an all-embracing ideological category may be seen from K.
Marx's definition: 'Every emancipation is a restoration of the human
world and of human relationships 10 man himself.'1.1
We must not, of course, fail to realize that behind the philosophy of
emancipation and its accompanying loss of the father there ultimately lies
a new form of gnosis. By gnosis I mean here an altitude of mind that can
develop in varied cultural contexts. It was an attitude that became
particularly dangerous to Christianity during the cultural collapse of the
136 The Message abol/t the God of jesl/s Christ
Hellenistic world in the second century after Christ. The world was no
longer experienced as an ordered, harmonious cosmos, as it had been in
the dassical age of Greece, but rather as alien, sinister and menacing.
Anxiety about life became widespread; the basic mood was a sense of being
lost in the present world. The experience of alienation led to an attempt to
break out of a cosmos and its structures that were felt to be a prison, and
to an abandonment of the material world in order to rescue the truly
divine in man. H. Jonas gives the following summary description of this
Promethean rebellion on the part of man as he seeks to free himself from
the traditional father-religions:
That turning-point in the history of religions (or myths) was in truth a
real revolt against the gods a~d a collapse of the gods, and the establish-
ment (dear in terms of myth) of a new dominion; in allegorical symbols
we experience on the scene of world-history the replacement of the old,
powerful father-religions by religions of the son, the replacement of
cosmic religion by acosmic religion: 'man' or the 'son of man' is exalted
above the ancient gods and becomes the supreme god or the divine center
of a religion of salvation ... The great gods who arc fathers of the world,
and who themselves had come to the fore in historical time and were
characteristic of a millennial stage of human culture, now everywhere
abdicate their power."
G. Bornkamm observes: 'Notthe least reason why the Christian faith stood
up against the drag of this religious movement and did not succumb to it
is that due to the crucified Jesus who was Son it had a renewed faith in
God as Father and therefore could not abandon the world which is God's
creation. 'IS
We can hardly be mistaken if we daim that today again Christianity is
undergoinga similar test. Modern science and technology and the industrial
society which these have made possible have eroded the concept of a
metaphysical order. They were a gigantic attempt on man's part to
understand and control the world and man's material, physical, biological,
sociological and economic dependencies. At the end of this development
man is in the position of the sorcerer's apprentice who can no longer free
himself from the spirits he has summoned up.'· The world that he himself
projected and constructed has become a barely intelligible system with its
unavoidable constraints; it has become a kind of second-order destiny.
Once again anxiety is spreading abroad, and the anxiety often turns
into a cynical contempt for the world. Nietzsche foresaw the nihilistic
consequences of the death of God, and said: 'There is no more up or down,
we plunge in all directions and wander as through an infinite nothing.' ''
God, the Father Almighty 137
In this situation in which all thinking based on a metaphysical order has
collapsed Christianity must raise anew the question of the ground of all
reality, the ground from which everything comes and which sustains
everything and assigns everything its measure. Christianity must learn once
again to affirm the world as coming from God's positive creative will and
10 defend it and man's natural ties 10 it against a radical denigration of
them. Only in this way is it possible 10 resist the loss of all norms, direction
and stability and 10 re-establish the security within which alone freedom
is possible and meaningful. We must therefore reflect anew on the first
article of the faith and ask ourselves what it means to confess God as the
Father almighty.
Taking as its point of departure the idea of vocation and election, the Old
Testament is able to make ils own in a critical way the legitimate point of
the mYlh. For the concept of covenant points back to the concept of
creation. God's sovereign call and choice presupposes that he is the master
of all reality, that is, that he is the Father who has created everything (Deut.
32.6; Mal. 2.10) and that he is therefore ground and lord of all reality (lsa.
45.9f.; 64.7). However, the father motif that is based on the idea of the
covenant does not simply point back [0 creation; it also points forward.
Only in the final age will people say to the children of Israel: 'You are "the
sons of the living God'" (Has. 2.1; d. II Sam. 7.14; Ps. 89.27). In the Bible,
therefore, the historical basis of the father motif is to be seen not only in
the idea of origin and of the authority of what is ancient, venerable and
primeval, but also in the idea of the future and of hope in the new. This
primordially new reality consists ultimately in the forgiving and merciful
paternal love of God (Has. 1 1.9; Isa. 63.16;Jer. 31.20). 'As a father pities
his children, so the Lord pities those who fear him' (Ps. 103.13). Israel can
always call upon this merciful love of the Father with the repeated cry:
'Thou art our Father' (lsa. 63.15f.; 64.7f.). The devout Jew of the Old
Testament is already able to call upon this Father-God as 'Father' with
great reverence and confidence (Sir. 23.1; 51.10). God is in a special way
'Father of the fatherless' (Ps. 68.6). It can be said of him that even if 'my
father and my mother have foresaken me ... the Lord will take me up' (Ps.
27.10).
The aspects which I have just pointed out show that the covenantal idea
of God as Father can be turned in a prophelic and critical way against the
concrete fathers of this world. In all truth the dignity of father belongs to
God alone. It is not any earthly father bUI God, from whom all falherhood
140 The Message about the God of Jesus Christ
is derived (Eph. 3.15 ), who defines what true fatherhood is. According to
the Bible, therefore, our talk of God as Father is not simply a sacral
apotheosis of paternal authority; God's fatherhood, being the source, is
also the norm of paternal authority and the critical standard by which it
is judged. At the same time, any sexist misunderstanding of the religious
concept of father is also excluded. This is clear, for example, from the fact
that the Old Testament can also translate the Father's loving mercy into
the language of womanliness and motherhood. (lsa. 66.13).
The new form which the Old Testament gives to the father motif as
compared with the form it has in the history of religions brings out what
is proper and specific to Old Testament faith in God: namely, God's
freedom and sovereignty, and his transcendence which is a freedom in love
and therefore manifests itself historically as a descent into immanence and
as a being-with-us. As Father, God is not only the origin but also embraces
present and future; he is a God of history. Judgmental distance and
redemptive nearness, judgment and grace, omnipotence and merciful
forgiveness: in the Old Testament father motif all these are integrated into
a unity-in·tension. The tension point beyond the uniry and presses for a
final clarification.
The concept 'reign of God' is a relatively late abstract formation for the verbal
statementthatJahweh is "ord or King iPs. 47.6-9; 93.8; etc.). The idea ofthe
reign of God does not therefore, have to do, primarily with a kingdom
understood in spatial terms, but with the historical manifestation of God's
lordship through events, with the revelation of his glory and with the proof of
God, the Father Almighty 141
his divinity. In the final analysis the reign of God represents a radicalizing
interpretation of the first commandment and its justification through God's
control of histoty: 'I am the Lord your God ... You shall have no other gods
before me' (Ex. 20.2f.). For this reason, the message of the coming of God's
reign is directly and inseparably connected in the preaching of Jesus with a call
to conversion and faith (Mark 1.15).
Because the reign of God and its coming are the doing and concern of God
alone, they cannot be merited, caused or coerced by either religious and ethical
achievements or by political struggles. The reign of God is given (Matt. 21.43;
Luke 12.32) and bestowed as an inheritance (Luke 22.29). This state of affairs
finds its clearest expression in the parables: the coming of God's reign in
God's own marvelous accomplishment and without relation to any human
expectations, resistances, calculations or plans. We cannot 4bring it to pass' by
conservative or progressive activity, by any evolutionary or revolutionary
practice; all we can do is prepare for it by conversion and faith. Only in exterior
and interior poverty, weakness and powerlessness can the human being be
attuned to the godliness of God. He can only pray: 'Thy kingdom come' (Matt.
6.10; Luke 11.2). One who thus believes and prays may experience the
omnipotence of God (Mark 9.23); therefore the principle holds that he who
prays already receives (Luke 11.9f.; Matt. 7.71.). Prayer made in faith is not
only assured of a future hearing; it itself is already an anricipation of the reign
of God because it makes room for God to be Lord and to act. It is not academic
discourse about God but talking with God or prayer that is for Jesus the vital
context (Sit: im Leben) of authentic theology.
The opposition which Judaism raised against this christological use of the Old
Testament has been taken up in :1 new way in modern biblical criticism. The
majority of critics are of the opinion that the messianic hope plays only a
secondary role and represents only a secondary current of thought in the Old
Testament, and is by no means to be regarded as thecenter of the Old Testament
or the key to its understanding. What is central to the Old Testament is rather
the promise that God himself will be the salvation of his people; the focus of
interest is in the coming of God and his kingdom and not in the coming of the
Messiah. By and large, modern biblical criticism has also adopted a second
presupposition, namely, that while Jesus understood himself wholly against
the background of the Old Testament, he did not think of himself as the
Messiah and did not proclaim himself to be the Messiah." If these two
principles of biblical criticism are valid, then the question becomes unavoidable
of (he continuiry between the Old Tesramcm and the New, and even between
Jt."Sus and Christi.miry, as the latter is already attested in the New Testament.
Does Jesus even still belong to Judaism, as M. Buber and R. Bultmann both
claim, though on the basis of very differenr presuppositions?!."' Moreover, what
164 The Message about the God of Jesus Christ
legitimacy has Christianity, if it cannot appeal either to the Old Testament or
to Jesus himself?
Thus all the major lines of Old Testament tradition converge in the
expectation of a Messiah: Davidism, prophetism, sapiential theology and
apocalyptic. All these movements find their fulfillment in Jesus the Christ,
the poor, non-violent, humble and suffering Messiah, the coming Son of
Man, who as the Logos is Wisdom itself. In him God has definitively
brought to fulfillment the promise regarding Zion; in him God has
definitively entered into history in order to establish his rule as a kingdom
of freedom in love. Jesus Christ sums up and at the same time goes beyond
the Old Testament hope." What, then, is new and specifically Christian in
the New Testament?
What is new about the message of Jesus is not only its content but also the
fact that he linked his 'cause', namely, the kingdom of God, indissolubly
with his own person. We hear over and over of 'now', 'today' (d. Luke
4 .21; 1O.23f.; Matt. 11.5). The connection between the decision one makes
regarding his person and message and the eschatological decision of the
Son of Man when he comes for judgment is dearest in Mark 8.38: 'For
whoever is ashamed of me and my words in this adulterous and sinful
generation, of him will the Son of man be ashamed, when he comes in the
glory of his Father with the holy angels. ' In the decision of faith or unbelief
the eschatological judgment is already being made. In the ministry,
preaching and whole person of Jesus God's 'cause' is already present and
Jestls Christ, SOli of God 169
at work; in Jesus the condescending movement of God, which can already
be seen in the entire Old Testament, reaches its climax. In Jesus, God has
definitively entered the time and space of this world. For this reason
the Davidic expectations of an eschatological kingship as well as the
expectations of the prophets, have been fulfilled in Jesus.
Even though Jesus does not explicitly claim christological titles, and
even though in particular he does not speak of himself as the Son of God,
the claim does find indirect and implicit expression of a very emphatic
kind. This indirect christology of Jesus himself can be shown in various
ways.
A first way starts from the preaching oEjesus. At first glance Jesus comes
on the scene like a rabbi, a prophet or teacher of wisdom. But closer
examination discovers some characteristic differences between him and
the three groups named. The contemporaries ofJesus were obviously aware
of the difference, for they asked one another in astonishment: 'What is
this? A new teaching! With authority ... ' (Mark 1.22,27; etc.). When
Jesus contrasts the words of the Old Testament with his own 'But I say to
you ... '(Matt. 5.22,28; etc.), he is not only givinga binding interpretation
of the Old Testament Law but at the same time going beyond it. His
formula 'But I say to you ... ' sets his words alongside and even above
what 'was said to the men of old', that is, what God himself had said under
the former covenant. In his 'But I say to you ... ' Jesus is thus claiming to
speak the definitive word of God. And in uttering this definitive words he
speaks differently from the prophets. He never says, like the prophets;
'Thus says the Lord', 'Oracle of Yahweh'. Unlike the prophets, Jesus does
not distinguish his own words from the word of God_ He says simply:
'Amen, amen, I say to you.' He evidently understands himself to be the
mouth of God, the voice of God. This is a claim without parallel in Judaism.
A second way of bringing out the implicit christology of Jesus himself
takes for its starting point the ministry and conduct of Jesus. One of the
best attested traits of Jesus' ministry is that he used to eat at table with
sinners and tax collectors; in other words, that he associated with those
who at that times were labeled as godless. He was therefore abused as the
companion of sinners and tax collectors (Matt. 11.19). This conduct on
the part of Jesus had only an indirect connection with his criticism of
society or with social changes. In the East a sharing of the table meant a
sharing of life; in Judaism, it meant in particular a communion in the sight
of God. Every meal was ultimately a prefiguration of the eschatological
meal and of eschatological communion with God. The meals Jesus takes
with sinners and tax collectors are therefore eschatological meals, anticipa-
tory celebrations olthe banquet of salvation in the final age. When therefore
170 The Message about the God of jesus Christ
Jesus accepts sinners to share his table with him, he is indirectly accepting
them into communion with God. Once again, then, this behavior of Jesus
toward sinners implies an unparalleled christological claim. Jesus himself
voices it indirectly: when he is attacked for his behavior toward sinners
(Luke 15.2), he narrates the parable of the lost son, which is really a parable
of the Father's forgiving love (Luke 15.11-32). Jesus thus identifies his
own activiry with the action of God toward sinners. Jesus acts as one who
stands in God's place. In him and through him God's love and mercy
become real here and now. It is not a long step from this to what Jesus says
in John: 'He who has seen me has seen the Father' Uohn 14.9).
There is still a third way of bringing out the implicit christology of the
earthly Jesus. It can hardly be denied that as a historical fact Jesus gathered
a band of disciples and, in particular, that the choice of the Twelve goes
back to him. At first glance, Jesus is here acting simply like a Jewish rabbi
who gathers a group of disciples. But there are significant differences
between discipleship under the rabbis and discipleship under Jesus. The
difference is already clear from the fact that one could not ask Jesus to be
accepted as a disciple; Jesus chose with sovereign freedom 'those whom he
desired' (Mark 3.13). Furthermore, there is no question, as there was with
the rabbis, of a temporary master·disciple relationship that would last until
the one-time disciple became a teacher in his turn. There is but one teacher
(Matt. 10.24f.; 23.8). Therefore the ties binding the disciples of Jesus to
their master are more extensive than with 'the rabbis: they share his
journeying, his homelessness, and his dangerous destiny. There is an
in divided community of life, a sharing of destiny for better or for worse.
The decision to follow Jesus means a breaking of all other ties; it means
'leaving everything' (Mark 10.28); ultimately one risks one's life and even
the gallows (Mark 8.34). Such a radical and wholehearted following
amounts to a confession of Jesus and thus implies a christology. The
christology implied in following also shows that not only is there a material
continuity of confession in the pre-Easter and post-Easter periods but also
that there is a sociological continuity between the pre-Easter and post-
Easter groups of disciples.
Finally, there is a fourth way. The most important pointer tp an indirect
christology in Jesus himself is the way he addresses God. It can hardly be
denied that Jesus called God Abba and that the manner in which he did so
was characteristic of him. Also significant is the fact that he always
distinguishes between 'my Father' (Mark 14.36 par.; Matt. 11.25 par.)
and 'your Father' (Luke 6.36; 12.30,32) or 'your heavenly Father' (Mark
11.25 par.; Matt. 23.9). He never includes himself with his disciples by
saying 'our Father'. The Lord's Prayer IS not evidence to the contrary,
Jesus Christ, Son of God 171
because he begins it by saying: 'When you pray, say ... '(Luke 11.2; Matt.
6.9). This differentiated usage is maintained throughout all the strata of
the New Testament down to the classical formulation in the gospel of
John: 'My Father and your Father' Uohn 20.17). There are good reasons
for asserting that the substance of this differentiation goes back to Jesus
himself. This exclusive 'my Father' points to an incommunicable and
unique relationship between Jesus and God. The linguistic usage renders
perceptible his special consciousness of being Son. Whether or not he
explicitly claimed the title 'Son' for himself, the way in which he speaks
implicitly says that although all are the children of God (Matt. 5.9, 45), he
is God's Son in a special and unique way. He is the Son, who alone makes
of us the sons and daughters of God.
This indirect approach to the 50n-christology is not simply a new
argument and justification for the traditional dogmatic christology, which
is also the christology contained in the post-Easter testimony of the New
Testament. Rather we have here, even materially, a new christological
starting point. This is so in two respects. First, we no longer start, like the
two-nature christology of Chalcedon, with the question of the relation
between the human and divine natures in Jesus Christ; rather, we see the
two-nature doctrine as indirectly and in its substance grounded in the
relationship of Jesus to his Father." In his being as Son Jesus has his radical
origin in God and radically belongs to God. The turning of Jesus to the
Father implies the prior turning of the Father to Jesus. The relation ofJesus
to the Father implies the prior relation of the Father to him, the self-
communication of God to him. The subsequent 50n-christology is therefore
simply the interpretation and translation of what is secretly present in
Jesus' obedience as Son and his self-surrender as Son. What Jesus lived out
ontically before Easter is interpreted ontologically after Easter. But there
is more. The new approach provided by an indirect christology makes it
possible, secondly, to link christology and soteriology right from the start.
Jesus is the mode in which the self-communicating, self-outpouring love
of God exists on the human scene; he is this for us. The being of Jesus is
thus inseparable from his mission and his service; conversely, his service
presupposes his being. Being and mission, ontological christology and
functional christology cannot be played off against each other; they cannot
even be separated from each other, for they condition each other. The
function of Jesus, his being-there (Dasein) for God and for others, is at the
same time his very being.
The indirect christology ofthe earthly Jesus is thus a personal summation
of his message about the coming reign of God as the reign of love. He is
this reign of God in his very person. Henceforth there can be no more talk
172 The Message abollt the God of Jeslls Christ
of God that ignores Jesus; in Jesus God defines himself in an eschatological
and definitive way as the Father of Jesus Christ; Jesus therefore belongs to
the eternal being of God. In his person he is the definitive interpretation of
the will and being of God. In him God has entered history once and for all.
Finally, I must mention a third and perhaps decisive novelty about the
ministry and preaching of Jesus. The revolutionary novelty and even
scandal of the cross for Jews and Gentiles alike (I Cor. 1.23) becomes clear
to us if we consider the popular Jewish messianic expectation and the
abhorrence felt by Romans at execution by crucifixion.'· Many exegetes
today are admittedly of the opinion that Jesus himself did not understand
his death as a saving event." On the other hand, we may point to the fact
that his violent death was a consequence of his ministry and preaching.
Jesus probably glimpsed the possibility of a violent end, for the hostility of
his adversaries and their intention to trap him were only too clear. He had
before his eyes the fate of the prophets and especially the fate of the Baptist.
He knew the Old Testament songs about the Servant of God in Second
Isaiah and the late Jewish ideas about the death of the just man. (Wisdom
2.20) and the expiatory significance attached to it (II Macc. 7.18, 37f.; II
Macc. 6.28f.; 17.22). Since he understood his entire existence as one of
obedience to the Father and service to human beings, it is certainly natural
to think that he made use of these pregiven ways of interpreting his own
destiny. How else are we to explain that the primitive community at a very
early stage preached the cross as an act of redemption? This was done
especially in the tradition about the Last Supper (Mark 10.22-25 par.; t
Cor. 11.23-25) and in the saying about ransom in Mark 10.45. In their
basic content these pericopes most likely go back to Jesus himself.42
The basileia message of Jesus and a soteriological understanding of his
death are in no way exclusive of one another. On the contrary, the violent
death of Jesus is as it were the concrete form taken by the breakdown of
the old aeon. Here God's omnipotence is completely absorbed into outward
weakness; here God takes the human condition, the human destiny, upon
himself, with all its consequences. He enters into abandonment by God.
There is no longer any human situation that is in principle cut off from
God and salvation. To that extent the death of Jesus on the cross is
not only the extreme consequence of his courageous ministry but a
recapitulation and summary of his message. The death of Jesus on the cross
is the final elucidation of what had been his sole concern: the coming of
the eschatological reign of God. This death is the form in which the reign
of God becomes a reality under the conditions of the present aeon; it is the
form in which the reign of God comes to pass in human weakness, riches
in poverty, love in abandonment, fullness in emptiness, life in death.
Jesus Christ, SOli of God 173
(c) The Son-ehristology of the New Testament
Soon after the death of jesus the New Testament was proclaiming that
after his ignominious death on the cross jesus was established as Son of
God through his resurrection and exaltation (Rom. 1.3f.) and that he who
is in the form of God (Phil. 2.6) is the Son whom God had sent into the
world (Gal. 4.4; Rom. 8.3). For Paul the message about the Son of God is
the central content of his gospel; he describes the latter simply as 'the
gospel concerning his [i.e., God's JSon' (Rom. 1.3 ). Finally, in the Prologue
of his Gospel john sums up the New Testament profession of faith by
proclaiming jesus Christ as the Word of God that in the very beginning is
with God and in fact is God Uohn 1.1) and that in the fullness of time
became flesh (1.14). At the end 01 his Gospel there is this comprehensive
confession: 'My Lord and my God' Uohn 20.28).
The question at this point is: 'how could such a development take place?
Liberal theology, represented by, for example, A. von Harnack, saw the
development as a suppression of the historical Christ by the pre-existent Christ
of speculative and dogmatic theology. 'The living Christ seems to have
been transformed into a confession of faith, and devotion to Christ into
Christology.''' Harnack therefore called for a return to the simple gospel of
jesus. According to the history of religion school, whose theses R. Bultmann
recapitulated in an impressive way;~01 the adoption of motifs from Hellenistic
piety and philosophy brought about a Hellenization of the gospel, a process
that has begun even in the New Testament itself.·' Scholars pointed variously
to parallels from Greek mythology orphilosophy or from the mystery religions,
to ideas of 'divine men' (theio; a"dres), or, above all, to the gnostic myth of
redemption. All these theses have since proved to be pseudo-scientific myths
inspired by fantasy. Our sources for the mystery religions and gnosticism come
only from the second and third centuries AD; there is no justification for
projecting these witnesses back into the first century and postulating an
influence on early Christianity; there is better reason to ask whether on the
contrary the sources in question were not influenced by Christianity.
The situation is different with regard to influences from the world of the
Old Testament and judaism. The title 'Son of God' has a firm basis in the royal
messianism of the Old Testament.oIf> For this reason it is not an accident that
the two royal psalms, Ps. 2 and 110, could become the most important supports
for the early church's christological proof from scripture. Ps. 2.7 says: 'You
are my son. Today have I begotten you' (d. Ps. 110.3). In the New Testament,
too, the Davidic sonship of the Messiah and the divine sonship of jesus are
seen as closely connected (Rom. 1.3f.; Luke 1.32-35). jesus' characterization
of himself as Son of Man inevitably called attention as well to the statements
in the apocalyptic literature about exaltation and pre·existence, as these are
to be found in the metaphorical discourses of the Book of Enoch and IV
174 The Message about the God of Jesus Christ
Esdras. 47 Most important, of course, is the idea of wisdom as a preacxisrenr
hypostasis that is already present at the creation (Prov. 8.22ff.) and that looks
everywhere for a place to dwell but finds it only in Israel on Zion (Sir. 24.8-12).
The parallels to the idea of the Logos in the Prologue of John's Gospel
are obvious." The writings of the Jewish religious philosopher, Philo of
Alexandria, show how easy it was to connect these Jewish specu13tions on
wisdom with Greek philosophical ideas. As a result all the essential components
of New Testament christology were prepared in the Judaism of the inter-
testamental period.
But the New Testament christology is not simply reducible to such Jewish
ideas. It is completely original and represents an unparalleled innovation."
The message of the exaltation and pre-existence of the crucified Jesus was
an intolerable scandal to both Jews and Greeks. The material basis of New
Testament christology can therefore be looked for only in the preaching
and ministry of the e3rthly Jesus himself as well as in the experience of
Easter that overcomes the scandal of the cross and in the message thereof.
According to the conviction of almost all exegetes the message of the
resurrection and exaltation of the crucified Jesus must be considered
the point of departure for the development of christology in the New
Testament.
Given this point of departure the Son-christology of the New Testament
was inevitable. The categories supplied by the history of religions served a
secondary purpose: to help give expression to an originally Christian
matter. The idea of pre-existence, in particular, proved to be not only
helpful but even necessary in the effort to hold fast to the unique filial
relationship of Jesus to God as expressed in his use of 'Abba' in addressing
God. Only the idea of pre-existence could guarantee that in the earthly life
and in the cross and resurrection of Jesus God himself was involved
and that in Jesus Christ God was revealing himself definitively and
eschatologically. The eschatological character of the person and work of
Jesus made it necessary, in the very narure of things, to say that Jesus
belongs to the eternal being of God. Otherwise Jesus could not have
'defined' God in an eschatological and definitive way. Furthermore, only
thus could the universal significance of Jesus Christ as the fulfillment not
only of the Old Testament but of all reality have been adequately expressed.
This makes it clear that in the Son of God statements of the New
Testament we are dealing not with speculations inspired by theory but with
soteriologically motivated assertions in which the issue is the definitiveness
and unsurpassableness as well as the universaliry of salvation. It must be
maintained that Jesus Christ is the only Son of God, who makes us in turn
jesus Christ, 5011 of God 175
the children of God (Rom. 8.14-17; Gal. 3.26; 4.5); in him God has
predestined us '10 share in the being and image of his Son' (Rom. 8.29).
These theses can easily be substantiated with the help of the most
important passages embodying the Son-chrislOlogy of the New Testament.
At the same time and by the same means it can be shown that this Son-
christology is not simply a late product of New Testament development
but is already present in the earliest, pre-Pauline strata of the New
Testament. According 10 the general judgment of exegetical scholarship
Rom. 1.3f. is such a pre-Pauline confession of faith: 'his Son, who was
descended from David according 10 the Aesh and designated or: constituted
Son of God in power according 10 the Spirit of holiness by his resurrection
from the dead'.'°This ancient 'two-stage chrislOlogy' contrasts, on the one
hand, the messianic dignityuf Jesus which has 10 do with the earthly hislOry
of salvation and is based on Davidic descent, and, on the other hand, his
divine glory and 10 that extent his divine sonship which are based on his
resurrection from the dead. Expressed here is the idea that because he is
Son of God Jesus fulfills the messianic hope of the Old Testament in a
qualitatively new way that is mediated by cross and resurrection. As the
Messiah on the cross he is also the Messiah in the Spirit. The striking thing
is that this ancient confession as yet says nothing explicitly about pre-
existence. Paul, who already presupposes the idea of pre-existence, inter-
prets the ancient confessional formula by using 'Son' as title of the subject
even of the first part of the confession. He is clearly saying that Jesus does
not first become Son by reason of the resurrection but is already the Son
even during his earthly life. But this assertion of pre-existence is not an
invention of Paul the Apostle; he has taken it from the tradition. This is
shown by the so·called mission formulas in Rom. 8.3 and Gal. 4.4 (d. also
John 3.17; (John 4.9f., 14). Talk olthe Son being sent by the Father clearly
presupposes the pre-existence of the Son.
The most important pre-Pauline testimony is the hymn 10 Christ in Phil.
2.6-11. 'Who, though he was in the form of God, did not count equality
with God a thing to be grasped, but emptied himself, taking the form of a
servant [or: slavel, being born in the likeness of men. And being found in
human form he humbled himself and became obedient unto death, even
death on a cross.''' There can be no question here of my going into all the
complicated exegetical problems which this passage raises. There is a broad
consensus among exegetes that this hymn 10 Christ is pre-Pauline. Generally
speaking, the exegetes are also in agreement that the self-emptying is of
the pre-existent Christ and not of the earthly Jesus. The incarnation of the
pre-eXlSlent Christ thus begins a journey of self-emptying that reached
its completion on the cross; the incarnation is understood in the light of
176 The Message aboul the God of Jesus Christ
the cross and as directed to the cross. The decisive question, then, is what
is meant by the self-emptying (kenosis). In the literal sense the term
ekenolhelt means 'he made himself empty'; a person described in the New
Testament as keltos is one who is empty-handed because he has been
deprived of something he previously possessed. A person who makes
himself em pry gives up his wealth and becomes poor. The hymn co Christ
is therefore in agreement with II Cor. 8.9, where it is said of Jesus Christ
that 'though he was rich, yet for your sake he became poor, so that by his
poverty you might become rich'. The riches of Jesus Christ are described
by the term morphe theO/t, and his poverry by morphii dolt/olt. The term
morphe may mean either the outward phenomenal form or visible figure,
or else the being itself. A third interpretation, often offered at the present
rime, which explains morphe as meaning status, position, attitude, and so
on, is inferred from biblical thought patterns, real or supposed, rather than
documented lexicographic.lIy. Since it is not possible to spe.k of God
h.ving .n outward form and since in the New Testament the verb
melamorphousthai always refers to a transformation in the orderof being,
it is hard to avoid concluding that the present p.ssage is speaking of
'essential form'.
This important text, then, is speaking of Jesus Christ who from eternity
existed in the essential form of God, but then emptied himself to the extent
of suffering death on the cross and was finally exalted co be Kyrios i.e.,
world-ruler possessed of divine rank. The christology of pre-existence .nd
the christology of cross or kenosis and exaltation are united in • v.st drama
that embraces heaven and earth. Chriscology here emerges within the
framework of soteriology. That is, because the pre-existent Christ, God's
equal, in ftee obedience takes upon himself the lot of a slave, anankii
(necessity) or inevitable domination by the cosmic powers is replaced by
freedom under the new Lord of the world. There is thus a change of reigns,
but a change accomplished not by violence but through the obedience and
weakness of the cross.
Pauline assertions about pre-existence are thus located within a firm
prior tradition. An important fact about these assertions is that Paul is not
interested in formal and abstract pre·existence as such. Rather he fills the
statements about pre-existence with a specific content; in every case the
statements are sotetiological statements. This is shown by the consecutive
clause that is at times added to the mission formula and clarifies the
soteriological significance of the statement about pre-existence; these
clauses assert liberation from the power of sin and the establishment of a
relation of filiation between human beings and God. The fact thaI the
mission is in the nesh and under the law shows that early chriscology was
Jeslls Christ, SOli of God 177
not solely a christology of the incarnation but also and above all a
christology of the cross. The handing-over formulas, which are analogous
to the mission formulas, also make this point clear (Rom. 8.32; Gal. 2.20;
d. John 10.11; 15.13; IJohn 3.16).52 They show that the point to be made
when pre-existence is asserted is that in Jesus Christ God's eternal self-
giving love has entered once and for all into history in order that this self-
disclosure of God's freedom in love may ground the freedom of the children
of God. In the incarnation of the Son of God an exchange therefore took
place: 'He was rich, yet for your sake he became poor, so that by his
poverty you might become rich' (II Cor. 8.9; d. Gal. 4.5; 2.19; 3.13; II
Cor. 5.21; Rom. 7.4; 8.3f.). The soteriological and universal cosmic
significance of the assertion of Jesus as Son of God is again taken up and
developed in the hymn to Christ in Col. 1.15-17. Jesus Christ is here said
to be 'the image of the invisible God, the first-born of all creation'; 'All
things were created through him and for him. He is before all things, and
in him all things hold together.''' Behind this statement about Christ as
mediator of creation there is once again a soteriological concern; the .:lim
is to prove the universality of the salvation given through Christ and at the
same time to assert that all other 'principalities and powers' have been
deposed and that we are bound to no other Lord save Jesus Christ and are
to live in the world with a Christian freedom.
The most important statements of a Son-christology and the ones most
momentous for subsequent development are in the writings of John. The
Prologue" of the Fourth Gospel already makes three basic assertions:
Verse la begins: 'In the beginning was the Word.' Here it is said that the
Word which became flesh in Jesus Christ (1.14) already was in the
beginning, that is, that it exists in an absolutely timeless and eternal way.
This is why Jesus Christ can say of himself in the Fourth Gospel: 'Before
Abraham was, I am' Uohn 8.58). Verse Ib continues in greater detail:' And
the Word was with God.' This being with God is described in 1.18 as a
personal communion, a communion in glory (17.5), love (17.24) and life
(5.26), so that in the Fourth Gospel Jesus can say of himself: 'I and the
Father are one' (10.30). A climax is reached in verse Ie: 'And the Word
was God.' 'God' without an article is a predicate here and not the subject;
it is therefore not identical with ho theos, of which we spoke earlier. What
is being said is that the Word is divine in nature. Despite all the distinction
between God and Word and tWO are united by the one divine nature. But
this statement about essence is ordered to a soteriological statement. For,
as the eternal divine Word, Christ is truly light and life (1.4). In him is
revealed therefore the origin and goal of all reality.
What the Prologue presents in a kind of programmatic fashion is often
178 The Message abollt the God of Jeslls Christ
the subject of discourse in the gospel that follows. At the climax of the
dispute berween Jesus Christ and the 'Jews' the statement is made that 'I
and the Father are one' (10.30). And at the end everything is once again
summed up in Thomas' profession of faith: 'My Lord and my God' (20.28).
finally, in 20.31 we are told that the purpose of the entire Gospel is 'that
you may believe that Jesus is the Christ, the Son of God, and that believing
you may have life in his name'. In like manner the First Letter of John ends
with the statement: This is the true God and eternal life' (5.20).
It is neither possible nor necessary to present in detail all the New
Testament statements having to do with a Son-christology: that Jesus
Christ is the image of God (Rom. 8.29; II Cor. 4.4; Col. 1.15), the radiant
light of God's glory and the perfect copy of his nature (Heb. 1.3), the
epiphany of God (I Tim. 3.16; II Tim. 1.9f.; Titus 3.4). There is one and
the same theme in all these statements: Jesus Christ is the word and image
of the Father, and in him the hidden God is revealed to us. But the revelation
is a revelation on the cross, a revelation in hiddenness; God reveals his
power in weakness, his omnipotence is at the same time an omnipatience
or omni-suffering; his eternity is not a rigid immutabiliry but movement,
life and love that communicates itself to that which is distinct from it. The
Son-christology thus implies both a new interpretation of God and a
change in our reality. The revelation, krisis and even revolution in the
picture of God leads to the krisis, transformation and redemption of the
world. It is only tOO easy to understand that this new picture of God, as
it has emerged in Jesus Christ, could not but lead to violent opposition
and that its implications could be brought to light only through lengthy
debate_
(d) The expla1lation of the divine sonship ofJeslls Christ in the history of
dogma and theology
It is not possible to provide here a complete picture of the development of
christological teaching in the early church. I must be satisfied with
highlighting a few decisive phases and a few Leitmotifs of this develop-
ment." In the earliest phase the development of christology was naturally
shaped by rwo rypes of discussion: the discussion with Judaism and the
discussion with Hellenism.
The encounter with judaism and its suict monotheism led [Q the danger of
diminishing the true divinity of Jesus Christ. The Jewish Christian group that
sought to rank Christ with the prophets, the specially graced and chosen ones
of God, or the angels, have come to be known as the Ebionites. We find the
JeslIs Christ, Son of God 179
same approach being taken again in the adoptionist christology of Theodorus
the Tanner and his disciple Theodotus the Money-Changer. This christology
is fully developed in Paul of Samosata, who presents the man Jesus Christ as
endowed with an impersonally conceived power (dynamis).
The other extreme is found in Hellenistic circles, where there is a diminish-
ment of the true humanity of Jesus Christ. The Docetists, as they are called,
sought to resolve the difficulty created by the incarnation, which was unworthy
of a God, and by the scandalous suffering of the Son of God. They did so by
adopting a dualistic and spiritualistic approach, and ascribing to Christ only
the semblance of a body or at least only the semblance of suffering. The later
New Testament writings, in particular the First and Second Letters of John
and probably the Letter to the Colossians and the Pastoral Letters, had already
had to resist preliminary forms of this docetist error. The confession of Jesus
Christ as having truly come in the flesh is regarded in these writings as the line
of demarcation between Christianity and non·Chrisrianity or even ~tnti·
Christianity (I John 4.2f.; d. 4.15; 5.5f.; II John 7). Ignatius of Antioch then
launches himself unreservedly into the battle. His line of argument is wholly
soteriological: every denial of the reality of the humanity of Jesus means a
denial of the reality of our redemption, for if Jesus only seemed to have a body,
then he only seemed to redeem us (Smym. 2); then the eucharist too is only an
illusion (Smryn. 7); then, finally, it is senseless for us to suffer in body for Jesus
and to endure persecution for him (Smym. 4.1). The whole of Christianity
then evaporates into a mere semblance of reality. Thus Ignatius already
achieves a christological vision in which the unity of Christ's twO modes of
being (flesh - spirit; having become - not having become; from Mary - from
God; etc.) is explicitly highlighted (Eph. 7.2).
The great divergence of views regarding the proper understanding of Jesus
Christ came in the second and third centuries in the struggle with gnosticism. 56
In this struggle Christianity was compelled for the first time to set forth its
teaching on God, redemption, man and the world in a systematic way; only
now did this teaching take a firm didactic and institutional form. There is, of
course, a good deal of disagreement among scholars on the origin and nature
of gnosticism. We know today that gnosticism already existed in pre-Christian
times as a syncretistic religious movement and that, as the Qumran texts show,
it had gained entrance into Judaism. The widespread and speedy success of the
gnostic current of thought was based on a new experience of God, world and
man that had no previous parallel in antiquity. The human being of late
antiquity no longer felt at home in the universe; he experienced the world
rather as alien and impenetrable, as a prison and a rigid system from which he
sought liberation. At the center of the extreme dualism that characterized
gnostic thinking stood the enigmatic figure of the god 'Man' who had fanen
into the sphere of matter and who liberates his self, which has been thrown
into the world and almost buried there, through knowledge (gnosis) of the
right path. In this context, therefore, redemption is conceived in physical terms
180 The Message about the God of Jesus Christ
as redemption from matter and the body, and not, as in Christianity, in spiritual
terms as redemption from sin that is conceived as disobedience to God. Over
against Christian dualism which is historical and based on freedom, gnosticism
set a metaphysical dualism in which God is the totally other, alien and new,
unknown and unworldly God, while redemption consists in an emancipation
from the pre-given order of things. Irenaeus of Lyons, Clement of Alexandria,
Tertullian and Hippolytus rook up the cudgels against this teaching which
threatened the very foundations of Christianity. They were obliged to defend
the reality of creation, no less than the reality of God and redemption, against
the calumnies leveled against them.
Once the church's theologians had defended the reality of the God of history
who speaks, acts and is present corporeally in Jesus Christ, the christological
problem in the narrow sense inevitably made its appearance: how enn God be
and remain God and yet be truly present in history? Celsus, an opponent of
Christianity, and a shrewd one, had already noted this problem: 'Either God
really changes himself, as they claim, into a mortal body ... or he does not
change, bur makes onlookers think he has so changed, and thus leads them
into errors and tells lies.'51 The debate over this question was the major theme
in the fourth-century conflict with Arius and Arianism. It was in this context
that the Council of Nicaea (325) issued its deeision which was to be normative
for the whole subsequent tradition.
The conflict had long been in the making, at least since the Apologists of the
second century had taken over the Logos concept of Greek philosophy (bur by
that time for practical purposes an idea that had invaded every part of life) in
order ro clarify conceptually the relation between the Father and the Son. The
way had been paved for this step by the wisdom literature of the Bible and by
John's hymn ro the Logos in the Prologue of the Fourth Gaspe\. The acceptance
of the Stoic Logos doctrine now turned the wisdom teaching and the Logos
idea of John into a comprehensive doctrine that explained everything: God,
world and history. The Logos was conceived as the rational principle at work
in the cosmos and in history. He is present in fragmentary form in every reality
(logos spermatikos), but only in Jesus Christ has he appeared in his full form."
As far as the relation of the Logos to God is concerned, Justin thinks of it in
subordinationist terms. The Logos is God's first production;S!II only in view of
the creation of the world does he become independent in relation to what is
outside God,60 that is, he becomes a divine person but one subordinate to the
Father." In developing this teaching the Apologists were able to call upon the
anthropological distinction between the immanent Logos (logos elJdiathetos)
and the expressed Logos (logos prophorikos) and apply it to God."
The Apologists with their first attempts were soon outstripped by [wo men
of genius who determined the course of the entire subsequent development:
Tertullian in the Latin West and Origcn in the Greek East. With a sure touch
and with juridical preciseness Tertullian had by abour 200 already coined the
decisive concepts used in later trinlurian theology.1Ol By so doing he spared the
Jesl/s Christ, S01l of God 181
West a good deal of the protracted and wearisome debate that the East was to
endure. But in Tertullian there is still a subordinationist tendency. The Logos
indeed exists prior to the crcation of the world, but it is only through creation
that he achieves his 'complete birth' (nativitas perfecta}." The Son proceeds
from the Father as the fruit from the root, the river from the source, the ray of
sunlight from the sun." The Father alone possesses the entire fullness of
divinity, the Son has only a part of it."
The theology of Origen (t 253-54) is doubtless superiono thatofTertullian
in speculative power. We are confronted in him by one of the greatest and
boldest of all theological projects. Origen unhesitatingly asserts the eternity of
the Son." The Son is the brightness of the Light." He is a hypostasis that is
substantially distinct from the Father" and is not a part of the Father.'o On
the other hand, he is not unqualifiedly good as the Father is;" he is not 'very
God' (alltotheos) but a 'second God' (dellteros theos}." The transcendental
attributes of the Father take form and figure in the Son." The Son is therefore
mediator of rcdcmption. H Even though Origen's intention is first and foremost
to do biblical rheology within the framework of the church's tradition, his
theology nonetheless represents the birthday of speculative theology, and one
in which the influence of Platonic thinking is unmistakable."
This encounter with contemporary philosophy was neither a calamity nor
a mere accident, as objecmrs to the Hellenization of Christianity believe; it
was hermeneutically necessary and was in the final analysis the form which
aggiornamento or 'updating' took at that time. On the other hand, the steps
then taken did ultimately lead to the crisis that is associated with the name of
Arius. The crisis was at bottom nothing else than the outbreak of fever in a
process that in its germinal stage was marked by a hidden virulence of which
the Apologists had little conception. For the Logos of the Stoics was essentially
monistic and made sense only in relation to the world. In later Middle
Platonism, on the other hand, there was an excessive emphasis on the absolute
transcendence, invisibility and unknowableness of God; in this context the
Logos served as a principle of mediation. The result was the danger of
subordinationism, that is, of making the Son less than the Father. The Logos
is begotten by the Father with a view to creation; the procession of the Logos
from the Father is thus made dependent on crcation. The Bible's soteriological
teaching on salvation was in danger of turning into cosmological speculation,
and this danger became acute in Arius, a 'leftist' disciple of Origen. 7' Arius
ventured to remedy in a one-sided way the imperfections in theological
subordinationism. For him God is ineffable, unbegotten, free of becoming,
without origin and immutable, as he is in Middle Platonism. The basic problem
then became how to mediate between the indivisible being which is incapable
of becoming, and the world of becoming and multiplicity. Here was the
usefulnessofthe Logos, a second God (dellteros theos), whom Arius understood
as being the first and most excellent creature and at the same time mediaror in
creation. Consequently, the Logos was crcated out of nothing, in time, as
182 The Message abol/t the God of jesl/s Christ
mutable and fallible; only because of his ethical behaviot has he been adopted
as Son. In Arius' thinking the God of the philosophers has evidently supplanted
the living God of history. His theology represents an extreme Hellenization of
Christianity.
(b) Kmosis-christology
If we take the testimony of the New Testament consistently as our
starting point and if we make this testimony the basis for the speculative
development of our faith in Christ, then we must take seriously the fact
that the Gospels are 'passion narratives with extended introductions' (M.
Kahler). The cross is then not simply the consequence of the earthly
ministry of Jesus but the very goal of the incarnation; it is not something
adventitious but the meaning and purpose of the Christ· event, so that
everything else is ordered to it as to a goal. God would not have become
truly a human being had he not entered fully into the abyss and night of
death. But this means that we must approach the question of the nature of
Jesus' divinesonship not from the vantage-point of his eternal and temporal
birth but from that of his death on the cross. The starting point of
christological renection must be the giving of the Son by the Father and
the self-giving of the Son to the Father and for the many, rather than the
generation of the Son by the Father as conceived according to the analogy
of the production of the intellectual word.'·!
Basic to such a christological approach is the hymn to Christ in Phil.
2.6-11, which speaks of the kenosis or emptying (Greek: ke/losis) of him
who was in the form of God and accepted the form of a slave.103 In
interpreting this important text we must take careful note of the fact that
it is not speaking of a transformation of nature, still less of a de-divinization
of God. Such an interpretation would contradict not only 11 Cor. 5.19:
'God was in Christ', but also what is said here in Philippians, for according
to this text the kenosis consists in the taking of the form of a slave and not
in the surrender of the form of God. Augustine is fully correct in his
interpretation: 'It was thus that he emptied himself: by taking the form of
a slave, not by losing the form of God; the form of a slave was added, the
form of God did not disappear."·' On the other hand, it is only with this
interpretation that the real problem becomes clear. We must negotiate the
190 The Message abo/lt the God of Jes/ls Christ
narrow path of making him who is God's equal the subject of the emptying
and of taking this emptying seriously while yet not depriving him of his
divinity. How is it possible, then, that the immutable God should at the
same time be mutable? How can the history of God in Jesus Christ be so
thought that it really affects God and is God's very own history, while at
the same time God remains God? How can the impassible God suffer?
The Bible makes unavoidable the question of the suffering of God. The
Bible tells us over and over that God is affected by the action and suffering
of human beings or, as the c,ase may be, allows himself to be affected
through compassion, anger and pity (Gen. 6.6; Ps. 78.41; Isa. 63.10; Hos.
11.8f.;Jer. 31.20; etc.).105 Consistently with this, rabbinical theology often
speaks of the pain in God. lo, The New Testament continues this line of
thought by telling of the anger of Jesus (Mark 3.5), his compassion (Mark
6.34), and his weeping over Jerusalem (Luke 19.41). Fundamental in this
context are the words of Jesus about being abandoned by God (Mark
15.34; Matt. 27.46) and the statement of principle in the Letter to the
Hebrews: 'We have not a high priest who is unable to sympathize with our
weaknesses, but one who in every respect has been tempted as we arc, yet
without sinning' (4.15). 'He can deal gently with the ignorant and wayward,
since he himself is beset with weakness ... Although he was a Son, he
learned obedience through what he suffered' (5.2, 8; d. 2.18; 4.15). It is
impossible to dismiss all this as simple anthropomorphism, or to ascribe
it solely to the human nature of Jesus, while leaving his divinity untouched
by it. Forthe kenosis is that ofthe pre-existent Son of God (Phil. 2.7), and
it is the humanness of God that has made its appearance (Titus 3.4). In his
humanness, then, and in his living and dying Jesus Christ is the self-
interpretation of God.
The fathers were compelled to differentiate this God of history as
understood in the Bible from mythological conceptions of gods who
undergo becoming and who suffer and change, and of their mythologically
interpreted incarnations. In effecting the differentiation the fathers were
to appeal to motifs of Greek philosophy and its axiom of God's impassibility
(apatheia: the apathia-axiom).107 In the process they doubtless often
defended God's impassibility in a way that betrays the influence more of
Greek philosophy than of the testimony of the Bible. lOB It is not the case,
however, as is often claimed, that the fathers simply took over the apathia-
axiom and thus abridged the Bible's testimony regarding the living God of
history. 109
The early fathers simply let the paradox stand. According to Ignatius of
Antioch, 'The timeless and invisible one became visible for our sake; the
incomprehensible and impassible one became capable of suffering for our
jestls Christ, SOI/ of God 191
sake. 'liD Irenaeus l l l and Melito III use similar language. Tertullian, known
for his paradoxes, says: 'God's Son was crucified, and precisely because it
was ignominious I am not ashamed of it. God's Son also died, and this is
credible precisely because it was in such bad taste. He died and rose again,
and this is certain because it is impossible.'II' In other passages he speaks
of the Delis mortlllls (dead God)' 14 and the Delis crt/ci{ixlls (crucified
God).11S He thus anticipates the formula of the Scythian monks in the
theopaschite controversy of the sixth century: 'One of the holy Trinity
suffered in the flesh.' ""
A mode of expression that was less bizarre and that showed a balance
achieved through reflection was very difficult for the fathers because they
regarded pathos (suffering) as a non·free external passive experience l17
and even as an expression of the human fallenness brought about by sin. II.
Given such presuppositions, such pathe (sufferings) could be ascribed to
God only insofar as he freely accepted them, with the result that in him
they would not be the expression of finiteness, lack of freedom, and
sinfulness but, on the contrary, an expression of his power and freedom.
This is the line taken in the response of Gregory Thaumaturgus l " and
Hilary"O and even of Augustine: 'If he was also weak, this was due to his
own fullness of power.'12I Gregory of Nyssa is very emphatic: 'But his
descent into lowliness represents a cerrain excess of power, so that even
what is as it were contrary to his nature is not a hindrance [0 him.'I22 From
here it is but a relatively short step to the most important patristic discussion
of the apathia-axiom, that of Origen. lll Origen moves beyond the idea of
free acceptance to that of love. If the Son had not from eternity felt
compassion for our wretchedness, he would not have become man and
would not have allowed himself to be crucified: 'First he suffered, then he
came down. What was the suffering he accepted for us? The suffering of
love.' Not only the Son but the Father as well is not simply 'impassible':
he tOO 'suffers something of the suffering of love'. I" Here a solution is
insinuated which has its basis in the innermost being of God himscif, in his
freedom in love.
This survey shows that the biblical and ecclesial confession of Jesus as the
Son of God is something that theology has still not completely assimilated.
The theology of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries is the attempt on a
grand scale to effect a new interpretation of the concept of God and his
immutability in the light of that confession or, more accurately, in the light
of the cross of Jesus Christ, and so to give new relevance to the biblical
understanding of the God of history. It has become clear in the process
that there are valid points of contact in patristic theology. But the attempt
to understand God and Jesus Christ in terms of the kenosis idea must be
antecedently aware that such an understanding must not turn into a
wisdom of this world but must hold fast to the folly of the message of the
cross, which is the wisdom of God (d. I Cor. 1.18-31 ). The point of
departure for such an attempt can therefore only be the testimony of the
Bible and not some philosophy or other, whether classical metaphysics
with its apathia-axiom, or idealism with its conception of the necessary
self-renunciation of the absolute, or modern process philosophy. We must
therefore resist all the attempts, anticipated long ago in gnosticism, to turn
the cross of Christ into a world principle, a world law or a world formula
or to explain it as a symbol of the universal principle of 'dying and living
again' (Stirb lind Werde).'"
The decisive argument can be set forth in two steps:
1. On the cross the incarnation of God reaches its true meaning and
purpose. The entire Christ-event must therefore be understood in terms of
the cross. On the cross God's self-renouncing love is embodied with
ultimate radicalncss. The cross is the utmost that is possible to God in his
self-surrendering love; it is 'that than which a greater cannot be thought';
it is the unsurpassable self-definition of God. This self-renunciation or
emptying is therefore not a self-abandonment and not a self-de-divinization
of God. The love of God that is revealed on the CtOSS is rather the expression
of God's unconditional fidelity to his promise. It must be said of the living
God of history that precisely as the God of history he remains true to
himself and cannot deny himself (II Tim. 2.13). The cross is therefore not
a de-divinization of God bur the revelation of the divine God. It is by the
very unfathomableness of his forgiving love that he proves he is God and
not a man (Has. 11.9). For the Bible, then, the revelation of God's
omnipotence and the revelation of God's love are not contraries. God need
Jeslls Christ, SOli of God 195
not strip himself of his omnipotence in order to reveal his love. On the
contrary, it requires omnipotence to be able to surrender oneself and give
oneself away; and it requires omnipotence to be able to take oneself back
in the giving and to preserve the independence and freedom of the recipient.
Only an almighty love can give itself wholly to the other and be a helpless
love.
God's omnipotence is therefore his goodness. For goodness is to give
oneself away completely, but in such a way that by omnipotently
taking oneself back one makes the recipient independent ... It is
incomprehensible that omnipotence is not only able to create the most
impressive of all things - the whole visible world - but is able to create
the most fragile of all things - a being independent of that very
omntpotence. 140
Here we have reached the key point: God's self-emptying, his weakness
and his suffering are not the expression of alack, as they are in finite beings;
nor are they the expression of a fated necessity. If God suffers, then he
suffers in a divine manner, that is, his suffering is an expression of his
freedom; suffering does not befall God, rather he freely allows it to touch
him. He does not suffer, as creatures do, from a lack of being; he suffers
out of love and by reason of his love, which is the overflow of his being.
To predicate becoming, suffering and movement of God does not, therefore,
mean that he is turned into a developing God who reaches the fullness of
his being only through becoming; such a passage from potency to act is
excluded in God. To predicate becoming, suffering and movement of God
is to understand God as the fullness of being, as pure actualiry, as overflow
of life and love. Because God is the omnipotence of love, he can as it were
indulge in the weakness of love; he can enter into suffering and death
without perishing therein. Only thus can he redeem our death through his
own death. In that sense Augustine's statement is valid: 'Slain by death, he
slew death.'''' 'He destroyed our death by dying and restored our life by
rising' (Hymn to the Cross). Thus God on the cross shows himself as the
one who is frec in love and 35 freedom in love.142
2. If God shows himself as the one who loves in freedom and who is free
in loving and if the cross is the eschatological self-revelation of God, then
God must in himself be freedom in love and love in freedom. Only if God
is in himself love can he reveal himself as such in an eschatological and
definitive way. From eternity, therefore, God must be self-communicating
love. This in turn means that God possesses his identity only in a distinction
within himself between lover and beloved who are both one in love. Here
we have a starting point for the understanding of the Trinity, and one that
196 The Message about the God of Jesus Christ
proceeds not from knowledge in the word but from self-communicating
love. This starting point helps us to do greater justice to the phenomenon
of self-emptying, which is essential to love, than is possible when, with the
tradition, we take the word as the starting point. On the other hand, since
love presupposes and includes knowledge of the beloved, this approach is
broad enough to integrate and make fruitful the profound insights of
Logos-christology. In addition, there is the factthatcontemporary linguistic
philosophy starts with the external, spoken word and not with the interior
word as Plato and Augustine did, and that it understands the spoken word
as a self-surrender on the part of the speaker and as a turning to other
human beings. This is a further point of view which allows Logos-
christology to be taken into a kenosis-christology, that is, a christology
of self-emptying and self-surrender, and thereby to be developed and
deepened.
There is a basis in the tradition for thus taking love as the point of
departure. As early as Origen we find the teaching that the Son proceeds
from the will, that is, from the love of the Father.'" It is Augustine, above
all, who recognizes that the Trinity discloses itself in light of the concept
of love. 'see, there are three things: lover, beloved and love. What is love
but a kind of life that unites or endeavors to unite two with one another,
namely, lover and beloved?'''' Augustine did not, however, pursue this
insight further. Or, more accurately, he begins with love but then introduces
the element of knowledge by arguing: 'The spirit cannot love itself if it
does not know itself.' 'Thus the spirit, its love and its knowledge form a
kind of trinity.'''' Within the approach by way of love there is thus the
basis for the theology of the word, but the latter was subsequently
developed, for the most part, in isolation. The only real exception is the
approach of Richard of st Victor (twelfth century) who thinks consistently
in terms of love. '46 I shall be discussing him in greater detail later on.
Love entails a unity that does not absorb the other person but rather
accepts and affirms the other precisely in his otherness and only thus
establishes him in his true freedom. Love, which gives to the other not
some thing but its very self, involves, in this very self-communication, a
self-differentiation and self-limitation. The lover must take himself back
because his concern is not with himself but with the other. More than this,
the lover allows the other to affect him; he becomes vulnerable precisely
in his love. Thus love and suffering go together. The suffering of love is
not, however, a passive being-affected, but an active allowing others to
affect one. Because, then, God is love he can suffer and by that very fact
reveal his divinity. The self-emptying of the cross is therefore not a
de-divinization of God but his eschatological glorification. The eternal
Jesus Christ, Son of God 197
intra-divine distinction of Father and Son is the transcendental theological
condition for the possibility of God's self-emptying in the incarnation and
on the cross. This statement is not simply a more or less interesting piece
of speculation; it signifies that from eternity there is place in God for man,
place also for a genuine sym-pathy with the suffering of human beings.
The Christian God, that is, the God who is thought of in terms of Jesus
Christ, is therefore not a God of a-pathia, but in the real sense of the term
a God of sym-pathy, a God who suffers with man.
This 'sym-pathetic' God as he reveals himself in Jesus Christ is the
definitive answer to the question of theodicy, the question on which theism
and atheism alike founder. If God himself suffers, then suffering is no
longer an objection against God. On the other hand, if God suffers, this
does not mean that he divinizes suffering. God does not divinize suffering,
he redeems it. For the suffering of God, which springs from thevoluntariness
of love, conquers the fateful character of suffering, which attacks us from
without as something alien and unintelligible. Thus the omnipotence of
God's love removes the weakness of suffering. Suffering is not thereby
removed, but it is interiorly transformed - transformed into hope. Kenosis
and suffering now no longer have the last word; the last word belongs to
exaltation and transfiguration. Once again, then, kenosis-christology
points beyond itself to a christology of Easter exaltation and transfigur-
ation, and is very closely connected with pneumatology. For according to
scripture the eschatological transformation and transfiguration of the
world is the work of the Spirit of God. Because according to the theological
tradition the Spirit unites lover and beloved, Father and Son, in their very
distinction, he is also the power that brings the world to its eschatological
transfiguration and reconciliation.
III
The Holy Spirit, Lord and Giver of Life
'I believe in the Holy Spirit, the Lord and giver of life': thus begins the third
section of the Christian confession of faith. Only with this final statement
does the confession reach its end and completion. For the life that has its
origin in the Father, and is given to us in the Son, is made our interior,
personal possession by the Holy Spirit, operating through the ministry of
the church. That which has its origin in the Father and its center in the Son
reaches its completion in the Holy Spirit.
The statement about the Holy Spirit is, of course, also full of intellectual
difficulties. As a matter of fact, the Holy Spirit does not play an outstanding
part in the average ecclesial and theological consciousness. The Holy Spirit
is the most mysterious of the three divine persons, for while the Son has
shown himself to us in human form and we can form at least an image of
the Father, we have no concrete grasp of the Spirit. Not without reason
has he frequently been called 'the unknown God'. Forgetfullness of the
Spirit is a charge often leveled against the Western ttadition in particular,
and it is true that the triad, Father- Christ- Spirit is replaced, in the minds
of many by the triad God- Christ- church. l I will have occasion to discuss
in greater detail the reasons and consequences of this forgetfullness of the
Spirit.
The real intellectual difficulties in pneumatology are to be seen as
springing not primarily from the ecclesial and theological tradition but
rather from the intellectual situation of the age and its lack of 'spirit'. The
loss of the dimension and reality which Western thinking has described by
the term 'spirit' is perhaps the most profound crisis of the present time.'
The discovery of the world of the spirit was the great accomplishment of
Greek thought, and Christian theology was able to make use of it in a
The Holy Spirit, Lord alld Giller of Life 199
manner both critical and creative. In Western philosophy spirit used to be
not simply one reality among others, but the truest of realities. In the
philosophy of the modern age, spirit even became the dominant basic
concept; spirit was for it the totality that gave meaning and unity and
grounded everything else amid the multiplicity of phenomena. The spirit
which permeated all reality made it possible to recognize what was one's
own in what was alien and to be at home in it. After the passing of Goethe,
Hegel and Schleiermacher this philosophy of spirit suddenly collapsed.
Since that time the idealist interpretation of spirit has largely yielded the
field to a materialistic and evolutionary interpretation. Reality is no longer
viewed as a manifestation of spirit, but rather spirit is understood as an
epiphenomenon of reality, being conceived as a superstructure built on the
economic and social process or as a surrogate and sublimation of man who
is defined as a being made up of needs. Finally, a positivist and supposedly
'exact' understanding of science demanded the renunciation of the concept
of 'spirit' because of its multiplicity of meanings and the impossibility of
providing an exact definition of it; it demanded that we remain silent
regarding that which we cannot define with precision. It is obvious that
this kind of materialist and positivist thinking could not but give way to
nihilism and turn into a devaluation and revaluation of all previous ideas,
values and ideals, which now become suspect of being mere ideological
cloaks for individual and collective interests.
What I have been saying represents, of course, only one half of our
situation. For that which past European history understood by 'spirit' is
present anew today in the mode of absence and in a way that is truly
terrifying. Our experience is of the spiritless condition of a reality which
has lost its soul and turned into a facade, a reality in which every
organization of things can only be felt as a form of coercion and in which
the isolated subject finds himself confronted by impenetrable processes
that generate anxiety and a sense of oppression. The experience is accom-
panied by a search for what used to be meant by spirit, but in the form
now of various utopian visions of a better, more human, and reconciled
world. Two such visions in particular call for mention: the utopian vision
of evolution or progress, and that of revolution. The two have in common
that they want to turn a reality alien to man into a human world in which
will be brought to pass something of 'that which manifested itself to
everyone in childhood and wherein as yet no one dwelt: home' (E. Bloch).
Yet both of these utopian visions must today be regarded as shattered. The
collapse of the vision of progress is evident on a wide scale in view of
external economic conditions and of the dangers lurking in technological
development. In the interim it has also become clear that any revolution is
200 The Message about the God of Jesus Christ
subject to the conditions of injustice and violence which it is resisting, so
that the injustice and violence of which the revolution itself makes use
bring into the desired new order of things the seeds of new injustice and
new violence. Therefore no revolution is possible that will not later be
betrayed as the formerly oppressed become oppressors in their turn. The
flight to the interior and the flight to ecstasy, whether religious ecstasy or
one of its surrogates, are evidently not solutions. Moreover, even in these
kinds of flight the cry for the spirit cannot be missed.
The only real replacement for human fulfillment and for the utopian
ideal of a reality that is unrent, undivided, and successful is art. According
to classical philosophy the beautiful is the sensible manifestation of the
idea; it is freedom made manifest or, in the language of today's thinkers,
the anticipation of definitive reconciliation.' In a work of art, then, there
is, at least according to the classical understanding of art, a foretaste of
that which Christian faith looks to with hope as to be accomplished by the
Holy Spirit; the transfiguration of reality. On the other hand, contemporary
artists think It possible to carry out the task of art only in the form of
criticism, protest and negation, given the spiritless condition of the present
age. Where all idea of the spiritually supra-sensible has been abandoned
and the beautiful has been separated from the true and the good, as in
nihilism,' the beautiful can only be understood as taking the form of a life-
enhancing ecstasy, an affirmation of the sensuous, a will to appearances,
or pure form. In contemporary art, therefore, the question is largely
left unanswered how a transformation of the world and man, a real
reconciliation of the world and man, are possible. The question is raised
of that which used to be expressed in the term 'spirit', but no answer is in
sight. The Christian message of the Holy Spirit raises this question and
intends to provide a super-abundant answer to it. It is the answer to the
distress of our times and the crisis of our age.
The struggle with the movements ofenthusiasrs that have continually appeared
on the scene in the course of the church's history led unintentionally to a
repression of the charismatic element and a certain institutionalization of the
Spirit. Montanism in the second half of the second century already marks an
important (urning-point,14 As the danger grew of the church becoming
'bourgeois't Montanism sought to revivify the original enthusiasm. The call to
conversion in face of the imminent end of (he world, together with an ethical
rigorism and ecstatic forms of communal life, awoke a powerful echo in hearts.
Tertullian set up 30 opposition of principle between (he ecc/esia spiritus
(church of the Spirit) and eeelesia /lltIIlen,s episcoportlm (the church which
consists of a number of bishops),15 Irenacus takes a different approach: he sees
the Spirit of God as active in the church, which is made up of followers of the
apostles. The church is the vessel in which the Spirit 'rejuvenates and keeps
rejuvenating' faith; 'Where the church is, there the Spirit of God is; where the
Spirit of God is, there the church is and all grace.''' According to the Apostolic
Traditio" of Hippolytus of Rome it is the Spirit who guarantees the preservation
of the tradition;" therefore 'let him [the believer] hasten to the church where
the Spirit flourlshes.'u
Because of the polemic against the Montanists and later against enthusiasts
generally, the striking charisms gradually faded away. Bur the charismatic
dimension of the church lived on in the martyrs, as it did in monasticism, from
which many bishops came, and later in the sainrs.l'J But even though there have
been repeated severe struggles between charismatic movements marked by
uncontrolled enthusiasm and often by a rigoristic undersrandingof the church's
holiness, and the institutional great church, the church's theologians have
never allowed themselves to be forced inco setting up an opposicion of principle
between Spirit and institution; they have rather seen the church 3S the place
and even the sacrament of the Spirit, and the Spirit as the vital principle or soul
The Holy Spirit, Lord alld Giver of Life 209
01 the church.'" On the other hand, a certain absorption 01 the Spirit by the
church is unmistakable in this approach.
Beginning in the twellth and thirteenth century the discussion 01 the reality
and ellective action 01 the Spirit in history took on a new dimension. Joachim
01 Flora, a Calabrian abbot," prophecied a coming new age 01 the church, an
age 01 the Spirit which would replace the age 01 the Father (the Old Testament)
and the age 01 the Son (the clerical church) with an age 01 monks, contempla-
tives, and viri spirituales (men 01 the Spirit). In this outlook the hope 01 the
eschatological transformation by the Holy Spirit became the expectation of a
renewal within history. In being thus historicized, the Spirit became a principle
of historical progress. While this renewal and progress was originally thought
of by the Fraticelli as a renewal of the church,Joachim's ideas were soon given
a secularized form. In that form these ideas became the source of the modern
idea of progress and the various modern utopias. We find Joachim's ideas
reappearing, transformed, in Lessing, Kant, Hegel, Schelling and Marx, and
even in the dreadful dream of a Third Empire. In the present as in the past,
Joachim's ideas or fragments of them have been at work in many rheological
trends and movements of renewal within the church.
The church's theologians have taken a critical attitude toward joachim's
ideas. Bonaventure was able, indeed, (Q find one posirive element in Joachim's
thinking, inasmuch as Francis of Assisi was for Joachim an eschawlogical
sign. 12 But on the key issue Bonaventure and Thomas Aquinas rook the same
stand: there is no salvation-historical advance beyond Jesus Christ; the Holy
Spirit must therefore be understood as the Spirit of Jesus Christ. Thomas
himself was extremely harsh in his judgment of Joachim; he would have
nothing to do wirh any theological interprerarion of individual historical
evenrsP In his view the new coven<lnt consists in 'the grace of the Holy Spirit,
which is given through faith in Christ' ('gratia spirillls sallcti, quae dalllr per
fidem Christi'). The 'new law' (lex lIova) or 'evangelical law' (lex evallgelica) is
therefore primarily an 'inward implanted law' (lex indita) and only secondarily
connected with anything external; externals serve only in preparation and
implementation. Therefore the law of the new covenant is a law of freedom
and not of the lener that kills; it is not law but gospel." Every historicization
of the acriviry of the Spirit must therefore fall short of the gospel and turn inro
a new legalism.
The different conceptions are based, to begin with, on rhe different images
used in order to gain a deeper faith-understanding of rhe doctrine of the Holy
Spirit. The dominant model of Larin rheology rakes for irs point of departure
rhe soul's rwo faculries of knowing and willing. The Farher, who knows and
expresses himself in his Son as in his Word, also wills or is moved by love to
unire himself ro this image of himself; in like manner, rhe Son gives himself
whoHy ro rhe Farher in love. This loving grasp and embrace is nor a generative
process comparable to rhe production of the Word by knowledge, in which
something substantially the same yet different emerges; rather, there is a
movement of the will, which seeks the union of what is distinct. Since the
beloved exists in the will of the lover as a power rhar moves and impels, the
beloved can be described as 'spirit' in the sense of :1 power that impels from
within. M. Scheeben has an even better explanation of how a reciprocal love
between Farher and Son can be described as 'Spirir': 'When we wish to express
the intimacy of union between two persons, we say that they are of one spirit,
or even that they are one spirit'.50
This interpretation of rhe Holy Spirit as mutual and reciprocal love between
216 The Message about the God of Jesus Christ
Father and Son is an essential of Latin pneumatology, which was established
especially by Augustine. 'The Holy Spirit is in a sense the ineffable communion
of Father and Son.''' 'This ineffable embrace of the Father and his Image is
not unaccompanied by pleasure, love and joy. This love, this joy, this bless-
edness, this happiness, or however this reality is to be described in a way
worthy of God has been called "use'" by Hilary. 'In the Trinity this "use" is
the Holy Spirit, who is not begotten but is the sweet blessedness of the
Begetter and the Begotten.''' This is how Anselm of Canterbury'" and Thomas
Aquinas,s.. in particular, understood the Holy Spirit in continuity with Augus-
tine. Latin theology thus uses a symmetrical represenrational model, according
to which the movement of trinitarian life is rounded off in the Holy Spirit in a
kind of circular movement. But Latin theology was not able consistently co
follow through on this model. For Augustine and the rest of the Western
tradition also wished to regard the Father as sole origin. Therefore, despite his
firmly asserted thesis that the Holy Spirit proceeds from both Father and Son,"
Augustine also insists that he proceeds originally (prillcipaliter) from the
Father." Thomas Aquinas accepts this formula and describes the Father as the
principiwn or fOilS fOfius triuitatis (source or fountainhead of the entire
Trinity)." It follows from this that the Son derives from the Father his power
to produce the Spirit; Thomas is therefore also able to say that the Holy Spirit
proceeds from the Father through the Son. Only in Anselm of Canterbury is
no room made for this point of view. Unfortunately, it was Anselm who
influenced the rater theological tradition at this point!
Alongside this model a second is to be found in Latin theology; its point of
departure is an analysis of love. According to Augustine, love has three
elements: the lover, the beloved, and the love itself.s8 Later on it was Richard
of St Vicror in particular who developed this approach; Alexander of Hales,
Bonaventure and the Franciscan School took it over from himY' According to
Richard St Vicror, perfect love, which is God, is wholly ce-static. It therefore
exists as Father, that is, as pure giver (gratllitlls). As gift wholly given away it
also exists as Son, that is, as gift wholly received from another (debitlls) and
wholly given away in turn (gratllitlls). Finally, it exists in the Holy Spirit as gift
wholly received (debitus); the Spirit is the common beloved (colldilectllS) of
Father and Son. He is gift in an unqualified sense.'" This second model has the
advantage that, unlike the first, it docs not understand the Holy Spirit as the
mUluallove of Father and Son, but more clearly and consistently brings out
the status of the Father 3S the source which gives love to the Son, a love which
the Son, who possesses it as given [0 him by the Father, together with the
Father who possesses it as ungiven, then bestows on the Spirit.
The Greeks, [00, use human images and analogies for understanding the
Son and the Spirit of God. But, unlike the Latins, the Greeks take as their
starting point not the interior word but the external, spoken word. For us
hum:ln beings this external word is associated with breath :lS :l movement of
the air. 'When we spe:lk a word, this movement of the air produces the voice,
The Holy Spirit, Lord alld Giver of Life 217
which alone makes the meaning of the word accessible [Q others.' In an
analogous manner, in God, too, there is a breath, namely, the Spirit 4 w hich
accompanies the word and reveals its efficacy'.61
Latins and Greeks thus start with different representational models. From
the divergent images used come different theological conceptions. According
to the Latins the Spirit proceeds from the reciprocal love of Father and Son;
the Greeks, on the other, speak only of a procession of the Spirit from the
Father. This does not mean that for the Greeks the Spirit is not also the Spirit
of the Son." For 'he proceeds from the Father and rests in the Word and reveals
him'.63 In this sense the Spirit 'proceeds from the Father, is communicated
through the Son, and is received by every creature. He creates by his own
power, makes all things be, sanctifies and holds together.''' The advantage of
this conception is that it maintains the position of the Father as sole source
within the Godhead and that the relation of the Spirit to activity in the world
is brought out more clearly than in the Latin conceptions, which are in danger
of turning the life of God in the Holy Spirit into something self-enclosed and
not turning outward to the world and history.
The different analogies used are matched by different concepts. The common
basis for the formation of concepts is John 15.26, where the Spirit is described
as one 'who proceeds from the Father' ("0 para tal/ patros ekporel/etai). All
the traditions have in common that in the Nicene-Constantinopolitan creed
they replace para with ek and replace ekporel/etai in the present tense with the
participle ekporeuomcllon, in order to bring out not only the temporal
procession but the abiding eternal procession.(;S The difference between Greeks
and Latins began when the Vulgate translated ekporel/etai as procedit, for
processio in Latin theology has a much more general meaning than ekporclIsis
in Greek theology. EkporclIcsthai means 4emcrge from, go forth from, stream
forth from'. In this sense the concept is applicable only to the Father, the first,
unoriginated origin; the co-operation of the Son in the procession of the Holy
Spirit, on the other hand, must be described by the verb proienai. Latin does
not make this fine distinction. According to Latin theology processio is a
general concept that can be applied to all of the inter-trinitarian processes, that
is, not only to the coming forth of the Spirit from the Father, but also to the
generation of the Son and to the breathing of the Spirit through the Son. As a
result, Latin theology is faced with a problem that does not have a parallel in
Greek theology. For Latin theology too must hold fast to the distinction
between the processio of the Son from the Father and the processio of the Spirit
from the Father. If the Spirit proceeded from the Father in the same manner
as the Son, there would be two Sons and no longer any distinction between
Son and the Spirit. Given the presuppositions of Latin theology, the distinction
between Son and Spirit can be preserved only by giving the Son a role in the
procession of the Spirit from the Father, whereas he does not have an active
role in his own procession from the Father. Admittedly, he plays a part not
principaliter, that is, as an origin, but only in virtue of the being he has received
218 The Message about the God of jesus Christ
from the Father. For this reason, Latin theology has always insisted that in the
procession of the Holy Spirit Father and Son form a single principle." In fact,
Latin theology can even say with Thomas Aquinas that the Spirit proceeds
from the Father through the Son. The disadvantage, of course, is that the
(i/ioql/e does not express in credal form the differentiation of roles which is
accepted in Latin theology.
The Greek theology of the Spirit likewise has its weaknesses. It is able to
express the special role of the Father in the procession of the Spirit, but in its
dogmatic credal formulas it is completely silent about the relation of the Spirit
to the Son. Simply to leave open the relation of Son and Spirit is, not of course,
a solution. For according co the scripture, in terms of the economy of
salvation the Holy Spirit proceeds from the Father Uohn 15.26), but he is also
communicated by the Son Uohn 14.16,26). But if the economy of salvation
and the theology of the inner life of the Trinity should not diverge but rather
correspond, and if the Son has a share in the sending of the Spirit in the history
of salvation, then he cannot fail to have a share in to the intra·trinitarian
procession of the Spirit. According to the scriptures, after all, the Spirit is the
Spirit of the Son (Gal. 4.6) or the Spirit of Jesus Christ (Rom. 8.9; Phil. 1.19).
According to Rev. 22.1 the water of life 'nows (ekporel/Omelloll) from the
throne of God and of the Lamb'.
These data from the Bible are probably the reason why the Greek fathers of
the first centuries did not object to early formulations of the (ilioqllc or its
equivalents in Ambrose, Augustine and Leo the Great. More th3n this,
formulations are (0 be found in some Greek fathers, especially Arhanasius,
Cyril of Alexandria and even Basil, that sound like the Western (ilioqllc." The
Greek fathers do, of course, speak mostly of a procession of the Spirit from
the Father through the Son," a formula which is not wholly foreign to the
Latins; this is tfue especially of Tertullian/''1 who, even before Augustine, had
Inid the foundation of Latin teaching on the Triniry. An interesting formula,
which combines the concerns of both West and East, is to be found In
Epiphanius of Salamis, who speaks of the Spirit 'who proceeds from the Father
and receives from the 50n'.70 While Epiphnnius seeks to medinte bctwcen the
two traditions from the side of Latin theology, Mnximus the Confessor in the
seventh century starts with Greek presuppositions in his efforts to mediate; "
in the later patristic period, as the latter is drawing to its close, he IS an
important witness to ecumenical unity between East and West.
The points of contact just indicated cannot and should not blur the
differences between the two traditions; they were to show, however, that
in the early centuries these differences were never taken as a challenge to
the common faith and that, on the contrary, because of the common
biblical basis and a common tradition there were bridges of many kinds
between East and West. Both theologies were trying to say objectively the
same thing. They bore witness to one and the same faith but in different
The Holy Spirit. Lord and Giller of Life 219
conceptual forms. In other words, they were complementary theologies.
each internally consistent and coherent but each also irreducible 10 the
other. The difference in terminology presented no problem at all in the lirst
eight centuries; it was never an occasion for controversy, much less for 3
rupture of ecclesial communion.
The {ilioqlle first became a problem when the Latins turned their theological
formula into a dogmatic confessional formula and thus unilaterally changed
the originally common text of the creed. The change lOok place initially in
various provincial Synods of Toledo in the fifth to the seventh centuries. n The
background of this development has still not been fully clarified. It is probable
that in the {ilioqlle these ptovincial synods were reacting against an offshoot
of Arianism, namely, Priscillianism. The imention of the fjlioqlle, in this case,
was to assert the consubstantiality of the Son with the Father and to emphasize
the point that the Spirit is the Spirit not only of the Father but also of the Son.
These 3fC concerns that were shared by the East 3S well. If is clear, therefore.
that the {ilioqlle was in no way originally directed at the East but represented
a development peculiar to the West at a rime when contacts with the East had
already been greatly weakened. so that eventually mutual understanding
ccased. To this extent, then, the {ilioqul! is the Western form in which the
Nicene-Constantinopolitan creed was received.
The controversy over the Latin tradition and reception broke out only when
Charlemagne atthe Council of Frankfurt (794) objected to the Second Council
of Nicaea (787) and its confession of the procession of the Holy Spirit 'from
the Father through the Son' and proclaimed instead the {ilioqlle which had
meanwhile been received in the West. The Council of Aachen (809) officially
added the {ilioqlle to the creed. For our present purposes we may ignore the
political background of all this, although it did determine the emotional
c1ima£t:. Rome was very reserved and even opposed (Q the development. Pope
Leo IIJ dolended Nicaea and thus the tradition and set himself against the
Carolingian council. He maintained his position when Frankish monks in the
monastery of St. Sabbas in Jerusalem introduced the {ilioqll' into the creed of
the Mass and gave occasion for considerable controversy. The pope defended
the teaching contained in the {ilioqlle but he refused its incorporation into the
creed. Pope Benedict VIIJ took a different attitude when Emperor Henry II
demanded that the (ilioqll' be incorporated into the creed of the Mass at his
coronation in 1014. With the agreement of the pope a new confessional
tradition was begun in the West. 7J
The Fourth Lateran Council (1215) and in particularthe Second Council of
Lyons (1274) defined the Western doctrine of the procession of the Holy Spirit
from (he Father and the 500.7'" Lyons rejected the Eastern misunderstanding
(which has lasted in part down to our own day) of the {ilioqlle: that there are
two principles or origins in the T riniry. According to the teachingof the Lateran
Council. Father and Son form a single principle in the procession of the Holy
220 The Message about the God of jesus Christ
Spirit. In a certain sense it can even be said that the West emphasizes the unity
of the Trinity even more than the East docs, since in the {ilioque it insists on
the equality and even singleness of substance of the Spirit with the Father and
the Son and, with regard to the distinction of persons, shows that the intra·
trinitarian movement of life and love between Father and Son ends in the Holy
Spirit as the bond of unity.
The introduction of the {i/ioque created a canonical as well as a dogmatic
problem for the East. From the canonical standpoint the East objected to the
introduction of the (iUoque as Illicit according to the canons. It saw in the
aCllon a viola lion of the seventh canon of the Council of Ephesus (431 ), which
had forbidden the formation of a different confession of faith (helera pislis)."
The Latins, however, saw in the {jlioquc not a different faith but an explication
of one and the same faith as had been professed by Nicaea and Constantinople.
It was above all Patriarch PhOlius in the ninth century who lOok up the
objective dogmatic question: - He opposed the Latin {ilioqlle and set in its
place the formula ek mOIlOll lOll palTOs (from the Father alone). This formula
has a legitimate meaning when ekporcltsis is given its strict Greek meaning
and taken in the Augustinian sense of prillcipaliler procedere. But with the
polemical meaning given it by Photius this formula is itself a novelty. In thIS
Monopatrism the texts of the Greek tradition that had asserted ::t procession
from the Father through the Son, or something comparable, were brushed
aside, and any agreement with the West was rendered impossible. The Greek
church canonized Photius' views, although without shelving the older fathers,
as Photius had. The Greek tradition is broader and richer than it seems to be
when viewed through Photius' polemical spectacles.
Gregory Palamas in the fourteenth century lOok a further and much more
decisive s[ep in [he theological dispute." According to him there IS no real
indwelling of the Holy Spirit in the faithful; what is poured out upon the
faithful is not the substance of God but only the uncreated action, radlonce
and glory (energeia); only his uncreated gift and not the giver himself. For this
reason it is not possible to argue back from the economic Trinity to the
immanent Trinity. The question then arises whether this radical theo!og;a
negat;va does not make the immanent Trinity irrelevant to the history of
salvation and deprive it of any role therein. The Neopalamite theologians of
our century (especially V. Lossky,1H have renewed this rejection in principle of
the {ilioqlfe; they see in Latin filioquism the root of all Latin heresies including
even the dogma of papal primacy. According 10 Lossky the {ilioqlfe connects
the Holy Spirit in a onesided way to the Son; this kind of christomonism no
longer assures the freedom of the Spirit in the church. On the other hand, since
V. Bolotov, church historian at St Petersburg, published his 'Theses on the
Fi/ioqlle',7'J a more historical judgment has to some extent prevailed even in
the Orthodox churches; these now regard the {ilioqlle as canonically irregular,
but not as a dogmatic error,
In the West [he view can be found at an early date that non-acceptance of
The Holy Spirit, Lord and Giver of Life 221
the (ilioqlle is heretical. But the positions of the great theologians of the high
Middle Ages on this matter are far more nuanced than is usually assumed.'.
In consequence, there was good reason (0 expect reunion with the Greeks at
the Council of Florence (1439--45)." The Council was aware of the Greek
distinction according to which the Son is indeed callsa of the procession of the
Spirit but not, like the Father, its prillcipimll. To that extent, the Council
acknowledges the formula 'through the Son', although it interprets this as
equivalent to the Western (ilioqlle which, it says, was rightly and reasonably
added to the creed." Because of this Western attitude it is understandable that,
even apart from political and emodonal reasons, the East was not satisfied
with the reunion offered and did not receive it. For the present-day Roman
Catholic Church the decisions of Pope Benedict XIV (1742 and 1755) are
normative: the Uniate Eastern Churches are allowed the use of the unaltered
creed of 381. This is to acknowledge thalthe formulas used in the two churches
are complementary.
The churches of the Reformation took over the confession of faith in its
Western form and therefore with the addition of the (ilioqlle. In the present
century K. Barth in particular has expressly defended the (ilioqlle."
Only with the contemporary ecumenical discussion has the question entered
a new phase." The discussion has led to the feeling that the West should restore
the original text by striking the (ilioqlle from the creed, and thus create the
conditions for a new dialogue on the Holy Spirit. But this suggestion would
produce fruit only if the East were at the same time to acknowledge that in
what it intends to say the (ilioqllc is not heretical but theologically legitimate.
In other words, East and West must reciprocally acknowledge the legitimacy
of their divergent theological traditions. Of course, if this acknowledgement
were to be given, there appears to be no reason why the West should renounce
its confessional tradition. Conversely, the West need not impose its traditio"
on the East. Such a unity in multiplicity is, in my view, a far morc appropriate
ecumencial goal than a monolithic confessional unity would be. In order to
reach this goal, it is necessary, of course, that the conversation between East
and West on the theological motives behind the (ilioqtte or its rejection be
carried to a signific.ntly deeper level. For in the final analysis, as the Neopala.
mite controversy has shown, the issue here is not a remote and abstract
theological problem but the relation between the economic Trinity and the
immanent Trinity or, to pm it more concretely, the way in which the Holy
Spirit works in the faithful and in the church.
In light of what has been said, any further ecumenical dialogue on the
(ilioqlle faces a twofold task. On the one hand, it must achieve a recognition
that East and West have two different traditions, based on a common faith,
which are both legitimate and which can therefore acknowledge and
complement each other, without either being reducible to the other. There
are present here complementary theologies and complementary formulas.
222 The Message about the God of jesus Christ
The essential concern of the (ilioque is twofold: to preserve the consubstan-
tiality (homoousios) of the Father and the Son, and to emphasize the fact
that according to the scripture the Holy Spirit is always the Spirit of Jesus
Christ, the Spirit of the Son. Conversely, the East is more concerned than
the West to maintain the monarchy of the Father and the freedom of action
of the Holy Spirit. These concerns are not contradictory, although no one
has as yet succeeded in reducing them to components and thus cancelling
while also preserving them in a higher, single theology of the Holy Spirit.
On the other hand, as the fact just noted shows, the dialogue between
East and West must make it dear that the two traditions are dealing with
different problems. The East in its confession of faith leaves open the
relation of the Spirit to the Son; the West for its part has difficulty in
conceptually distinguishing the relation of the Spirit to the Son from the
relation of the Spirit to the Father. The ultimate question that waits in the
background is that of the relation between the activity of the Holy Spirit
in the economy of salvation as the Spirit of Jesus Christ, and the being of
the Spirit within the Trinity. A dialogue on the different formulas of the
past must be conducted with an openness to the future, in order to bring
clarification to the still unresolved problems on both sides.
Only the future can show whether such a dialogue can lead to a new
common formula that accepts both traditions and at the same time opens
a way forward. One possible formula would be: 'qui ex Patre per Filium
procedit' (who proceeds from the Father through the Son). But more
important than such a commonly accepted formula is unity in the objective
truth. I have no doubt that such unity exists today despite all the differences
in images, concepts and accents, and that the differences of the theologies
in this area do not amount to a difference that should divide the churches.
Likewise more important than a new commonly accepted formula is that
the misunderstandings of the past should stimulate us to be sensitive to the
concerns of the other tradition and thereby to clarify and enrich our own
tradition, thus deepening the existing unity in truth and making both
parties more dearly conscious of it. The issue here is not a useless quarrel
about words but a deeper understanding of our salvation, that is, the
question of how the salvation effected by Jesus Christ is communicated
through the Holy Spirit. Is the Holy Spirit himself the gift of salvation, or
is salvation an uncreated or created gift that is distinct from the giver? In
what manner are we incorporated into the life of the triune God? These
are questions truly worth discussing. A hasty elimination of the (ilioque
could easily tempt us to leave problems untouched instead of seeking an
answer to them.
The Holy Spirit, Lord alld Giver of Life 223
(b) Suggestiolls for a theology of the Holy Spirit
A more profound theology of the Holy Spirit"' is confronted with the
difficulty that, unlike the Father and the Son, the Spirit is faceless as it were.
He is like the wind that blows where it will: 'You hear the sound of it, but
you do not know whence it comes or whither it goes' Uohn 3.8). Thomas
Aquinas long ago acknowledged the linguistic problem in speaking of the
Holy Spirit.'. The Holy Spirit is often described as 'the unknown God'."
H. Urs von Balthasar calls him the Unknown One beyond the Word." In
a special way the Holy Spirit expresses the mystery of God whose depths
no one knows but he (I Cor. 2.11). It is possible within limits to see the
differences berween the latin and Greek conceptions of the Holy Spirit,
which found critical expression in the latin addition of the {ilioqu. to the
creed, as originating ultimately in the fact that the Greek emphasize
especially the incomprehensibility of God and the mysteriousness of the
Spirit, while the latin doctrine of the Trinity with its analogies from the
life of the human soul strike the Greeks as rational or even rationalistic.
The Greeks regard the theological deductions which lead to the {ilioqu. as
an intolerable injection of rational thinking into the realm of the mystery
of God. This is not to deny, of course, that in its own way latin theology
likewise intends to preserve the mysteriousness and non-manipulable
freedom of the love and grace of God, which the Holy Spirit is in person.
In view of the mysteriousness of the Holy Spirit a theology of this divine
Person is possible only if we take as our point of departure what the word
of God reveals to us about him and what we know of the activity and
effects of the Spirit in the history of salvation. The starting point must not
be speculation, Neoplatonic or idealistic, but the experience of the Spirit
in history: such experience as is attested and authentically interpreted in
scripture and in the traditions that explain scripture. The basis of a theology
of the Holy Spirit is not to be found in analogies from the life of the human
spirit. The latin tradition in particular has been accusromed to such
analogies ever since Augustine; in them the Son is correlated with know-
ledge through the interior word and the Spirit with the will and the loving
union of Father and Son. Such analogies can indeed shed some light as
supplementary aids to understanding; the starting point and foundation,
however, even in Augustine, is the testimony of faith to the action of the
Spirit in the history of salvation. Only in Scholasticism, and especially in
Anselm of Canterbury and (with less genius, but with more hair-splitting
to make up for the lack) in the decadent controversies of the thirteenth and
fourteenth century schools, did such speculative deductions gain pride of
224 The Message about the God of Jesus Christ
place, whereas Thomas Aquinas is still resolute in starting from the faith
of the church and the experience of the Spirit as gift.
Of the many images which scripture uses in describing the action and
effects of the Holy Spirit (breath, ait, wind, water of life, fire or tongues of
fire, ointment and anointing, seal, peace), the most inAuential in the history
of theology has been the characterization of the Holy Spirit as gift and, in
connection with this, a~ love. According to scripture the Spirit is God's
eschatological gift; as such he completes the works of God. The scriptures
regard the Spirit as the gift without qualification (Acts 2.38; 8.20; 10.45;
11.17; Heb. 6.4; d. John 4.10). New Testament statements about the
Spirit aretherelore frequently accompanied by the verbs 'give' and 'receive'.
Through the gift of the Holy Spirit the love of God is poured out in our
hearts (Rom. 5.5). This means that the Spirit is even now given to us as a
first installment of eschatological fulfillment (II Cor. 1.22; Eph. 1.14).
With sighs he is already bringing about the eschatological fulfillment of
creation in the kingdom of the freedom of God's children (Rom. 8.1811.).
The same language recurs in the fathers of the church. Following Hilary,"
Augustine in particular developed a pneumatology of the Spirit .s gift'·
which Peter Lomb.rd>' and Thom.s Aquin.s" took up .nd c.rried further.
In addition, the Greek fathers emph.sized the point th.t.s eschatological
gift the Spirit is the sanctification, fulfillment, completion and go.1 of all
realiry; he effects the divinization of m.n and reality so that God m.y be
all in all (I Cor. 15.28)."
It is the task of theology to develop these d.ta of scripture .nd tradition
into a theology of the Holy Spirit. This does not mean drawing conclusions
from the data of scripture and tradition as though they were premises, and
thus p.ssing from the realm of binding faith into the realm of non-binding
private speculation. The point is, r.ther, to penetr.te more deeply into the
inner spirit and meaning of what is believed, in order to reach an
understanding of that which is believed (intellectus fidei). This is done by
seeking to grasp the intern.1 connection between the various experiences
and interpretations of faith (nexus mysteriorum), as well as their mutual
correspondences (ana/ogia fidei), and thus come to understand the one
mystery that is manifested in the various mysteries of faith. The point,
therefore, is not to do away with the mystery by rationalizing it but to gain
a deeper understanding of the mystery as mystery.
This penetration and understanding of the depths of the divinity is not
possible to the human spirit by its own power, but is the doing solely of
the Spirit of God (I Cor. 2.11). Theology itself is therefore a spirit-ual
process, something done in the Holy Spirit. For if we could grasp the
mystery of God with our finite intellectual powers, we would degrade his
The Holy Spirit, Lord alld Giver of Life 225
divinity; in knowing him we would misunderstand him; in trying to
conceive him we would be laying violent hands on him. If God is to remain
God in our knowing of him and not turn into an idol which we knock
together or tailor to our own measure, then God must not only reveal
himself to us 'objectively' but must also grant us the 'subjective' power to
know him; he must give us the Holy Spirit as the Spirit of faith (II Cor.
4.13) who enlightens the eyes of our heart (Eph. 1.18). He is the Spirit of
wisdom and understanding (Isa. 11.2). Only through the Holy Spirit is it
possible for us to address God as Father (Rom. 8.15; Gal. 4.6). The Spirit
gives us the ability and power to recognize as such the love of God that is
given to us in Jesus Christ and to take delight in it. In the Holy Spirit who
is God in us we are able to acknowledge God over us, God the Father, as
the one who in his Son is God among us. The Spirit enables us to recognize
God's grace as grace; through him we are able to grasp God's gift as a gift,
his love as his love; the Spirit is the subjective possibility of revelation."
Since the Spirit, in an eschatological and definitive way, reveals God's
eschatological giftness and eschatological love in us and for us, he must
also be in himself God's graciousness. For if he were not God's love and
giftness in himself 'first of all' but were this only for us, he could not reveal
to us the Godness of God, which, as we saw earlier, consists in the freedom
of his self-communicating love. The Spirit would then not reveal God as
he is but only God as and insofar as he shows himself in history. In order
that the Holy Spirit may be the subjective possibility of the eschatological
and definitive revelation of the love and thus the Godness of God, he must
himself be this freedom in love; that is, he must be God's love in person.
He must be not only God's gift but also the giver of this gift; he must
embody in a manner personal to himself that which God is by his nature.
This thesis is not an arbitrary inference from the Spirit's action in the
history of salvation to his personal divine being. That kind of inference
must inevitably be powerless in the face of the mysteriousness of the Spirit.
We can say nothing about the inner divine being of the Spirit that is not
revealed to us by the Spirit himself and attested in scripture. The only thing
in our power is to be led and enlightened by the Spirit so as to know the
internal connection and internal correspondence berween what revelation
says about the action of the Spirit in the history of salvation and what it
says about his divine being.
These reflections are confirmed and carried further by Augustine's
comments on the subject. Augustine asks himself the question: how is it
possible to call the Spirit the gift and love of God when love and giftness
are the very nature of God and therefore common to all the divine persons?
In his answer he distinguishes berween love in the substantial sense and
226 The Message abollt the God of Jeslls Christ
love in the person31 sense. In the substantial sense love is the very being of
God and common to all the divine persons; in the personal sense it is said
in a special way of the Holy Spirit. 9s According to Augustine, then, the
Holy Spirit expresses in a personal manner the giftness and love of the
Father and the Son; he is in his very person the reciprocal love of the Father
and the Son. 96 Unlike the Son he proceeds from the Father qllomodo datlls
(as given) and not qllomodo nallIs (as born)." The Spirit thus shows that
the giftness and love of God do not first become a reality in the form of a
gift made in the course of history, but are instead a reality from all eternity;
in other words that God is from eternity 'givable' (dO//abi/e)." The Spirit
is thus 'God in such a way' 'that he can at the same time be called the gift
of God'." Here we have the deepest reason why the Holy Spirit as gift is
at the same time giver of the gift.
We may sum up and say that the Holy Spirit reveals, and is, the giftness
of God as gift, love as love. The Spirit thus expresses the innermost nature
of God - God as self-communicating love - in such a way that this
innermost reality proves at the same time to be the outermost, that is, the
possibility and reality of God's being outside of himself. The Spirit is as it
were the ecstasy of God; he is God as pure abundance, God as the overAow
of love and grace. IOU On the one hand, then, the immanent love of God
reaches its goal in the Spirit. But at the same time, because in the Holy
Spirit the Father and the Son as it were understand and realize themselves
as love, the love of God in the Spirit also moves beyond God himself.
This loving streaming-out-beyond occurs not in the form of a necessary
streaming-out but in the personal manner of voluntary sharing and free,
gracious self-communication. In the Spirit God has as it were the possibility
of being himself by emptying or divesting himself. In the Holy Spirit God
is eternally givable. With this in mind the fathers often compared the Spirit
to the wafted perfume of an ointment lOl orthought of him as the radiating
beauty of God, the traces of which can be seen in created beauty, in the
wealth of created gifts, and in the abundance that marks creation. IOI
As completion within God the Spirit is, then, also the eschatological
completion of the world.
This theology of the Holy Spirit affords correctives to numerous tenden-
cies in Eastern theology as well as to the Neo·scholastic type of Western
theology. Unlike the Palamite theologians, I understand grace not as
uncreated energy but as the real self-communication of God in and through
the indwelling of the hypostasis of the Holy Spirit. Through the indwelling
of the Holy Spirit, who has been given to us, we participate in the divine
nature (Il Peter 1.4). But, differently from what took place in the self-
communication of the Son of God, we do not, through the Spirit, become
The Holy Spirit, Lord alld Giver of Life 227
children of God by reason 01 a generation, that is, substantially; rather we
become sons and daughters 01 God through gilt and grace or, in other
words, we become children 01 God by adoption. (Rom. 8.15,23; Gal. 4.5).
In thus taking seriously what the New Testament says about the
indwelling of the Holy Spirit and in speaking not only of an indwelling 01
God that is simply appropriated to the Holy Spirit but rather 01 a
personal (hypostatic) indwelling, I also diller lrom Neo·scholasticism in its
understanding 01 grace as a created reality distinct from God. 10' Grace is
rather first 01 all uncreated grace, God's sell-communication in the Holy
Spirit. To say this is not to exdude created grace. For uncreated grace
changes the human person within; it has created ellects, and it requires an
acceptance by man that is possible only through grace. Therefore uncreated
grace, or the indwellingol the Holy Spirit, requires created grace to prepare
the way lor it, just as it also has created grace lor a consequence. It is
impossible, therefore, to conceive 01 the sell-communication 01 God in the
Holy Spirit apart lrom the manilold gifts 01 the Holy Spirit that are distinct
lrom God and therefore created.
All this makes it dear that a theology of the Holy Spirit as both giver
and gilt, and thus a theology 01 the Holy Spirit as sell-g,ft, is the ultimate
ground or, in other language, the transcendental theological condition for
the possibility 01 the reality and ellective realization 01 the salvation that
is bestowed on us through Jesus Christ. It is also dear, then, that the
theology 01 the Holy Spirit does not take us out of the realm of faith but
on the contrary leads us more deeply into to. This theology proves its value
by giving us a deeper understanding 01 what salvation really is. Thomas
Aquinas, in particular, has given a magnificent explanation 01 how the
action and ellects 01 the Holy Spirit are to be understood in the light 01 the
Holy Spirit as divine love in person.''''
Since the Spirit is divine love in person, he is, first 01 all, the source 01
creation, lor creation is the outflow of God's love and a participation in
God's being. The Holy Spirit is the internal (in God) presupposition of this
communicability of God outside olhimself. But the Spirit is also the source
of movement and life in the created world. Wherever something new arises,
whenever lile is awakened and reality reaches ecstatically beyond itself, in
all seeking and striving, in every lerment and birth, and even more in the
beauty of creation, something 01 the activity and being 01 God's Spirit is
manilested. The Second Vatican Council sees this universal activity of the
Spirit not only in the religions 01 mankind but also in human culture and
human progress. lOS We may even say that because the Spirit is the inner
condition for the possibility 01 creation, the latter is already always more
228 The Message abollt the God of jeslls Christ
than pure nature.'.' Through the presence and action of the Holy Spirit
creation already always has a supernatural finality and character.
Secondly, the Holy Spirit is in a special way a source in the order of
grace. He is at work everywhere that human beings seek and find friendship
with God. A loving union with God is possible for us only through the
Holy Spirit. 107 Through the Spirit we are in God and God is in us. Through
him we are God's friends, sons and daughters, who, because we are
impelled from within, serve God not as slaves but as free beings and who
are filled with joy and consolation by this friendship with God. The grace
of the Holy Spirit, which is given through faith in Jesus Christ, is thus, as
Thomas Aquinas has shown, the law of the new covenant. This law is a
law written in the heart, as interior law that moves us from within, and
therefore a law of freedom.'·' Joy in God is the real freedom of the children
of God. This freedom manifests itselfin the many charisms (I Cor. 12.4-11 )
and fruits (Gal. 5.22f.) of the Holy Spirit. The supreme gift and fruit of the
Spirit is love (I Cor. 13), for he is truly free who is not tied to himself but
can surrender himself in the service of love (Gal. 5.13). This freedom that
is given by the Spirit shows itself most fully in a love that renounces self
even in the situation of persecution and suffering. In perseverance under
persecution and in the patient endurance of suffering, the interior independ-
ence of the powers and principalities that press on us from without reaches
its most complete form. Not without reason is the Spirit often described
both in scripture Uohn 15f.) and in tradition as strength (rob"r) for
resistance. He is at the same time the Spirit of truth Uohn 15.26; 16.13)
who brings true reality to light despite efforts to distort and suppress it by
violence and lies, and thus allows the splendor of God's glory to radiate
upon the world once again. This healing and transforming power of the
Spirit finds its most beautiful expression in the well known hymns to the
Holy Spirit Velli Creator Spirittts ('Creator Spirit, come'; ninth century)
and Velli Sancte Spirittts ('Come, Holy Spirit'; twelfth century). In these
hymns the Spirit is described as the life·giving creative Spirit who, as the
Holy Spirit, also fills the heart with the breath of the grace-life of love. He
expels the powers of evil, deanses what is soiled, fructifies what is arid,
gives warmth to what is cold and heals what is ill. In the sanctifying action
ofthe Holy Spiritlhe eschatological transformation and fulfillment of man
and world dawns in us.
Thirdly, what has been said of the Spirit has consequences for the
understanding of the church. If the Spirit is the authentic presence and
realization of the salvation given through Jesus Christ, then whatever is
external in the church - scripture and sacraments, offices and certainly the
discipline of the church - has for its sole task to prepare men for receiving
The Holy Spirit, Lord and Giver of Life 229
the gift of the Spirit, to serve in the transmission of this gift, and to enable
it to work effectively .'09 This means that the reign of Christ extends beyond
and embraces more than the visible church. Wherever there is love, the
Spirit of God is at work, and the reign of Christ becomes a reality even
without institutional forms and formulas. 110 It also means that the Holy
Spirit is the internal life'principle or soul of the visible church. 11I The
church must live by the power of the Spirit and constantly renew itself by
that power. The constant presence and operation of the Spirit keeps the
church always young. The action of the Spirit in the church takes the form
of making Jesus Christ present ever anew in his newness. 1I2 Precisely as
the Spirit of Jesus Christ the Spirit is the Spirit of freedom from the letter
that kills. The Spirit preserves the church in its fidelity to tradition by
leading it in a prophetic way into the entire truth and making known to it
what is coming Uohn 16.13). He is not a kind of ideological guarantee of
the church's status quo, but rather the Spirit of continual renewal. Above
all, he makes known to the church ever new missionary opportunities, and
points out ever new ways for it to go. He urges the church to heed his
action in the 'signs of the times', to interpret these, and in their light to
gain a deeper understanding of the Christian message.
In all these ways, the Spirit, who searches and knows the depths of the
godhead (I Cor. 2.11), enables us to gain an ever deeper knowledge and
ever greater love of God. Therefore it is he who also leads us into the depths
of God by enabling us to know who God is as Father, Son and Spirit. He
discloses to us the triune being of God and makes possible that knowledge
of the Trinity in which the deepest mystery of the God of Jesus Christ finds
its abiding and binding expression.
PART THREE
There arc a number of passages in the Old Testament in which God is depicted
as speaking of himself in the plural; in these especially the fathers of the church
saw imimations that there is more than one person in God. They appealed, for
example, [0 the statement: 'let us make man in our image, after our likeness'
(Gen. 1.26; d. 3.22; 11.7; Isa. 6.8). Contemporary exegetescannot acceptthis
explanation. Also improbable is the explanation often given in the P;1St, that
we have here a 'plural of majesty': God speaks of himself as 'we' just as kings
and popes used to speak of themselves as 'we'. It is likely, in fact, that the
plural is the stylistic device know as the 'plural of deliberation': the plural used
when a person is taking counsel with himself and engaging in soliloquy." The
we-formulas do at least suggest, however, that the God of the Old Testament
is not lifeless but a living God, characterized by a superabundant fullness of
vitality and compassion.
For the church fathers and the medieval theologians a further important
element in the biblical basis for the confession of the triune God was the
manifestation of God in the form of three men or angels to Abraham under
the oaks of Mamre (Gen. 18). This scene is extremely rich in meaning not only
for theology but also for the history of piety and art. We find it in many
iconographic represcnt3cions and in particular in Rublev's famous fifrcenth -
century icon. lJ But once again it is less easy for us to accept this imerpretation
of the passage. On the other hand, the passage does suggest" mysterious
interaction within the one God who speaks and acts and manifests himself in
three figures. Finally, the church fathers cited the two angels near the throne
of God in Isa. 6, and the triple 'Holy!, offered to God. This interpretation, too,
seems impossible to us today. Once again! however, it has great symbolic
importance, for in its own way it shows that in {he time of the church fathers
the trinitarian confession did not originate in pure theory and abstract
speculation but rather had its vital context (Sitz ill! Leben) in the doxology,
that is, in the liturgical glorification of God."
More important than the texts thus far mentioned is the figure of the 'angel
of Yahweh' (Illa/ak" ja"we) in the Old Testament. He accompanies Israel
on its journey in the wilderness (Ex. 14.19), helpsthose in need (Gen. 16.7;
I Kings 19.5; I Kings 1.3), and protects the devout (Ps. 34.8). He makes
known God's power (Zech. 12.8) and knowledge (II Sam. 14.20). While
in these passages the angel of Yahweh is a revelatory figure distinct from
God, at other times he is identical with Yahweh (Gen. 31.11, 13; Ex. 3.2,
Establishmellt of the Doctrille of the Trillity 243
4f. ). The 'angel of the Lord' thus represents an effort to bridge the gap
between the being of God, which to man is incomprehensible and hidden,
and God's active and substantial presence in history.J> The angel of Yahweh
thus prefigures the whole later problem of the identity and difference
between God in himself and the form he takes in revelation. It also brings
out in a most expressive manner the fact that the Old Testament God is a
living God of history.
In the later writings of the Old Testament the conviction that God is
superabundant life finds expression in passages that talk of various
hypostases. The most important ofthese is divine wisdom, which is spoken
of as a kind of hypostasis distinct from God (d. especially Provo 8). Also
noteworthy arc the personifications of the divine Word (Ps. 119.89;
147.15ff.; Wisdom 16.12) and the divine Spirit (Hag. 2.5; Neh. 9.30; lsa.
63.10; Wisdom 1.7) . 'These personifications bear witness to the wealth of
life in Yahweh and, from the viewpoint of the history of revelation, are a
first hesitant anticipation of the disclosure in the New Testament that the
one divine substance is marked by a pluripersonal fullness of being.'''
These personifications provided the New Testament with a point of
departure.
Behind these various hints and indications there is a common objective
question. By its very nature the Old Testament understanding of God as
personal inevitably led to the question: who is God's appropriate vis-a·
vis? An I wit.hout a Thou is unthinkable. But is man, the human race, or
the people the appropriate or proper vis·a·vis for God? If man were God's
sale vis-a-vis, then man would be a necessary partner of God. Man would
then no longer be the one who is loved with an abyssal free and gracious
love, and God's love for man would no longer be God's gracious act but
rather a need of God and a completion of God. But such a conclusion
would be utterly contradictory to the Old Testament. The Old Testament
therefore raises a question to which it gives no answer. The Old Testament
picture of the living God is not finished and complete but open to the
definitive revelation of God. It is only 'a shadow of the good things to
come' (Heb. 10.1).
The Leitmotiv or dominant theme is stated in the vety first verse: the gloty of
the Father and the Son. This glory includes salvation or, to use John's term,
life. In turn, life consists in knowing the only true God and Jesus Christ whom
he has sent, (17.3). In John, 'to know' is more than a simple act ofthe intellect;
true knowledge includes acknowledgment of the lordship (in being and action)
of God; it includes the glorification of God. Those who know God as God and
acknowledge and glorify him, are in the light; they have discovered the meaning
of their life and the light that shines in all reality Uohn 1.4). Doxology is thus
at the same time soteriology.
The theme is then developed in detail. The Son glorifies the Father by
bringing to completion the work the Father has given him (17.4) and specifically
by revealing the Father's name to men (17.6), leading them 10 faith (17.8) and
sanctifying them in truth (17.17, 19). Parallel with the glorification of the
Father through sanctification in truth is the communication of life. The Father
has this life in himself; he has also granted the Son to have life in himself (5.26)
and to bestow it on men (17.2). This life consists in knowing that Jesus ChriS!
is life, because he is life from life, God from God, light from light (17.7). Life
consists therefore in knowing the glory which Jesus has with the Father, even
before the world existed (17.5). 'I desirethatthey ... behold my glory which
thou haS! given me in thy love for me before the foundation of the world'
(17.24). Those who acknowledge this facr share in this same eternal love
(17.23,26) and in the glory ofthe F3!her and the Son (17.22). The knowledge
and confession of the eternal divine sonship of Jesus brings communion with
him and through him with God (17.21-24).
The glorification of the Father by the Son thus has for its goal the participation
of the disciples in this glorification and in eternal life. Thus Jesus' prayer of
praise to the Father leads in the sc:ccmd part to a prayer of petitionj doxology
248 The Trinitarian Mystery of God
leads to epidesis. Theobjectof the petition is that the disciples may be preserved
in truth (17.11) and may .bide in unity with one .nother, with Jesus .nd,
through Jesus, with God (17.21-24). This prayer of Jesus for his disciples is,
in the final analysis, a proyer for the sending of the other Por.dete, the Spirit
(14.16). This Spirit is the Spirit of truth (14.17), who will guide the disciples
into the whole truth (16.13). He does this by glorifying Jesus (16.14) and
bearing witness to him. He does not speak on his own authority but only of
what Jesus is and of what is from the Father (16.14f.; eI. 14.26). Through the
action of the Spirit, then, the union of Father and Son becomes the union of
the disciples among themselves. The Spirit drows the f.ithful into the unity
which is the mork of the divine being (el. 10.38; 14.10f., 20, 23; 15.41.;
17.21-26).
The unity of Father and Son thus becomes the ground that makes possible
.nd vitalizes the unity of the faithful, and the unity of the latter is in turn
to be a sign to the world (17.21). The revel3tion of eternal love leads to
the gathering of the scattered flock under. single shepherd (10.16). The
unity, peace .nd life of the world thus come .bout through the revel3tion
of the glory of the F3ther, Son and Holy Spirit. The trinit3rian doxology
is the soteriology of the world.
In the First Letter of John we find v.rious trinitarian groupings (4.2;
5.6-8). These indude the so-called Johannine Comma [section of a
sentence]: 'There are three who give testimony in heaven: the F3ther, the
Word, and the Holy Spirit; and these three are one' (I John 5.7f.).
This trinitari.n formul. is generally regarded today however, as a later
insertion.·' Extremely import.nt is the summorizing statement that God
is love (I John 4.8,16). This means, to begin with, that in the revelational
event which is Jesus Christ God h.s shown himself to be love. But
this revelational event consists precisely in m.king known the eternal
communion of love, life and reciproc.1 glorification between Father, Son
and Spirit, in orderth3t through this revebtion the disciples and, with their
help, mankind may be drawn into this s.me communion of love and life.
The revelational statement 'God is love' is therefore at the same time a
statement about the being of God and, as such,. st3tement about salvation.
Only because God is love can he reveal and communicate himself to us as
love. The unity of church .nd world, the peace and reconciliation of
mankind have their ultimate ground and ultimate possibility, .s seen by
Christians, in the acknowledgment of the glory of God in the love of Father,
Son and Spirit. This summary of the entire New Testament mess.ge alre.dy
lays the found3tion for the 13ter specul3tive development of the doctrine
of the Trinity, a development which h.s for its sale aim to understand the
Establishmellt of the Doctrille of the Trillity 249
trinitarian confession of scripture in terms of its deepest roots and in the
overall context of the whole reality of salvation.
The New Testament message thus proves to be trinitarian not only in
the details of what it says but also in its basic structure. In saying this, I
oppose the thesis of O. Cullmann that the basic structure of the New
Testament profession of faith is purely christological, so that 'when all is
said and done the development of christological formulas ultimately
distorted the interpretation of the essence of Christianity'" This thesis is
antecedently improbable in view of the fact that the revelation in the New
Testament presupposes Old Testament revelation and brings it to its
transcendent fulfillment. Therefore, contrary to what O. Cullmann bel-
ieves, the New Testament docs not concern itself solely with the journey
of Jesus Christ to the Father; rather, faith in Jesus Christ is based in turn
on the testimony of the Father (Matt. 3.17; 17.5; John 5.37f.). People
believe in Jesus because the Father has raised him from the dead and
established him as Lord. Moreover, the saving act of Jesus Christ includes
the sending of the Holy Spirit. Only in the Holy Spirit is it possible to
confess Jesus as Lord (I Cor. 12.5f.), and only in the Spirit do we have a
share in the reality of Jesus. Consequently, a christological confession is
possible only in the form of a trinitarian confession. Faith in Christ and
existence as a Christian depend on the confession of the Trinity.
The outcome of the Arian conflict (in which the outcome of the gnostic
conflict played a part) and subsequent developments was the definition by
the Council of Nicaea (325) of the oneness in being (hollloollsios) of the
Son with the Father,12S and the definition by the Council of Constantinople
(381) of the Spirit as having the same dignity as the Father and the Son.126
The confession of Nicaea culminates in the statement that the Son is one
in being (ho",00lls;05) with the Father. But the term hOllloollsios soon
proved to be 'the sensitive point of the Nicene symbol, the arrow stuck in
the side of Arianism, and the sign of contradiction that was to be debated
for over half a century'.l27
The concept did have several disadvantages: it was not biblical but
gnostic in origin; in addition, it had been condemned in a different but not
fully explained sense at a Council of Antioch which had been convoked in
269 against Paul of Samosata; finally, even its content was not completely
unambiguous. The intention of the concept was to express the truth that
the Son is not created but begotten and that he belongs on the side not of
258 T"e Trinitarian Mystery of God
creatures but of God. The question that arose, however, was this: docs
"0"'00IlSi05 mean the same being with the Father or of one being with the
Father? The first interpretation could be misunderstood as tritheistic, the
second as modalist. The answer to the question emerges from the context
rather than from the term and concept itself. After all, the confession of
Nicaea begins with a confession of the one God, the Father, who by his
nature can only be one and unique. The Son, who is no less divine than the
Father, is of the being and hypostasis of the Father (being and hypostasis
still had the same meaning at Nicaea). It follows that the Son likewise
possesses the essentially unique and indivisible divine being that is proper
to the Father. The unity of being and not merely the sameness of being in
Father and Son is thus clear only as a conclusion from the whole tenor of
the confession. 12 !!
This interpretation of "0",00Ilsi05 has certain implications for the
doctrine of the Trinity that underlies and is implicit in the Nicene creed:
1. The Council docs not proceed monotheistically from the one being of
God and then speak in trinitarian language of the Father, Son and Holy
Spirit as the three ways in which this one being concretely exists. The creed
starts rather with the Father and understands him as the 'summit of unity'
in which the Son and the Spirit are comprehended. We thus have a genetic
conception of the divinity, in which the divinity originates in the Father
and streams forth in the Son and the Holy Spirit.'"
2. The Council obviously lacks the conceptual tools for expressing in an
adequate way the unity of being and distinction of persons. At this point
Nicaea presses beyond itself. The clear distinctions which Tertullian had
already made could win adherence only after a long and difficult process
of clarification.
The needed clarification was won in the half-century between Nicaea (325)
and Constantinople (381). The Semi-Arians were of the opinion that the
homoollsios meant a modalisric blurring of the distinction between Father and
Son, and they sought to rescue the distinction by adding a single letter to the
word and speaking instead of ho",o;oIlS;OS (i.e., like the Father butnor identical
with him), This compromise was untenable because it did not do justice to the
profound concern expressed in the "omooIl5;05. A solution began to emerge
when Athanasius, the great champion of the Niccne orientation, effected a
rapprochement at the Council of Alexandria in 362 by accepting a distinction
between three hypostases and one being. This meant that two concepts used
as identical at Nicaea were now differentiated. ull
The more precise conceptual clarification of this distinction was the work
of the three Cappadocian Fathers (Basil of Caesarea, Gregory of Nazaianzus,
and Gregory of Nyssa). Basil followed the Stoics in looking upon the being
Establishmellt of the Doctrille of the Trillity 259
(ol/sia) as something general and not limited to a particular entity. Thus the
generic concept 'man' is the common predicate of any individual human beings.
The hypostases (hypostaseis) , on the contrary, are the concrete individual
cmbodimems of this common being. Hypostases come into being as complexes
of idiomato, i.e., individualizing characteristics. These idiomata arc here
understood nor as accidents bur as constitutive elements of the concrete
cxis(cnr. 1J1 Peculiar to the Father is the fact that he owes his being to no other
cause; peculiar co the Son is his generation from the Father; peculiar to the
Holy Spirit is that he is known after and with the Son and that he has his
substance from the F3ther.lJ!
\V/cstcrners had trouble with this distinction, because hypostasis was often
translated into Latin by the word substantia. DJ It would seem to Westerners,
therefore, that three hypostases meant three divine substances, thus leading to
trithcisrn or a doctrine of three Gods. Conversely, Tertulliilnts distinction
between natura ilnd persona WilS difficult for the East, because persona was
translated as prosop01f; prosopoll, however, meant a mask, that is, a mere
appearance, and thus suggested modalism. For this reason Basil issued a
warning that, as understood in the confession of faith, the persons (prosiipa)
in God exist as hypostases. 1H Once this equivalence was generally accepted,
all the major church provinces were saying materially the same thing despite
the different concepts used: Caesarea (Basil), Alexandria (Athanasius), Gaul
(Hilary), Italy and especially Rome (Damasus). Thus after one of the most
turbulent periods in the history of the church all the presuppositions for a
solution were at hand.
The resolution came with the Council of Constantinople (381) and its
reception by the Roman synod under Pope Damasus (382). In its doctrinal
letter Constantinople gave expression to the distinction between the one
substance (ol/sia; sl/bstalltia) and the three perfect hypostases (hypostaseis;
sllbsistelltiae).IJS This meant that the Nicene formula, according to which
the Son is from the being (ol/sia) of the Father was now dropped. lJ6 But
the Roman synod, like Pope Damasus in his doctrinal letter of 374,Jl7
spoke of one sllbstalllia and three personae.'" The difference was not
merely one of terminology. While the creeds of Nicaea and Constantinople
start with the Father and then confess the Son and the Spirit to be one in
being or substance with the Father, the West replaces this dynamic
conception with a more static approach that starts with the one substance
and then says that it subsists in three persons. But these differences were
not regarded at that time as dividing the church. The two formulas bring
out the possible plurality and wealth of theologies that are based on a
single common faith. A synthesis of the two differenct vocabularies and
approaches came only at the fifth ecumenical council, the Second Council
of Constantinople (553), which combined them in one and the same
260 The Trinitarian Mystery of God
formula. Meanwhile Boethius and Leontius of Byzantium had clarified the
concept of person, which the East had originally found so difficult. \J9 As
a result the Council could take hypostasis and person as synonyms, and
state: 'If anyone does not confess that Father, Son and Holy Spirit are one
nature (physis; natllra) or essence (ollsia; sllbstantia), one might and
power, a Trinity one in being (hornoollsios), one Godhead 10 be worshipped
in three hypostases (hypostaseis; sllbsistelltiae) or persons (prosopa;
personae), anathema sit."'O The Council then adds 10 this static and
extremely abstract technical theological definition a statement that is more
dynamic in character and based on the history of salvation: 'For one is the
God and Father from whom all things are, one is the Lord Jesus Christ
through whom all things are and one the Holy Spirit in whom all things
are,'I"1
A comparison of the two formulas shows the long and difficult road
travelled in the doctrinal development leading from the Bible to the 'fully
developed' dogmatic confessional formula. These passionate debates were
'not involved in useless hair-splilling and conceptual quibbles. The aim was
the greatest possible fidelity and exactitude in the interpretation of the
biblical datum. This last was so new and unparalleled that it turned all
traditional conceptual thinking upside down. It was therefore by no means
enough simply 10 apply concepts from Greek philosophy 10 the traditional
confession of faith. All such allempts ended in heresy. The need was 10
reAect on the data of scripture and tradition and 10 break away from the
one-sidedly essentialist thinking of Greek philosophy and into a personalist
thinking that did justice 10 the scriptures, thus laying the foundation of a
new type of thought. From the theological standpoint, this shift made it
possible to bring out the specifically Christian form of monotheism as
distinct from that of either Judaism or paganism. To that extent, the
wearisome and difficult debates with gnosticism and with the heresies of
right and left retain a permanent basic significance for the church and its
identity. No wonder, then, that in the later period the formulas we have
been examining were constantly repeated.'" The best known example is
the QlliClllllqlle, also know as the (Pseudo-) Athanasian Creed. ~'J Of
course, the price to be paid for this conceptual clarity also became clear in
the course of time. This consisted in the increasing danger that the abstract
conceptual formulas would become independent and lose their character
as interpretations of the historical action of God through Christ in the
Holy Spirit. The vital historical faith of scripture and tradition threatened
to rigidify into abstract formulas which are .materially correct but which,
isolated from the history of salvation, become unintelligible and function-
less for an existential faith.
Establishment of the Doctrine of the Trinity 261
The Nicene-Constantinopolitan confession was thus, on the one hand,
the result of long and passionate debate; as such it has remained down to
our own day the common foundation for all churches of both East and
West. On the other hand, that confession was also the point of departure
for further theological reflection. After Nicaea and Constantinople this
reflection led to a momentous change of perspective. Tertullian and Origen
were still taking as their starting point the divinity of the Father and then,
in the interests of the economy of salvation, asserting the equality of Son
and Spirit with the Father. 14 ' Origen even distinguished within this one
economy specific areas of operation for Father, Son and Spirit.'" Basil,
however, rejected this view, 146 andon the basis of the one nature theologians
now concluded that the three divine persons act together in all operations
ad extra. This thesis was common to the fathers of both East and West,'47
although the Eastern fathers brought out more clearly the fact that this
common action still expresses the internal trinitarian structure of God;
that is, that the Father acts through the Son in the Holy Spirit.'48 The shift
in outlook shows most clearly in the liturgical doxologies, thus indicating
once again that these were the Sit: im Leben of the trinitarian confession
of faith. In the original liturgical doxology glory is given to the Father
through the Son in the Holy Spirit. But Basil already makes a change which
is then taken over at Constantinople: the Spirit is glorified together with
the Father and the Son. Thus a doxology based on the one nature or
substance of God takes its place alongside the doxology that reflects the
history of salvation: 'Glory be to the Father and to the Son and to the Holy
Spirit.'J49
This development took place in both East and West, although in different
circumstances. In both cases the need was to eliminate (he last traces of
Arianism. In the East these traces took the form chiefly of Eunomianism, which
reduced Arian thinking to a formal, dialectical, almost rationalistic system,lSO
In order to counter it, the Greek Fathers were compelled to emphasize the
mysteriousness of God and the eternal processions in God.'" As a result, they
no longer started with the order found in the economy in order then to make
their way back to the order within God. Trinitarian theology and the economy
were henceforth separated. The emphasis on the Father having shown his face
to us concretely in Jesus Christ was replaced by a radically negative theology
afa Neoplatoniccast, in whichgrearcrsrress was pur on the incomprehensibility
of God than on the truth that the Incomprehensible had, in an incomprehensible
way, made itself comprehensible in Jesus Christ. l52 God's trinitarian being was
regarded as unknowable in itselfj only its rays, or energies, 3rc knowable. ISJ
Hints in this direction that are to be found in the Cappadocian Fathers were
262 The Trinitarian Mystery of God
developed in the fourteenth century, especially by Gregory Pal am as. The
Trinity thus ccased to have any function in the economy of salvation. IH
It is obvious that the West, too, regarded the incomprehensibiliry of the
Trinity as beyond question. U5 But there, especially in Augustine, analogies
between the human spirit as image of God and the T riniry played a key role.
In the West, the conflict with Arianism led to such an emphasis on the
homoousios that the one nature or substance of God became the basis on
which the entire doctrine of the Trinity was explained. Over and over we find
in Augustine such statements as: the Trinity is the one true God, 1J6 or: God is
the Trinity.1.S7 The distinction of the three persons was made within the one
nature and, in the final analysis, remained a problem for Augustine.'" This
Augustinian tendency was accentuated in Anselm of Canterbury,159 The term
of this development in the Latin West was the formula of the Fourth Lateran
Council, according to which in their action ad extra the three divine persons
are a single principle of operation. "'This applied not only to the act of creating
but also to the history of salvation. Thomas Aquinas even held the thesis that
in the abstract anyone of the divine persons could have become man. 161 Even
in the early Middle Ages, however, and cert.inly in Thomas himself there were
contrary tendencies in the direction of 3 Trinity that reflects the economy of
salvation; of these I will be speaking further on. "1 But in late medieval
Nominalism a complete sep:u3rion was made between God's being in itself
and God's action in the history of salvation, and the potetttio ordinala or
'ordered power' of God th.t is reve.led in the history of s.lvation threatened
to give place to a divine freedom that is completely arbitrary in its exercise 16)
and no longer bears the stamp of the inrra·divine trinitarian Structure.
The Reformers took over the trinitarian confession,164 but it was no more
fruitful in their case than it had been in Scholasticism. With some anenuations
the trinitarian confession has also become part of the basic unifying formula
of the World Council of Churches. " .• In practice, however, many churches and
even many Catholic communities and Catholic Chrisrians seem to regard this
confession .s no more than. relic of venerable antiquity. The difficulty is that
the churches have all too long emphasized and defended the intern.l triuneness
of God without saying wh.t this should me.n for us. The doctrine of the
immanent Trinity, which was originally mean{ to be the basis and guarantee
of the doctrine of the economic Trinity, has in practice become 3n independent
entity. No wonder, then, that at the time of the Enlightenment people asked
what practical value it had. Since the answer was 'None', the doctrine of
the Trinity was either jettisoned IN or, at best, preserved, from a sense of
duty, .s a kind of appendix. Characteristic of this second appro.ch is F.
Schleiermacher's thesis in his The Christian Faith: 'Our faith in Christ and our
living fellowship with Him would be the same although we had.no knowledge
of .ny such tr.nscendent f.ct {as the Trinityl, or although the fact itself were
different: 167 And in fact many, if not the majority of Christi3ns today are in
practice pure monotheists, i.e., believers in a monopersonal God.
Establishment of the Doctrine of the Trinity 263
This situation, in which living and experiential faith is in danger of losing
the basic structure proper to it as Christian, poses a powerful challenge to
theologians. They will not succeed in once again making the trinitarian
confession a vital part of experiential faith unless they are able to bring
home to Christians the importance of this confession for their salvation.
This in turn means that they must pay greater attention to the connection
between the economic Trinity and the immanent Trinity. The soteriological
motives which in Irenaeus and Tertullian and especially in Athanasius lead
to the development of the homool/sios doctrine, must once again be
emphasized so that the Trinity may recover its importance for man and his
salvation. There is need, in addition, to highlight once again the brilliant
insights of Origen as clarified and purified with the aid of Nicaea and
Constantinople 3nd, in response to the neo-gnostic currents of our time,
to develop a comprehensive and specifically Christian vision of reality on
the basis of the trinitarian confession. There is need, in other words, to
hold fast to the Nicene·Constantinopolitan confession of the independent
reality of the immanent Trinity, while at the same time saying what this
doctrine means for us within the economy of salvation. Here we have the
basic task of a contemporary doctrine of the Trinity.
II
Exposition of the Doctrine of the Trinity
It was Hegel who attempted the most important and momentous of these new
approaches. In his philosophy of religion (to which I limit myself here) Hegel
st:lrts from the modern alienation and separation between religion and life,
Expositioll of the Doctrille of the Trillity 265
between weekday and Sunday.' As a result of this separation, the weekday
becomes the world of the finite, lacking in any true depth, while religion for
its part is emptied of all concrete content; religion turns cold and dead,
wearisome and burdensome. 'Religion shrivels and becomes a maner of mere
feeling, an empty elevation of the spirit to something eternal, and so on. -of For
this reason theology has been reduced to a minimum of dogmas. 'Its content
has become extremely attenuated despite all the talk and erudition and
argumentation.'s But the exegesis and history serve in fact only to do away
with the basic doctrines of Christianiry. The symbol, the regula fidei, is no
longer regarded as binding.' 'As a result, people have only a general knowledge
that God is, and they regard him simply as a supreme being that is empty and
dead in itself and cannot be grasped as a concrete content, as spirit ... If God
as 'spirit' is not to be simply an empty word for us, then he must be conceived
as a triune God." In this respect, according to Hegel, there is a great deal more
dogmatic theology in philosophy than in dogmatic theology itself.'
Hegel's intention, therefore, is to recover the living God and for him this
means the triune God. But he wants to do this in his own fashion. He wants
to reduce the naive represeneacion of Father, Son and Spirit to concepts; he
wanes to understand God as a spirit whose essence it is to make himself an
object for himself in order then to remove this distinction through love.' His
intention, therefore, is to go beyond the abstract concept of God as supreme
being and to think God as a spirit who becomes objective to himself in the Son
and then recovers himself in 10ve.1O Hegel is here expressly harking back to
gnostic and Neoplatonic thinking. 1I In the final analysis the divine Triniry is
the interpretation of the statement that God is love. For 'love is a distinguishing
of two who nonetheless are not simply distinct in relation to one another'.1l
This in turn means that the divine Trinity is a mystery for the imagination and
for abstract thought but not for speculative thinking. 'The nature of God is
not a mystery in the usual sense of the word, least of all in the Christian religion.
Here God has given himself to be known as he is; here he is made plain.''' It
was this reduction of religion to the level of the imagination and the speculative
sublimation of religion in an absolute concept that first and foremost elicited
the opposition of the theologians and the churches. They saw in Hegel's
approach a failure to preserve the mystery and hidden ness of God."
It would be wrong, however, to dismiss Hegel's speculation about the Trinity
as simply a new form of gnosticism. For from one point of view it is directly
opposed to the gnostic systems. The gnostic systems organize their thinking in
a scheme of descent and decline, whereas Hegel's thinking must be regarded
as a scheme of ascent and progress. At the beginning stands something abstract
and general, namely, the Father, who then first defines himself in another self,
namely, the Son, and finally, in a third, the Spirit, becomes a concrete idea.
Admittedly, this process does not produce anything new. 'The third is also the
first'; 'What is produced already exists from the beginning.' 'The process, then,
is simply a game of self·preservation, of self·confirmation.'1S It is a fact,
266 The Trillitariall Mystery of God
however, that truth can be identified only with the whole, and that the whole
exists only at the end. Hi In a sense Hegel has thus rediscovered the eschatological
dimension ofthe Trinity, which the theological tradition had largely forgotten
and according to which God will be 'all in all' (I Cor. 15.28) only at the end
when the Son hands the kingdom over to the Father. But despite this point of
contact, Hegel's thinking on the whole runs counter to the traditional view.
For according to the biblical and traditional conception, what stands at the
beginning is not emptiness but the fullness of being, namely, the Father as
origin and source. Consequently, while it is possible to argue about whether
Vatican I understood Hegel correctly, it did in fact make an important point
when it condemned the proposition that 'God is the universal or indefinite
begin which, by self-determination, constitutes the universality of beings
differentiated into genera, species and individuals.'17
This condemnation at the same time alludes to a third area of problems in
the debate with Hegel, and in fact to the basic problem: Hegel's determination
of the relation between God and world. He does not indeed simply identify
the procession of the Son with the act of creation; nor does he understand the
world-process and the historical process as simply a theogonic process in which
God becomes and finds himself. He keeps the levels clearly distinct. But how
does he do so? For Hegel the Son is the abstract determination of otherness,
while the world is the concrete realization of otherness, so that 'in themselvt!s'
the two are the same." For Hegel it i, valid to say: 'Apart from the world God
is notGod.'19 'God is creator of the world; it belongs to his being, to his nature,
to be a creatof. '20 Consequently for Hegel the distinction between the economic
Trinity and the immanent Trinity is in the last analysis an abstract onc;
considered concretely and in themselves, the two coincide. 'Spirit is the divine
history, the process of self-distinction, sepaution, and return.' This process
takes three forms: one in the realm of thought, aparc from the world; an ocher
in the realm of representation, in the world and its history; and the other
in the community,21 in Ilnd for whose consciousness Jesus Christ is the
mllnifestlltion of God, Ilnd in which therefore the eternlll movement which is
God rellches consciousness!! Ilnd God IlS Spirit is present. H 'This Spirit insofllr
as it exists Ilnd reaches self-realization is the community.'!" God and world;
the history of salvation, the history of the world, and the history of the church:
all these are here dialectically aufgehobell (reduced to components, annulled,
preserved, and elevated to a higher level) in one another, but in such a way
that the decisive point of the Christian faith is in danger of being lost: God as
freedom that exists in and for itself and that communicates itself in [he freedom
of love. But God thus understood presupposes the real and not simply abstract
distinction between the immanent and economic Trinities. At this point, which
is the main point, Hegel's thinking remains profoundly ambivalent and
irremediably ambiguous.
Given the ambiguiry of Hegel's thinking it is not surprising that his system
should have been received in various ways. Some, e.g., Ph. K. Marheineke,
Expositioll of the Doctrille of the Trillity 267
,pproached it from the ecclesi,1 ,nd orthodox st,ndpoint; others, e.g., L.
Feuerbach and K. Marx, were expressly interested in a critique of religion. For
Feuerbach the mystery of theology is ,nthropology, while the mystery of the
Trinity is the mystery of communal, socict<ll life; it is the mystery of the
necessity of the Thou for the I; it is the truth that 'no being whatsoever, be it
m,n or God or be it called "spirit" or "I", can be true, perfect ,nd absoillte
being in isolatio,,; that the trllt" and perfection are only the ,m;on and unity
of beings that arc similar in essencc',B The Trinity is therefore a projection
and, so to speak, an encoded representation of human intcrsubjectivity and
love. The human soul, which in the p,st supplied im,ges ,nd ,nalogies of the
Trinity, now becomes the prototype ,nd the re,lity. For Feuerbach this
'mounts to saying that faith is to be replaced by love. For it is faith that sets
God apart and [Urns him into a particular being; it thus separates believers
from unbelievers and is the contrary of love, which embraces everything. Love
makes God a universal being and convens the statement that God is love inro
the statement that love is God." On the other h,nd, Feuerbach is far from
sharing the n,ivete of m,ny theologi,ns of our own d,y who think they c,n
give Christianity a new opportunity in the time ahead by 'sublimating' a
dogmatically defined f,ith in the practice of love. Feuerbach is ,ware that in
setting f,ith aside for the sake of love he is striking a decisive blow at
Chriscianity: 'Christianity owes its perpetuation to the dogmatic formulas of
the Church: l ? He does not reflect, however, that to maintain the Godness of
God is ,Iso to defend the hum,nness of m,n. For the preservation of
the difference between lovers that remains even in love also preserves the
unconditional dignity and unconditional worth of the individual person within
the human genus into which Feuerbach and, even more resolutely, Marx wish
to ,bsorb the individu,J.2K The transcendence of God proves to be the sign ,nd
safeguard of the transcendence of the human person. 29
Up to this point, in dealing with the mysteriousness of the Trinity I have been
taking 'mystery' in its Scholastic sense: a mystery is a truth which in principle
transcends the powers of the human mind, is certified only by a divine
communication, and, even after its communication, cannot be positively
understood. 36 In this Scholastic approach mystery is understood, first of all, as
u property of a proposition. It speaks of mysteries in the plural; it is asserted
that there are many mysteries of faith, but there is no explicit reflection on
whether these many mysteries are simply aspects of a single mystery. Secondly,
mystery is understood in terms of reason, without the question being asked
whether this reference is not too narrow and superficial and whether the
standpoint adopted should not rather be that of the human person as a whole
and the mystery of its existence. Thirdly, the revelation of mystery is understood
as a transmission of true propositions (revelation as supernatural information
and instruction) rather than being conceived as a personal communication.
Fourthly, mystery is defined in a purely negative way as the unknowable and
incomprehensible. Fifthly, and consistently with such a definition, mystery is
thought of as something provisional; it will someday be eliminated, when we
see God 'face to face' in the beatific vision. No account is taken of the fact that
mystery is essentially connected with the self-transcendence of the human spirit
and with the Godness of God and that it is to this extent something positive.
This Scholastic concept makes it possible to distinguish a mystery from a
riddle and a problem, both of which in principle can be gradually solved,
whereas in principle mystery cannot be thus removed. But such a concept of
mystery is not clearly distinguished from the everyday use of this word and
from the unpleasant associations of secrecy connected with it. Such terms as
secret diplomacy, secret police, military secrets and secretiveness suggest a
distressing lack of openness and so on; they suggest the painful need of locks
and keys. Especially in its religious application, the word mystery, thus
understood, becomes suspect. It seems to abet a flight from the bright light of
the intellect into the half·darkness of feeling and to provide religious justific-
ation for mental fatigue and even intellectual dishonesty. Against this back-
ground itis understandable that the attack of the Enlightenment on Christianity
should have found expression especially in hostility to the concept of mystery.
The very title of Christianity Not Mysterious (1696) by John Toland, an
English deist, is typical. And in fact the concept of mystery can become 'the
270 The Trinitarian Mystery of God
refuge of rendencies' 'which distort Christian ralk abour God and blur rhe
distinction between belief and superstition'.J7
The light of divine truth does not need this kind of artificial eclipse in
order to reveal its brilliance. '43 Revelation is 'supra-rational, not irrational
or anti-rational. It represents an enrichment of reason, not a spurning or
constriction of it. '44
The correspondence between the mystery of man and the mystery of
God means, to begin with, that reason can show that what the mystery of
the Trinity asserts is not contradictory or nonsensical. It does not amount
to the absurd claim that one equals three, or similar nonsense.·' On the
positive side, there arc three ways of attaining to a deeper understanding
of the mystery of the Trinity as accepted in faith: 1. by examination of
analogies from the natural world; Augustine in particular travelled this
path in his teaching on the Trinity; 2. by showing the nexl/s mysterioTllm
(the connection of the mysteries with one another) or the hierarchia
veritattlll' (the hierarchy of truths):46 all the mysteries of faith together
form a structured whole, and by reason of the internal harmony and
coherence of this structure the individual truths of faith become credible
and intelligible. As far as the doctrine of the Trinity is concerned, this
connection between the truths of faith means showing that the economic
Trinity and the immanent Trinity are inseparable and, furthermore, that
the trinitarian confession provides the basic structure for all the other
truths of faith as well as their overarching context. 3. The third way is by
showing the connection between the trinitarian faith and man's meaning
and goal, namely, eternal communion with God, which is given through
Christ in the Holy Spirit.·' We may combine these three ways and say that
the mystery of the Trinity can be understood as a mystery if it can be shown
that it proves its worth as an interpretation of reality, that is, of the order
of creation and the order of redemption.
272 The Trillitarian Mystery of God
The First Vatican Council stated that with the help of grace reason can
gain a certain understanding of the mysteries of God 'from the analogy
with the objects of its natural knowledge'." Theologians reflecting on the
doctrine of the Trinity adopted this principle at a very early stage and
looked to the natural world for images, parables and analogies that would
enable them to penetrate more deeply into the mystery of the Trinity. As
early as the second century we find the ciassical comparison with fire,
which is not diminished by the fact that another fire is lit from it." Another
ancient comparison, between the source of light, the light and the radiance
of the light'· played an important role later on, especially in Athanasius. 51
In fact, this image even made its way into the church's confession of faith:
'Light from Light, true God from true God'." Tertullian introduced a
series of other comparisons: root and fruit, source and stream, sun and ray
of the sun."
Augustine was the most prolific of these theologians in discovering traces
(vestigia) of the Trinity in creation. The whole eleventh book of his De
Trinitate is devoted to this subject. In addition to the images already
mentioned," Augustine points out that according to Wisdom 11.20, God
has arranged all things 'by measure and number and weight'. In this triad
he sees an image of the divine Trinity." But for him the true image of God
is man (Gen. 1.28)" and, more specifically, the human soul. 57 This idea of
man as image of God is the starting point for Augustine's psychological
speculation on the Trinity, which in turn determined the course of all later
reflection on the mystery of the Trinity in Latin theology. Here again
Augustine can refer back to earlier beginnings and especially to the
comparison with the interior word and with the will, these being analogies
customary ever since the Apologists and Origen." Within Latin theology,
Augustine could build especially on preliminary work done by Tertullian,
Hilary and Ambrose." In the final analysis, however, Augustine proceeds
in a fully independent manner; his psychological doctrine of the Trinity is
the product of his own genius.'· With great speculative power and depth
Augustine detects in the human spirit ever new ternaries: mens - tlotitia-
amor (mind - knowledge - love), memoria - intelligelllia - voltllltas
(memory - intelligence - will), and others. I shall speak of these in detail
further on.
There is, of course, a question that needs to be answered: what do these
analogies really achieve? They are doubtless not meant as proofs in the
strict sense of the term; they are not a demonstration but a subsequent
illustration that presupposes the confession of the Trinity. They represent
Expositioll of the Doctrille of the Trillity 273
an attempt to put the mystery of the Trinity in the language of our present
world. Admittedly, then, they move within a hermeneutical circle. They
not only interpret the Trinity in terms of the world and more particularly
of man but, conversely, they also interpret the world and man in the light
of the mystery of the Trinity; on the basis of the doctrine of the Trinity
they postulate a particular model for human knowing and loving. This
reciprocal clarification has its basis in the correspondence (analogy)
between God and world, the order of creation and the order of redemption.
It is understandable, then, that because of his divergent conception of
analogy" Karl Barth should sharply criticize the doctrine of the vestigia
trillitatis. He is afraid that this ambivalent undertaking may lead to a high-
handed justification of the doctrine of the Trinity on the basis of man's
understanding of the world and himself and thus to a defection from
revelation. He therefore regards the attempt to find traces of the Trinity as
frivolous and as distracting us from the real task, which is not to illustrate
revelation but to interpret it, that is, to make it intelligibile in its own
terms." Catholic theology, which persists in maintaining the analogy
between God and world, cannot accept this radical criticism. Riskiness is
not a theological argument for abandoning a task seen as necessary; it is
rather a challenge to do the task well, accurately and conscientiously.
One point in Barth's criticism is indeed valid: that theological under-
standing must come primarily not from without, that is, from analogies
with the world, but from faith itself or, more accurately, from the
"exus mysteriorum or internal unity of the various assertions of faith. 63
The real vestigium trillitatis is therefore not man but the God·man Jesus
Christ. A real understanding of the doctrine of the Trinity from within is
gained only in the light of the economy of salvation. This brings us to the
approach to the doctrine ofthe Trinity that is predominant today: namely,
the unity of the immanent Trinity and the economic Trinity.
On the basis of the scriptures, tradition has endeavored to give more precise
expression to the two processions in God.1IS The procession of the Son is
described as generation, that 01 the Spirit (on the basis of John 15.26) as a
procession in a narrower sense. In view of the original meaning of the word
'spirit' (namely wind, breathing, breath), traditional theology describes the
procession of the Spirit as a 'breathing' or spiration (spiratio). But while
the concept of generation is immediately intelligible, we experience some
embarrassment in our attempts to characterize the procession of the Spirit.
This conceptual poverty is only apparently lacking in Eastern theology. Because
Eastern theology has no general concept to cover the intra-trinitarian 'comings
forth', it is able to reserve the concept of 'procession' to the Spirit. lifo Yet we
look in vain to this theology for some more precise explanation of the concept.
As far as I know, the only attempt at such an explanation thar is to be found
in the tradition comes in Albert the Great,H7 to whom M. J. Scheeben refers.1I1!
According to Albert processio signifies an ecstatic going-beyond-oneself and
self-transcending, a being-out-of-oneself such as is proper to love. As we
compare the internal procession of the Son that is, his generation, with the
procession of the interior word in the act of knowledge, so we compare
procession of the Spirit, that is, his spiration, with the being-out-of-oneself or
ec·stasy of love. Thus the Son is the Word and Wisdom of the Father, while
the Spirit is the love 01 the Father and Son and the bond ollove between them."
The processions in God in turn are the basis of relations in God. Relation
means reference to another.'"' The concept of relation therefore has three
elements: a subject (terminlls a quo), a term (terminus ad quem) and a
foundation. There is a relative opposition berween the subject and term of
the relation. The two processions in God yield four such relations:
I. The relation of the Father to the Son: active generation (generare) or
Fatherhood;
2. The relation of the Son to the Farher: passive generation (generar;) or
sonship;
3. The relation of the Father and the Son to the Holy Spirit: active
spiration (spirar.);
4. The relation of the Holy Spirit to the Father and the Son: passive
spiration (spirari).
280 The Trinitarian Mystery of God
Three of these relations are really distinct from each other: fatherhood,
sonship and passive spiration. Active spiration, on the other hand, is
identified with fatherhood and sonship and belongs to Father and Son in
common, whereas passive spiration is really distinct from fatherhood and
sonship. This means that the two processions in God ground three really
distinct relative oppositions. The latter are the prototypes and primal
ground of the dialogical and relational interaction and co-presence of
Father, Son and Spirit in the history of salvation.
It was the brilliant insight of the fourth- and fifth-century fathers - an
insight with a basis in Athanasibs,91 and developed in the East especially by
Gregory ofNazianzus, 92 and in the West even more clearly by Augustine"-
that fatherhood, sonship and passive spiration are relational realities, so
that the distinctions in God affect not the one divine substance or
one divine being but only the relations in God. This insight was later
incorporated into official church teaching." It led to the basic trinitarian
principle: 'In Deo omnia sunt unum, ubi non obviat relationis oppositio
(In God everything is one where there is no opposition of relationship). '95
The statement that the distinctions in God are in the form of relations is
of fundamental importance because it represents a break-away from a one-
sidedly substantialist type of thought. The final word belongs not to the
static substance, the divine self-containment, but to being-from-another
and being-far-another. In the created world rclations presuppose sub-
stance. Relations are essential only to the full self-realization of the being;
they do not exhaust the reality of the being. A human being is and remains
a human being even if he selfishly closes himself against relations with
others; in fact he may not be regarded exclusively as a relational being that
has meaning and value only to the extent that it exists for others and for
the whole, since the human person has value and dignity in himself. In
God, however, ·such distinctions between substance and relation are
rendered impossible by the simpliciry and perfection of the divine being.
In God substance and relation are really identical; God is relation and
exists only in the intra-divine relations; he is wholly love that surrenders
and bestows itself. This relational reality of God, which is identical with
his being or substance, presupposes real, mutually distinct relational
realities. To that extent the distinction between the one substance of God
and the relations is not a purely mental one (distinctio rationis ) but one
that has a foundation in reality (distillCtio virttlalis), in that the relation is
directed to a term which is really distinct from the substance.'6 Thus the
distinctions based on the relations once again bring out the ecstatic
character of God's love.
The three mutually opposed relations in God - fatherhood, sonship and
Expositioll of the Doctrille of the Trillity 281
passive spiration - are abstract expressions for the three divine persons.
Person (hypostasis)," as used in the early church and by the Scholastics,
means the ultimate subject of all being and action (principi,,,,, ql/od). The
Mture, for its part, is that by which the person or hypostasis is and acts
(principiI/III qllo). The person or hypostasis is both irreducible to anything
else and incommunicable to others; to that extent it is a unity distinct from
every other such unity: the one here, the other there. For this reason the
classical definition of' person is: 'Persona est natllrae ral;mralis individuo/is
substantia (3 person is an individual substance of a radonal nilrure).''' The
weakness of this definition, which comes from Boethius, is that it seems
to understand personality and individuality as identical. Individuality,
however, defines a what and not a who; it describes the person's nature,
not the person as such. Nonetheless the content of Boethius' 'individuality'
is incommunicability, an immediacy based on an ultimate indivisibility
and unity." This aspect finds expression especially in the definition
of person that is given by Richard of St Victor: 'lIatllrae rationalis
incomnumicabilis existentia (an incommunicable existence of a rational
nature),'IOO At bottom, Thomas Aquinas has the same thought in mind
when he replaces the concept of substance (which is related to the concept
of nature) with that of subsistence: that which is the subject that 'srands
under' the nature or substance. lol This conceptual refinement has import-
ance not least for the doctrine of the Trinity. For talk of three substances
is easily interpreted as meaning three Gods. Whereas if we speak of three
subsistences, we are saying that the numerically one divine nature or
substance is 'possessed' by three subjects or that it exists in three relatively
distinct modes of subsistence.
In what does the ultimate, indivisible unity and therefore the ground of
distinction in God consist? According to what has been said thus far it
consists of the relations. This explains Thomas' definition of the divine
persons: the divine persons are subsistent relations.l oz In fact, if not in
terminology, this doctrine was also adopted by the Reformers; in our day
it has been put forward among others by K. Barth. ID ]
At this point a serious logical difficulry arises. How can the absolute unity and
simplicity of God permit of any numbering, any counting? Numbers, after all,
have meaning only in the realm of the quantitativcj there can be no counting
in the sphere of pure spirit, which is the sphere of God. As Basil says, God is
'wholly beyond number'. I . . Or, as Augustine says, because God is not
Expositioll of the Doctrille of the Trillity 283
quancitativc, he is not tripartite; the three persons cannot be counted up; God
is not greater than each individual person." O In this sense we must join the
Eleventh Council of Toledo in saying of the Trinity that it 'is not without
number; yet it is not comprised by number (nee rccedit a lIumera nee capilllT
"wucro)'.111 The question, then, is whether and to what extent talk of "three'
persons is logically meaningful.
The point which prompts the question already makes it clear that in the
realm of the spirit and above all in the realm of God number can only be
predicated analogously, if at all. The application becomes meaningful only if
we reflect on the ground and meaning of the possibility of numbers and
cQunting, namely, unity as a transcendental property of being and one that
adds nothing to being except a negation of division. This kind of unity belongs
to every existent reality, although differently depending on its existential rank.
Such unity belongs in the highest degree to the person, which is an 'individual'
in the sense of possessing an ultimate undividedness and therefore incommunic-
ability. When we talk of three persons in God, we are saying materially that
the Father, the Son, and the Spirit are each that kind of undivided and indivisible
ultimate uniry.11l
Since the number three is here used only analogously, it follows that the
concept of person is not applied to the three persons as a generic concept. 11l
The meaning of person here cannot be derived from any presupposed generic
concept of person. We must rather heed what Hilary says and not determine
the meaning of the reality from the words used but rather understand the
words used in the light of the reality.'" This point can also be made clear by
looking at the reality, for in God it is not only the unity but also the distinction
that is always greater than in the created world. In other words: not despite
the fact that God is absolutely undivided unity but precisely because of this
fact, he can and must also be infinite differentiation, and therefore he permits
of pcrsonal distinctions which in each case are rcalized with an infinite
differentiation by the mode of subsistence in which the one divine nature exists.
All the trinitarian concepts thus far examined lead to a final, all-inclusive
basic concept: the being-in-one-another and mutual penetration of the
divine persons, or the trinitarian perichoresis. 1U This concept has a
scriptural basis in John 10.30: 'land the Father are one' (d. 14.9ff.; 17.21).
This being-in-one-another and mutual penetration are attested in the
tradition at a very early stage. II. Hilary has a classical formulation of the
relationship of Father and Son: 'One from the Other, and both are One;
not One made up of Two, but One in the Other, because in the Both there
is no otherness."17 'God in God, because he is God from God."" Augustine
observes: In the Trinity 'there is no mixture or confusion. Each person is
in himself, and yet three are each wholly in the others; each of them in the
other two or the other two in each of them, and thus all are in all.''''
284 The Trinitarian Mystery of God
Following Fulgentius of Ruspe,l2o the Council of Florence describes as
follows this reciprocal coinherence: 'On account of this unity the Father
is wholly in the Son and wholly in the Holy Spirit; the Son wholly in the
Father and wholly in the Holy Spirit; the Holy Spirit wholly in the Father
and wholly in the Son.''''
Such is the common conviction of both the Eastern and the Latin Western
traditions. However, the East and the West have developed differenttheological
systems on this common basis. 1M6 The twO systems may be described somewhat
schematic.lly .s follows. In their theology of the Trinity the Greeks st.rt with
the three hypostases or persons; "lore precisely, they start with the Father as
origin and source within the Godhead. Their concern is to protec(the monarchy
of the Father, who as sole origin ensures unity in the Trinity. According to the
Greek understanding it is the one God the Father who bestows his divine
nature on the Sao, so that the Son possesses the one identical divine nature
with the Father. The s.me holds for the Holy Spirit, who proceeds from the
Father and receives the one divine nature from the Father (through the Son).
The Greek conception thus starts with the persons and advances from one
person to another. Unity is assured by the Father 35 origin and source of the
divinity and as principle of its unity~ the one nature is thus envisaged only
indirectly.
The Latin approach is different and has largely been determined by the
genius of Augustine. The Latins begin directly with (he one divine nature or
the one divine substance and one divine being. The three persons come into
view only mediately as three personal, i.e., distinct manners in which the one
substance subsists. The one divine being does not exclude the three persons
(that would be Sabellianism), but rather exists only in these three person. I
manners of subsisting. Nonetheless, the one divine being is the basis on which
everything is built in the effort to understand the three persons in God. For
knowing and willing arc the essemial activities of the spiritual nature. In
knowing himself, God begets his eternal Word; he is therefore Father and Son.
The Holy Spirit then proceeds as the third person from the mutual love of both
Father and Son. In this concepcion of the Trinity, unity in trinity is made
psychologically intelligible; for this reason historians speak of a psychological
doctrine of the Trinity in Augustine. The difference between the Greeks and
rhe Latins can be formulated thus: The Greeks say 'One God in three persons',
the Latins say 'Three persons in God.'
The difference berween the two .pproaches can also be brought out with
the help of im.ges. The line is • suitable im.ge for the Greek conception: the
Father begets the Son, and through the Son the Holy Spirit proceeds from him.
In the procession of the Spirit the life process in the Trinity reaches its
completion, while at the same time in the Spirit it also presses out beyond itself.
A triangle or a circle is a more suitable image for the Lacin conception: [he
Father begets the Son; the circle of trinitari.n life is then closed in the Spirit as
Expositioll of the Doctrille of the Trillity 297
the reciprocal love between Father and Son. The Greek conception is thus
more open to the world, while the Latin is more self-enclosed. This difference
can also be seen in artistic representations of the Trinity. The classical artistic
representation of the Trinity in the Orthodox Church is of the three men or
angels visiting Abraham (Gen. 18) - three figures who, however, in Rublev's
famous ikon are depicted as forming an incomparably beautiful unity. The
most important ecclesiastical representation of the Trinity in the Western
church is the 'Throne of Grace', in which the three persons form a single united
figure: the Father sits on the throne and holds the cross with the Son on it,
while between the two the Spirit hovers in the form of a dove.
Each of the two conceptions is magnificent in its own way, but each also has
its dangers. It is clear that the Greek conception is more concrete and more
biblical and reflects the history of salvation. But it formally asserts the inner
unity of the three persons rather than makes this unity intelligible from within.
The Latin conception is by comparison the fruit of greater reflection and
speculative thought, but it is also more abstract. It is in danger of being unable
to bring out fully the distinction of the three persons and, ultimately, in danger
of letting the three persons evaporate as it were into mere modi, modes of
being of the one divine nature. This danger is especially present in the form
which Anselm of Canterbury gave to the Latin doctrine of the Trinity. As a
result, the Western conception has often been subjected to rather sharp attacks
from Orthodox theologians, who even accuse it of being a radical revision of
the trinitarian dogma. 11I7 Even among Catholics a latent preference for the
Eastern conception is ascertainable today.
The dash of the two approaches comes to a head especially in the dispute
about the fjlioqlle.'HK The Greeks accuse the Latin formula of eliminating the
monarchy of the Father and dissolving the unity in God because it accepts two
processions in God; they object, in addition, that it identifies the Spirit with
the nature common to the Father and the Son and therefore unable to ensure
the hypostatic independence of the Spirit. The Latins dismiss these objections
as misunderstandings of their conception of the Trinity. They, too, say that it
is from the Father that the Son has his 'power' to spirate the Spirit; consequently
the Spirit proceeds pri/lcipaliter from the Father, so that the latter's monarchy
is preserved in the Latin conception no less than in the Greek. Finally, even in
the Latin conception the Spirit does not proceed from the one divine nature
but from the two persons (duo spiralltes) who as persons form a single principle
in the procession of the SpiritlM9
More important than such disputes, which arc basically fruitless because
they are based on mutual ignorance or misunderstandings, is the realization
that the contrast between the two conceptions makes a valid point but also
that these schematic generalizations do not do justice to a historical reality
which shows far more diversity.190 Thus in the East alongside the conception
of the Cappadocians there is also that of the Alexandrians, and especially of
Athanasius, which corresponds more to the Latin conception. Even John
298 The Trillitariall Mystery of God
Damascene, who sums up the patristic tradition in a way that has become
normative for Orthodoxy, starts with the one God and only then passes on to
<I presentation of the three hYPOSf3SCS. IY1 Elsewhere, too, among the Greek
falhers we come upon formulas that have a very essentialist ring; for example,
God from God, Light from Light, Essence from Essence, Wisdom from
Wisdom, and so on. III:! Conversely, in addition to the essentialist tradition
which was established by Augustine and was intensified to the extreme by
Anselm of Canterbury'" and whIch is represented today by K. Banh and K.
R3hner,I'I~ there is also a more 'personalist' tradition. It was 3dopted in
antiquity by Hilary of POlliers and In the Middle Ages by WIlliam of 5t
Thierry,'''! the friend of Bernard of Clairv3ux and the adversary of Abelard, 3
modalist. Its most important representative is Richard of St. Victor, who wrote
the most important treallse on the Trmity between Augustine and Thomas
Aquinas. He was followed by Alexander of Hales and Bonaventure. I"''' In their
own way all of these theologians make their own the concern which the Greeks
sum up In the 'monarchy of the Father' and which Augustine too respects,
since he -like Bonavcnrure and Thomas Aquinas later on - teaches that the
Spirit proceeds princlpaliter from the Father. A doctrine of the Trmity that is
decidedly based on the history of salvation is to be found in the M,ddle Ages
in Rupert of Deutz, Gerhoh of Reichersberg, Anselm of Havelberg, and
others.I'J1
In this as in many other questions Thomas Aquinas sought for a syntheSIS
that would strike a balance between the various conceptions; he ended with
one that is really not very far removed from that of John Damascene, whose
writings Thomas knew well and esteemed highly.1 Q H Thomas Aquinas is thus
proof that we must not exaggerate the differences between East and West. The
differences exist, but they do not reach up to heaven, and the walls that have
often been artificially erected arc transparent and permeable in both directions.
As Thomas Aquinas in particular shows, the Western tradition is In a position
to make its own all the concerns of the East and to elevate these to 3 higher
level of reOection.
K. Barth starts with the concept of revelation because he is convinced that this
contains within itself the problem of ,he Trinity.2.2In his view, the roO! of the
doctrine of the Trinity is the statement: 'God reveals Himself as the Lord,'20J
This sentence means that God is 'the same in unimpaired unity, yet also the
same in unimpaired variety thrice in a different way', namely, as revealer,
revelation and revealedness. 204 Revelation is 'the self·unveiling, imparted to
men, of the God who according to His nature cannot be unveiled to men'.
Because he is so sovereignly free, God 'can become so unlike Himself that He
is God in such a way as not to be bound to His secret eternity and eternal
secrecy, but also can and will and really does assume ,emporal form'.2.s But
in this process he himself remains the Revealer. Precisely as Deus reve/atlls he
is still the Deus absconditus. 206 He is the sovereign subjectofhis own revelarion.
Finally, revelation also means revealedness, for revelation also includes the
self-unveiling that is granted to men. It is a hislOrical event through which the
existence of certain human beings is so affected that while they cannot indeed
grasp God, they are able to follow him and respond to him.'07 Barth's doctrine
of the Trinity thus brings out ,he unchangeable subjectivity of God2.' and is
thereby a variant on the modern theme of subjectivity and its autonomy.209
The three modes of being in which the Trinity manifests itself belong to the
self-constitution of the absolute subject. This is a distinctly modern or, more
accurately, a distinctly idealist pattern of thought, which links Barth 10 Hegel
despite all the material differences between them. 2I •
We find a similar thought structure in K. Rahner. In keeping with his
anthropological approach to 'heology his starting point is of course the
subjectivity not of God but of man. This means that he aims to understand ,he
mystery of the Trinity as a mystery of salvation. Salvation occurs when man's
Exposition of the Doctrine of the Trinity 301
indigent telatedness to an absolute mystery is filled by the irreducibly free and
gracious self-communication of this mystery. In this sense Rahner can 53Y:
'Man is the event of a free, unmerited and forgiving, and absolute self-
communication of God.'ll1 The concept of self-communication includes 'the
absolute nearness of God as the incomprehensible mystery which remains
forever such 'the absolute freedom . .. of this self-communication', and 'that
t1
We can develop our own syslemalic approach 10 Ihe doctrine of Ihe Trinity
if, while bearing in mind all Ihe queslions and answers of Ihe Iradition, we
lislen once again 10 Ihe lestimony of scrip lure, which is Ihe primordial
documenlOf Ihe faith. I shall once again sIan wilh Ihe final prayer of Jesus,
Ihe so-called high-priesdy prayer in John 17, which, as we saw earlier,
provides Ihe dearesl New Teslamem basis for a doclrine of Ihe T rinily .224
This prayer was utlered al Ihe momem when Jesus saw his hour coming,
since Ihe eschalOn was al hand (17_1,5,7). As a resull, Ihis prayer, spoken
al Ihe momem of depanure, comains as il were Ihe leslamem of Jesus. AI
Ihe momem of complelion il once again summarizes Ihe overall meaning
of Ihe saving work of Jesus Chrisl, and il does Ihis in Irinilarian form. The
high-priesdy prayer comains Ihe emire doclrine ohhe Trinity in basic form
and in a nUlshell.
1. The meaning of the doctrine of the Trinity. The high-priesdy prayer
begins wilh Ihe words: 'Falher, Ihe hour has come; glorify Ihy Son Ihal Ihe
Son may glorify Ihee' (17.1). The reference is 10 Ihe eschalOlogical hour,
Ihe hour when Ihe emire work of salvalion is compleled in a comprehensive
and surpassing manner. This completion takes place in Ihe cross and
exallalion of Jesus as Ihe eschalOlogical revelalion of God. When Ihe Falher
glorifies Ihe Son by exalting him, Ihe Falher himself is in lurn glorified by
Ihe Son; in Ihe glorification of Ihe Son Ihe Falher's own glorificalion is
made manifesl. The Son's glory is Ihal which he has from elernity wilh Ihe
Falher (v. 5). The eschalOlogical revelalion, Ihen, is a revelalion of Ihe
elernal being of God, a revelalion of Ihe Godness of God. It is said Ihal
from elernilY God possesses Ihe glory of his Godness because Ihe Falher
glorifies Ihe Son and the Son in lurn glorifies Ihe Falher.
Now Ihe failhful are incorporaled into Ihis elernal doxology. They have
304 The Trinitarian Mystery of God
accepted and acknowledged the revelation of the Father's glory by the Son
and of the Son's gloty by the Father. The Son is therefore glorified in them
(v. to). This glorification takes place through the action of the 'other
Paraclete', the Spirit of truth. He guides the faithful into the whole truth;
but because he says nothing on his own authority but only says whatJesus
is and what Jesus has from the Father, he too acknowledges the glory of
the Son and of the Father (16.13-15). The Spirit is, and effects, the concrete
presence of the eternal doxology of Father and Son in the church and in
the world. He is the eschat~logical accomplishment of the glory of God;
he is its presence within the confines of his lOry. This is possible only because
he himself proceeds from the Father (15.26) and because as Spirit of truth
he is the revealedness and radiance (doxa) of the eternal glory of God.
The intention of the trinitarian confession is thus not really a teaching
about God but the doxology or eschatological glorification of God. The
doctrine of the Trinity is as it were simply the grammar of the doxology.
The trinitarian confession is concerned with the 'Glory be to the Father
through the Son in the Holy Spirit'. In this liturgical hymn of praise the
eternal glory of God the Father, Son and Holy Spirit is revealed in an
eschatological and definitive way. The eschatological glorification of God
is at the same time the salvation and life of the world. 'This is eternal life,
that they know thee the only true God, and Jesus Christ whom thou hast
sent' (v. 3). In the intention of scripture this confession is not abstract
speculation but participation and communion of life. The issue in the
trinitarian confession is therefore communion with God. The doctrine of
the Trinity acquires its meaning from the unity-in-tension of doxology and
soteriology. There is no need to choose between the approaches of Karl
Barth and Karl Rahner.
The unity-in-tension of doxology and soteriology means that the
acknowledgment of God's glory does not represent a humiliation for
humanity. The acknowledgment of God's absolute subjectivity does not
mean a suppression of our subjectivity; on the contrary, this acknowledg-
ment redeems, liberates and fulfills humanity. Thus the trinitarian confes-
sion is the final concrete determination of our undetermined openness and
of the idea of God that gleams indeterminately therein and lights the way
for all thinking and action. us It is the surpassing answer 10 the question
which we do not simply have but are. The meaning of humanity and the
world, and the life and truth of humanity and the world, consist in the
glorification of the triune God, and through this glorification we are
incorporated into the intra-trinitarian glorification and we have commun-
ion with God. In the trinitarian confession, then, the meaning of Jesus'
message about the coming of God's reign is fulfilled in an anticipatory
Exposition of the Doctrille of the Trinity 305
manner. For that message 100 is concerned precisely with the revelation of
the lordship and glory of God as life of the world and fulfillment ofhuman
hope."'ln its deepest meaning the doctrine of the Trinity is the normative
explanation of jesus' message about the kingdom. It sums up the core of
jesus' message and is the summation of the Christian faith.
2. The content of the doctrine of the Trinity. According to the high-
priestly prayer, the glorification of God and the life of the world consists
in knowing and acknowledging the God of jesus Christ as 'the only true
God' (v. 3). Unity and uniqueness are essential predicates of God. Once
again, then, there is question of the knowledge of the nature of God, of
God's Godness. This knowledge of the oneness of God is distinguished
both from philosophical monotheism and from the monotheism of the Old
Testament by the fact that it includes knowledge of him whom the Father
has sent (v. 3) and who is one with the Father (v. 21£.). The world has not
known the oneness of God; he alone who from eternity is one with the
Father has brought knowledge of this oneness and has revealed the name
of the Father (v. 25f.; d. 1.18). Knowledge of the unity and oneness of
God is possible only through knowledge of the unity between Father and
Son. Into this oneness, 100, the faithful are 10 be incorporated. They are 10
'be one even as we are one' (v. 22), and they are 10 be made perfect in this
oneness (v. 23). This unity of the faithful among themselves as well as with
the Father and the Son is the work of the Spirit, according to john as well
as the rest of the New Testament. This connection is clearly brought out
in john 14.15-24. The coming and remaining of the Spirit is at the same
time the return of jesus and his dwelling in the faithful, so that he is in
them as he is in the Father.
The revelation of the Trinity is thus the revelation of the deepest and
utterly hidden nature of the unity and oneness of God, which in turn
grounds the unity of the church and, via the church, the unity of the world.
In its content, then, the doctrine of the Trinity is the Christian form of
monotheism. More accurately: the doctrine of the Trinity concretizes the
initially abstract assertion of the unity and oneness of God by determining
in what this oneness consists. The oneness of God is defined asa communion
of Father and Son, but indirectly and implicitly also as a communion of
Father, Son and Spirit; it is defined as unity in love.
The precise meaning of unity in love becomes known by contrasting it
with other forms of unity.'27In the material world we encounter quantit-
ative unity and therefore units that can be counted. Each of these units is
composed of various linked entities; science has not succeeded, at least
thus far, in throwing light on the ultimate and smallest units. The
delimitation and numerical pooling of such quantitative units presupposes
306 The Trinitariall Mystery of God
universal concepts of species and genus. These generic and specific unities
are the work of the human powers of abstraction. They presuppose the
unity of the person. The person is a unity that exists in and for itself and
is therefore capable of bringing into focus and reflecting on its own multiple
dimensions in self-consciousness. But even though the person is a unity
that cannot be communicated to a higher unity, its existence is nonetheless
possible only in co-existence with other persons. The human person is
possible only in the plural; it can exist only in reciprocal acknowledgment,
and it finds its fulfillment only in the communion of love. Persons thus
exist only in mutual giving and receiving.
In this final observation we have developed a preapprehension that
enables us to understand the unity in love which according to the Gospel
of John exists in God and is the very being of God. It is, of course, only a
preapprehension that can be applied only analogically to God. For in the
human realm the co-existence of persons is an expression of their finiteness
and neediness. Human persons are dependent on each other in a great
variety of ways. No single person is wholly identical with himself; none
exhausts the nature of humanity and all of its possibilities. Among human
beings, therefore, communion in love is always erotic as well; that is, the
love is a love that seeks fulfillment. All this is excluded from God by his
very nature. God docs not possess being; he is Being in absolute perfection
that has no slightest trace of neediness. He is therefore absolute oneness,
perfect self-identity and complete self-possession, personal unity in the
most perfect sense.
And yet if God is not to be understood as a solitary narcissistic being
who (to put it paradoxically) would be highly imperfect by reason of his
very perfection and would inevitably suffer from his own completeness,
then God can only be conceived as co-existent. On the other hand, if God
is to remain God and not become dependent on the world or man, then he
must be co-existent within himself. Within the unity and simplicity of his
being he must be a communion in love, and this love cannnot be a love
marked by need but only a love that gives out of the overflowing fulness
of his being. This is why in his farewell prayer Jesus speaks repeatedly of
giving (vv. 2., 6, 2.2). Because God in his perfection and simplicity is
everything and does not possess anything, he can give only himself. He can
only be a pure giving and bestowing of himself. God's oneness must be
thought of as love that exists only in the giving of itself. In God, therefore,
the communion of love is not a communion of separate beings, as it is
among men, but a communion within a single nature. The principle is valid
here: 'Alii have is yours and a\l you have is mine' (17.10 JB). Augustine
has formulated this truth with the utmost accuracy: the Trinity is the one
Exposition of the Doctrine of the Trinity 307
and only God, and the one and only God is the Trinity.228 The doctrine of
the Trinity is therefore concrete monotheism.
The understanding of God as communion-unity has far-reaching impli-
cations for our understanding of reality. Monotheism has always been a
political program as well as a religious: one God, one realm, oneemperor. 229
This connection is clear in John J7 from the fact that the unity in God is
the model and ground of the unity of the church and that the unity of the
church in turn is the sacrament, that is, the sign and instrument, of the
unity of the world (v. 23). But what kind of unity is meant? Evidently not
a rigid, monolithic, uniformist and tyrannical unity, which excludes,
absorbs or suppresses every kind of otherness. A unity of that kind would
bean impoverishment. God's unity is fullness and even overnowing fullness
of selness giving and bestowing, of loving self-outpouring; it is a unity that
does not exclude but includes; it is a living, loving being with and for
one another. This trinitarian understanding of unity as communion has
implications for the political sphere in the broadest sense of this term and
therefore for the formulation of the goals of unity in the church, in society
and in the human race; in other words, for the peace of the world. E.
Peterson has proposed the thesis that the doctrine of the Trinity puts an
end to political theology.2JO It would be more accurate to say that it puts
an end to a particular political theology that serves as an ideology to justify
relations of domination in which an individual or a group tries to impose
its ideas of unity and order and its interests to the exclusion of others. The
doctrine of the Trinity inspires an order in which unity arises because all
pool what they have and make it part of the common store. Such a
vision is as far removed from a collectivist communism as it is from an
individualistic liberalism. Forcommunion does not eliminate the individual
being and rights of the person but rather brings these to fulfillment through
the giving away of what is the person's own and the reception of what
belongs to others. Communion is thus a union of persons and at the same
time maintains the primacy of the always unique person. This primacy,
however, finds its fulfillment not in an individualistic having but in giving
and thus granting participation in what is one's own.
K. Hemmerle has expounded the consequence for Christian spirituality
of such a trinitarian understanding of unity as communion-unity.2lI The
resultant spirituality is contemplative, but in all things it pays heed to the
traces of love that it finds in all things and most of all in the cross of Jesus
Christ. The self-giving of God in Jesus Christ is not only the ground but
also the abiding measure upon which this spirituality repeatedly focuses
its gaze in order to make it its own measure. While contemplative, this
spirituality is also active and involved in the world. It attunes itself to God's
308 The Trinitarian Mystery of God
self-giving for men. It thus becomes a service in the world and for the
world. Finally, in its contemplation and its action it is community-
orientated and ecclesial. It draws its vitality from union with others. It is
not dependent on the pleasure and disposition of the individual, but
recognizes 'binding obligations' in the full sense of the phrase.
3. The abiding problem of the doctrine of the Trinity or, better: The
mystery of the Trinity. I said above that that the trinitarian communion-
unity is radically different from communion-unity among human beings
in that it is a unity in one and the same being and not simply a communion
of separate beings. The ana logy here involves an always greater dissimilarity
despite all the similarity. The concrete mode of trinitarian unity amid the
distinction of persons is therefore for us a mystety that cannot be eliminated.
Recent discussion of an appropriate understanding of person as applied to
the Trinity only shows once again the difficulties and aporias that face all
theological thinking at this point. But even in this most difficult of all
questions in the theology of the Trinity the high-priestly prayer offers us
points of contact and guides for further and deeper reflection. The answer
is once again suggested by the movement of giving and receiving, the
movement of love, which God is. For if we pay careful attention to the text
we see that in this movement there are three distinct relations.
The Father is purely a giver and sender. He is thus the unoriginated
origin of divine love, a pure source, a pure outflowing. The Son receives
life, glory and power from the Father; but he does not receive it in order
to keep it for himself, to possess it, and to take full enjoyment of it for
himself; rather, he receives it in order to empty himself of it (Phil. 2.6f.)
and to pass it on. love that terminated in the two-in-oneness of the lovers,
and did not selflessly press out beyond itself, would be only another form
of egoism. The Son is therefore the mediator; he is even pure mediation, a
pure passing-on. Finally, in the Spirit the faithful receive the gift of the
Father through the Son, so that they may share in this gift. The Spirit is
nothing by himself; he is a pure receiving, pure donation and gift; as such
he is pure fulfillment, eternal joy and blessedness, pure endless completion.
Since he is the expression of the ecstasy of love in God, God is, in and
through him, an eternal movement of pure exuberance reaching beyond
himself. As gift within God, the Spirit is God's eschatological gift to the
world; he is the world's definitive sanctification and completion.
Perfect and complete communion within the one being of God thus also
includes distinctions in the way this one being is possessed. In the Father,
love exists as pure source that pours itself out; in the Son it exists as a pure
passing-on, as pure mediation; in the Spirit it exists as the joy of pure
receiving. These three modes in which the one being of God, the one love,
Exposition of the Doctrine of the Trinity 309
subsists, are in some sense necessary because love cannot be otherwise
conceived; to that extent the trinitarian confession has an intrinsic plaus-
ibility for the believer. The Trinity nonetheless remains a mystery because
there is a question here of a necessity in love and therefore in freedom, a
necessity which cannot be deduced in advance of its self-revelation and of
which there can be no rational grasp after it has been revealed. The logic
of love has its own internal coherence and its own power to convince in,
and not despite, its irreducible and unfathomable freedom.
Each of the three modes in which the one love of God subsists is
conceivable only in relation to the other two. The Father as pure self-giving
cannot exist without the Son who receives. But since the Son does not
receive something but everything, he exists only in and through the giving
and receiving. On the other hand, he would not have truly received the
self-giving of the Father were he to keep it for himself and not giveit back.
He exists therefore insofar as he receives himself wholly from the Father
and gives himself wholly back to the Father, or, as it is put in the farewell
prayer of Jesus, glorifies the Father in his turn. As an existence that is
wholly owed to another, the Son is therefore pure gratitude, eternal
eucharist, pure obedient response to the word and will of the Father. But
this reciprocal love also presses beyond itself; it is pure giving only if it
empties itself of, and gives away, even this two-in-oneness and, in pure
gratuitousness, incorporates a third in whom love exists as pure receiving,
a third who therefore exists only insofar as he receives his being from the
mutual love between Father and Son. The three persons of the Trinity are
thus pure relationality; they are relations in which the one nature of God
exists in three distinct and non-interchangeable ways. They are subsistent
reiations.2J2
These considerations bring us back by a new path to the Augustinian
and Thomist concept of trinitarian person as subsistent relation. I have
rendered this concept concrete with the help of the reflections offered
by Richard of St Victor. At the same time, I have found a systematic
conception of the doctrine of the Trinity in which the concerns of the Greek
and Latin doctrines of the Trinity can be aufgehoben (set aside, preserved
and elevated to a higher level) in a higher unity. In principle, this view of
the Trinity begins, as does the Greek, with the Father, the unoriginated
origin; but insofar as it conceives the Father as pure love, as pure self-
giving, it is able to understand the processions of the Son and of the Spirit
according to their inner 'logic', after the manner of Latin theology, and to
conceive these processions, in faith, as forms of the one impenetrable and
incomprehensible love of God and as expressions of the one mystery of
salvation.
310 The Trinitarian Mystery of God
The question remains, of course: what is the value of such a systematic
exposition of the doctrine of the Trinity? What does it have to do with the
doxological and soteriological meaning of the confession of the Trinity? I
have already given a first answer to this question: our concern is with the
intellecttls fidei, an understanding of the faith from within. What is meant
is not a rationalistic understanding, an understanding according to the
criterion and in the framework of the human reason, which would then,
by comparison with faith, be the greater and more comprehensive power
that could serve as measure and standard. The 'understanding of faith' is
rather a conceptualizing on the basis of faith and an understanding in faith;
it is an understanding that does not lead away from faith to a supposedly
higher knowledge. The aim is a deeper initiation into the faith itself, a
faith-filled understanding of the mystery as mystery, and specifically as the
mystery of an unfathomable and for that very reason convincing love.
In these remarks I have already anticipated a second answer. Because
the mystery of love is the supreme criterion and one established by
revelation itself, it yields further criteria for understanding the reality in a
new and more profound way. By way of analogy the trinitarian commun-
ion-unity shows itself to be the model for a Christian understanding of
reality. The development of the doctrine of the Trinity means a breaking
out of an understanding of reality that is characterized by the primacy of
subject and nature, and into an understanding of reality in which person
and relation have priority. Here the ultimate reality is here not the
independent substance but the person, who is fully conceivable only in the
relationality of giving and receiving. We might even say: the meaning of
being is the selflessness of love. Such a 'trinitarian ontology',m like any
other ontology, cannot of course be convincingly established by induction.
Self-assertion, blind facticity, abstract historicity or the irreducible
obscurity of reality constantly make their presence felt and seek to
contradict such an interpretation. The interpretation is nonetheless plaus-
ible because it does justice in a greater degree to the human experience of
reality while bracketing none of that experience. In addition, it is capable
of incorporating and 'letting stand' those experiences of reality that will
not fit into any system: guilt, loneliness, the grief caused by finiteness,
failure. In the final analysis, it is an interpretation in the key of hope, an
anticipation of the eschatological doxology under the veil of history.
Finally, the trinitarian confession yields a model for a Christian spirit-
uality of hope and of the selfless service that hope inspires. For the
trinitarian persons are characterized by their selflessness. They are, each
in his own way, pure surrender, self-emptying. Their eternal keno tic
existence is the condition for the possibility of the temporal kenosis of
Exposition of the Doctrille of the Trinity 311
the Son, and thus a type of Christian humility and selfless service.>"
Consequently it is the very nature and content of the trinitarian confession
that causes it to be pronounced in the act of baptism, which grounds
Christian existence. This confession is the very heart not only of the
Christian faith but also of the following of Jesus, which is based on this
faith, and of the Christian's being incorporated into the death and
resurrection of the Lord.
4. The systematic place of the doctrine of the Trinity follows from the
point just made. This doctrine is in a sense the summation of the entire
Christian mystety of salvation and, at the same time, its grammar. It is its
grammar because it is the intrinsic condition for the possibility of the
histoty of salvation. Only because God is perfect freedom in love within
himself can he also be freedom in love in dealing with what is outside of
himself. Because in his very being he is one with himself through being
with and in another, he is able to empty himself out in histoty and in this
very emptying reveal his glory. Because in himself God is pure gift, he is
able to give himself in the Holy Spirit; as the innermost being of God, the
Spirit is at the same time the outermost, the condition for the possibility
of creation and redemption. Consequently the trinitarian confession is at
the same time the summary of the entire Christian mystery of salvation.
For the fact that God the Father is the salvation of the world through Jesus
Christ his Son in the Holy Spirit- this fact is the one mystery of faith which
is contained in the many mysteries of faith. The Father as unoriginated
origin in God is also the ground and goal of the history of salvation; from
his all comes forth and to him all returns. The Son as pure communication
in God is the mediator whom the Father sends and who in turn gives us
the Holy Spirit. The Spirit, finally, as completion in God is the eschatological
completion of the world and man. Just as he is God's way to what is outside
himself so also he effects the return of all created reality to God. Through
the Spirit soteriology ends in doxology; at the end of time all of reality will
be incorporated into this doxology when God is 'all ill all' (I Cor. 15.28).
Finally, the thesis that the doctrine of the Trinity is the grammar and
summation of the entire Christian mystety of salvation provides us with
the answer to the much-discussed question of the place of the doctrine of
the Trinity within dogmatic theology.2lS Given the importance of the
doctrine of the Trinity, the question and its answer are not simply a matter
of scientific organization but much more one of theological content that
has serious implications and determines the overall theological approach
to a dogmatic theology.
Three classical solutions call for discussion. The first solution, which
received its classical formulation in Thomas Aquinas, puts the doctrine of
312 The Trillitariall Mystery of God
the Trinity at the beginning of dogmatic theology, in keeping with a
dogmatic epistemology. In practice the treatise De Deo uno precedes the
treatise De Deo trino. This arrangement implies a twofold preliminary
theological decision: it presupposes the priority of theologia (the study of
God in himself) over oeconomia (the study of God's action in creation and
history); and it takes seriously the fact that in the history of salvation and
in the theo/ogia which interprets it the most important thing is God's deeds
and words and therefore that everything in theology must be studied slIb
ratione Dei (in the light of God). The positioning of the treatise De Deo
uno before the treatise De.Deo trino implies, in addition, a choice of the
Western theology of the Trinity as established chiefly by Augustine, a
theology that starts with the. one essence of God, deals with the three
persons in terms of this one essence or nature, and thus leads in practice
to stripping the Trinity to a large extent of any function in the economy of
salvation. Despite its being placed before the other dogmatic treatises the
doctrine of the Trinity is, in this approach, largely without influence on
the further presentation of dogmatic theology.
The second solution is represented by the renewed Protestant theology
of our century, which has received its classical formulation in Karl Barth.
In this theology the salliS Christus (Christ alone) is not simply a basic
material theological principle which says that all salvation comes to us
through Christ alone. Rather it is also a fundamental formal theological
principle that says we can speak of God only through Jesus Christ and his
mediation. Given the critical assessment of natural theology to which this
salliS Christlls principle leads, it follows that even the prolegomena to
dogmatic theology-or, as post Barthian theologians like to say, theological
hermeneutic - must already speak of christology and the doctrine of the
Trinity. The prolegomena are now no longer simply a preamble to dogmatic
theology but rather that which has to be said first and foremost in dogmatic
theology itself, an instruction on the correct way to speak of God. It follows
from this basic approach that the distinction between the treatises De Deo
uno and De Deo trino is abandoned and the doctrine of the Trinity is shifted
into the dogmatic prolegomena or, if you will, dogmatic hermeneutic, thus
becoming the grammar for all other dogmatic statements. The result of
such an a·theistic theology which is so radically grounded in christology
is that the difference between it and real atheism is emphatically asserted
in faith but hardly demonstrated in an intellectually satisfactory way.
At this point a third solution suggests itself. This is an approach
consistently taken by F. Schleiermacher, the father of Neoprotestantism
and one that is being attempted today even in Catholic theology, as, for
example, in the 'Dutch Catechism'."6 In this approach the Trinity is
Expositioll of the Doctrille of the Trillity 313
regarded as the crowning conclusion and to that extent the summation of
all dogmatic theology. It is sufficiently clear from Schleiermacher that in
this approach the doctrine of the Trinity can also become in practice a
mere appendix. The intrinsic reason for this is easy to understand: if the
doctrine of the Trinity is treated simply as a summation, then it is difficult
to show how it can also serve as the grammar for all other dogmatic
statements. The doctrine of the Trinity necessarily ceases to be the basic
proposition of theology and becomes instead a postscript to theology.
From the idea, just mentioned, of the doctrine of the Trinity as the
grammar of theology in its entirety it follows that an introductoty treatise
De Deo trino is indispensable atthe beginning of dogmatic theology. 'But
this initial treatise should not be an attempt to cover a theme which can be
then marked as read, but a preliminary orientation with regard to a theme
which is still to be dealt with.'2J7It might perhaps be said more accurately:
this treatise would have to deal with a theme that subsequently keeps
surfacing in different variations as in a fugue. For dogmatic theology does
not form a system in the sense that everything can be logically deduced
from a principle. It is a structured whole in which each partial statement
reflects the whole in a different way. For if the Trinity is the one mystery
in the many mysteries, then in the nature of things there is a 'perichoresis'
of the individual dogmatic treatises, each of which deals with the whole
from a particular point of view. In the theology of the Trinity the one
theme that is present in the many themes of dogmatic theology becomes
itself thematic. But in this reflection on the oneness and wholeness of
dogmatic theology the theology of the Trinity presupposes not so much
the other dogmatic treatises as the church's confession of faith, which it
reflects upon in its entirety in the perspective of its ultimate ground and
ultimate goal. The material object of the doctrine of the Trinity is thus the
entire confession of faith with all three of its parts: 'I believe in one God,
the Father almighty ... And in one Lord, Jesus Christ ... I believe in the
Holy Spirit.' The formal object or point of view from which the doctrine
of the Trinity deals with the whole of the Christian faith is God as ground
and goal of all these confessional statements. The material dogmatic
statements made in the other treatises are intelligible as theological
statements only when their formal object is first named; that is, when it
has been made clear what we as Christians mean when we speak of God,
namely, the God of Jesus Christ to whom we have access in the Holy Spirit.
In view of all these considerations we must maintain the priority of the
treatise on the Trinity over the other treatises.
If, however, we are to avoid the negative consequences which this
approach has had both in classical Catholic and in modern Protestant
314 The Trillitariall Mystery of God
theology, we must reflect anew on the inner structure of the doctrine of
God or, concretely, on the relation between the treatise De Deo 11110 and
the treatise De Deo trino. We must therefore take seriously the fact that
when we speak of God and to God we always mean - according to the
Bible and the early church - the Father who is known to us through the
Son in the Holy Spirit. The one God, as Augustine repeatedly insists, is
therefore the triune God. This means that we cannot first speak in a general
way about the being of God and only then of the three divine persons. On
the contrary, after the fashion of the Eastern doctrine of the Trinity, we
must start with the Father as the origin and source of the Trinity and show
that the Father possesses the one divine substance in such a way that he
gives it to the Son and to the Spirit. In other words, the abstract doctrine
of the being of God must once again be incorporated into the doctrine of
the concrete revelation of God's being and thus into the doctrine of the
Triniry.lt is to the creditofthedogmatictheology presented by M. Schmaus
that it made a significant advance in this direction. 238 This new approach,
which we owe to the tradition of the Eastern church, need not lead to an
abandonment ofthe achievements of Augustinian trinitarian theology. For
if we start with the Father as the origin and source of the Trinity we are
led to conceive of the one divine nature as love. Then it becomes possible,
more than in Eastern theology, to understand the Triniry entirely in terms
of its innermost root, as is done, for example, by Richard of St Victor; that
is, as the mystery of perfect love that communicates and empties itself and,
to that extent, as the grammar and summary of the entire Christian mystery
of salvation.
This approach from the economy of salvation likewise need not lead to
the dismissal of natural theology and, with it, of the legitimate concern at
work in the old treatise De Deo tina. For the economy of salvation
presupposes the natural or, beller, the creaturely quest of man for God
and responds to it in a surpassing manner.219 The trinitarian self-revelation
of God is thus the surpassing answer to the question and quest which man
not only has buds: the question and quest of God. The trinitarian revelation
and the trinitarian confession of faith are the ultimate, eschatological
and definitive determination of the indeterminate openness of man. The
doctrine of the Trinity is concrete monotheism. This thesis closes the circle
of our reflections, which began with the contemporary atheistic situation.
It has been shown that the trinitarian confession is the Christian answer
to the challenge of modern atheism. This thesis brings me to a concluding
summary reflection.
ExpositiOl' of the Doctrine of the Trinity 315
The journey from the situation that is given its character by modern atheism
to the trinitarian confession offaith has been a long one; for many, perhaps
too long. It seems to them that the real question calling for an answer today
is the question of God's existence and not that of his inner mystery. In
addition, they regard the theology of the Trinity as often nothing but an
impertinent prying into the mystery of God. They are therefore more or
less content with a theistic confession of faith. But this kind of theological
contentment has, I think, been shown in the chapters of this book to be
based on an inherently untenable position. A theistic faith today is a
Christian faith which has already been undermined by the Enlightenment
and atheism, and in the nature of things it repeatedly turns into the atheism
which it is intended to prevent, but whose arguments it cannot defend itself
against. In the face of the radical challenge to the Christian faith, help will
come not from a feeble, general and vague theism but only from a decisive
witness to the living God of history who has disclosed himself in a concrete
way through Jesus Christ in the Holy Spirit.
The way beyond theism and atheism, as travelled today by many
inAuential representatives of Protestant theology, is safe from the dangers
which threaten theism only if it docs not throw the baby out with the bath
water; that is, if it does not answer the questions of atheists by avoiding
the problems of natural theology and making a direct leap into a supposedly
radical faith and if it does not hastily extend its criticism of theism to a
criticism of monotheism. For monotheism is the answer to the question
raised at the natural level about the unity and meaning of all reality. It is
precisely this ambiguous and open question that is specified in a concrete
way by the trinitarian self-revelation of God, so that the trinitarian
confession is concrete monotheism and as such the Christian answer to the
God-question of the human person. The God of Jesus Christ - that is, the
God who gives himself to be known through Jesus Christ in the Holy Spirit
- is the ultimate, eschatological and definitive determination of the
indeterminate openness of man; he is therefore also the Christian answer
to the situation created by modern atheism. As a result, the proclamation
of the triune God is of the greatest pastoral importance in the present-day
situation.
It is obvious that the complicated exegetical, historical and speculative
questions with which the theology of the Trinity must grapple are not the
direct object of the proclamation of the trinitarian mystery of God. The
discussion of such questions is necessary in order to defend the confession
against challenges, to make it at least possible to discuss the doctrine with
316 The TrinitariQ/1 Mystery of God
its 'cultured despisers', and, more important still, to open up the doctrine
to those who venerate it in faith. Such discussions are therefore of
fundamental importance for the proclamation of the doctrine, even if only
indirectly.
The direct object of the proclamation, as the church's confession of faith,
is the economic Trinity and the God of Jesus Christ who in the Spirit gives
us life and freedom, reconciliation and peace. Of course, the proclamation
cannot stop there. For according to the Lord's farewell prayer true life
consists precisely in knowing and glorifying God. For its own sake therefore
soteriology must pass over into doxology. For amid all the vicissitudes and
instability of history man's salvation consists in having communion with
the God who through all eternity is love. It is precisely an anthropologically
oriented theology that must also be a theological theology which takes into
account that the ad maiorem homillis sa/litem (to the greater salvation of
man) is possible only by way of the ad maiorem Dei g/oriam (to the
greater glory of God). It is therefore possible for theology to develop the
anthropological relevance of what it says only if it remains theology and
does not turn into anthropology. It is the acknowledgment of the Godness
of God that leads to the humanization of man.
It is undoubtedly pleonastic to speak, as I did at the beginning of this
book, of theological theology as a program; the formula 'theological
theology' makes sense only as a polemical formula which serves to remind
theology of its own proper theme. The challenge raised by atheism and,
even more, by the crisis in atheism must cause theologians to attend once
again to the theological dimension which is denied by atheism and has
been suppressed or simply forgotten, and to revive an awareness of it as
the one supremely important thing for man. This is all the more necessary
because the proclamation of the death of God has meanwhile led to the
public proclamation of the death of man. If this answer is not to stop half-
way and is to allow the God of Jesus Christ to have his full impact, then
the answer must take the form of the confession of the Trinity. Precisely
because this confession takes seriously the Godness of God, his freedom
in love, it is able to rescue the freedom in love and for love that has been
given us by God through Jesus Christ in the Holy Spirit, and'thus to rescue
the humanity of man at a time when it is most threatened.
Abbreviations
PART ONE
PART TWO
PART THREE
- - -