Globalisation and Global Justice
Globalisation and Global Justice
Globalisation and Global Justice
net/publication/249044083
CITATIONS READS
7 712
1 author:
Goran Collste
Linköping University
49 PUBLICATIONS 140 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
All content following this page was uploaded by Goran Collste on 15 January 2017.
Introduction
When I spoke with one of our Nigerian master students in applied
ethics the other day, he told me the story about when SAP came to
Nigeria. SAP was the acronym used for Structural Adjustment
Programmes which were enforced by the World Bank and the
International Monetary Fund (IMF) during the military dictatorship in
the 90th. He was a boy at the time but he still remembered the fear and
resentment it caused; because of privatisation of the health care sector,
poor people no longer had any chance to get health care, because of
economic liberalisation, poor farmers had to sell their farms,
unemployment grew and the number of poor people increased.
1
standard of living for many farmers. Due to pressure from the World
Bank and the IMF, in India the Rupie was devalued in 1991 in order to
increase export. The farmers were accordingly advised to grow
commercial crops like cotton and sugar instead of staple crops like rice
and wheat. To be able to do this the farmers had to get loans from the
newly privatised banks. The interest rate raise, the farmers could no
longer pay the interests and many of them lost their small farms. The
policy led to a domestic decrease in food supply and subsequently to
starvation. Now, one can notice a suicidal epidemic among Indian
farmers. In Andhra Pradesh the suicide rate grew from 200 1999 to
2000 last year, Christian Aid reports. Furthermore, according to the
report, the SAP has had similar consequences in other parts of the
globe. Two other Christian Aid-studies report that the liberalisation of
the market has crushed the poultry production in Ghana and led to a
decrease of sugar-cane production in Jamaica with unemployment,
drug-dealing and prostitution as results.1
2
One aim of this article is to show that many decisions behind
economic globalisation are basically ethical. Hence, economic
globalisation touches upon questions of well-being and of justice. I
will discuss two versions of global justice: global rectificatory justice
and global distributive justice and I shall argue that both versions have
a moral force and relevance in the present discussion about global
justice.
3
to for example fees on education and health care in the long run will
bring about economic development. This argument is weakened by
our pictures from the Nigerian master student and Christian Aid and it
has been questioned by former chief economist of the World Bank and
Nobel Prize winner Joseph Stiglitz in his book Globalization and its
discontents. He writes: “The history of the past fifty years has not
supported these theories and hypotheses”2.
However, let us for a moment assume that the justification hold good.
Still it presupposes premises that can be scrutinised from a moral point
of view. When analysing the arguments for structural adjustment
programmes one should take a closer look at concepts like “lower
standard of living”, “in short and long run” and “development”.
“In short and long run” can also be interpreted in different ways. For
how long will the lowering of the living standard last? When will the
economic development begin – in 5 years, 10 years or 50 years? And
what does “development” mean? A higher standard of living for
4
everyone? Or perhaps a higher standard only for those who already
have a high standard? Or does it mean a higher standard particularly
for those who where hit by the previous lowering?
5
programme implies then that the interests of certain individuals can be
sacrificed for the welfare of others, i.e. a moral – and indeed a very
controversial – decision. It comes for example in conflict with Kant’s
second formulation of the Categorical imperative: “Act in such a way
that you treat humanity…always at the same time as an end and never
simply as a means”3 . This imperative implies that a human being may
never be used as a means for others, but this is exactly what structural
adjustments programmes in certain cases imply. Some individuals are
hit by poverty and illness, for the sake of an increased welfare for
others.
6
The message to nations in crises is: accept the conditions or abstain
from loans! Furthermore, which makes the question from a moral
point of view even more demanding, elites that care less about the
welfare of the population often govern the receiving nations.
7
writes: “No more than Canute’s soldiers can we oppose the tides of the
borderless world’s ebb and flow of economic activity”4. As a
consequence, the room for political initiatives is limited and the only
option for politics is to adjust to globalisation in order to benefit from
it.
8
terrorism, global media and global implementation of human rights,
just to mention some examples. Hence, globalisation refers to different
social processes that have a global reach.
9
1982 to 1999. Total volumes of foreign investments grew from $15
billions to $240 billions from 1970 to 1990. The yearly sales volume
of the world’s 50 largest companies increased from $540 billion1975
to $2100 in 1990. Today 50 of the world’s 100 largest economies, are
companies, the rest are nations! Finally, the global financial market,
i.e. the global trading of currencies, securities, bonds etc, increased
from $20 billion per day 1973 to $1800 billion per day 1998! 6 Taken
together, the rapid increase of global trade, foreign investments, the
number and volume of transnational companies (TNC) and the global
financial market, form a more or less integrated global economy. As
the economists Francis Adams and Satya dev Gupta writes:
10
How, then, is globalisation a question for ethics? Globalisation is a
challenge for ethics in at least two ways. First, one aspect of
globalisation is that we are linked to people at a distance. The impact
of our collective actions, for instance in the form of consumption,
production, banking, travelling etc transcends national borders and
this means that the scope of our moral responsibility is becoming
wider. As a consequence it is arbitrary to let national borders delimit
social ethical reasoning and discussions about justice. Thus,
globalisation makes it obvious that methodological territorialism does
not work in social ethics any longer. Secondly, one aspect of
globalisation is that national sovereignty is hollowing and the states
are losing control.8 Important economic and political decisions
shaping the future of societies are taken less and less at a domestic
level and more and more at a global level within global institutions.
My examples of the implications of the imposed structural adjustment
programmes (SAP) are here illustrative. Hence, while economic
globalisation affects how wealth and power is globally distributed, it
has become necessary to discuss social ethics in a global context and
to develop principles of global justice.
11
an income of $146 billion. The richest 200 persons have an income of
$1042 billion. More than 1 billion people lack access to clean water
and 2.4 billion have insufficient sanitary equipment. 1.2 billion people
are very poor and earn less than $1/day. Behind these figures is a
reality of misery, humiliation and hopelessness!
25000
20000
Rich
15000
Middle
10000
Poor
5000
0
1975 1985 1995
12
In face of globalisation and the global divide, ethical theory must
become globally sensitive. The implications of globalisation for
ethical theory are thus twofold. It questions a traditional view of moral
responsibility that limits responsibility to our fellow national citizens
and it questions a methodological and normative ethical
“territorialism” in favour of ideas of global justice.
13
Africa, British, Portuguese and Dutch of Asia, the slave trade etc,
Europe and North America prospered while many colonies sank in
despair. What happened during this period in history is well captured
in the title of Brazilian author Eduardo Galeano’s book Venas abiertas
de América Latina (Open Veins of Latin America).
How, then can we relate this to ethical theory. Referring once again to
Aristotle’s view:
14
Locke’s intention was to justify property rights. However, according
to Locke, property rights are justified as long as “there is enough, and
as good left in common for others”.11 This condition has become
known as Locke’s proviso. In accordance with Locke’s proviso one
could argue that the present global distribution of possessions is not
morally justified because it does not leave enough for the others. This
argument presupposes then that the underdevelopment of the poorest
1/3 of the world’s population, or the 1/5 who live on only 1$/day, is
one side of the coin and the possessions by the ancestors of the
colonial powers is another side of the coin. Global wealth and poverty
is interrelated. Hence, if this presupposition holds true, redistribution
in favour of the poor is mandatory. It is in line with this argument that
philosopher Hillel Steiner in An Essay on Rights argues for a global
fund that would secure that every individual gets his or her fair share
of resources.12
15
result of unjust historical acquisitions, i.e. plunder, theft and war, one
could, also in line with Nozick’s entitlement theory, argue for a global
redistribution of property. Historical injustices thus beg for rectifying
actions.
It seems to me that GRJ has some moral force. Let me illustrate the
argument: Assume that I live a life in prosperity and welfare. My next
door neighbour, on the other hand, lives in poverty and misery. Let us
also assume that many years ago my grandparents stole the land from
my present neighbour’s grandparents and our present difference in
welfare is the result of this historical fact. Then, it seems that my
neighbour with good reasons could demand to get a part of my land or
income, and thus, that I have some moral obligations to my neighbour.
And these obligations are generated by the acts of my forefather.
Even if the GRJ has some moral force, it is not without problems. It
presupposes the possibility of historical and collective responsibility.
Is it reasonable that the fact that some of our forefathers acted wrongly
towards the forefathers of say Africans, Asians or Latin-Americans
implies that we who lives today have a responsibility towards, and are
obliged to compensate, present Africans, Asians and Latin-
Americans? From the point of view of moral individualism this seems
doubtful. One could argue that the oppressor owe something to the
oppressed at the time of colonialism, but not that individuals living
later, i e the grandsons and granddaughters, who themselves neither
16
acted as oppressor nor oppressed owe anything to each other. On the
other hand, if there is a causal relation between the welfare and
positions of the grandchildren of the oppressor and the oppressed
respectively, i.e., if they have benefited and lost because of the former
exploitation, it seems fair that the grandchildren of the oppressor
compensate the grandchildren of the oppressed.
17
As I have interpreted GRJ, global justice depends on some historical
facts. Hence, if the history of colonialism and imperialism can be
described in another and for the colonial powers more favourable way,
the cause of rectification is undermined. However, irrespective of
historical course of events, the question of social justice is relevant
and important, both domestic and global, and not least in the light of
the present poverty in the third world. This means that we also must
look for a theory of global distributive justice (GDJ).
18
methodological territorialism and extends the idea of a social contract
to – what he calls - a Society of Peoples. However, this theory is rather
a theory of just international relations- than a theory of global justice.
(See my critique of The Law of Peoples in Collste 200513)
19
The first principle corresponds to Rawls’s sixth principle in his Law of
Peoples16. It suggests that there are some crucial moral concerns, or
from the right-holders point of view, some crucial moral claims that
applies equally to each human being. These moral concerns and claims
imply obligations on the part of governments and other institutions,
including global ones. Thomas Pogge uses in connection to the UN
Charter §2817 the concept “global institutional order” for the subject of
these rights and he writes: “…our global institutional order is to be
assessed and reformed principally by reference to its relative impact
on human rights fulfilment.”18
20
The second principle takes into account the need for a democratic
global order. It is warranted by a principle of autonomy, e.g. that each
person has a right to influence those decisions that affect his/her life
and by a principle of democratic equality. In the present global
(dis)order, poorer nations have much less influence on international
organisations like the World Bank or the IMF than the wealthier
nations have. The global order suffers from a democratic deficit that
according to the second principle of global justice should be altered.21
21
redistribution. Hence, in the absence of a global government the
principles will demand more of institutional and political regulation of
the global interactions and processes than is presently the case. This
development is however in accordance with recent globalisation
processes concerning human rights enforcement, environmental
protection and other forms of regional and global co-operation and
institutionalisation.23
22
among peoples and individuals around the world? However, even this
objection is successively weakened by globalisation. One aspect of
globalisation is precisely the increasing importance of governing
social institutions and financial agreements on a global level. Besides
the United Nations with its sub-institutions, one can notice a growing
influence of international economic institutions like the IMF, the
World Bank and the WTO as well as a global scheme of property
rights, multilateral agreements of investments etc. Even regional
communities like the EU and NAFTA can be included in a global
basic structure. Financial and economic organisations direct and
redirect economic resources on a global level and many nations are
economically and politically dependent on their policies. Hence, the
global basic structure requires principles of justice as much as the
basic structure of individual societies. The new emerging global basic
structure is the subject of global justice.24
Conclusion
Globalisation has an economic as well as a moral aspect. This fact was
illustrated by a decision to implement Structural Adjustment
Programmes (SAP) in poor countries. Further, I argued that
globalisation has at least two implications that are important for a
discussion about justice. First, globalisation implies that there are new
powerful actors besides nations on the global scene. These actors often
elude political control and accountability. Secondly, globalisation
23
implies global interdependence, which challenges the “methodological
territorialism” of many theories of justice.
24
American farmers are outstripped from the market. Who owes
something to whom?
Acknowledgements
I have benefited from comments by Martin Andersson, Nigel Dower
and Carl- Henric Grenholm on earlier versions of this article. It is
written within a project financed by the Bank of Sweden's
Tercentenary Foundation.
Notes
1
Dagens Nyheter, 2005-05-16
2
Stiglitz, J, Globalization and its Discontents, London: The Penguin Press, 2002, p.79
3
Kant, I, Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals, in Ethical Philosophy, Indianapolis, Hacket 1994 (1785),
p.35
4
Ohmae, K, Putting Global Logic First, in The Evolving Global Economy, ed. Ohmae, K, Boston, Harvard
Business Review Book, 1995
5
Scholte, J A, Globalization, a critical introduction, New York, Palgrave, 2000, p.56
6
Scholte, J A, Globalization, a critical introduction , p. 125, Ostry, S, Technological Change and International
Economic Institutions, i Dev Gupta, S, The Political Economy of Globalisation, Boston: Kluwer, 1997, p.
242, Eatwell, J , The Liberalisation of International Capital Movements: The Impact on Europe, West and East
in Understanding Globalisation, Stockholm: A&W, 1988.
7
Adama, F, Dev Gupta, S, The Political economy of Globalisation: An Introduction, in Dev Gupta, S. The
Political Economy of Globalization, Boston, Kluwer, 1997.
8
Sassen, S, Losing Control? Sovereignty in an Age of Globalization, New York: Polity, 1996
9
UNDP, Human Development Report, 2000, New York, Oxford University press, 2000, World Development
Report 2003. Sustainable Development in a Dynamic World. The World Bank and Oxford University Press,
Washington 2002.
25
10
Aristotle, The Nichomachean Ethics, Book V:2, Oxford, oxford University press, 1980
11
Locke, John, Two Treatises of Government, § 27,London, Dent, 1977 (1690) p.130
12
Steiner, H, An Essay on Rights, Oxford: Blackwell, 1994
13
Collste, G, Globalisation and Global Justice, Studia Theologica, Vol 59, No 1, 2005, pp 55-73
14
With global institutions I mean global organisations like TNCs and with international institutions I mean
international organisations like the World Bank, the International Monetary Fund, United Nations, the European
Union etc.
15
According to the UN Commission on Global Governance, “At the global level, governance has been viewed
primarily as intergovernmental relationships, but it must now be understood as also involving non-governmental
organizations (NGOs), citizens’ movements, multinational corporations, and the global capital market.”
(www.egg.ch/chap1.html, 2002-02-28)
16
Rawls, J, The Law of Peoples, 1999, p.37
17
“Everyone is entitled to a social and international order in which the rights and freedoms set forth in this
Declaration can be fully realized” (UN Declaration of Human Rights, §28)
18
Pogge, T., The International Significance of Human Rights, i The Journal of Ethics, 4, 2000, p.55
19
Pogge, T., 1999, p 64 See also Nussbaum, M, Women and Human Development, The Capabilities Approach,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2000, for a discussion about basic human rights in a global context.
20
Ignatieff, M., Human Rights as Politics and Idolatry, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001, p.57
21
See Held, D, Democracy and the Global Order, Stanford, Stanford University Press, 1995
22
Rawls, J, A Theory of Justice,p.280
23
In Democracy and the Global Order (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1995) political scientist David Held
sketches a conception of democracy and political institutions in an age of globalisation. The so called “Tobin-
tax” is one proposal to introduce a tax on global financial transactions with the aims to slow down global
speculation and to get resources for development projects in the third world. (Tobin, J, A Currency Transaction
Tax, Why and How, Open economics review, 7:493-499, 1996)
24
Buchanan, Allen, Rawls’s Law of Peoples: Rules for a Vanished Westphalian World, Ethics Vol. 110, (2000),
pp 697-721
26