Introduction To Syntax: Manuela SCH Onenberger and Cornelia Hamann, Revised by Michael Treichler
Introduction To Syntax: Manuela SCH Onenberger and Cornelia Hamann, Revised by Michael Treichler
Introduction To Syntax: Manuela SCH Onenberger and Cornelia Hamann, Revised by Michael Treichler
1 Introduction
Linguistic theory has the following three main objectives:
3. to gain some insight into how the human brain works by studying lan-
guage
∗
This introduction to syntax is aimed at 1st-year students in English linguistics at the
University of Oldenburg. Various sources were used, in particular the syntax manuscript
by Genoveva Puskás (2002), the book ’English Grammar: A generative perspective’ by
Liliane Haegeman and Jacqueline Guéron (1999), and Cornelia Hamann’s lecture notes.
We are grateful to Solveig Bosse and Danica Grade for helpful comments.
1
not perfect and errors can occur, as, e.g. in slips of the tongue or in-
complete sentences. In other words, these errors belong to the domain
of linguistic performance, and are independent of the linguistic compe-
tence. The concept of performance more or less corresponds to Saussure’s
concept of parole.
Syntax is one of the core domains of linguistics. Other core domains are mor-
phology, semantics, pragmatics, phonetics, and phonology. While morphology
investigates the internal structure of words, syntax concentrates on how words
are arranged in a sentence. It is concerned with the structure of sentences and
the smaller parts which make up sentences. It studies the rules which govern
word order and sentence structure. Some of the aspects discussed in syntax
are:
Word order: there are variations in word order between languages spoken
nowadays (e.g. English vs. German) as well as within a language from a
diachronic point of view (e.g. Old English vs. present-day English).
(4) a. Harry and Ron think that they get on very well with each other.
b. They think that Harry and Ron get on very well with each other.
c. That Harry and Ron get on very well with each other is what they
think.
(5) a. Dobby washes his new sock [with colourful stripes] [with care].
b. *Dobby washes his new sock [with care] [with colourful stripes].
2
Ambiguities: some sentences have more than one meaning. If the ambiguity
is structural - as opposed to lexical1 - it can be related to the syntactic structure
of the sentence.
(7) Hermione has often smiled at her best friends after a quidditch game.
Labelled Bracketing:
1
Example (i) is a case of lexical ambiguity. The ambiguity is due to the different meanings
of match, which can either refer to a sporting encounter or a thin piece of wood used to
light a fire.
(i) Harry has lost the match.
3
2 Word Categories
2.1 Lexical Categories
A basic distinction is drawn between lexical categories and functional cat-
egories. Section 2.1 discusses lexical categories, and Section 2.2 functional
categories. In English there are five lexical categories: N(ouns), Adj(ectives),
Adv(erbs), V(erbs) and P(repositions)2 . Lexical categories are open-class
categories, (i.e. new members can easily be added to the list of nouns, verbs,
etc.), and they have a rich semantic content.
1. Morphology
In English, nouns can usually be inflected for plural, i.e., they bear an
overt morphological mark for plural. The regular form is -s (pronounced
as [r], [z], or [Iz], which are allomorphs of the morpheme plural), as in
(11-a),(11-b),(11-c), but there are also less productive forms, as in (11-d)
and (11-e).
There is hardly any overt case distinction in modern English. The phrase
the wizard is a subject in (12-a) and an object in (12-c). Although the
wizard has different functions in (12-a) and (12-c) (subject vs. object)
and occupies different positions, no difference in case is visible. When the
wizard is replaced by a pronoun, as in (12-b) and (12-d), a case distinction
2
Adverbs are sometimes not regarded as a separate lexical category, but subsumed under
the category of Adjectives.
4
between nominative and accusative becomes visible. The same holds for
the phrase the witch. Nouns still show genitive case marking, as in (13),
a difference which is also visible in pronouns.
2. Distribution
Distribution considers in what environment a word can appear. As shown
in (14), nouns can be preceded by e.g. articles (14-a), possessive pronouns
(14-b), or demonstratives (14-c):
English adjectives do not inflect for plural - as opposed to German: das alte
Haus vs. die alten Häuser - but there is morphological marking for comparative
and superlative forms. Comparative and superlative may be realised as bound
morphs (er, est), as in (16-a) and (16-b), or appear as free morphs (more, the
most), as in (16-c).
5
they modify the noun, as in (18-c), but they can also be predicative, i.e.,
they appear in a sentence with e.g. (copula) be, as in (19-c).
Some types of adverbs, e.g. usually, frequently, often, can modify a whole
sentence:
6
2.1.4 Verbs (V)
Some examples of verbs are given in (25).
Verbs can show inflection, as in (26), where -s stands for 3rd person singular
present tense (26-a), and -ed for past tense (26-c),(26-d).
Verbal inflection in English is very poor. In the present tense only two forms
are distinguished (sleep vs. sleeps). A comparison with German and Italian in
(27) shows that German has five (or four (e.g. machen)) different forms, and
Italian has six different forms. In the past tense English only has one form
(slept (irregular), jumped, kicked ). Verbal inflection is also visible in the suffix
– ing in present participles (sleeping, jumping, kicking).
Verbs can co-occur with auxiliaries (28-a) and modals (28-b), which, as we
shall see in Section 2.2.2 have to be distinguished from verbs:
7
Prepositions in English are invariant, i.e. they never show any inflection.
They are usually followed by nominal constituents, as in (30-c). Some prepo-
sitions can also be followed by a sentential constituent (31-b).
Nouns, adjectives, adverbs, verbs, and prepositions are usually classified as lex-
ical categories. Typically lexical categories have rich semantic content. If you
replace ’dog’ by ’wolf’ or ’before’ by ’after’ the meaning changes drastically.
Lexical categories are open-class categories, which means that speakers regu-
larly add new members. In this respect, prepositions are atypical. Although
they have rich semantic content, it is hard to create new prepositions.
8
b. the cats, the oxen
c. a cat, an ox
d. cats, oxen
(33) water, rice
English also has a set of modals (e.g. can, may, must, shall ), which do not
have rich semantic content. Their role is to express the modality of the sen-
tence, i.e. necessity or possibility, and other similar concepts. Like auxiliaries,
modals need to co-occur with a lexical verb:
9
The auxiliaries have and be also have an infinitival form. The infinitival form
have follows the modal may in (38-a) and the infinitival form be follows the
modal might in (38-b) . Note that if the modals had been omitted from these
sentences, the finite forms of these auxiliaries would have surfaced, i.e. has in
(38-a) and is in (38-b).
Modals do not carry an –s in 3rd person singular present tense: she can/*cans,
nor do they have an infinitival form: *he should can eat more (cf. Er sollte
mehr essen können). The forms may and might, for example, do not necessarily
express a difference in tense, i.e. present vs. past tense (other modals do, cf.
can/could ), but a difference in probability. Compare (39-a) with (39-b), in
which might suggests a somewhat lower probability than may.
(40) a. I believe [(that) Alice and Humpty Dumpty are good friends].
b. Alice regrets [that Humpty Dumpty eats too much].
c. She wonders [whether he will ever get tired of eating marshmal-
lows].
d. He will of course ask her again [if he can have some more].
e. [For Humpty Dumpty to go on a diet] would be quite pointless.
10
3 Phrase Structure
3.1 Constituents
The words of a language can be grouped into different categories. In a sentence,
these words combine to form larger units, called constituents. A sentence is
not simply a string of linearly ordered words: words combine to form larger
units, which in turn combine to form a sentence. Consider the sentence in
(41):
There are groups of words in this sentence which seem to belong together, as
indicated by the bracketing in (42). Most of us share the intuition that the
bracketing in (42-a) is natural, whereas that in (42-b) is not.
3.1.1 Substitution
Substitution is a manipulation in which a unit is replaced by a shorter form,
called a pro-form. Units containing a noun can usually be replaced by pro-
nouns, temporal adverbials by then
11
(44) a. *Harry will meet THEM friends after dark.
b. *Harry will meet THEM dark.
3.1.2 Clefting
Clefting isolates a constituent by moving it into the slot ( ) in the frame it is
that/who, which results in putting emphasis on the constituent:
(45) a. It is HARRY who will meet his closest friends after dark.
b. It is HIS CLOSEST FRIENDS that Harry will meet after dark.
c. It is AFTER DARK that Harry will meet his closest friends.
In (45) Harry, his closest friends, and after dark are again identified as
constituents, while his closest and after do not pass the clefting test:
(46) a. *It is HIS CLOSEST that Harry will meet friends after dark.
b. *It is AFTER that Harry will meet his closest friends dark.
3.1.3 Questions
A constituent can be questioned. This means that a constituent can be re-
placed by a question word, as in (47):
(47) a. WHO will meet his closest friends after dark? (who = Harry)
b. WHO(M) will Harry meet after dark? (who(m) = his closest
friends)
c. WHEN will Harry meet his closest friends? (when = after dark)
We can show that the target of the question can only be a constituent:
Once more we have identified Harry, his closest friends, and after dark as
constituents.
3.1.4 Deletion
Deletion is another constituency test. It has to be handled with care, however.
Only certain/optional units can be omitted/deleted from a sentence and can
12
thus be identified as constituents, as shown in (49). Both after dark and closest
pass this test. Note that deleting closest and after dark at the same time, as
in (49-c), does not show that closest after dark is a constituent. This might
be quite obvious, since after all closest and after dark are not adjacent to each
other; friends intervenes. In (50-a), on the other hand, nothing intervenes
between in the belfry and after dark and still in the belfry after dark is not a
constituent. Deletion cannot identify all constituents: Although we know that
his closest friends is a constituent, it does not pass the deletion test (50-b) (cf.
Section 4.2).
3.1.5 Movement
A unit which forms a constituent can be moved, unless this movement violates
other constraints3 . (The symbol marks the site from which the constituent
has been moved.)
As shown for other tests, movement only affects strings of words which form
a constituent:
To summarize, the constituency tests do not apply in the same way to all
constituents. This is why they should be considered as indications rather
than as acid tests. Certain constituents cannot be identified as such in the
substitution test, for example, not because they do not form constituents,
but because there is no pro-form which could function as a proper substitute.
Although dark is nominal, the pro-form it cannot substitute for it.
3
The Clefting-test in Section 3.1.2 and the Question-test in Section 3.1.3 also involve move-
ment.
13
If a string of words can be identified as a constituent by one of the constituency
tests that is enough. Although we have shown that his closest friends is a
constituent using various tests, any one test would have been sufficient.
3.2 Ambiguity
Constituency tests can be used to disambiguate structurally ambiguous
sentences. The sentence in (54) is ambiguous, since it can have more than one
interpretation. It can either mean that Hermione used binoculars to see the
witch, or that the witch herself had binoculars (and Hermione might just have
good eye-sight).
These tests show that the sentence in (54) is structurally ambiguous. None
of the words in (54) gives rise to this ambiguity, but depending on how we
organise the elements of the sentence we obtain two different interpretations.
14
do not form a constituent. In fact, the modal seems to be a constituent by
itself. This can be shown by the yes/no question test. The verb does not
usually form a constituent by itself, which can be shown by pseudoclefting.
3.3.2 Pseudo-Clefting
Pseudo-clefting is a process similar to clefting. Part of the sentence (i.e. the
subject and the modal/auxiliary and the appropriate form of do) are preposed
and inserted in the frame what is [...] .4 The string of words in the frame
[...] identifies the verbal unit. This test again shows that will does not belong
to the verbal unit.
(58) a. What Harry will do after dark is [meet his closest friends].
b. What Harry will do is [meet his closest friends after dark].
c. *What Harry does is [will meet his closest friends after dark].
4
To illustrate this point consider the example in (i) containing an auxiliary rather than a
modal. The corresponding pseudo-cleft is shown in (ii). Since the auxiliary has selects
a past participle, and not an infinitive, the appropriate form of do is done.
(i) Harry has met his closest friends after dark.
(ii) What Harry has done is [meet his closest friends after dark].
In (iii) the verb meet occurs in the 3rd person singular present tense form meets. In
the corresponding pseudo-cleft in (iv) the inflected form does has to be used.
(iii) Harry meets his closest friends after dark.
(iv) What Harry does is [meet his closest friends after dark].
In all these pseudo-clefts the verbal unit is identified as [meet his closest friends after
dark]. In other words, neither the modal will, nor the auxiliary has, nor the inflection -s
are part of the verbal unit.
15
Both pseudo-clefting and the yes/no question test show that the modal and
the verb belong to two different constituents.
16
4 Argument Structure
4.1 Subcategorization
We have shown that words often combine with other words to form larger
constituents. Let us look at some of these words and at verbs in particular and
see what kinds of constraints they impose on the composition of constituents
and the sentence. Consider the examples in (59):
The verb sleep in (59) is intransitive, which means that it cannot co-occur
with an object (59-b). On the other hand sleep can be accompanied by other
types of constituents, which tell us more about the sleeping event. Peacefully
(59-c) tells us more about the manner of sleeping and at night (59-d) tells
us more about the time of sleeping. These constituents are not obligatory,
i.e. they can be left out without rendering the sentence ungrammatical (see
(59-a)). Such optional constituents are called adjuncts.
Besides intransitive verbs there are also transitive verbs and ditransitive
verbs. Transitive verbs require one object, as shown in (60). The verb deliver
is transitive. It must be followed by a direct object (mail ). Leaving out the
object, as in (60-b) and (60-d), renders the sentence ungrammatical. The
constituent during meals is optional. Replacing the obligatory constituent
mail by the optional constituent during meals does not improve the sentence
(60-d). We say that the transitive verb deliver selects a nominal object or
subcategorizes for a nominal object. The direct object which is selected
by the transitive verb or which is subcategorized for by the transitive verb is
called a complement.
Other verbs can select other types of complements. The verb live in (61)
selects a prepositional complement, the verb wonder in (62) selects a sentential
complement.
17
b. *Unicorns live.
(62) a. Ron wonders [whether Harry will be attacked again].
b. *Ron wonders.
c. *Ron wonders [another attack on Harry].
There are also verbs which require two complements. These verbs are ditran-
sitive:
5
The abbreviations DP, PP, etc. are discussed in Chapter 5.
18
4.2 Complements and Adjuncts
As mentioned above, a distinction must be drawn between obligatory con-
stituents and optional constituents. The subcategorization frame of a verb
lists the constituents which are selected by the verb. Each verb has its own
subcategorization frame, which is part of the lexical entry of a verb. Sen-
tences contain other constituents besides those subcategorized for by the verb.
Consider the examples in (66).
Although the subject Hermione is not subcategorized for by the verb solve, it
is an obligatory constituent of the sentence. There is a constraint which says
that every English sentence must have a subject which is actually prnounced.
The fact that the sentences in (66) have to have a subject is not specific to
these sentences, but a general property of English sentences.
The verb solve is transitive and selects a nominal complement (the puzzle).
The constituent in the library is an adjunct; it is not selected by the verb solve.
In contrast to the nominal complement the puzzle in (67-a), in the library in
(67-b) can easily be left out without rendering the sentence ungrammatical.
19
The noun solution is closely related to the verb solve. Although solution like
solve takes a complement, as in (69-a), it is possible to omit the complement of
solution, as in (69-b), while it is not possible to omit the complement of solve
(cf. (67-a)). The fact that the complement of the noun solution can be left
out does not mean that of the puzzle is an adjunct. In general, complements
of nouns, as opposed to those of verbs, can be left unexpressed.
From a syntactic point of view these sentences are grammatical, because the
transitive verbs startle and thank are followed by a direct object (DP). From
a semantic point of view, however, these sentences are anomalous, which is
indicated by the diacritic #.
The function of a verb is to relate ’participants’ in the sentence. These par-
ticipants are the arguments of the verb. In (70-a), for example, the verb startle
takes two arguments: the argument in the subject position, which causes the
startling, and the argument in the object position, which is being startled.
The roles are formally expressed as thematic roles, and are assigned by the
verb. The type of thematic role depends on the meaning of the verb. It is
crucial to know what the verb means in order to be able to decide what kind
of role the arguments will play. The notion of thematic role is distinct from
the syntactic notion of subcategorization. In (71-a) the transitive verb frighten
subcategorizes for a complement, which is realised by the Cheshire Cat. The
subcategorization frame of frighten in (71-b) expresses the fact that frighten
takes a DP complement, but does not say anything about the thematic role
borne by this complement. Moreover, the fact that frighten needs a subject is
not even expressed in its subcategorization frame, because this is a property
common to all verbs and therefore does not need to be explicitly mentioned
in a verb’s subcategorization frame. Thus frighten takes two arguments: the
subject argument and the object argument.
20
(71) a. The little mouse frightened the Cheshire Cat.
b. frighten, V [ DP]
We now need the process of thematic role assignment, which ensures that the
arguments which are realised are compatible with the meaning of the verb.
In other words, from a semantic point of view, a verb like frighten assigns a
thematic role which expresses the fact that someone/something (animate) is
doing the frightening, and another thematic role which expresses the object
which is frightened. These two thematic roles are assigned to the two obligatory
arguments of frighten. In example (72) the verb frighten assigns the thematic
role of agent to the argument in the subject position (the little mouse) and the
thematic role of patient to the argument in the object position (the Cheshire
Cat).
Verbs assign thematic roles to their arguments, that is to their selected com-
plements and the subject. Do all verbs assign thematic roles? Consider the
examples in (73):
All the examples in (73) contain the verb snore. In (73-a), the subject is the
only argument: it is assigned a thematic role. In (73-b) the verb snore is
accompanied by an auxiliary verb, and in (73-c) by a modal. But in all these
sentences we only have one argument (Hedwig). We conclude that auxiliaries
and modals do not assign thematic roles. Remember that neither auxiliaries
nor modals have a rich semantic content. It is therefore not really surprising
that they do not assign thematic roles: they do not express any kind of action,
or state. Lexical verbs, on the other hand, do assign thematic roles.
21
5 Syntactic Representations
It should be evident by now that a sentence is not just a string of words put
next to each other: words combine to form units which in turn combine to
form larger units. In other words, there is a hierarchy in the ordering of words
within a sentence. In this chapter, we are going to examine the different levels
of hierarchy we can identify within a sentence. The difference between positions
occupied by complements and adjuncts will play a major role. Ultimately we
want to derive an abstract schema which is common to all the word categories
introduced in the previous sections. This abstract schema is called X-bar
schema, represented by means of a tree diagram in (74).
(74) XPE
yyy EEE
y EE
yy EE
yy
Specifier X’
E
yyy EEE
yy EE
y EE
yy
X Complement
5.1 Phrases
Consider example (75), which we will analyse in detail.
(75) The old wizard will concoct the poisonous potion in the classroom.
(76) [the old wizard] [will] [concoct the poisonous potion in the classroom]
22
There is a variant of the substitution test called the do-so test, which only
works for VPs, shown in (78):
(78) a. The old wizard will concoct the poisonous potion in the classroom
and Malfoy will do so too.
b. The old wizard will concoct the poisonous potion in the classroom
and Malfoy will do so at home.
c. *The old wizard will concoct the poisonous potion in the classroom
and Malfoy will do so a sleeping draught at home.
(79)
23
order of words can be read off the tree diagram.
(80) The old wizard will concoct the poisonous potion in the classroom
after the next full moon.
(81)
Using the do-so test we can identify snore at night as a constituent in (83-a).
We can also identify snore as a constituent in (83-b):
(83) a. Neville and Harry snore at night and Ron does so too.
b. Neville and Ron snore at night and Ron does so during classes.
Since snore is intransitive it does not select a complement. Like other verbs,
snore can be modified by an adjunct, here the time-adjunct at night, which is
adjoined at the VP-level:
24
(84)
Turning to the example with the ditransitive verb put in (85) we can show
that put a crispy bone under the sofa on Sunday is a constituent (86-a), as is
put a crispy bone under the sofa (86-b). However, neither put a crispy bone
(86-c) nor put (86-d) are constituents. We conclude that a crispy bone and
under the sofa are complements of put and occupy complement positions, while
on Sunday is a time-adjunct, which is adjoined to VP. The structure of the
VP is depicted in (87).
25
5.1.2 The Noun Phrase (NP)
In this section we will look at the nominal constituents in (88), which do not
have a determiner6 . The essential word in these nominal constituents is the
noun: wizards in (88-a) and teachers in (88-b). The Noun (N) is the head of
the Noun Phrase (NP).
6
The strings wise wizards and old teachers of alchemy from Rome could be preceded by a
determiner, as in (i):
(i) a. [DP these [NP wise wizards]] b. [DP the [NP old teachers of alchemy from
Rome]]
The constituents in (i) are called Determiner Phrases (DP), which will be discussed in
Section 5.2.1. In fact, wise wizards and old teachers of alchemy from Romeare also DPs,
in which the Determiner, which heads the DP, is nonovert. Remember that English does
not have an indefinite plural article, as opposed to French des, for example.
26
(89)
(91)
27
5.1.4 The Prepositional Phrase (PP)
The structure applied to VP, NP, and AP can also be extended to Preposi-
tional Phrases (PPs), which are headed by prepositions (Ps), as in (92):
(93)
(94)
7
The variable X can stand for V, N, A, etc.
28
5.2 Functional Categories
5.2.1 The Determiner Phrase (DP)
The determiner (D) is not part of the NP. However, a special relationship holds
between the determiner and the noun heading the NP. The determiner and the
noun have to agree in number (singular vs. plural) in English. The determiner
this is singular and the noun heading the NP must be singular as well (95-a).
The determiner these is plural and the noun heading the NP must be plural as
well (95-b). A reasonable assumption is that the determiner – the head of the
Determiner Phrase (DP) – selects the maximal projection of N, namely
NP, as its complement. The detailed structure of the DP these tiny dragons
and the DP Hagrid is given in (96). It is customary not to show the detailed
structure of a constituent if it only contains a head (and no complement(s) nor
any adjuncts), as in (96-b’) (and also (96-a)), where the triangle means that
no detailed structure is shown.
The subject DP the old witch can be identified as a constituent by e.g. substi-
29
tution (she) and the VP buy a new broomstick by e.g. pseudo-clefting (What
the old witch may do is [buy a new broomstick]). The modal might is not
contained in the VP. This can be shown by the yes/no question test, in which
might is moved to the beginning of the sentence, and the VP itself does not
move:
Without entering the intricacies of this hypothesis, the Inflection (I) is taken to
be the head of the sentence (IP). In sentences without modals and auxiliaries
inflection is marked on the lexical verb. However, both pseudo-clefting and
yes/no questions show that the inflection is not part of the VP. The same holds
for auxiliaries, which can carry inflection. Although modals do not inflect,
they behave like auxiliaries and are therefore treated in the same way, i.e. as
30
elements in I.
The phrase marker of example (97) is given in (101). The head of the
sentence – the Inflectional Phrase (IP) – is I, which is occupied by the
modal might. I selects VP. VP and I project up to the intermediate level
I’ (I-bar). The subject, a DP, sits in the specifier of IP (Spec,IP). One of
the differences between a specifier position and an adjoined position is that
there is only one specifier position in a maximal projection, while there is no
limit on the number of adjoined positions. Thus there is only one [Spec,IP] in
a (simple) sentence.
(101)
31
b. Gromit may believe [ CP that a lost sheep should feel unhappy].
(103)
32
Since complex sentences consist of more than one clause there is more than
one Spec,IP position, i.e. one per clause (IP).
In these examples, the inflectional affixes –s and –ed are bound to the verbal
stem smile. If we form yes/no questions based on these sentences we obtain the
sentences in (105), in which the inflectional affixes are no longer attached to
the verbal stem smile, but to the stem of do. Since inflectional affixes must be
bound, the dummy verb do is used to host them. Note that do does not have
any semantic meaning in these sentences, and that is why it is often referred
to as a dummy verb.
In fact, the dummy verb do is also used in other contexts, e.g. with sentential
negation (i.e. not) unless a modal or auxiliary is present:
Modals and auxiliaries behave alike: they can be fronted in questions and they
are incompatible with do. Lexical verbs, on the other hand, cannot be fronted
in questions and cannot precede negation. They require the presence of do
in these contexts, which is sometimes referred to as do-support. Do–like
modals and auxiliaries can be fronted in questions and can precede sentential
negation.
33
The fact that the inflection surfaces on the lexical verb in (104), but on
do in (105) and (107-a), suggests that the inflection itself is dissociated from
the lexical verb at some abstract level. In the theory of generative syntax we
embrace here, (at least) two levels of representation are distinguished: one
level, called Deep Structure, and another level, called Surface Structure,
which more or less coincides with the actual sentence we perceive (in written
or spoken form).
Let us examine the sentences in (108), in which the inflection occurs on the
auxiliary (108-a), and on the lexical verb (108-b):
The Deep Structure ’Hagrid –ed free his pet dragon’ does not correspond
to an actual sentence. At Surface Structure the words are arranged so they
correspond to an actual sentence. Thus the inflectional affix –ed must appear
bound to a verbal stem. In theory, –ed and free could combine by either
raising the verb free up to –ed in I, or by lowering –ed onto the verb in V.
To determine which option is actually chosen in English, we can look at the
34
position of adverbs, modifying the VP, such as quickly.
The adjunct quickly modifies the freeing event and is therefore adjoined at
the VP-level. Since the inflected verb freed linearly follows the adverb in the
grammatical example in (110-a), we conclude that the inflection is lowered onto
V, which is called affix-hopping. Affix-hopping is a type of movement.
A trace (abbreviated as ’t’) under I indicates the original position of the
inflection, i.e. the position occupied by the inflection at Deep Structure. The
trace t and the moved element –ed are coindexed. Note that affix-hopping
involves movement from a head-position (I) to another head position (V).
35
occurred, the D-Structure and the S-Structure of these sentences coincide.8
444 yy
y EE
EE
yy
They I VP
yEE
yyy EEE
yy EE
yy E
will AdvP E VP
yyy EEE
y EE
yy EE
yy
adamantly V’
yEE
yy EEE
y
yy EE
yy E
V DP
guard D’
E
yy EEE
yyy EE
y EE
yy
D NP 6
666
66
the secret
8
From now on, we will use tree diagrams in which the words are not on one line. They may
be more difficult to read but nevertheless you should try to become acquainted with the
diagram style introduced in (113-a)
36
b.
IP
yEE
yy EEE
y
yy EE
yy E
DP
7 I’E
77 yyy EEE
777 yy
y EE
EE
7 yy
Harry I VPE
yyy EEE
y y EE
y EE
yy
may AdvP VP
777
77
77
slowly V’
E
yyy EEE
y EE
yy EE
yy
V DPI
uuu III
uu II
uu II
uu I
regain consciousness
To summarize, in this section two levels of representation were introduced:
D-Structure and S-Structure. D-Structure is an abstract level encoding in-
formation relating to selectional and functional properties of words. Between
D-Structure and S-Structure movement can take place, which may influence
the order of words. Affix-hopping is a type of movement which does not change
the linear order of words. A case where movement does have an impact on
word order is discussed in the next section.
37
and S-Structure coincide – there is movement of will before S-Structure in
(114-b), resulting in a different word order. What kind of position could will
have moved to? Recall from 5.2.3 that there is a higher projection than IP,
namely CP, which we needed to account for embedded sentences: embedded
sentences are CPs introduced by a complementizer in C. A complementizer
linearly precedes the subject, and so does will in (114-b). We deduce that
will occupies the same position as the complementizer, i.e. C, and that is has
moved from I to C (from a head-position to another head-position). The trace
in I indicates the original position of will and is co-indexed with will in C.
love D’E
yy EEE
yyy EE
y EE
yy
D NP
> >>
>>
>>
the presents
38
b. S-Structure of (114-b):
CP
C’
yRRRRR
yyy RRR
yy RRR
yy RR
C IP
y yRRRRR
yy RRR
yy RRR
yy RR
Willi DP I’E
yyy EEE
y EE
yy EE
yy
D’
E I VP
yy EEE
yyy EE
y EE
yy
D NP ti V’
::: yEE
:: yy EEE
y
:: yy EE
yy E
Gromit’s friends V DP
love D’
yEE
yy EEE
y
yy EE
yy E
D NP
> >>
>>
>>
the presents
39
The D-Structure of (116) is shown in (117-a); the S-Structure in (117-b). We
co-index the moved elements with their respective traces. Since there are two
movements we choose two different indices.
(117) a. D-Structure:
IPR
yy RRRRRR
yyy RRR
y RRR
yy
DP I’E
yyy EEE
y EE
yy EE
yy
D’
E I VP
yy EEE
yyy EE
y EE
yy
D NP will V’
::: yEE
:: yy EEE
y
:: yy EE
yy E
Gromit’s friends V DP
3 3
333
3
love what
b. S-Structure:
CP
E
yy EEE
yyy EE
y EE
yy
DP 8 C’R
888 yyy RRRRRR
88 y RRR
8 yyyy RRR
Whatk C IP
y yRRRRR
yy RRR
yy RRR
yy RR
Willi DP I’E
yyy EEE
y EE
yy EE
yy
D’
E I VP
yy EEE
yyy EE
y EE
yy
D NP ti V’
::: E
yy EEE
:: yy EE
:: yy EE
yy
Gromit’s friends V DP
love tk
40
Let us briefly summarize this chapter:
• Except for affix-hopping, the Surface Structure and the Deep Structure
of declarative sentences in English is the same. Affix-hopping is a type
of movement which involves lowering the inflection in I onto the verb in
V. The lexical verb does not move.
6 References
Haegeman, Liliane (2006), Thinking syntactically: A guide to argumentation
and analysis. Oxford: Blackwell.
Haegeman, Liliane and J. Guéron (1999), English grammar: A generative
perspective. Oxford: Blackwell.
Haegeman, Liliane (1994), Introduction to government and binding theory
(2nd edition). Oxford: Blackwell.
Ouhalla, Jamal (1994), Introducing transformational grammar: From prin-
ciples and parameters to minimalism. London: Arnold.
Puskás, Genoveva (2002), English linguistics 1rst year handout: Introduction
to syntax. Ms., University of Geneva.
Roberts, Ian (1997), Comparative syntax. London: Arnold.
41