DAVIS Ethics and The University PDF
DAVIS Ethics and The University PDF
DAVIS Ethics and The University PDF
UNIVERSITY
Ethics and the University brings together two closely related topics, the practice
of ethics in the university (“academic ethics”) and the teaching of practical or
applied ethics in the university.
Michael Davis is Senior Fellow at the Center for the Study of Ethics in the
Professions, and Professor of Philosophy, Department of Humanities, Illinois
Institute of Technology. He is the author of Thinking Like an Engineer: Essays in
the Ethics of a Profession (1998).
PROFESSIONAL ETHICS
General editor: Ruth Chadwick, Centre for
Professional Ethics, University of Central
Lancashire
GENETIC COUNSELLING
edited by Angus Clarke
FOOD ETHICS
edited by Ben Mepham
Michael Davis
The right of Michael Davis to be identified as the Author of this Work has been
asserted by him in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised
in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or
hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information
storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers.
Preface vii
Series editor’s preface xi
PART I
Introduction 1
PART II
Research ethics 43
v
CONTENTS
PART III
Teaching ethics 109
Notes 221
Bibliography 255
Index 266
vi
P R E FA C E
This book brings together two closely related topics, the practice of ethics
in the university (“academic ethics”) and the teaching of practical (or
applied) ethics in the university. The topics are related in at least three
ways. The first is historically: a discussion of academic ethics seems to
belong to a wider “ethics boom” in teaching professional ethics, social
ethics, and business ethics. The second is substantively: some fields of
professional (or institutional) ethics, especially the ethics of scientific
research, overlap substantially with academic ethics. Because about half
of all scientists employed in research are employed by universities, many
questions of research ethics are questions of academic ethics as well. The
third is causally: teaching professional ethics, social ethics, or business
ethics can itself generate questions of academic ethics (or, at least, of
“professorial ethics”). For example, if teaching medical ethics is a kind of
inculcation of proper values, how can an academic committed to freeing
the mind of mere inculcation ethically teach medical ethics? Ethics and
the University works at the intersection of these historical, substantive,
and causal relations. Its purpose is both to clarify the field and extend
discussion on certain central topics.
Part I provides a high-altitude survey of the field, marking distinctions
important throughout the book. Chapter 1, “The ethics boom, philosophy,
and the university,” offers an explanation of the emergence of practical
ethics as a university subject, putting that subject into a wider social and
historical context. This chapter distinguishes several senses of ethics
and explains the sense in which the ethics boom is new, generating new
problems for the university that wishes to make room for it. Academic
ethics is a special topic within the complex of topics now identifiable as
“the ethics boom.”
Chapter 2 considers the relation between academic freedom, academic
vii
P R E FA C E
viii
P R E FA C E
ix
P R E FA C E
x
SERIES EDITOR’S
P R E FA C E
xi
S E R I E S E D I TO R ’ S P R E FA C E
xii
Part I
INTRODUCTION
1
THE ETHICS BOOM,
P H I L O S O P H Y, A N D T H E
UNIVERSITY
It was the best of times, it was the worst of times, it was the age of
wisdom, it was the age of foolishness,…we were all going direct
to Heaven, we were all going direct the other way – in short, the
period was so far like the present, that some of its noisiest
authorities insisted on its being received for good or for evil, in
the superlative degree of comparison only.
With these words Charles Dickens began A Tale of Two Cities, rebuking
all those “noisy authorities” who would claim for their age some priority
over others. No age is without some experts to declare it the best of times
and others to declare it the worst. Yet, Dickens would not, I think, deny
that times change. His rebuke must, then, be directed at those who, without
good evidence, declare that their age differs in some important way from
others. The age in which one lives always looks different from those of
which one knows little or nothing.
I have, I admit, a personal stake in this reading of Dickens. I want to
claim that our present concern with “ethics” distinguishes this age from
others. I am therefore a candidate for Dickens’ rebuke. To avoid it, I shall
proceed in this way. I shall begin this chapter by considering what the
“ethics boom” is supposed to be; then examine the evidence for the
boom; and, having shown the boom to be real, explain why we are having
it. The boom’s novelty, its connection with academic philosophy, is a
corollary of that explanation and an appropriate way to introduce our
subject; ethics and the university.
3
THE ETHICS BOOM
What boom?
Looking back over the last three decades, what I seem to see is not one
boom but many. The first is in medical ethics. By the early 1960s, physicians
were already struggling with many questions they did not feel prepared
to answer. Medical technology made it possible to keep patients alive
long after they had no hope even of consciousness. What did doing
one’s best for the patient mean in such circumstances? When, if ever, may
a physician justifiably cease trying to preserve life when there is hope of
preserving it?
Medical technology was also becoming increasingly expensive.
Physicians confronted hard questions of distribution. Do we buy a dialysis
machine to keep a few dozen patients alive or instead spend the money on
an outpatient clinic that will serve many more people but perhaps save no
lives? How do we decide who gets dialysis if we can’t provide dialysis for
all who need it? Should physicians make such decision? If not physicians,
who?
Medical technology was also changing the practice of medicine. The
old personal relationship between physician and patient, the symbol of
which was the house call, was becoming increasingly impractical. The
progress of medicine seemed to force physicians to specialize more, to
depend more on tests that could only be performed in an office or at a
hospital, and to cooperate more closely with other physicians. The lone
doctor with their little black bag was going the way of the passenger train
and the forty-acre farm. In this less personal environment, traditional
practices like giving a placebo looked much harder to defend. Lying to an
old friend for his or her own good seems one thing; lying to a helpless
stranger, another.
Physicians spoke of these changes in the way they practiced medicine
as raising issues of “medical ethics.”1 At first, they talked about these
issues among themselves. Soon, however, they recognized that they were
not equipped to resolve them. So, as befits an era of increasing
specialization, they began looking for help from specialists in ethics.
Medical schools had no such specialty. But every university had courses
with “ethics” in the title. Usually, these were taught by philosophers. So,
going for help to philosophers seemed to make sense. And, at a few
universities, that is what members of the medical faculty did.
They were surprised by what they found. Philosophers, it turned out,
taught moral theory, not practical ethics. And the moral theory to which
they devoted most of their time was far from practice. The philosophers
4
THE ETHICS BOOM
5
THE ETHICS BOOM
law schools by surprise. Legal ethics had until then been an optional
course struggling to survive in an increasingly rich curriculum. My own
experience will illustrate the difference between the way legal and medical
ethics developed.
In the spring of 1974, I was a young assistant professor of philosophy
in a department that had one of the earliest courses in medical ethics. One
day my departmental chair called me into his office and asked what I knew
about legal ethics. “Nothing,” I replied. “No matter,” he said. “You’re
smart. You do ethics and philosophy of law. The rest you can learn.”
He had, he said, received a call from the law school. They needed a
three-credit course in legal ethics by next spring. No one on their faculty
could teach it. They hoped the philosophy department would do for legal
ethics what it had done for medical ethics. He was asking me because the
medical ethics people were too busy and I was the only member of the
department besides himself who knew much about law. The law school
was prepared to pay handsomely. They would give me the fall to teach
myself what I needed to know. All they asked was that the course be
given next spring to the senior class. When I hesitated, he smiled, “I know
what you’re thinking. What can a philosopher tell lawyers about their
own ethics? Don’t worry, lawyers are like doctors: if they’re desperate
enough to ask a philosopher’s help, they need it.” Thus began my initiation
into professional ethics.
I went over to the law school that fall. What I found surprised me.
Lawyers needed much less help than physicians had. The legal literature
was significant (though not philosophically sophisticated).3 Lawyers had
been teaching legal ethics for some time. There were a few good texts.4
Lawyers had specialists in ethics in a way physicians did not. Indeed, the
law school was already planning to hire one of those specialists for the
following year.
Still, lawyers were not so different from physicians. In 1970, the
American Bar Association (ABA) had replaced its model “Canons of
Ethics,” originally adopted in 1908 but much amended since, with a new
“Code of Professional Responsibility.” The Code distinguished between
“canons,” “mandatory rules,” and “ethical considerations.” There was a
good deal of confusion about the distinction. Underlying this confusion
were deeper questions: Was there a difference between legal ethics and
professional responsibility? Was the Code just another statute or
something else? If something else, what? How did the answer to these
6
THE ETHICS BOOM
questions affect the way the Code should be interpreted? How did it
affect what a lawyer should do?
When most people think of Watergate, they think only of lawyers and
politicians. But I think of engineers too. Spiro Agnew resigned as Vice
President of the United States not because of what he had done as Nixon’s
Vice President but because of what he had done while holding office in
Maryland. He had solicited bribes from civil engineers seeking state
contracts. Many had paid. Engineers all over the country were appalled
that so many engineers could be involved in such a flagrant violation of
professional ethics. The scandal contributed to the unease engineers
already felt about the part engineers had had in the then-recent
controversies surrounding the faked testing of Goodrich’s A-7D airbrakes,
the Ford Pinto’s exploding gas tank, and the DC-10’s misdesigned cargo
door. Many were also concerned about what was happening to the
engineers who had warned the public of the danger posed by the Bay
Area Transit Authority’s computer controlled trains.5
In 1975, an anonymous donor offered the Illinois Institute of
Technology (IIT) $500,000 to improve the philosophy department. IIT’s
president, a chemist, convinced the donor to give the money to establish
an “ethics center” to do something about the ethics of engineers, scientists,
architects, and other professionals. The model was to be the Hastings
Center. The following year the organization at which I now work, the
Center for the Study of Ethics in the Professions, was established. Perhaps
only by coincidence, the University of Maryland established its Center
for Ethics and Public Policy in the same year.
IIT’s work in professional ethics followed the pattern of medical ethics,
beginning with engineering. Faculty in philosophy, engineering, and the
social sciences met to discuss engineering ethics, using cases like the
DC-10 cargo door to understand the part engineers had (or could have) in
what were ultimately corporate decisions. Soon the philosophers and
engineers were team-teaching a course. Eventually, the philosophers
taught it alone. Similar courses in architecture ethics and computer ethics
followed.
The boom in business ethics seems to date from this period as well.
Other professions – accounting, nursing, journalism, financial analysis,
public administration, dentistry, and so on – each have their own story.
For example, interest in the ethics of scientific research seems to have
become significant only in the early 1980s. Only in the last few years has
it begun to have the proportions of a boom (as I shall explain in Chapter
7
THE ETHICS BOOM
3). And only in this decade has interest in academic ethics become
noticeable. Any boom is yet to come.
8
THE ETHICS BOOM
9
THE ETHICS BOOM
10
THE ETHICS BOOM
the boom. If Watergate had not happened, there would have been no
boom. We must reject this explanation. As I have described the boom, it
began before Watergate, with medical ethics in the early 1960s. Medical
ethics cannot be dismissed as “the exception that proves the rule.” There
are at least two reasons: First, we can point to boom-related activity in
other fields before Watergate. For example, the ABA rewrote its code of
ethics (the first time) in the late 1960s. Second, medical ethics by itself is
just too important to be treated as a “mere exception.” Physicians were
the first to draw philosophers into applied ethics. From then on, medical
ethics has been the model for most other fields. Today, medical ethics
remains by far the largest field of applied or professional ethics.
While we can’t attribute the ethics boom to Watergate (or to any
other particular scandal), we can none the less see that Watergate and
similar scandals have had a part in generating the boom. Perhaps, then,
we should attribute the boom to a pervasive climate of scandal. Perhaps
our society is especially corrupt and so especially in need of ethics.
Though this explanation has a certain appeal, we should, I think, put
it aside. Like the previous explanation, this one does not fit medical ethics.
Though medicine has had its scandals (for example, overcharging
Medicaid), these do not seem to have had much to do with how medical
ethics has developed. Technology, not scandal, seems to direct that field.
The pervasive climate of scandal has another disadvantage as
explanation. Explaining the ethics boom by such a climate would require
claiming that our time is worse ethically than the times preceding in which
there was no boom. We would be in danger of joining the “noisy
authorities” Dickens rebuked. We could avoid that rebuke only by
presenting good evidence that our time is indeed worse ethically than its
predecessors. What evidence do we have of that? The answer seems to
be, none.
Counting scandals may seem a promising way to show that our time is
particularly corrupt. The result is likely to be disappointing. Few years are
without a major scandal. The number does not seem to change much from
decade to decade (perhaps because news media must limit the number of
scandals they report). That, anyway, is the impression I derived from a
morning’s unscientific browsing through old newspapers. Perhaps the
more refined methods of a sociologist or historian could produce more
interesting results. But, for now, counting scandals does not seem likely
to prove that our age is worse than others.
11
THE ETHICS BOOM
12
THE ETHICS BOOM
13
THE ETHICS BOOM
14
THE ETHICS BOOM
15
THE ETHICS BOOM
New York, by far the largest U.S. city, had just under 700,000.35 By 1900,
three U.S. cities had a population over one million,36 and nearly 40 percent
of Americans lived in a town of 2,500 or more.37 Today, we no longer think
in terms of cities but “metropolitan areas,” vast concentrations of people
in which municipal boundaries have become mere technicalities. More
than half of all Americans now live in a metropolitan area of more than a
million.38 Very few live in a town under 2,500. The United States long ago
became an urban society.
In a town of 2,500, everyone knows everyone else’s business. Gossip
is enough to maintain order among inhabitants and allow them to work
together effectively. In a large city, no one knows more than a few others.
Order cannot be maintained by conscience, family, church, and
neighborhood alone. Cities must work through such formal organizations
as police, zoning commissions, charities, unions, and large corporations.
Like these other organizations, professions are primarily urban creatures.
The period between 1850 and today has also been a period in which
religion became less important in public life (even as Americans seem to
have become more attached to religious symbols like the slogan “In God
We Trust”). Perhaps part of what explains this decline is a corresponding
decline in the religious commitment of individuals. But more important, I
think, is that religion itself can no longer provide a common vocabulary
for evaluation of conduct.
In 1850, the United States could accurately be described as a
“Protestant nation.” Unitarians, Jews, and even Catholics were quite
marginal. Differences between Episcopal, Presbyterian, Methodist,
Baptist, and the like were relatively small. As Protestants, all were united
by a tradition emphasizing the divinity of Jesus, the authority of individual
conscience, and hostility to the claims of Catholicism. But by 1900, one
would have had to say “Christian nation” to include the many Catholics
already important in public life. The common ground between Protestants
and Catholics is much narrower than that between Protestants.
By 1950, the common ground had become even narrower. Americans
were then talking about a common “Judeo-Christian” tradition. Today, it
is hard to find a term inclusive enough for the religious diversity of American
society. The substantial number of Muslims among us can perhaps be
included by appeal to the “Abrahamic tradition.” Islam belongs to the
same family of desert religions as Judaism and Christianity. All three share
a belief in one god and certain very general moral teachings historically
16
THE ETHICS BOOM
connected with that belief. The same cannot be said of Hinduism and
Buddhism. Hinduism has many gods; Buddhism, none. These religions
challenge the very foundation of the Abrahamic tradition. Yet, American
cities now include significant numbers of Hindus and Buddhists – as well
as many people who have no religion at all.
Without a common religious tradition, we cannot depend on religion
to provide common standards of conduct. The major religions of the
world do, of course, agree on some general standards. All, for example,
condemn murder, perjury, and theft. This agreement is, however, too general
to decide most disputes. And it is not itself a common standard. The
agreement is contingent and must be discovered case by case. If the
resolution of a particular case is disputed, the different religions provide
different, and perhaps conflicting, procedures for settling the dispute (for
example, appeal to different holy books). Particular cases will have to be
discussed in terms more or less independent of religion (though, in general
at least, in a way consistent with what the various religions teach). So, in
a society like ours, religious vocabulary is inherently divisive.
If we cannot depend on a common religious tradition for common
standards of conduct, what can we depend on? For most of this century
at least, I think the dominant answer was: law. By “law,” I mean centralized
decision making, especially decision by government, a command backed
by force rather than an appeal to faith or reason. Whether the great contest
of the twentieth century was between communism, fascism, and
democracy, or between dictatorship and freedom, it was largely a contest
for control of centralized power. For most of the twentieth century, the
law’s ability to regulate most conduct was not in dispute. Centralized
decision seemed to provide the common standard society needed. So, for
example, the New Deal was so successful an experiment in central planning
that it was still offered as a model well into the 1970s.
Yet, today, we doubt the law’s ability to govern well very much of life.
We try to decentralize decisions we once tried to centralize. We substitute
“the market” for central planning. We “deregulate,” “privatize,” and
“contract out.”
Though this tendency is more obvious in government, it is not limited
to government. The last two decades have also seen something similar in
private business. Large corporations have been contracting out many
services formerly performed “in house.” They have decentralized much
17
THE ETHICS BOOM
18
THE ETHICS BOOM
use, safety, food, and drugs – also owe their existence in part at least to
market failure. Markets do not automatically exclude force and fraud.
They have difficulty protecting economic interests that lack sufficient
cash, non-economic interests generally, and any interest of third-parties.
Markets work well only within an environment of restraint protecting the
less well informed, the relatively powerless, and third parties. For most of
this century, the law provided most of that restraint. The problem now is
finding alternatives to law.
Ethics is such an alternative. The ethics boom consists of a variety of
institutions likely to generate common standards by a highly decentralized
process. Ethics centers, ethics journals, ethics courses, and ethics training
provide ways to think through particular problems and develop particular
standards of conduct resolving them. The same institutions provide a
way of helping “society” adopt the proposed standards without central
decision. The very discussions by which a particular profession,
corporation, or other social group comes to agree on a standard of conduct
is a means of turning the standard into a social practice. So, for example,
insofar as discussing pollution helps me to see that we will all be better off
if we all stop polluting, I will be less inclined to pollute than before. And
insofar as I see others showing the necessary restraint, I will tend to do
the same.
Philosophers have been important in the ethics boom because they
have traditionally specialized in arguments that appeal to rational persons
as such rather than, like ministers, in arguments that appeal to those who
share a common religious tradition or, like government officials, in other
means of getting people to do as they should. Philosophers represent an
organizing power relatively neglected until recently, the power of secular
reason.
Ethics doubtless has disadvantages as a means of social organization
(most of which won’t be clear until we have had more experience with it).
For our purposes, however, what is important is the way ethics, whatever
its disadvantages, avoids the disadvantages of law. Ethical standards are
not, like law, imposed. They must be worked out by those to whom they
are to apply. They must appeal to the reason of those to whom they apply,
usually by benefiting them or those they care about. Responsibility for
obtaining obedience does not, as in law, fall primarily upon functionaries
but instead upon the individuals directly concerned. The conscience of
each individual is the primary source of control. Supporting conscience
are all those informal pressures basically honest people can bring to bear
19
THE ETHICS BOOM
on one another when they share a common enterprise. Since all those
subject to an ethical standard necessarily have an interest in maintaining
it (even when they also have an interest in getting around it themselves),
there is little need for the complex machinery of central control.39
20
THE ETHICS BOOM
But, unlike ethics in the second traditional sense, it is not merely the
study of how ordinary morality resolves such issues or even the study of
how particular moral theories (the ethics of particular philosophers or
schools) resolve them. Applied ethics actually tries to work out special
standards even when ordinary morality or moral theory leaves an issue
unresolved. That is obvious for professional ethics, since professional
ethics typically consists of special standards embodied in a formal code.
But it is true as well for the evolving standards governing an ordinary
social issue like abortion or pollution. Such issues are not necessarily
settled by ordinary morality or moral theory. They may yield only to
agreement on a new standard.
We need to recognize this fourth sense of “ethics” quite explicitly,
since the very terms we use to describe the ethics boom require it.41 Since
this fourth sense of “ethics” is at most two centuries old, and not widely
used until this century, even the terms characteristic of the ethics boom
testify to its relative novelty.42 The ethics boom seems to be a new response
to new circumstances. We must now consider in more detail the university’s
place in that response.
21
2
ACADEMIC FREEDOM,
ACADEMIC ETHICS, AND
PROFESSORIAL ETHICS
22
ACADEMIC FREEDOM AND ETHICS
Case Two. Professor B turns to the lone black student in class and says,
“We have a nigger student here.” Professor B does this to help students
understand the power of racist language to harm even when no harm is
intended. Though this purpose is appropriate to the course (Business
Ethics), the black student takes offense and later demands that Professor
B be disciplined. “I couldn’t move,” she recalls, “I wanted to run but was
afraid I didn’t have the strength to make it to the door.”2
These cases differ in some ways. For example, in the first, the objection is
to what the professor thinks, as indicated by his participation in debate
outside the institution; in the second, to what he did in class, not at all to
what he thinks. Yet, what concerns me here is something these cases
share.
One feature they share is the newsworthiness of their subject, racial
harassment. Racial harassment on campus (even more than sexual
harassment) makes news today. I don’t know whether that is because
such harassment is increasing, because the victims no longer fear to
speak up, because our conception of what counts as harassment has
changed, or because of some combination of these or other factors. But,
for my purpose, it does not matter. Nothing I say will require that these
cases concern racial harassment or any particular explanation of the current
newsworthiness of that subject. All I require is that these two cases be
hard to resolve to everyone’s satisfaction; indeed, and more to the point,
that they be hard to resolve to anyone’s satisfaction. If they are hard to
resolve, they are so because they pull us in opposite directions.
We can, for example, readily understand why Professor A’s department
relieved him of responsibility for required courses. We may even judge
that action as, all things considered, worthy of Solomon. And we – or, at
least, those of us who have ourselves faced prejudice – can also
understand why black students would feel uncomfortable sitting in
Professor A’s class knowing what he thinks of their race. (“How can he
treat us fairly?”) Yet, the professor in many of us is also likely to think that
both the department and the black students may have lost more than they
gained. The skills black students could develop confronting Professor A
would almost certainly prove useful later; and Professor A might learn
something too. From this perspective, it is unfortunate that Professor A
does not discuss his views on race in class.
Something similar is true of our second case. Professor B probably
could not have made his point as effectively had he used a word less
23
ACADEMIC FREEDOM AND ETHICS
charged with history. His purpose was the wholly proper one of bringing
home a significant fact. He seems to have succeeded. His student’s pain
provides a measure of his success in that. So, from this perspective, he
seems to have been doing exactly what a professor should do. And, yet
we can also understand the altogether human reaction of the black student.
By some standard we all recognize, Professor B seems to have gone too
far. Discipline may not be the right response to what Professor B did, but
praise of Professor B’s technique, or even indifference, does not seem
right either.
That is enough about our cases for now. We can, I hope, agree that
they are hard cases. But hard cases of what? They might, for example, be
hard cases all things considered. That would do us no good. They must
be hard cases for academic ethics, for that is now our subject. Are they
hard cases of that? That depends on what we mean by “academic ethics.”
What do we mean? The answer is not self-evident. The term seems to
have gained currency only recently. Like any new coinage, it is likely to
cause confusion even if its value is clearly stamped upon its face. So, to
avoid confusion, let me explain what I mean by “academic ethics.”
24
ACADEMIC FREEDOM AND ETHICS
25
ACADEMIC FREEDOM AND ETHICS
26
ACADEMIC FREEDOM AND ETHICS
(public service, for example). Each serves such an ideal insofar as what it
aims at (and achieves) is more than what morality, law, and market require.
The ideal is moral insofar as those to be served are not the members of the
profession itself. An organization that does not aim at a moral ideal is (by
definition) a business, trade association, social club, or other organization
of self-interest, not a profession, however much good it in fact does.
So, for example, lawyers form a profession. They claim to aim at justice
for all under law, are organized more or less accordingly, and seem to have
had some success. They have done more than morality, law, and market
require. The market merely requires them to take enough paying clients to
make a living. The law requires only that they provide legal help under
certain special circumstance (that is, when a judge orders it). Morality
requires only that, in addition, they sell legal help the way an honest
grocer sells cheese; it does not require lawyers to organize to serve legal
justice.
Few lawyers are public servants, that is, government employees. Most
serve private clients under arrangements privately made. Yet, insofar as
what each lawyer does satisfies a common standard designed to contribute
to justice for all under law (beyond what morality, law, and market require),
each has part in a public service. Each contributes a share to achieving a
moral ideal.3
Though each profession is defined (in part) by the moral ideal it serves,
professions as such are defined (in part) as a way to make a living. A
profession is an occupation, not a hobby. Though professionals should
love their work, there can be no profession of amateurs. An organization
that does not serve a moral ideal in a way calculated to earn its members
a living is not a profession but a charity, government, or other organization
of public service. So, students, however public spirited, cannot form a
profession. They must first become practitioners of a paying art.
We already had one reason to distinguish academic ethics from
professional ethics – the academy is an institution and institutions are
not professions. That reason may have seemed so slight as to be
Pickwickian. We now have two more substantial reasons. First, a profession
is an organization of professionals. So, insofar as students are more than
honorary members, any organization of academics including students
cannot be a profession. Second, an organization cannot be a profession
unless its chief purpose is to benefit nonmembers. While the purpose of
the academy remains to be worked out, this much seems safe: Whatever
else we think it should be, the academy must be an educational institution.
27
ACADEMIC FREEDOM AND ETHICS
28
ACADEMIC FREEDOM AND ETHICS
they serve that good in the best way possible. While recognizing that
their standards are open to widely different readings, members of a
profession should suppose that there is (generally) a best reading and
that the profession itself determines which that is. “Lay people” may
participate in the discussions, but their participation, however valuable,
is contingent and merely advisory.
Lawyers form an interpretative community. They have, for example,
long debated among themselves whether the ideal they aim at, “justice
under law for all,” is mere legal justice (what the law happens to give) or
justice more broadly understood (what the law should give).
Professions are, however, more than interpretative communities – they
are legislative communities. Not only can they reinterpret their standard
of conduct; they can also rewrite it. Even their ultimate purpose, the moral
ideal they aim at, is subject to change. For example, physicians now seem
to be giving up the preservation of life as an end for their profession for
some combination of protecting the healthy from disease, curing the sick,
and comforting the dying.
I say “seem” only because some doctors claim this is “really” what
they meant all along, only now technology has forced them to be more
explicit. Perhaps they are right. The distinction between reinterpreting a
standard and rewriting it is sometimes hard to draw in practice.
Nonetheless, it is a distinction worth keeping in mind. Most interpretative
communities, including professions, are free to break with the past by
legislation should interpretation lead to an impasse.
Those professions that are interpretative communities develop an
ethics literature (or, at least, an ethics lore), that is to say, a body of
interpretations together with supporting reasons and alternatives rejected.
Many professions, especially law and medicine, now have such a literature;
the professorate does not. Why? Have we just been too busy doing
professional ethics for others? Or is there something about our profession
discouraging discussion of its ethics? Does a rich literature require a
crisis in the profession which, happily, the professorate has not yet
suffered?5 These are questions I hope historians and social scientists will
investigate. The few hypotheses I shall offer below I offer only as a way
of trying to understand academic ethics.
Most of what I have said about professional ethics would be true of
institutional ethics as well. Like professions, institutions can be organized
to provide a public service, can adopt special standards of conduct, and
29
ACADEMIC FREEDOM AND ETHICS
30
ACADEMIC FREEDOM AND ETHICS
31
ACADEMIC FREEDOM AND ETHICS
32
ACADEMIC FREEDOM AND ETHICS
33
ACADEMIC FREEDOM AND ETHICS
34
ACADEMIC FREEDOM AND ETHICS
35
ACADEMIC FREEDOM AND ETHICS
36
ACADEMIC FREEDOM AND ETHICS
conduct. So, all else equal, each should respect the academic freedom of
every other academic because each voluntarily benefits from the others
doing the same. Academic freedom does imply something like ethical
standards. But there is more to academic ethics than that. What? We must
return to the two cases with which we begin.
37
ACADEMIC FREEDOM AND ETHICS
While the policy seems not to have contemplated the problem posed
by Professor A, it explicitly protects Professor B. His words were, it seems,
germane enough to meet any reasonable standard of reasonableness.
This resolution of the two cases protects academic freedom, but at
some cost. The principles invoked are silent concerning ordinary morality,
the non-academic interests of students, and any interest academics may
hold in common except using, extending, and transmitting knowledge. In
38
ACADEMIC FREEDOM AND ETHICS
this respect, the principles seem open to the taunt Shaw directed at
vivisectionists in The Doctor’s Dilemma:
39
ACADEMIC FREEDOM AND ETHICS
40
ACADEMIC FREEDOM AND ETHICS
what they were doing testifies to the need for academic ethics as a distinct
way to talk about such matters.
What then of our two wild professors? To those expecting a final
answer here, I offer two reasons for not providing the desired “closure.”
First, I do not yet have an answer I want to defend. Second, and more
important, even if I did, giving it here would suggest the opposite of what
I want to suggest. The purpose of this book is to begin a discussion that
should take many years, much careful thought, and more honesty about
what we do than I find in the literature so far. The demand for a resolution
of the hard cases now amounts to a refusal to admit the need for that long
discussion. Those who think that they can do without it are, of course,
free to try. Indeed, I urge them to try. They will, I hope, learn much from the
silence or confusion that ensues.
41
Part II
RESEARCH ETHICS
3
THE NEW WORLD OF
RESEARCH ETHICS: A
P R E L I M I N A RY M A P
45
THE NEW WORLD OF RESEARCH ETHICS
46
THE NEW WORLD OF RESEARCH ETHICS
47
THE NEW WORLD OF RESEARCH ETHICS
48
THE NEW WORLD OF RESEARCH ETHICS
49
THE NEW WORLD OF RESEARCH ETHICS
had till then worried privately about what they saw around them. Betrayers
also created a common vocabulary for scientists, scholars, and government
officials interested in the problems Betrayers identified. Suddenly there
was a field defined by the topics Betrayers discussed.
This way of defining the field was not without disadvantages. Betrayers
was in fact almost entirely about empirical research in physics, biology,
and medicine. While it managed to touch on a great many other issues, its
focus was fraud. Early response to Betrayers was largely concerned with
“fraud in science,” so-called. Very soon, however, we find somewhat
more general terms as well, especially “misconduct in research” and
“cheating in science.” The positive terms “research ethics” and “ethics
of scientific research” seem only now to be catching on.13
We may identify six topics central to research ethics, all related to
fraud and all discussed extensively in Betrayers:
50
THE NEW WORLD OF RESEARCH ETHICS
51
THE NEW WORLD OF RESEARCH ETHICS
52
THE NEW WORLD OF RESEARCH ETHICS
53
THE NEW WORLD OF RESEARCH ETHICS
the impression back then that there was too much misconduct in research.
While admitting the evidence does not now rule out that possibility, I find
two other explanations much more plausible, especially since they are
consistent with each other. One is that the rate of research misconduct
actually has increased recently; the other is that science today can no
longer tolerate even the traditional rate of misconduct. What might be
said in support of these two explanations for the new interest in research
ethics?
Reasons for thinking that the rate of research misconduct might
actually have increased include:
54
THE NEW WORLD OF RESEARCH ETHICS
You will have noticed a close relation between these reasons for
thinking misconduct more common or less tolerable than in the past and
the list of topics under discussion in research ethics. I assume the reason
for that close relation is obvious. One question for the new field of research
ethics is whether we really have a problem of research misconduct or only
the impression of one. Another is: if we have a problem, what is its extent
and cause?
55
THE NEW WORLD OF RESEARCH ETHICS
should only add that the federal government, especially the NSF, has
been actively encouraging study. There have been both individual research
projects (for example, one to determine how research ethics is now being
taught in graduate school) and research conferences. There have even
been conferences bringing together those studying research ethics with
those holding the levers of power in science. One of these conferences
recommended changes in the way scientific journals review submissions.17
By regulation, I mean adopting standards explicitly defining
misconduct in research. The agency adopting the standard may be a
professional society, a research institution, or a government. Some of the
sciences had such standards well before 1982. For example, the American
Psychological Association adopted a comprehensive code of ethics in
1973 (a major revision of its 1963 code). A substantial part deals with
research ethics. In contrast, the American Physical Society only adopted
a code of ethics in 1991. The problem today does not seem to be an
absence of such standards so much as a failure to make those standards
an explicit part of the research environment.18
By punishment, I mean setting up procedures enforcing the standards
of research ethics, whatever the particular penalties might be and whatever
the agency administering them. Rep. Conyers provided one example of
what might be done, enforcement by the ordinary machinery of the criminal
law. Several academic organizations recently provided a more interesting
one, enforcement within research organizations themselves. The example,
though titled “A Framework for Institutional Policies and Procedures to
Deal with Fraud in Research,” in fact deals with a wide range of research
misconduct, including even “serious scientific error.”19
The “Framework” recommends procedures for soliciting, examining,
and settling complaints, provides a list of appropriate responses, and
only omits to provide guidance on how to proportion punishment to
misconduct. The omission is unfortunate, though understandable. What
university disciplinary procedures most need today is, I think, some
standards for judging the seriousness of various forms of misconduct
and a corresponding scale of penalties. For example, plagiarism, whether
deliberate or accidental, is “unacceptable conduct” within a university.
Yet, deliberately plagiarizing someone else’s research seems much more
serious than deliberately plagiarizing a few paragraphs from someone
else’s survey of the literature. Universities (wisely, I think) do not fine for
breaches of academic ethics. They cannot imprison. They are therefore
left with few options between “censure” (which outsiders are likely to
56
THE NEW WORLD OF RESEARCH ETHICS
regard as a wrist slap) and discharge (which seems too severe for all but
the most serious wrongdoing). Research institutions need to experiment
with such intermediate penalties as reduction-in-rank, revocation-of-
tenure, and suspension-of-research-for-a-term-of-years.20 Here, perhaps,
research ethics might benefit from contact with recent work in theory of
punishment.21
By education, I mean just what you think, changes in the way future
researchers are taught. Until recently very little was said about the ethics
of research in most graduate programs. Graduate students either caught
on from a few anecdotes professors or other students told or from an
occasional reprimand received, overheard, or rumored. Formal instruction
in research ethics was virtually unknown. In this respect, graduate
education in the sciences is at least a decade behind professional
education in law and medicine. But change seems to have begun. Some
researchers, including the man who uncovered and reported Bruening’s
misconduct, Robert Sprague, now teach a course in research ethics, while
others have begun to deal explicitly with research ethics in ordinary
undergraduate or graduate courses.22 (Chapters 7–8 provide some
examples of what can be done.)
That brings me to the last practical response, changing the environment
in which researchers actually work. Some of the other responses may
change the environment as well. For example, explicitly defining research
misconduct can make researchers more likely to notice misconduct and
report it. Teaching research ethics can have the same effect. Insofar as
researchers think about research ethics more often, and talk about it more
openly, the working environment of researchers will discourage
misconduct in a way it would not otherwise.23
But certainly more can be done. Whether it should be done is harder
to say. We could, for example, try to reduce the pressure on researchers
by reducing the importance of sheer quantity of publications in decisions
to tenure, say, by allowing only five publications to be submitted in support
of a tenure recommendation.24 But would limiting the effect of sheer quantity
in this way actually reduce overall pressure on young researchers or
simply make them more dependent on the senior researchers whose letters
of support will have to explain the importance of those few publications?
The last question may suggest that the response to research
misconduct is already well ahead of our knowledge. While true, it is, I
think, less so than it seems. After all, we have experience outside science
57
THE NEW WORLD OF RESEARCH ETHICS
58
4
SCIENCE: AFTER SUCH
K N O W L E D G E , W H AT
RESPONSIBILITY?
The problem
This chapter began as a contribution to a conference, “Knowledge and
Responsibility: The Moral Role of Scientists.” The conference’s sponsors,
the Midwest Consortium for International Security Studies and the
American Academy of Arts and Sciences, seemed to assume that
something in the nature of scientists, their knowledge, imposes special
moral responsibilities on them, whatever they may do, say, or wish. The
assumption is, however, not limited to the organizers of that conference.
For example, two researchers, one at the University of Texas at Houston
and the other at the Uniformed Services University of the Health Sciences
in Bethesda, Maryland, declared in a joint paper on “The Social
Responsibilities of Biological Scientists”:
59
S C I E N T I S T S : W H AT R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y ?
60
S C I E N T I S T S : W H AT R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y ?
A case to consider
61
S C I E N T I S T S : W H AT R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y ?
62
S C I E N T I S T S : W H AT R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y ?
as each person (at their rational best) has a veto. Nothing can be morality
unless each person wants it to be. Morality, so defined, is, however, also
objective (or, at least, inter-subjective). Nothing can be morality unless
every person (at their rational best) wants it. Morality, though personal to
each, is a common possession of all.
The twin tests of unanimity and rationality together provide a standard
of practical justification. The test of unanimity assures that morality will
be something that those subject to the standards will take an interest in.
The test of rationality (that each – at their rational best – wants the
standards) makes morality a rational undertaking as well. Morality must
be both desired and desirable.
Morality, though justified, may still be either actual or ideal. Actual
morality consists of those justified standards actually in place in our
society; ideal morality, of those standards we endorse when we ignore
the costs of changing current practice. Actual morality is, in part, a product
of historical accident in a way ideal morality is not. Nonetheless, actual
morality binds us while ideal morality merely offers terms of exhortation,
grounds for criticism of existing moral rules (however justified now), and
so a basis for planning the future.
Whether actual or ideal, there are at least three kinds of moral standard:
rules, principles, and ideals.
A rule requires (or forbids) a course of action. “Don’t kill” and “Keep
your promises” are moral rules. Rules have exceptions. For example, “self-
defense” is an exception to “Don’t kill.” To fail to do what a rule requires
(or to do what a rule forbids) is wrong, unless justified under some
exception. Rules lay down relatively rigid standards of conduct. Even
when justified, doing what a rule forbids may leave behind liability to
make good the harm one caused.
Principles, in contrast, do not concern conduct directly. They merely
require certain considerations to have a certain weight in deliberations.6
They state reasons. For example, “Help the needy” does not require us to
give charity whenever we can but to give the needs of the needy significant
weight when we are making allocations. Principles are primarily standards
of deliberation.7
Moral ideals do something more complex. Like rules, they are concerned
with conduct; but, like principles, they do not require any particular
conduct. Instead, they present the conduct in question as a state of
affairs good to try for or approach but not bad to ignore or fall short of.
The injunction, “Be a hero,” is commonly thought to state a moral ideal.
63
S C I E N T I S T S : W H AT R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y ?
Moral ideals are morally important insofar as they give others a reason to
help, reward, or at least praise those who try to realize a particular ideal.8
That is enough about morality generally. Where does responsibility
fit in? By “responsibility,” I mean what a rule requires, that is, a duty or
obligation. Why understand “responsibility” in this way? Why not
understand “responsibility” as indicating that a certain (moral) principle
applies or even that some (moral) ideal might be realized?9 The answer is
simple. Such an understanding would not serve our purpose. To say, for
example, that someone has a responsibility to report wrongdoing is, it
seems, to say more than that he ought to give such-and-such weight to
reporting (as a principle would) or that it would be good for him to report
(as an ideal would). Rather, to say that someone has a responsibility to
report wrongdoing is, all else equal, to say that not reporting would be
wrong.10
To point out a responsibility is, of course, not to require a course of
action come what may. We are not always justified in fulfilling a
responsibility. Rules can have exceptions; and, even when no exceptions
apply, there may still be sufficient reason to excuse us from doing what
the rule requires (though the excuse will generally leave behind liability
for costs imposed on others). In this respect, too, responsibilities do not
seem to differ from obligations, duties, or requirements. This should come
as no surprise. Except for “requirement,” all of these terms have similar
etymologies, arising from debts (things owed, due, and for which one
must answer).
Talking in terms of obligation, duty, or requirement none the less
seems clearer than talking in terms of responsibility. Why, then, are
discussions of what scientists ought to do generally cast in terms of
responsibility? I can think of only one reason, one of no importance here.
“Obligation” has a legal connotation (“the obligations of contract”);
“duty,” a military connotation (“my station and its duties”); and
“requirement,” a harsh suggestion of command (as its origin fully justifies).
“Responsibility” is, in contrast, a civil and civilian word, connected less
with bargains than with roles and rights, words of discretion and judgment,
while “responsibility” says no less than “duty,” “obligation,” or
“requirement,” it says it more gently.
What then makes a moral responsibility “special”? Let’s say that a
responsibility is special if, and only if, it derives (at least in part) from a
rule obliging some people but not all. A moral responsibility, then, is
special if it binds only some moral agents.
Is there a paradox here? How can a standard of conduct be both moral
64
S C I E N T I S T S : W H AT R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y ?
(one everyone wants everyone else to follow) and special (oblige only
some)? Consider the obligation to keep a specific promise (for example, to
meet my class tomorrow). “Keep your promise” is (we may assume) a
moral rule, that is, a rule everyone wants everyone else bound by even if
that means being bound by it oneself. Hence, the obligation derived from
it, the obligation to keep this promise, is moral too. Yet, this promise is not
a standard of conduct binding everyone, only a standard binding those
who make the promise. The obligation to keep this promise, though moral,
is special.
A special moral responsibility is, then, simply the consequence of a
rule which, though applying only to some, derives it moral force from a
rule applying to all. A special moral responsibility is a special case of a
general moral responsibility. Convention, while the obvious way to create
special responsibilities, may not be the only way. For example, the
responsibility of parents to care for their own children, though a natural
duty (if any is), seems both moral and special.11
So, an adequate answer to the question with which we began would
offer an argument establishing: (a) that “I” (the physicist) have a moral
duty (or obligation); (b) that all other scientists share that duty (or
obligation); and (c) that the duty (or obligation) applies to them because
they are scientists (rather than, say, because they are employees, citizens,
or neighbors). Are there any such arguments? Let’s see.
65
S C I E N T I S T S : W H AT R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y ?
Such a requirement, though still controversial, falls well short of what the
original Good Samaritan did.
Nonetheless, what even the original Good Samaritan did falls well
short of what we want to ask of me. On the one hand, the immediate harm
“I” would prevent is relatively minor, misleading a Senate committee
concerning possible space-based defenses. The more substantial harms
– for example, waste of billions of dollars on research and development –
are not imminent. They cannot begin for at least a year, that is, after the
project is funded, contracts given, and work begun. They are also not
certain. The project may be rejected for reasons – such as cost or diplomacy
– having little to do with what BIN says.
On the other hand, “my” burden will be great whatever good I do. I
will breach two significant obligations, the obligation of confidentiality
every employee owes an employer and the special obligation imposed by
classified research. I will risk my research classification, my job, and my
ability to find other employment in my field. And, like most whistleblowers,
I will probably lose many friends, become entangled in litigation, and
66
S C I E N T I S T S : W H AT R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y ?
otherwise darken my prospects for a long time.13 Even many who accept
some version of the Good Samaritan argument should find counter-intuitive
a version strong enough to apply here.
To say this is, of course, not to say that we would not prefer to live in
a world where people took more of an interest in the public welfare than
we do here. It is, rather, to admit that at least some of us (even at our
rational best) are probably unwilling to accept the burdens necessarily
accompanying a rule requiring us to be Good Samaritans. Requirements
have costs as well as benefits. The problem with a Good Samaritan rule is
the cost, not the benefit.
That, however, is not the weakness of the Good Samaritan argument
most relevant here. We are looking for an argument establishing a special
responsibility of scientists as such. No ordinary Good Samaritan argument
can do that. A Good Samaritan argument would apply to anyone who
came to know what I know. Even a secretary typing my memo would have
precisely the same responsibility for precisely the same reason. Being a
scientist is, at best, contingently related to the information a particular
scientist has. So, the responsibility in question would not be a
responsibility of scientists as such – except in the Pickwickian sense that
it happens to be my responsibility and (we are supposing) I happen to be
a scientist.
67
S C I E N T I S T S : W H AT R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y ?
supposed will, I think, make clear how unattractive the argument is (if it is
to cover a case like mine). The rule of status must, I think, look like this:
Go out of your way to help change public policy when: (a) you
have a special competence with respect to the policy in question;
(b) that competence gives you special authority or credibility (a
special ability to guide deliberation on the policy); and (c) that
competence also reveals to you a significant threat to the public
health, safety, or welfare.15
68
S C I E N T I S T S : W H AT R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y ?
69
S C I E N T I S T S : W H AT R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y ?
70
S C I E N T I S T S : W H AT R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y ?
71
S C I E N T I S T S : W H AT R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y ?
This rule offers a basis for (what we might call) an argument from
individual complicity. The rule would require me to reveal what I know if,
for example, BIN used data I developed to support its proposal. There
would, however, be no corresponding responsibility if, as we are assuming,
BIN simply ignored my data.
That is one objection to the rule of individual complicity. There is
another. The rule makes only the most tenuous connection between my
status as a scientist and my responsibility to reveal what I learned. My
responsibility derives not from the fact that the information in question is
scientific (though it is), or from the fact that a scientist is involved (though
at least one is), but from the fact that the information in question, scientific
or not, is mine and I have (unjustifiably) put someone in need of it.
There is, however, a version of the argument from individual complicity
that may seem to get around this objection. Each of us, it might be said,
has a moral obligation to avoid being the source of misinformation when
72
S C I E N T I S T S : W H AT R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y ?
we can. When someone speaks “as a scientist” and all other scientists
remain silent, the public may justifiably conclude that they speak for all
scientists (that is, expresses the scientific community’s consensus). If
there is in fact disagreement among scientists, the silence of each scientist
would contribute to public misinformation. Each scientist, by her silence,
would have become a source of misinformation when, by speaking up,
she could avoid doing so. Hence, each scientist as such would have a
moral obligation to break the silence (though the act of one or a few would
free the rest from any need to act).24
The appeal of this argument, though admittedly great, depends on
two doubtful assumptions.
One doubtful assumption is that not speaking up makes one a source
of misinformation – in other words, that not informing is, under the
circumstances, misinforming. The assumption seems to turn a relatively
uncontroversial moral rule (“Don’t deceive”) into a much more
controversial rule of epistemic Good Samaritanism (“Prevent deception”).
It would then be open to many of the objections already made against
Good Samaritan arguments.
The other doubtful assumption upon which this version of the
argument from complicity rests is that, in a case like mine, the problem is
that one side will have scientists to speak for it while the other side will
not. That is generally not the problem. Generally, both sides will have
scientists to speak for them. The problem is, rather, that unless I speak,
the public (probably) will not learn all that science has to teach about the
effectiveness of computer-assisted radar in a “star wars” defense. What
will mislead the public is not misinformation but missing information.25
Arguments from individual complicity, whatever their merit, thus seem
ill-suited to our purpose, defining the special moral responsibility of
scientists. That responsibility is collective, not individual (though special
responsibilities eventually do fall on individuals). We might, then, want
to consider a rule of collective complicity:
Go out of your way to help change public policy when: (a) you
have a special competence with respect to the policy in question;
(b) that competence gives you special authority or credibility (a
special ability to guide deliberations on the policy); (c) that
competence also reveals to you a significant threat to the public
health, safety, or welfare (relevant to the policy); and (d) you are
a voluntary member of the very community of competence that
helped to create the threat.
73
S C I E N T I S T S : W H AT R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y ?
This rule is, of course, a close relative of the Good Samaritan rule
offered as the basis for one version of the argument from status. The chief
difference is the final clause. No one is subject to this rule unless, first,
she voluntarily becomes a member of a certain community of competence
(by learning the appropriate skills) and, second, that community of
competence helps to create a threat (for example, by teaching skills to
people who then misuse them). Those who do not want to remain in the
community can let their competence atrophy. (Their membership is, in this
respect, voluntary.) Those who want to remain must either accept
responsibility for helping to clean up when their colleagues mess up or
take precautions to assure that their colleagues do not mess up.
The rule of collective complicity imposes collective responsibility on
even unorganized groups. In this respect, it departs from the common-law
theory of tort on which I modeled it. The common law imposes collective
responsibility only where there is a “corporation,” “partnership,” or
“company,” that is, an organized body claiming to maintain, or at least
capable of maintaining, good order among its members. The rationale for
limiting collective responsibility in this way is straightforward. We do not
want to be held responsible for the conduct of those we neither control
nor purport to control. Whatever advantages might come from being able
to hold others responsible for conduct over which they have no control
does not seem enough to repay us for the burdens we would have to bear
if others could hold us responsible in that way.26
If, however, we confine the rule of collective complicity to
“corporations” (that is, organized groups), it cannot yield the argument
we are looking for. Scientists as such are not organized in the way required.
There are, of course, scientific organizations of various sorts, everything
from umbrella groups like AAAS to various interest groups (the Society
for Imaging Science and Technology, for example). There are also political
organizations of scientists – Scientists Against Star Wars – a form of
organization I shall ignore hereafter. But, I need not, as a scientist, belong
to any of them. And, even if I did, I would not belong to one organized to
maintain good order in my field or even claiming to do so.
Scientific societies are, as such, not organized to maintain good order
in science. Generally, they are technical rather than professional
organizations.27 A technical society is (primarily) concerned with
“technique,” that is, with competence in the field. In scientific (technical)
societies, competence is generally understood as knowledge of the field
74
S C I E N T I S T S : W H AT R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y ?
75
S C I E N T I S T S : W H AT R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y ?
I have tried to identify and refute all interesting arguments for the claim
that scientist as such must have a special moral responsibility. Suppose
that I have succeeded: what are we entitled to conclude? We are not
entitled to conclude that scientists, as a matter of fact, have no special
moral responsibilities because they are scientists. We are, instead, entitled
to conclude only that any special responsibilities they have must depend
on conventions. For some sciences, such conventions exist. These
sciences have, in effect, organized as professions. While the American
Physical Society did recently adopt a code of ethics, its doing so will not
help here.29 Its code of ethics does not cover cases like mine.
Could a science have a code of ethics covering cases like mine? Of
course. Consider what my responsibilities would have been had I been an
engineer: One provision of the engineers’ code declares: “[if] their
judgment is overruled under circumstances where the safety, health,
property, or welfare of the public are endangered, they shall notify their
employer or client and such other authority as may be appropriate.”30
Since the Senate committee seems to be an appropriate authority to notify,
I would, as an engineer, have had a responsibility to notify them (at least
after I had exhausted all reasonable means within my laboratory).
By itself, this first provision does not, however, decide what I, as an
engineer, would be required to do. There may be an exception for
confidential information. After all, another provision of the code says:
“[engineers] shall not disclose confidential information concerning the
business affairs or technical processes of any present or former employer
without his consent.”31 The information I would disclose is at least
arguably confidential because it concerns BIN’s business affairs (and is
“classified”) and BIN has not consented to its release.
Since these two provisions seem to conflict, neither explicitly giving
the other precedence, my responsibility is still not clear. The code requires
interpretation. Sometimes a code gives little or no guidance concerning
how to resolve a conflict like this. The resolution is left to individual
judgment. In this case, however, the code is quite explicit. Engineers are
supposed “[to] hold paramount the safety, health, and welfare of the
public in performance of their professional duties.”32 When the public
health, safety, or welfare conflicts with the interests of an employer or
client, the public interest takes precedence.
76
S C I E N T I S T S : W H AT R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y ?
So, if (as we may assume) giving the Senate committee the information
I developed will assure a better informed decision concerning public
expense, such decisions are part of the public welfare, and the information
can be given to the committee without unduly compromising national
security, then my responsibility, as an engineer, is clear. If I cannot convince
BIN to reveal what I discovered, I have a obligation to reveal it myself. For
an engineer, the public welfare pre-empts an employer’s (or client’s) right
to confidentiality. I-the-engineer have “no choice.”
For me-the-physicist, however, any special responsibility to report
my data to the Senate committee must have another source. And, as I
have argued, there seems to be no other. Unless BIN is going to use my
data, claiming my authority for it, I am not implicated in BIN’s testimony.
Nor am I an ordinary rescuer (or Good Samaritan); I can come to the
public’s aid only by breaching my employer’s trust (and risking substantial
harm to my own interests). Nor can I justify my conduct merely by pointing
to my status as a scientist. I am going beyond what is required of scientists.
Indeed, I am going beyond what is required of employees and citizens
too. I will, then, have to act as an individual, justifying my act in the way
people do when they violate a moral rule for reasons they believe to be
good. In this, “I” am no worse off than I would be if I missed class
because I stopped to rescue a drowning child at great risk to myself.33
Would “I” in particular, or scientists in general, be better off if scientists,
like engineers, had a code of ethics speaking to issues like this? That
depends on what scientists (at their rational best) want. Do they want to
trade individual freedom for corporate responsibility? They may not,
preferring (quite rationally) to leave decisions to individual scientists
without collective guidance; or only to give guidance in the form of
statements of principle or ideal.34
Which they prefer cannot be known until standards of conduct have
been laid before the appropriate bodies, debated, and voted up or down.
I would hope philosophers could contribute to that process not, as I have
done here, by considering what can be squeezed from the nature of
scientists, but by formulating standards scientists might find attractive
and arguments to make clear the attraction.
77
5
UNIVERSITY RESEARCH
A N D T H E WA G E S O F
COMMERCE
78
R E S E A R C H A N D T H E WA G E S O F C O M M E R C E
79
R E S E A R C H A N D T H E WA G E S O F C O M M E R C E
80
R E S E A R C H A N D T H E WA G E S O F C O M M E R C E
the reality behind them. That reality turned out to be much more familiar
than I had surmised from my initial immersion in the debate over university–
business research links. While the AAAS panel did not allow me to report
much of what I had learned, Wayne State’s conference did. I was therefore
grateful when, having heard what I might say, the conference organizers
invited me to be one of Nader’s respondents.
I shall now report what I learned from my inquiries, beginning with
what I learned from people in business and then going on to what I
learned from university researchers. While leaving to social scientists the
job of determining how accurately I have represented university–business
links, I shall conclude by pointing out some lessons to be drawn from
what I report (assuming my report catches an important part of the reality
of relations between university and business).
81
R E S E A R C H A N D T H E WA G E S O F C O M M E R C E
82
R E S E A R C H A N D T H E WA G E S O F C O M M E R C E
83
R E S E A R C H A N D T H E WA G E S O F C O M M E R C E
Something missing? Notably missing from this list of reasons for wanting
closer links with university researchers is access to equipment.
Biotechnology companies may be unusual in this respect. But that was
not a consideration they mentioned. Why not? The explanation does not
seem to be that business research is better funded than university research.
No one with experience of both made such a suggestion. What they did
say suggests the following explanation. A company developing a
particular technology is likely to have many more researchers working in
a small field than is even a large biology department. So, even if the
amount spent on equipment per researcher were the same, the
biotechnology company’s aggregate fund for equipment suitable for a
particular field would be greater. The biotechnology company would be
more likely to have the full range of equipment needed for work in that
small field (while having far less in the way of equipment needed for other
fields, even those closely related but not part of its research plan). As in
other respects, so with equipment, the university tends to be the generalist,
the business, the specialist.
84
R E S E A R C H A N D T H E WA G E S O F C O M M E R C E
85
R E S E A R C H A N D T H E WA G E S O F C O M M E R C E
86
R E S E A R C H A N D T H E WA G E S O F C O M M E R C E
Money? Notably absent from this list of reasons is money, a reason upon
which Nader laid great stress. The researchers I talked to suggested three
reasons why money as such is not important. First, for them, money is
primarily a means of getting equipment and supporting students. Money
is thus implicit in the reasons they did list. Second, they thought that
biotechnology companies generally wanted to link up with the best
biology departments, that is, those whose researchers were also most
likely to win government grants. Links with business did not so much
increase their research support as change its source and, with its source,
the arguments necessary to justify it. Third, and perhaps most surprising,
most biotechnology companies did not seem to have vast pools of money
to dump into new research. Getting money out of a company was at least
as hard as getting it out of the government. Indeed, the major difference
between the two was that getting money out of a company was a much
more personal affair, with memos, phone conversations, and meetings
often taking the place of a formal application.
87
R E S E A R C H A N D T H E WA G E S O F C O M M E R C E
88
R E S E A R C H A N D T H E WA G E S O F C O M M E R C E
89
R E S E A R C H A N D T H E WA G E S O F C O M M E R C E
90
6
OF BABBAGE AND KINGS:
A STUDY OF A
PLAGIARISM COMPLAINT
The discovery
91
OF BAGGAGE AND KINGS
92
OF BAGGAGE AND KINGS
Seeing how excited Berg was about the Proceedings, Galler told him
something of the internal workings of the Annals, including the history of
Van Sinderen’s still unpublished article, and gave it to Berg, suggesting
he see what he could do with it.
Why did Galler do that? Berg offers this explanation (based on what
Galler told him at the time): both reviewers had wanted to delay
recommending publication until sure the original letter could not be found
because, if it could be found, the translation would be unnecessary (and
therefore not worth publishing). Neither reviewer was quick to give up
the search. Meanwhile, Van Sinderen gave Galler a good deal of grief for
the long time it was taking the journal to make a decision. Eventually
Galler forced a decision from the reviewers, leaving both them and him not
quite satisfied. Apparently, Galler saw Berg as an opportunity to put to
rest remaining doubts about publishing Van Sinderen’s paper.
Early in January 1984, Berg “tackled” the paper. He soon realized that
Van Sinderen had missed some holdings of Babbage correspondence.
Using indexes at the University of Michigan, Berg was led from Babbage
to a file of Quetelet’s correspondence in Belgium (in the Archives of the
Royal Academy). Berg wrote for a copy of the file on 22 February. By 26
March 1984, he had before him a photocopy of the missing English version
of the letter, in Babbage’s own hand and dated 27 April 1835.
Complications
Pleased with what he had found, Berg called Galler the next day (while in
Ann Arbor on other business). Berg expected warm congratulations. He
got something else. As Berg remembers their talk, Galler almost
immediately changed the subject to a letter Berg had written to Van
Sinderen in February. It was, Berg recalls, a long letter in which he praised
Van Sinderen’s translation, explained how he came to examine Van
Sinderen’s paper, and told Van Sinderen about some sources he had
discovered. Berg also mentioned the delay in publication, sketched what
he knew, and concluded that Van Sinderen was owed an apology (which,
apparently, Van Sinderen took as an apology).
Galler said Van Sinderen had “laid it in to him” for telling tales out of
class. Why had Berg, of all people, been offering an apology for something
the Annals had done? Galler seemed to view the letter both as a breach of
his confidence and as hurting Berg’s relationship with Van Sinderen. His
tone was severe: Berg had no business offering an apology to Van Sinderen,
93
OF BAGGAGE AND KINGS
and no business repeating what Galler told him about the workings of the
Annals.
Badly shaken by this exchange, Berg tried to repair the damage. As
soon as he had hung up the phone, he sent Galler a copy of the Babbage
letter (through campus mail), hoping that seeing the document might help
Galler regain perspective. Berg then went to the office of the University’s
Vice President for Academic Affairs, looking for an explanation of what he
had done wrong and advice about what to do next. A secretary made an
appointment for him with Robert Holbrook, an economist then serving as
Associate Vice President for Academic Affairs (and a member of the
University’s Joint Task Force on Integrity in Scholarship). The
appointment was for a few days later.
When they met at the appointed time, Holbrook treated Berg cordially,
heard him out, and then declared that Berg’s ignorance should excuse the
breach of editorial confidentiality. And, he added, Berg’s discovery was
in any case significant enough to outweigh such a small sin. Berg left with
the impression that Holbrook might “straighten Galler out.”
Berg also wrote letters of apology to Van Sinderen and to the two
outside reviewers (whom he had referred to by name). Berg’s letter to Van
Sinderen seems to have worked. In a letter dated 25 June 1984 (“cc –
Galler”), Van Sinderen thanked Berg for “your ‘peace offering’,” adding
that it was “not really necessary, as I always have positive thoughts
about people who are interested in Charles Babbage.”
Soon after mailing these letters, Berg dropped by Galler’s office. This
visit went no better than the phone conversation. Galler tried to convince
Berg that the discovery was not important enough to warrant publication
in the Annals, certainly not worth a note, and not even a letter to the
editor to correct the historical record. After all, Galler argued, the letter
differed in only small ways from the translation Van Sinderen had made
from the French. The differences were not important to the later history of
computing.
Berg could not understand Galler’s response. Had Berg not found the
lost “ur-letter” of computing? Had he not shown that it still existed, dated
it, and provided the full text? Until his discovery, who could say how long
the original letter was or how well Quetelet had translated it? Scholars
would hereafter know that Quetelet had omitted three paragraphs at the
beginning and two at the end (and what those paragraphs said). They
94
OF BAGGAGE AND KINGS
95
OF BAGGAGE AND KINGS
14 May 1984). He also wrote anyone active in the field whom he had not
already told, sending each an “unprint” (that is, a copy of the original
Babbage letter, a brief summary of what Berg had done, and a copy of Van
Sinderen’s article).
Much of this must have made Galler unhappy. As Berg recalls their
next meeting (early July), Galler told Berg he had been receiving phone
calls advising him to publish Berg’s discovery as a letter. As Galler recalled
the meeting (letter of 10 August), he told Berg he would continue to help
with Berg’s history activities provided Berg “dropped the extraneous
correspondence dealing with personalities and past events which were
really none of your business.” If Berg did not drop the correspondence,
Galler “would have nothing further to do with you.”
Berg did not do as Galler asked. For example, on 24 July he wrote to
the History of Science Society, sending them a copy of the Babbage letter,
and – by way of explanation – stating:
These letters did not always have the effect Berg intended. For example,
Van Sinderen responded to Berg’s letter of 30 July with a two-and-a-half
page synopsis of their correspondence (“cc – B. Galler”). While he ended
by urging Berg to forget the past, he was clearly upset that Berg should
“write me again, page after page of concerns and speculations about who
did what to whom containing, among other things, unfounded suspicions
that it was [one of the two reviewers], a close friend of mine, who delayed
publication of my article in the Annals.”
On 10 August, after receiving a copy of Van Sinderen’s letter to Berg
96
OF BAGGAGE AND KINGS
(dated 31 July), Galler wrote Berg again: “[You] did not take my advice
[but] continued to participate in the kind of activity which can only be
destructive to your relationships with other historians.” Therefore (with
“great reluctance”), he had to “terminate” his relationship with Berg.
Galler did, however, add that Berg could continue to submit work to the
Annals. Any submissions would be sent out to reviewers in the usual
way: “There will be no bias against you.”
This letter did indeed end their relationship. Doubting Galler would
treat him better than he already had, Berg submitted nothing to him again.
Until Galler retired as editor-in-chief in 1987, Berg’s contact with the Annals
only concerned other matters and these contacts were always with other
editors. Berg’s two-page note on the missing letter did not appear in the
Annals until January 1992.3
Plagiarism?
97
OF BAGGAGE AND KINGS
The note gives no credit to anyone for finding the missing original. It just
says that the letter is in the Royal Library. Van Sinderen receives two
mentions for his translation; Berg receives nothing for finding the original.
Berg first read this note early in December 1989. The more he looked at
it, the more disturbing he found it. There was, first, a shortening of the
title of Van Sinderen’s article. The date, and only the date (“of May, 1835”)
had been omitted from the reference (replaced by the usual mark of elision).
Had the date not been omitted, Berg thought, it would have been obvious
that Van Sinderen did not know of the letter’s actual date (now indicated
in print for the first time). Second, there was that reference to the
“Bibliotheque Royal.” The Royal Library had, Berg believed, transferred
its Quetelet collection to the Royal Academy several decades before. The
scholar who found the letter would not have made that mistake.4
Last, as far as Berg could see, the letter was (except for light editing
and the omission of the first three and last two paragraphs) the one he
had discovered.5 If there was any reason to credit either the French
translation or Van Sinderen’s retranslation, was there not more reason to
credit Berg for finding the original? The original pre-empted all translations.
There was also a good reason to get the Academy’s permission to publish
the letter: scholarly custom. Berg had sought, and received, that
permission, which was granted on condition that the Academy receive
proper credit in print. The Works of Babbage neither credited the Academy
for the letter (though apparently relying on it) nor indicated receiving
anyone’s permission to publish it.
Berg held in his hand what purported to be the definitive edition of
Babbage’s work, opened to the page supposedly containing the text of
the most famous letter in the history of computing. Yet, what that footnote
told readers is that they had before them neither the original letter Berg
had found nor Van Sinderen’s translation of the French version of Quetelet,
but something new, a mix of the two “edited for readability.” The rest of
the original, though available for inclusion, was omitted. What could
explain this?
The explanation could not be that the editors had confined
themselves to previously published work. They did not claim to have
such a policy, and in fact, they had not followed such a policy. (They
had, for example, included what seemed to be a previously unpublished
“Statement to the Duke of Wellington.”) Berg supposed the worst.
98
OF BAGGAGE AND KINGS
Thank you for your letter of 22 May and the information enclosed.
I was particularly interested to read Babbage’s letter to Quetelet,
especially the comment “but it will take many months to work out
all the details.” How true that proved to be!7
Berg could see no point in writing to Bromley. What could he write someone
he believed guilty of plagiarism? What could such a letter accomplish?
So, on 4 January 1990, he wrote to the Australian Academy of Science
(AAS), providing relevant documents and asking for an investigation.
The AAS responded within two weeks: “The matter to which you refer is
exceedingly complex, but this Academy has neither the facilities nor indeed
the ability to investigate the possible misdeeds of scientists working in
this country…” It was a response that would become familiar.
Berg then wrote the chancellor of the University of Sydney, Bromley’s
home institution. He received no response, not even a courtesy
acknowledgment of receipt. After what he considered a decent interval,
Berg wrote to Australia’s Prime Minister. The Attorney-General’s
Department responded on 12 October. Treating Berg’s letter as an inquiry
99
OF BAGGAGE AND KINGS
100
OF BAGGAGE AND KINGS
We have received your letter of June 19, 1992. This and any
future letters, on matters we have already addressed, will not be
answered because to do so will waste valuable resources.
This is where the present King of Belgium comes in. He failed Berg as
well, handing Berg’s letter to his Cabinet Chief who wrote to Berg (3
September 1991) to confirm the can’t-do-anything letter that the Prime
Minister’s Diplomatic Advisor had sent a few weeks before. No one in
Belgium seemed to care that a document in the Royal Academy had been
published without permission (and without proper credit).
This list of addressees, though interesting in its way, is worth our time
primarily because of what it tells about Berg’s search for a forum. Whatever
we think of the complaint itself, we must agree that Berg’s search for an
avenue of redress was reasonably thorough. So, to dissolve any suspicion
that he might have gotten a hearing had he done a little more, I must tell
something more of what he did. Berg sought the help not only of the
appropriate universities, the Works’ publisher, and several national
governments, but of some lesser governments, politicians, professional
societies, and even the news media.
Because the Works’ publisher was located in New York City, Berg
wrote New York City’s Police Department, the District Attorney of the
County of New York, and the Citizen’s Action Center (an arm of the City’s
Office of the Comptroller). Each of these thought his complaint lay in
someone else’s jurisdiction. The State’s Department of Law referred him
to the State’s Department of Education (on 20 August 1991). By then,
Berg had exchanged several letters with an Assistant Commissioner for
Higher Education Services who eventually suggested (20 May 1991) that
Berg write to the editors of the Works and, if they did not respond
satisfactorily, “consult a lawyer to see whether your claim has any legal
standing.” Michigan’s attorney general gave much the same advice (25
November 1991).
The Center for Law in the Public Interest referred Berg to the law firm
101
OF BAGGAGE AND KINGS
of Hall and Phillips (Los Angeles). The opinion of Hall and Phillips was
that “while you have a legitimate grievance, this is not the type of grievance
we handle” (24 April 1992). They did not say who did.
Politicians showed no interest whatever. The White House referred
him to the Office of Government Ethics (30 October 1990). That Office had
already referred him to the Designated Agency Ethics Official in the
Department of Education (2 August 1990). The Office of the Vice President
simply thanked him for writing (10 December 1990). Congressman Dingell,
known for his hearings on fraud in science and protection of
whistleblowers, declined to help Congressman Conyers’ constituent,
sending Berg’s letter on to him (8 November 1991). On 15 April 1992,
Congressman Conyers wrote, “This is an issue that needs to be worked
out at universities and other educational institutions.” Bill Clinton wrote
that he had “turned your letter over to my staff for review and study” (27
November 1991). That was the last Berg heard from Clinton (except for a
letter of 5 August encouraging Berg “to work for the changes you want in
America”). Berg heard nothing at all from any of the other candidates
then competing in the presidential primaries. The President’s Office of
Management and Budget sent Berg’s complaint to the Inspector General
at the Department of Education (2 December 1991).
Back in England, Neil Kinnock, Leader of the Opposition, suggested
Berg apply to the Patent Office or New Scotland Yard (9 January 1992).
Berg already had.
The professional societies might seem a more likely venue than
politicians. In fact, they proved no more helpful. Some came out sounding
much like the politicians. For example, both the American Association for
the Advancement of Science (28 December 1989) and the National
Academy of Sciences (29 December 1989) pleaded lack of resources to
investigate such a charge in what sound like form letters. (But each also
pointed out work it had done to raise ethical standards in science.) The
Phi Beta Kappa Society’s rejection (18 January 1990) at least sounded like
the work of an individual. Noting the society had “nothing to do with
your difficulty,” the letter concluded it would be inappropriate to get
involved now. The letter closed by suggesting that Berg write to the
American Historical Society’s newsletter Perspectives (18 January 1990).
The American Historical Association “[did] not feel that it can intervene
in this situation and is unable to advise you regarding other courses of
action” (7 May 1990).10 Among the professional societies responding in
this way were the New York Academy of Sciences (30 May 1990), the
102
OF BAGGAGE AND KINGS
103
OF BAGGAGE AND KINGS
Yet, to the (British) Council for Science and Society must go any
award for the best reason for doing nothing. Having thanked Berg for the
documents sent, the Council’s chair observed (6 December 1990),
“Unfortunately, the Council is now being forced to shut down, as we are
caught in a financial crisis.”
Berg even tried to go public. Mary McGory (Washington Post)
declined, pleading “[it] is over my head and out of my line” (4 October
1991). William Buckley (National Review) thought Berg’s case “too far
removed from too many of our readers’ understanding and interests” (15
October 1991). John Maddox (Nature’s editor) was “sorry to have to echo
what your other correspondents have had to say, that I am afraid there is
nothing we can do to help” (18 May 1992). Dear Abby was sorry too, “but
since legal matters are out of my area of expertise, I cannot help you” [no
date]. Dennis Selby, Assistant to the Nation’s editor, judged that “it is a
question of attribution rather than plagiarism [but, in] any event, The
Nation is not the most appropriate venue for this matter” (30 June 1992).
Time simply thanked Berg for writing (2 July 1992).11
“Blowing the whistle” is not as easy as generally thought.
104
OF BAGGAGE AND KINGS
not been good for anyone. The complaint did not die but faded into a
shadow, darkening the reputation of everyone connected with The Works
of Charles Babbage (until I published my first article on the subject).
That cannot be good for them or for scholars generally (or for anyone else
in research). What explains the silence? A clear conscience? Guilt? A
dislike of controversy?12
The fourth, and last, irony is one common in cases of whistleblowing.
We, the public, have only half the story, a complaint resting on clear and
substantial evidence, but still only a complaint.13 Until the other side has
been heard, any judgment we make must be provisional. But, though the
other side does not defend itself, we must make a judgment (however
provisional). And what can we conclude except that Berg was wronged?
Silence is a poor defense.14
But ironies do not justify retelling that story in a work on ethics and
the university; only insight into ethics in the university can. I think we
may state those insights as five lessons.
The first lesson of Berg’s story is that there is a geographic misfit
between the field in which we would hope to maintain research ethics and
the institutions we have for maintaining it. The sun never sets on those
whom Berg seemed justified in accusing. Like the field they work in, the
history of computing, they gird the globe. Yet, the institutions that we
would most like to have original jurisdiction over a case like Berg’s are
geographically small units, universities. None has control over more than
one important party in the case.
The second lesson is that many universities do not know what to do
with a complaint like Berg’s. Only in the last few years, primarily in the
United States, have universities begun to establish formal procedures for
dealing with cases of faculty research misconduct. Though largely
designed to deal with wrongdoing in the laboratory rather than in the
library, a university having such procedures should also have a routine
for responding to a complaint like Berg’s. Such a university might give
Berg no more satisfaction than did the King of Belgium, but it would not
have fallen into the embarrassing silence of the Universities of Sydney or
Warwick.
A third lesson to draw from Berg’s story is that there is a problem of
what lawyers call “diversity of citizenship” for procedures designed to
maintain research ethics. The scholarly world is not, as we often suppose,
coextensive with the academy. In some fields, the history of computing
being only one, there are significant numbers of non-academics. We need
105
OF BAGGAGE AND KINGS
106
OF BAGGAGE AND KINGS
107
Part III
TEACHING ETHICS
7
ETHICS ACROSS THE
CURRICULUM
In 1990, IIT’s Center for the Study of Ethics in the Professions received a
grant of more than $210,000 from the National Science Foundation to try
a campus-wide approach to integrating professional ethics into the
technical curriculum. In 1996, the Center received another $100,000 to
continue the project, with the emphasis on passing on to other institutions
what was learned at IIT.1 I was the principal investigator under both
grants. In this chapter, I describe what we at IIT did, what we learned, and
what others, especially philosophers, can learn from us about teaching
professional ethics in the university. We set out to develop an approach
that others could profitably adopt. I believe that we succeeded.
111
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
112
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
113
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
not tested on their understanding of the guest lecture. (The same faculty
who do not feel comfortable teaching ethics are likely to feel uncomfortable
grading an exam question on ethics.) The connection made between ethics
and professional education is necessarily limited because there is only so
much one can pack into an hour or two of guest lecture. Having been
raised, the topic is dropped, never to be raised again that semester.
The “outside course” is not limited in this way. It is generally a full-
length course with the requirements and grading usual in other courses in
the department. Usually, that department is philosophy (though,
occasionally, religion, political science, or sociology). Since the late 1970s,
IIT’s philosophy section has offered four such optional courses: Business
Ethics, Moral Issues in Engineering, Moral Issues in Architecture and
City and Regional Planning, and Moral Issues in Computer Science. We
recently added Medical Ethics (as part of a joint program in engineering
and medicine). Many other universities have similar courses (as well as
courses in journalism ethics, agricultural ethics, and so on).
Some professional programs give their students the option of an outside
course in the ethics of their profession (or even in hnical elective. students
take one of these outside courses as a ities elective.anities electives, only
a minority of professional students learn the ethics of their profession in
this way. At IIT, such students represent less than a quarter of any
graduating class. And IIT is, I think, well ahead of most institutions of
higher learning in this respect.
Cynics will suppose that resistance to requiring the outside course
comes primarily from the professional programs, jealous of their turf. That
is not my experience. While much of the resistance has come from the
professional programs, the concern seems to be not turf but the humane
treatment of students. This is especially true in engineering where current
requirements are already so demanding that almost half of all students
take five years to complete what purports to be a four-year program.
Perhaps more surprising is the resistance of philosophy, the “section”
of the Humanities Department that would gain turf if an outside course were
required of all students. The philosophy section believed that they could
not possibility teach all the undergraduates such a requirement would
generate without either (a) enlarging class size from the present maximum of
25–30 to 100–50, or (b) doubling the size of the section, with almost
114
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
everyone required to teach at least one required ethics course (along with
the required humanities introduction and one other course). Neither option
(or some combination) seemed attractive.
The first option was unattractive because it would change the way
courses in professional ethics are taught. Quadrupling class size would
make impossible the three to five writing assignments (or, at least, their
careful reading and close grading) customary in philosophy classes.
Quadrupling of class size would also reduce substantiality the
opportunities for an instructor to question any one student, for a student
to defend an opinion, to hear how others evaluate it, and so on. In short,
quadrupling class size would make courses in professional ethics relatively
poor philosophy courses.
That was philosophy’s objection to the first option, radically increasing
class size. It had four objections to the second option. First, no one in the
philosophy section likes teaching students taking a course because they
, Humanities 102 (shared with English, History, and Foreign Languages).
Requiring a course in professional ethics would mean that every member
of the department would every semester have to teach at least one (and
perhaps two) more required courses. Second, philosophers not in ethics
disliked teaching so much ethics. Third, even with a doubling of the
philosophy section, the usual offerings of non-ethics courses would have
had to be cut back somewhat. Students who wanted to study philosophy
would face an impoverished program (in a enlarged section). And fourth,
no one seriously expected the administration to come up with the money
necessary to double the section. A required outside course was simply
unrealistic.
The outside course must therefore be voluntary. Voluntary and outside
the professional program, it suffers one disadvantage of the guest lecture.
It looks optional (because the curriculum treats it that way). Voluntary or
not, it also suffers from another disadvantage of the guest lecture; it
seems to teach something members of the profession (as represented by
faculty in the professional program) need not know.
The in-house course can overcome both these disadvantages. The
in-house course, even if optional, is part of the professional program,
taught along with other technical electives by members of one’s
profession. Clearly, some professionals (the ones teaching the course)
know the profession’s ethics well enough to teach it. And, in most
115
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
116
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
Outline of a solution
117
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
118
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
The workshop was open to any IIT faculty member teaching in any study)
with a professional purpose. These programs range from architecture to
physics, from business to design, from engineering to psychology. Though
most programs give a bachelors degree, a few (like law) give only a post-
baccalaureate degree. We ignored this distinction. We chose not to define
he workshop to faculty teaching undergraduates. We thought that the
more varied the professional background of those participating, the richer
the program was likely to be. We would be laying the groundwork for
understanding professional ethics across disciplines. While most of the
workshop participants each year came from engineering, computer science,
and business, the participation of those from other programs (including
ROTC, biology, mathematics, law, English, psychology, and public
administration) clearly improved the discussion of issues cutting across
disciplines.
Many workshops carried out under the banner of Across the
Curriculumurse in ethical theory capped with some applications to
professional ethics. We had heard that, while participants generally
enjoyed these workshops, relatively few thereafter integrated ethics into
their technical courses. Such workshops seem to support research in
professional ethics (and perhaps in-house courses), not integration of
ethics into technical courses. Our workshop, on the other hand, was
supposed to teach professional faculty enough ethics, and enough about
teaching ethics, to make them both willing and able to discuss issues of
professional ethics in their courses, to give assignments with an ethical
dimension, and to hold students responsible for the work assigned. So,
our workshop had to be different from its predecessors.
To find out how it could be different, we met over sack lunch almost
weekly for more than a year (1989–1990) with eight faculties from computer
science, engineering, psychology, and public administration (and a few
philosophers, of course). About half had been associated with the ethics
center for a long time. At first, the discussion was quite abstract, but soon
it began to focus on particular readings, some suggested by us and some
by the other faculty. Some faculties also tried writing and presenting a
case. In this and similar ways, we used the lunches to “test market” ideas
(ours and theirs).
“Test marketing” was extraordinarily useful. I was often surprised both
119
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
by what these faculty knew and by what they did not know. While most
knew quite a lot about their own profession’s ethics, and several knew a
good deal of philosophy, all had trouble with activities I do almost without
thinking. For example, asked to write a brief ethics case for discussion,
most came in unsure whether they had done as asked, when in fact they
had.13
We concluded that what blocks teaching professional ethics in
professional courses is primarily lack of experience with teaching ethics.
Professional faculty will teach professional ethics when they have enough
background to feel confident that they can teach ethics. That background
consists of such nuts-and-bolts matters as how to devise problems for
homework or class discussion and how to grade work consisting almost
entirely of non-mathematical reasoning. 14 Ethical theory, though
occasionally helpful, is relatively unimportant.
We planned a workshop requiring about thirty hours in class (five
morning sessions back to back in June and then two all-day sessions, one
in July and one in August). There was also to be substantial reading and
two required presentations (one at each of the all-day sessions). In the
next section, I describe the workshop day by day; in the section after that,
the support rendered during the academic year; in the penultimate section,
the student evaluations, faculty evaluations, and other evidence of
success (or failure); and, in the concluding section, what I take to be the
important lessons to be learned from what we did.
120
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
121
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
entirely of reminding participants to use the terms just defined in the way
they had been defined. Our purpose was to let workshop participants
experience what students would experience in class if left more or less on
their own. By 10:15, participants were agreed on what engineer) should
do (write the report as requested, taking care to say nothing false, but
start looking for another job).
After a fifteen-minute break, we reconvened for a discussion of how
to analyze an ethics problem. My co-leader presented a seven-step method
(identify problem, check facts, and so on).20 First someone from business,
then an engineer, and eventually everyone recognized the method as
basically the The method was not peculiar to philosophy.
By 11:00, we were ready to look again at Catalyst B. This time we
proceeded step by step, following the method. This discipline seemed to
change the focus of discussion. While most participants ended with the
same position as before, everyone seemed to feel that the discussion
went better this time. Clearly, a discussion of ethics need not be a free-for-
all. Far from hurting the discussion, disciplining it had actually helped.
Many expressed satisfaction at having an outline (the seven-step method)
they could use to lead class discussion of an ethics problem.
The morning ended with my co-leader giving a preview of issues in
professional ethics. Does it matter in Catalyst B whether any of the chief
characters is an engineer or other professional? What is a professional,
anyway? Does a professional owe special loyalty to employer, coworkers,
public, profession, or what? What might such loyalty require? What part
should a code of ethics play in answering such questions?21
Day Two was signed) readings were accounts of utilitarian and Kantian
moral theories. In addition, we suggested Kant’s Foundations of the
Metaphysics of Morals, Mill’s Utilitarianism, and a brief discussion of
relativism.22 We were surprised, especially the first year, at how many
faculty took our suggestions.
Explaining the day’s plan at 8:30, I stressed (to the evident relief of
participants) that moral theory was not something they should teach. We
would teach them enough about it to make clear that they need not know
more to integrate ethics into their technical courses. In particular, they
should notice the dialectic of criticism and correction by which seemingly
radically different theories ended up (in the hands of an expert) giving
much the same answer to practical questions. This is no accident. A moral
122
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
theory that gets results much different from the others is open to counter-
example (and so, refutation) to which the others are not. I did, however,
admit that theory has its uses. Many teachers find that some one theory
suits them better than the others, that it provides them with a comfortable
framework for guiding class discussion or thinking through a problem on
their own.
The session on utilitarianism began at 8:45 much like any class in
moral theory. I pointed out that the foundation of any utilitarian theory is
an analysis of (non-moral) good. While there are many analyses, will
serve for our purposes. Utilitarians define the morally right ( the good.
This makes their theories t utilitarians are not (as we shall see) the only
teleologists.
Maximizing the good is the most popular, but not the only, way
utilitarians have of defining the right. The good for utilitarians is objective,
a certain state of the world. But, because we cannot know how our acts
will in fact turn out, we cannot actually know what good our acts will do.
Choosing acts must therefore be done based on something more subjective
than actual outcome, that is, on what we are justified in expecting our acts
to accomplish. We may then summarize the thod
This lecture took about half an hour, including some good questions.
I then showed a five-minute segment of the Ethics Resource Center’s
video, A Matter of Judgment. The video consists of five independent
vignettes, each involving a conflict of interest. In the part I showed,
nsibilities, sees an opportunity to start a business of his own, perhaps
with great advantage to himself, his wife, and a software inventor. Should
Jeff seize what may be the opportunity of a lifetime if doing so means
taking advantage of contacts made through his employer (possibly to the
123
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
1 identify your act (what you are actually proposing to do), for example,
tell someone something you believe to be false;
2 identify the end you have in view (what is actually moving you to do
the act in question), for example, getting something without paying
for it;
3 consider whether (assuming the world otherwise remains as you believe
it to be) you could still achieve that end if everyone is permitted to act
the same whenever he has the same end in view;
4 reject the act if you find it would not achieve the end you have in view
in a world where everyone were permitted to act the same when he
had the same end in view.
We then tried to apply Kant’s tests to Jeff’s choice. This turned out
to be harder than expected. We had to consider carefully what Jeff’s act
and motive were to apply the test of consistency; whether Jeff’s employer,
presumably a corporation, counted as a person for purposes of the test of
124
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
125
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
126
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
of how to teach it). The two readings offered two ways to think about
professional ethics, code-based and role-based.27
From 8:45 to 9:15, my co-leader presented the standard analysis of
professions: they are occupational groups delivering important services,
making a commitment to serve the public in ways beyond what market,
law, and morality demand, requiring judgment and training not easy to
acquire, and characterized by evolving standards of conduct expressed
in a code of ethics. She also provided an analysis of responsibilityfessions
(and their codes), noted differences in the structure of professions (for
example, the way clients are much less central to engineering than to
lawyering), and identified some problems in the concept of ional autonomy.
At this point, about 9:15, we distributed a copy of an engineering
code of ethics (ABET, 1989, including Guidelines), and returned to Catalyst
B. The assigned reading for the day included Phase 2 of that case, reporting
events over the month after the first decision. This gave faculty a chance
to see the possibilities in a case in stages. Choices have consequences.
One consequence of a particular moral choice may be harder choices later.
But the primary purpose of looking again at Catalyst B was to see what
difference treating it as a case of professional ethics made. d es of a
profession with special obligations beyond what other employees have.
Many of the engineering faculty had not seen their profession’s code
of ethics before (and of those who had, none had seen the long version
we handed out). The other faculty were in much the same situation. As we
used the code to analyze Catalyst B, they expressed surprise at how the
code affected their judgment of what ould do. The situation had more
structure than they had supposed. And that structure suggested they
should have taken a tougher initial line than they did. Because they had
not, they now faced a more difficult Phase 2. They saw clearly the potential
value of a code in shaping class discussion.
At 10:00, after a fifteen-minute break, I offered advice on how to
identify ethical issues in technical courses. Ethics, I argued, is part of the
normal context of professional practice. Ethical standards are similar to
other professional standards in at least three ways: (1) They have the
same purpose as other standards, that is, to standardize the profession’s
work for the public’s benefit; (2) ethical standards develop in the same
127
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
way other standards do, beginning with common sense, getting modified
as the profession’s experience grows, and never becoming final (since
experience continues); (3) most important, like other professional
standards, ethical standards need practical context to make sense. They
are, after all, guides to professional judgment. Judgment can only be
exercised in a context. Teaching professional ethics is, in fact, part of
teaching professional practice.
How then do you find ethics issues in a technical course? You must
see the course material in its professional context. How do you do that? I
then made a number of suggestions to be found in Chapter 8: read the
profession’s code, draw on your own experience, and so on.
Having identified some issues, how can you make room for them in a
technical course? You can:
128
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
At about 11:00, my co-leader took over. Her subject was methods for
doing ethics in class. The line between her subject and mine was, of
course, far from sharp. No one seemed to mind. My co-leader’s
presentation differed in two respects from mine. First, she systematically
went through a list of methods, giving an example or two of each from her
own experience. This both augmented my list and reorganized it. Second,
she gave the advantages and disadvantages of each method. For example,
case studies can be long narratives, short vignettes (or scenarios), mere
hypotheticals (what if I did x?), or slight modifications of problems already
in the course (for example, mini-design problems). Narratives can have
substantial impact, but they take time to lay out; vignettes, such as Catalyst
B, take much less time but are therefore less realistic; hypothicals take
even less time, but tend to invite students, especially if inexperienced, to
doubt that such-and-such could happen; mini-design problems probably
will not have much impact unless there are a lot of them during the semester
(for more on this, see Chapter 8).
In much the same way, my co-leader discussed projects, films, computer
simulations, role playing, discussion (whole class, small group, debates,
and so on), and writing assignments (again, see more about these in
Chapter 8). Having demonstrated that there are a great many ways to
teach professional ethics, we adjourned.
Day Four dealt with cognitive and moral issues of teaching
professional ethics. Can ethics be taught? Should it be? Where does
what one person does in the classroom on one day fit into institutional
goals? All three readings for the day dealt with the empirical literature on
teaching ethics. What works? What does not work? How do we know?
The third reading, while summarizing this literature, tried to deal with
specific fears faculty may have about teaching professional ethics
(indoctrination, appearing holier-than-thou, and so on).29
At 8:45, my co-leader began summarizing the empirical literature. The
good news is that moral development does not end in childhood. We go
on developing moral judgment (and picking up relevant moral information)
well into adulthood. Ethics certainly can be taught. The bad news is that
we know little about how to teach it, especially about how to affect conduct.
What do we know? Most important, the lecture method common in
technical courses is unlikely to contribute much. Discussion of cases,
especially when guided to bring out clashing arguments and force their
evaluation, is necessary to improve judgment. These discussions should
be integrated into the wider discussion of related technical issues, with
129
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
some examples of how others have handled similar problems and with
information about resources a professional might be able to mobilize to
evaluate his own position or that of others.
There are a few other rules we can derive from our experience as
teachers: Avoid theories alone (pure philosophy), too many dilemmas (for
example, either lose your job or cause a thousand innocent people to die),
and too many hypotheticals. Stress the similarity between technical issues
and ethical issues. In both, we need to define the problem, gather facts,
develop options, inventory resources, consider costs, and so on.
At 9:45, we considered whether, assuming we could teach ethics in
the ways open to us, we should. As teachers, we are committed to
imparting information, skill, judgment, and the like in order to benefit the
recipient, our students. Teaching ethics should not be mere training, that
is, imparting information, skill, judgment, or the like for the benefit of a
third party. How can teaching ethics benefit students? There are, I argued,
four benefits teaching ethics can bestow on students: (1) increased ethical
sensitivity; (2) increased knowledge of relevant resources and standards
of conduct; (3) improved ethical judgment; and (4) improved willpower
(ability to act ethically when they want to) (for a fuller explanation of
these benefits, see Chapter 8). Whatever students want to do with what
they are taught, they will not want to get into ethical trouble because they
did not see the ethical element of the situation or were ignorant of the
relevant standard, because they showed poor judgment, or because they
lacked the resources to say s
Teaching ethics is, in part, like teaching more technical material. What
we teach gives power, a power that can be used for evil as well as for
good. While we cannot know how our students will use what we teach,
we have good reason (in general) to believe that they mean well. The
problem of what to do with a student who does not mean well is the same
whether we are teaching ethics or more technical material.30
Can we teach ethics ethically? Indoctrination is unethical. A teacher,
or at least a university professor, should not get students to believe a
claim or recognize a standard by means that bypass their reason. But the
methods that teach ethics successfully, that is, those discussed earlier,
do not involve indoctrination. They appeal to reason in much the way
more technical teaching does. So, faculty need not try to appear neutral
with respect to their profession’s ethics any more than they need appear
130
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
neutral with respect to technical standards. Faculty need only make clear
what is simply their opinion (something about which respectable members
of the profession can disagree) and what is in fact settled among members
of the profession. Even settled questions can, of course, be reopened.
But those wishing to reopen them bear a heavy burden of proof (just as,
for example, would a student who wanted to reopen discussion concerning
the location of oxygen in the periodic table).
What about the bright student who really does have a fundamental
disagreement with the profession; for example, an engineering student
who does not care about the safety of the public? A faculty member can
still grade the student’s work, evaluating it for awareness of issues,
knowledge of standards, and so on. The faculty member should give the
student a good grade if she has mastered the material, but also probably
should take the student aside and urge her to consider whether she really
wants to work in a field where she does not share the fundamental
commitments of those with whom she will be identified. Joining a profession
is not the only, or even the surest, way to make money.
After many questions and a fifteen-minute break, the last hour was
devoted to strategies for teaching ethics. The emphasis was on strategies.
Faculty should not try to do everything all at once. Instead, they should
try to build on what came before and to lay the groundwork for more later.
So, for example, faculty teaching a first-year course might naturally
emphasize increasing ethical sensitivity, for example, by raising an ethical
issue now and then (by vignette, war story, or forensic case). The theme
would be, is something that can come up.ond year course might instead
work at increasing ethical knowledge, for example, by handing out a code
of ethics at the beginning of the term, raising easy ethical issues early in
the term for which students must find answers in the code, and raising
harder ethical issues later in the term for which students can provide an
answer only by interpreting provisions that are not directly on point.
Faculty teaching third-year courses might in addition allow discussion of
ethical issues in class, give homework assignments requiring students to
make a recommendation taking those ethical issues into account and
providing a defense of that recommendation going beyond a mere citation
of relevant code provisions (and including perhaps even a justification or
critique of the provision). Faculty teaching a fourth-year course might in
addition send their students out to various employers in the area to find
131
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
out how questions like those discussed in class are handled there
(including what resources a young professional might call on should she
disagree with a supervisor on how to handle the question).31
I presented this as only one model. By the second year, I had to warn
IIT faculty that most of their sophomores would, as freshmen, have seen
a copy of their profession’s code, have had some experience working with
it, and have participated in significant classroom discussions of
professional ethics. Faculty would have to adjust the model accordingly.
Nonetheless, the basic idea was still sound. Don’t try to do everything at
once. Start small. Push on. Know what colleagues are doing. Coordinate
with others when possible. Have a long-term plan (subject to change as
experience suggests). Check for impact by testing, graded assignments,
or the like.
Day Five continued the focus on pedagogy. After describing what we
intended to cover and taking questions left over from the day before, we
turned to practical matters. Both readings for the day combined discussion
of the importance of teaching ethics with ideas for how to do it.32
The first year we had several workshop participants who had tried to
teach professional ethics in technical courses describe what happened.
Participants found the ROTC instructor’s description most interesting,
since ROTC had tried to integrate ethics systematically and seemed to
have been reasonably successful. Although even the ROTC instructor
admitted to considerable dissatisfaction with what he had done, these
reports had the effect of reducing general anxiety about teaching ethics.
Some technical faculty had done it and lived to tell the tale. This took
about an hour.
We felt no need to reduce anxiety this way in later workshops. By
then we had faculty who, having graduated from our workshop, had
much more satisfying experiences. So, we took a different tack. From 8:45
to 9:15, an English instructor who, having taken the workshop, described
four techniques she had used to integrate writing into coursework (without
much work for her), for example, the an hour to write two sentences
summing up the discussion, as a way both to provide faculty with some
quick measure of what students had heard and also as a way to help
students to organize and retain the experience before it began to fade).
Along the way, she gave examples of how such techniques might help
faculty trying to integrate ethics. She also noted that these techniques
helped to satisfy the faculty’s responsibility for integrating writing into
technical courses.
132
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
133
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
for the tangent to a curve. For unusual curves, the routine will give an
incorrect result (a line not in contact with the curve). The only way students
have of knowing whether a particular curve is unusual is to sketch it and
the supposed tangent. Students seldom bother even though they are
regularly told that checking their calculated result against a curve is part
of doing such problems.
Since most of his students are would-be engineers, one of our
workshop’s participants, a math professor, thought to use engineering
ethics to explain what is wrong with not checking. As engineers, his
students are responsible not only for the accuracy of their calculations
but for the usefulness of the answer. Unless they do the sketch, they
cannot honestly vouch for the answer’s usefulness. But, because they
will be engineers, anyone to whom they gave the answer would quite
properly expect the answer to be useful. So, to give the answer without
checking it against a sketch (or without warning that they have not checked
it) is deceptive, a clear breach of engineering ethics. Should students get
credit for such dishonesty? (While he planned to say just this and go on,
he was ready to pull out an engineering code of ethics and read appropriate
sections should students object. He was also prepared to suggest students
verify his claims with engineering faculty.)34
Example 2. An engineering professor revised a problem from a text in
applied thermodynamics (a third-year course). The original problem asked
students to determine the evaporator and condenser pressures, the mass
flow rate of refrigerant, the compressor power input, and the coefficient of
performance for two refrigerants (freon and 134a), given a certain vapor-
compression refrigeration system. To this, our workshop participant added
information about cost, advertising department hopes for the new non-
freon system, and some other typical context, and asked students to
recommend a refrigerant and justify the recommendation. Students could
get extra credit for research beyond the text (though the text in fact
contained more than enough about the refrigerants, ecological information
and economic information).
Because the freon system would have a 3 percent cost advantage
over the 134a system, students could not just choose refrigerant 134a.
Their recommendation would have to take environmental impact into
account, the economic costs of developing a system using freon when
freon systems may well be prohibited by law in a few years, and perhaps
other considerations as well. As part of going over the problem in class,
134
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
135
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
said something about more than one or if what she said was particularly
good. There would then be a smile of understanding.
I do not want to give the impression that workshop participants were
dull. They were overall by far the best students I have ever had. The only
time I had any doubt about their ability was on this question of grading.
I now think that the problem is that, despite everything we had been
through, many faculty still felt that er or grading philosophy. They had
not yet fully assimilated how much like other grading the grading
professional ethics was. They were to look for sensitivity, knowledge, or
judgment. This could be shown in words (for example, a note on the side
pointing out the toxicity of an effluent in a routine problem), but it could
also be shown in, say, the presence of a sketch in a calculus problem of
the sort I described earlier.
I said that they still felt that grading ethics meant grading character or
philosophy, not that they believed that. The problem went deeper than
belief. Going through a problem or exam question with one workshop
participant, making clear how easy grading ethics was in the context of
his own course, did not seem to help the rest much. I generally had to start
over with the next. And, for all this one-on-one effort, my success was, I
now know, only partial. I gave most workshop participants enough
confidence to try grading an ethics assignment, no more. Most faculty
left the workshop not quite convinced that they could do it, and they
remained unconvinced until they actually gave an assignment, graded it,
and found that neither they nor their students found any cause for
complaint. There is no substitute for that experience.
136
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
appreciated. But our faculty only occasionally used the new acquisitions
(and that use seemed only slightly greater than in past years). We gained
more from their involvement in the library than they did. Material support
was not crucial to getting ethics into their courses.
Neither was the continuing seminar. It worked well in one respect.
Those attending the two sessions we held during the first term enjoyed
them. In another respect, however, the seminar worked badly. We were
never able to get even a bare majority of workshop graduates to attend.
The usual excuse, none the less seemed less than the whole story. My
impression, and it is only that, is that faculty whose courses were going
well had no need of a Other things squeezed out the continuing seminar
because it had a low priority for them.35
Those who did attend attended out of general interest, the same reason
they would have attended any other event the subject of which was
professional ethics. Indeed, many of these attended a sack-lunch series
on research ethics we organized the second term (independently of ethics
across the curriculum). Attending the workshop increased their interest
in professional ethics, making them more likely to attend other ethics-
related activities (whether or not specially designed for them). They found
their own social support. We therefore scheduled no sessions of the
continuing seminar after the second term.
Our experience with rent. The first year, most workshop participants
were at one time or another glad to call on me as an experienced teacher of
ethics willing to answer a few questions, look at a proposed assignment,
suggest a source of cases, or the like. The questions were never hard; the
time required to answer them never more than a few minutes; the total time
devoted to such consultations probably did not exceed six hours. The
consultations were in fact a natural continuation of Day Seven. Yet, I
often had the feeling that, had I not been there to consult, the faculty
member would have given up. After the first year, I had only a few such
consultations.
Learning to teach professional ethics is, I now think, a lot like learning
to use a new computer (or new software). appropriate experience, much
of what is necessary to use a new machine (or program) is intuitive; the
manuals seem to devote page after page to the obvious. But for those
lacking that experience, the same manuals (and prompts) often seem cryptic.
I have sat in front of my computer, manual before me, at a loss how to
137
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
Evidence of success
138
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
1 Did this course increase your awareness of ethics issues likely to arise
in your professions or job?
2 If “no”, what might have helped increass your awareness of such
issues? If “yes”, please explain how it increased your awareness.
3 Did this course do anything to change your understanding of the
importance of professional or business ethics?
139
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
There was also a catch-all question, and finally, a question asking about
previous experience with ethics:
7 In your opinion, did this course spend too much time on professional
or business ethics, too little, or just the right amount? Is there anything
that should have been done differently? Explain.
8 Did you have any professional or business ethics in a class before
this one?
What can we learn from these student evaluations? For most classes,
the student responses were quite favorable. Variations seem to have little
to do with discipline, class size, or level. Consider, for example, CS 105 (a
large first-year class), MAE 205 (a mid-size second-year class), and CBK
504 (an MBA class). For question 1, the number answering in order) 101
out of 110; 15 out of 19; and 15 out of 24.38
In general, the responses tended to be more negative for questions 3
and 5 – but ully here. The comments accompanying es were generally
positive. For example, a substantial number of students, having answered
, 3, and 5, might answer question 7 in some such ways as this: t.bed as
That brings me to the last category of evidence of success, the most
subjective but also the most interesting. Starting about the October after
the first workshop, various university publications began coming to us to
do stories on Ethics Across the Curriculum. We would tell them what we
knew and then refer them to workshop participants. Eventually, favorable
stories appeared in IIT publications. I was invited to sit on two university
committees, one to propose ways to integrate creativity into the curriculum
and the other to do the same for quality. But, the high point of expressions
of administrative regard occurred at a faculty meeting when IIT’s president
140
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
observed, with obvious pleasure and awe, that one of our workshop
participants had integrated ethics into Thermodynamics. In short, it
seemed that, even in the first few months after our first workshop, the
administration had received enough feedback from our graduates to
conclude that we knew what we were doing.
But something more subtle was also happening. Faculty who had
thought that the engineering curriculum left no room for the innovations
they wanted, began to talk about integrating this or that into standard
courses. They regularly referred to Ethics Across the Curriculum as a
model for what can be done. They had a new way to look at curricular
change.
Concluding lessons
What lessons can we draw from all this? The most important is that the
barriers to integrating ethics into the professional curriculum are not what
they have commonly been supposed to be. That most faculty know little
moral theory is, for example, not a barrier to teaching professional ethics
(except insofar as an unjustified fear of not knowing moral theory
intimidates scholars who like to know a field before they teach it). The
barriers are much more mundane, deriving in large part simply from lack of
classroom experience (for example, knowing how to respond when a
student challenges a code provision). Because teaching, like other
professions, is largely a matter of judgment, and d for the focus of any
effort to integrate ethics into technical courses must be on getting faculty
to start doing it as quickly as possible. There is no substitute for experience.
This is not to say that faculty in business, engineering, biology, or
any other academic discipline cannot benefit from moral theory. They
certainly can. Indeed, some participants of our workshop have suggested
an advanced workshop on moral theory. Having a better sense of what
philosophers do, they can see how knowing more philosophy might be
relevant to what they do in the classroom or just worth study for its own
sake. What our experience shows, however, is that those reasons for
studying philosophy are largely independent of integrating ethics into
technical courses. If you want to integrate ethics into technical courses
quickly (and effectively), a workshop in moral theory is not what you
141
ETHICS ACROSS THE CURRICULUM
want. You want a workshop focused on how to teach ethics such as that
described here.
Our success also suggests another lesson. Insofar as we succeeded
more than others before us, we did so because our workshop was different
from theirs. It was different because we worked out its contents in close
cooperation with faculty like those who would eventually take it. (Indeed,
most of the faculty who helped to design the workshop eventually took
it.) Not only careful planning, but careful ide what faculty actually need to
include ethics in technical courses. Those planning a workshop should
take care not to assume they have more than good hunches about what
the workshop should include until they have consulted with their potential
students. Designing ethics workshops is still a field where nobody knows
much, and those who claim to know a lot usually turn out to know nothing.
We need all the help we can get.
142
8
CASE METHOD
While much has been written about “the case method,” most of it is about
the teaching of law or business.1 Little has been written about teaching
practical (professional or applied) ethics. Of that little, most has been
rather theoretical – concerned, for example, with comparing case-based
with theory-based teaching.2 The instructor who looks for guidance on
how to develop an ethics case, how to use one in class, or how to write or
grade a homework assignment or exam question involving such a case
will find only a few scattered remarks.3 The instructor who would like to
use a few ethics cases in a course to which “the case method” is foreign
will find even less.4 The purpose of this chapter is to begin to fill that gap
in the literature.
143
CASE METHOD
144
CASE METHOD
145
CASE METHOD
or proves (or disproves) it, allowing discussion to leave that point for the
next. In short, whatever the analogies between the philosopher’s example
and the law school’s or business school’s case, a philosopher’s example
is not a case.
Like lawyers, physicians have cases. In the early 1960s, when
physicians began asking philosophers for help with problems of medical
ethics that the new technology of medicine had already begun generating,
they presented the philosophers with “cases,” just as lawyers might have
done.9 For physicians, however, a case is a medical problem, a particular
patient with a certain set of symptoms, not a legal problem.10 The
physicians’ cases were never “hypothetical.” Often the patient still lay in
bed across the street. These living cases were seldom short, spare, or
sharply focused. Often they were not even fixed. The patient might reveal
some important detail of her life between one discussion of the case and
the next, or take a turn for the worse, or make a new demand. A philosopher
could even go and look if he wanted to, adding to the facts of the case
himself.
Those philosophers who made peace with the responsibility that goes
with helping physicians decide what to do in actual cases, found the
narrative, the unexpected details, the ambiguity, and the practicality of
these cases exhilarating. They were also impressed by how much both
they and the physicians seemed to learn from the discussion, even when
there was no agreement on what to do.
Not surprisingly, some of these philosophers tried to introduce
(something like) these discussions into their own teaching, especially
into the new undergraduate courses in medical ethics and social issues
then taking shape. Because the physician’s case contained too much
technical information and assumed a good deal of institutional knowledge,
the philosophers could not just bring the physician’s case into an
undergraduate, or even a graduate, class in philosophy. They had to
rewrite the case. The rewrite was usually shorter than the typical law
school or business school case, much less technical than the physician’s.
The philosopher’s “case” was, however, not just a new version of the
philosopher’s example. The case was designed to provoke discussion
rather than to kill it. If a case had a right answer, it would not be immediately
obvious or easy to demonstrate. Often there was (or at least seemed to
be) no unique right answer, only several pretty good ones (and several
pretty bad ones too).
It is, I think, easy to gloss over this history, to see the ways in which
everyone’s cases are the same and miss the ways they differ. So, let me
146
CASE METHOD
147
CASE METHOD
What is a case?
The purpose of this section is to demonstrate the useful variety among
cases. I shall make fifteen distinctions. Since most of the distinctions are
independent of the others, the number of combinations possible is quite
large. While I doubt that the fifteen exhaust the list of potentially useful
distinctions, I do believe the list to be long enough to discourage defining
“case” too narrowly. I also believe the list to be long enough to remind
anyone writing a case of some useful possibilities that might otherwise
not come to mind.
148
CASE METHOD
Long (and very long) v. short (and very short). Business school
cases can be quite long, many times longer than Prof. X’s thirty-pager.
Such very long cases are worked through over several days or weeks, the
instructor focusing first on one aspect of the case (some problem of
finance, say) and then on another (a problem of personnel or legality).
Very long cases generally contain a good deal of background material,
not only records of the company involved and other case-specific
information, but also material typical of a text in economics, history,
psychology, or sociology. Very long cases may, in fact, be no more than a
way for business schools to have their cases and textbooks too.
I have never seen a hundred-page ethics case. Indeed, until Prof. X’s
case, I had considered a ten-page ethics case quite long. In this respect,
ethics cases seem to resemble legal cases. While published decisions can
be several hundred pages, the cases in a legal casebook are generally
only a few (carefully edited) pages; few cases are even twenty pages. But
even most of the cases in legal texts are long compared to most of the
ethics cases I use. Mine are generally only a paragraph; few fill a single
typewritten page. And, though certainly short, they are not as short as
ethics cases can be. A case can be a single sentence, for example, “What
would you do if you were in a two-person life boat on an empty, ice-cold
sea with a lawyer and doctor and the boat could not long stay afloat with
all three of you on board?”
What length a case should be seems to be entirely a matter of what an
instructor wants to accomplish, how much time is available, what the
students already know, and how much they can be expected to read. So,
for example, I generally use short cases because I generally assign a
substantial amount of reading along with the cases.13 Cases provide an
opportunity to use ideas in the accompanying readings. They are the
equivalent of problem sets in a math course.
Perhaps I need not add that making a case long does not mean that it
will be any more real (or realistic). The decision to add a fact is as much a
pedagogical judgment as the decision to leave one out. No matter how
long (or short) we make a case, we have to make decisions of relevance,
suitability, and readability. Except where relevant information is skimpy,
we will always leave out far more than we put in, no matter how much we
put in. Length guarantees nothing but additional cost to print the case,
additional demands on student time, and so on. Length, as such, is a
disadvantage. All else equal, the shorter the case, the better.
149
CASE METHOD
Dr. Derva Marcus quit her job at a health maintenance group (and
went into private practice) because she did not like the idea that
the cost of any specialist to whom she referred a patient would
come out of a special fund the residue of which would be, at
year’s end, her annual bonus. “I didn’t want to think about whether
I would be losing money if I ordered an ophthalmologic
examination,” she explained. Is the practice Dr. Marcus describes
unethical?
150
CASE METHOD
You are the “ethics officer” in a medium-size law firm. Today you
have before you one of the firm’s most successful negotiators,
Allen Dirblock, and the very angry credit manager of the largest
department store downtown. The credit manager has accused
Dirblock of “lying, swindling, taking advantage of my good nature,
conduct unbelievable even in a lawyer.” Dirblock described what
he did in this way:
“This was a pro bono client. She owed $3000 on a couch
destroyed by fire. She had only $1000. I knew the store’s policy:
at least half, or the debt goes to a collection agency. So, before
going to the credit manager, I asked the client to give me $500. I
removed all my money from my wallet and put that $500 in. Then
we went to the credit manager. After the usual dancing around, I
offered to settle for $500, all the money she had. He refused. ‘I
can’t go below $2000,’ he says. We go around a couple more
times and then I say, ‘Look, this women lost everything in the
fire. What say we settle?’ I then take out my wallet, remove all the
money in it, and gently place the bills in a rough pile in front of
him, saying, ‘I feel really strongly about this case. She could be
my mother. How about $1000, the $500 she has and all the money
I have in my wallet?’ He agreed. I didn’t lie the way he did when
he said he couldn’t go below $2000. I did mislead him, as he tried
to mislead me. But that’s negotiation.” The credit manager agrees
that’s what happened, but adds that when he heard “through the
151
CASE METHOD
152
CASE METHOD
153
CASE METHOD
course, is true. But it is also true that being able to think about how a
decision will look to those not directly involved (especially if it turns out
badly) can sober a decision maker who might otherwise succumb to too
narrow (or too hopeful) a view of what she is doing. Students probably
need help not only in learning to make their own decisions, but also in
learning how to evaluate those of others and how to see their own as
others might. So, the best strategy may well be a judicious mix of the two
kinds of case, along with an occasional switch in the middle: “You say
that is what she should have done, but what would you have done if you
had been in her place? What should you have done?”
Would v. should. “They” cases seem always to ask what should be
done or have been done (when they do not ask what is the “right,”
“moral,” or “ethical” thing to do). “You” cases, however, are sometimes
written with “should” and sometimes with “would.” I do not like “would”
for two reasons. First, “would” seems to ask for a prediction. Since I do
not teach students how to predict their own conduct, but how to choose
it, I do not think it fair to ask them to make such predictions. Second,
“would” seems to ask students to reveal something about themselves
beyond what they know about ethics. Asking them to do that seems to me
to invade their privacy.
Those are my reasons for preferring “should” to “would.” When I
have offered these reasons to instructors who use “would,” they usually
tell me that I have a point but a) asking students what they would do often
helps clarify their thinking about what really matters (what should go into
a “should” judgment), and b) that students seem to regard the “would” as
asking for neither prediction nor self-revelation but for a kind of “personal
should.” I see their point, but – .
Top v. bottom. Most cases in the news, most of the Harvard cases too,
involve decisions near the top of an organization. Our students will,
however, graduate into jobs much closer to the bottom. Only after many
years, and only with a good deal of luck, will they rise to be in a position
like Thiokol’s expert on booster rocket seals, the Du Pont vice-president
asked to decide whether to bar women from certain hazardous jobs, or the
like. Should not our cases reflect that reality? Should not our cases be
drawn solely from first-job experiences?18 I think not.
Many top-level decisions are simply more dramatic versions of low-
level decisions; they are first-job reality written large. Why give up the
dramatic large print? Some top-level decisions may, of course, have no
154
CASE METHOD
(exact) counterpart lower down. Still, studying them may help students to
see high-level decisions as ethical decisions, to see their own first job as
part of an ethical career at the end of which may wait those top-level
decisions, and to think about how first decisions may help to shape later
decisions. My students do not find the top-level cases boring, though
they often need a good deal of background information to understand
what is at stake. The top-level decisions seem to be the equivalent in
practical ethics of Homer’s heroes or Shakespeare’s kings. First-job cases
may, all else equal, be better for enhancing judgment than top-level
decisions, though even that remains to be shown.19 Since top-level cases
may be better for other purposes, for example, for enhancing sensitivity
or knowledge, I see no reason not to use both kinds of cases. Indeed,
given student interest in the big cases, I think it unwise to restrict one’s
cases to those originating at the “bottom.”
Success (the positive) v. failure (the negative). Ethics stories may be
divided into two categories, those that turn out well (successes) and
those that turn out badly (failures). Because ethics problems have yet to
turn out, they cannot be categorized in this way. They can, however, be
categorized in an analogous way. What makes some problems is that the
agent has the opportunity to do something good (for example, save lives
that would otherwise be lost). No one has done anything wrong; indeed,
wrongdoing is not among the live options. The problem is produced by a
conflict of considerations all of which are (more or less) good. These are
the analogues of success stories. In other problems, the source of the
problem is someone’s (at least apparent) wrongdoing (usually that of the
agent’s superior, colleague, or client). The problem may seem to pose a
“dilemma” (in the strict sense), two choices, both bad. These are the
analogues of failure stories.
In many fields, the primary source of ethics cases is the newspaper.
Newspapers seldom report ethical success (presumably, because, short
of heroism, such success is too common to be news). Most newspaper
accounts concerned with ethics are reports of ethical failure: scandals,
crimes, disasters. An instructor who relies only on newspapers for ethics
cases may end with a collection of cases consisting entirely of failures.
Students fed entirely on such cases may become cynical about the very
possibility of ethical conduct: “What do we learn in our professional
ethics course? How bad we are!”
While failures, both stories and problems, are important for teaching
what can go wrong (a part of expanding a student’s “moral imagination”),
155
CASE METHOD
success stories have at least three additional uses. First, success stories
show that ethical conduct is possible, thus reducing cynicism. Second,
they may provide examples of how to conduct oneself ethically – and live
to tell about it. That is, they may contain insight into the “art of ethics,”
for example, that you will do better if you develop a reputation for accuracy,
if you have an alternative to the proposal you think objectionable, or if
you build a coalition before confronting a superior. Third, just as failures
provide a vocabulary for what can go wrong (“a Challenger situation”),
so success stories provide a vocabulary for what can be done right
(“Horatio at the bridge”). Success problems, in contrast, have only one
use, to give students an opportunity to practice judgment in situations
where no one has done anything wrong.
Single issue (poor) v. multi-issue (rich). Cases can be narrowly
focused. The Marcus case, for example, is about conflict of interest; once
you have discussed what to do about the conflict of interest the bonus
plan creates, there is not much left to say about the case. Other cases are
about several ethical issues. They are “rich” in possible uses. Prof. X’s
case was rich (in this sense). Generally, the shorter a case, the poorer it
will be. But even a relatively short case can have several issues, as, for
example, the Dirblock case does. Rich cases are better for examinations,
where you want to see how many issues a student can spot. Poor cases
are better for a class where you want to focus on identifying, analyzing,
and responding to a particular issue, not several.
Single stage v. multi-stage. In real life, problems often grow. We make
a small decision, without much thought, thinking that will be the end of it.
Our decision has consequences and, a few days or weeks later, we have
the same problem on our desk, somewhat more complicated now. Again
we decide. We may hear nothing more of the decision, or it may have new
consequences producing yet another decision. And so on. Generally,
cases – both problems and stories – have a single stage: we decide the
case and go on to another. We are not later asked to clean up the mess we
did not foresee. A diet of single-stage cases may leave the impression that
(in Macbeth’s words) “it were done when ‘tis done,” whereas often:
156
CASE METHOD
“final,” it pays to think about what new decisions this one might generate,
especially those it might generate if things do not go as we hope or
expect. Multi-stage cases invite computer simulation, but can be done
well on paper. The first stage is a conventional problem (for example, a
situation where “you” are faced with the question whether you should
obey what you believe is an unethical order). You resolve it, say, by
obeying under protest. You go to the next stage: A few weeks later your
boss’ superior asks why you did what you did. Do you tell her the whole
truth, including the protest, or just some part? Why? You decide. There
may then be a third stage, a fourth, and even a fifth. Indeed, in principle,
nothing prevents a multi-stage problem from being as long and complex
as a novel.20
Ordinary v. technical language. The philosopher’s case is typically
put in language allowing someone not trained in philosophy or any other
particular discipline to reach the ethical issues. Such cases are in “ordinary
language.” Cases can also be given the characteristic format of a particular
discipline. Some disciplines, especially engineering, accounting, and many
of the sciences, organize their teaching around numerical problems. Other
disciplines have a less formal equivalent, for example, the rendition of
symptoms in medicine or the details of site measurement, tagging, and
logging in archeology. Those who hope to make a discussion of practical
ethics seem continuous with a specific technical education probably
should use some ethics problems where the ethical issue must be reached
through the typical techniques. Here, for example, is a typical ethics case
in technical language (for a first course in environmental engineering):
157
CASE METHOD
philosophy, where students do not all have the same technical training or
where the instructor does not share the technical background of the
students.
Personal v. policy. For some cases, all the likely responses are what
one or a few people should do (or should have done). For others, all the
likely responses are what an organization or other large group should do
(or should have done), especially, what rules they should have (or should
have had). Cases of the first sort concern what is often called “personal
ethics”; the second, what is often called “social ethics” or “policy.” Many
cases have both a personal and a policy aspect, that is, “you” should do
such-and-such now, but your organization should make such-and-such
changes so that you don’t have to make such a decision again. Where
“your” organization is a government, policy issues are also political issues.
The line between practical ethics and politics is not sharp. The best rule
of thumb for distinguishing them is that a case belongs to politics rather
than practical ethics if all the likely responses require new laws.
The line between ethics and politics is not sharp because the line is
primarily a convenience for teachers. A particular problem may have a
personal resolution, a policy resolution (a new corporate rule), and a
political resolution (a new law). The line between ethics and politics is
none the less important because courses in practical ethics (as distinct
from courses in political philosophy) tend to focus on what individual
agents, or some private organization to which they belong, can do, rather
than on what government can do.
Living v. frozen. A “living case” is one that is still in progress. Most
cases, especially published cases, are “frozen”; they will always be as
they are now. Generally, the ordinary classroom must make do with frozen
cases; the clinic’s living cases belong to another realm. But, there are
exceptions. For example, someone teaching engineering, business, or
journalism ethics during the semester when the Challenger exploded
would have had a chance to treat that disaster as a multi-stage case,
returning to it every few weeks to review the events, make a new evaluation,
say what should be done, and then see what happens. Instructors can
also create living cases, for example, by having students write and adopt
a code of ethics for the class (or laboratory) at the beginning of the term
and then, from time to time, describing cases arising under the code and
asking for guidance, including suggestions for revising the code. An
instructor can even create a fair imitation of a living case, for example, by
presenting a multi-stage case over several days, stage by stage.
158
CASE METHOD
159
CASE METHOD
and the decision harder, until the situation became unlikely indeed and
the panelists just scratched their heads. While useful for teaching students
how to probe legal theories, this testing to destruction is probably a poor
way to teach ethics. Students are likely to develop an exaggerated sense
of how much disagreement about ethics actually exists on questions they
are likely to face.
The business school’s version of the “Socratic method” is more closely
linked to cases than the law school’s. The business case is supposed to
be an ordinary business decision. The business school’s “Socratic
method” is supposed to be a method a manager could use in dealing with
that decision. A good manager asks questions of subordinates, colleagues,
or even superiors because she wants to know the answer. She leads
discussion to a resolution none may have foreseen. Learning to ask the
right questions, to probe a position until understood, is a skill managers
should have. Business students who learn to do what their business
professors do will probably be better managers than those who do not.25
Lawyers can, of course, turn the “Socratic method” they learned into
(something like) the manager’s questioning. They will, however, have to
give up the sarcasm (which tends to alienate others rather than to help
with problem solving); they may also have to learn how to overcome the
tendency of legal colleagues to respond to questions in the defensive
way they learned in law school. And, like managers, they will have to omit
the truly strange hypotheticals with which law professors test theories to
destruction.
Because the business school’s “Socratic method” corresponds to the
way managers approach a problem, business professors can, and
frequently do, claim not to know what the “right answer” to a case is. That
is a modest claim, one worthy of Socrates. Sometimes they claim there is
“no single right answer” (meaning that there may be several), a claim that
tends to keep discussion going after students have found one good
answer. Sometimes, however, business professors claim that there is “no
right answer” (meaning not even one). This last claim seems dubious: it
must rest either on a theory of knowledge or on evidence.
The theory, whatever it is, would presumably have to be right about
what there is to know. The professor who used such a theory to defend
his claim that there are no right answers would, then, have to explain why
theories can be right but decisions cannot be. He would find himself in a
forest of mirrors from which few return.
The alternative, defending the claim that there is no right answer by
160
CASE METHOD
161
CASE METHOD
cases available, and their purpose in using cases. This, then, is a good
place to consider what kinds of ethics there are, what teaching can
accomplish, and what role cases might have in that teaching.
The term “ethics” can, as we have seen, be used in at least one of three
senses relevant here: (a) as a synonym for ordinary morality, (b) to name
a field of philosophy, and (c) to refer to those morally permissible standards
that apply to members of a group because of that membership. Those
concerned to teach ordinary morality tend to focus on moral judgment;
those concerned to teach philosophical ethics focus on moral theory, and
those concerned to teach the special standards of a group focus on those
standards, their interpretation and application. Their use of cases should
differ accordingly.
I shall say no more about using cases to teach ordinary morality for
three reasons. First, teaching ordinary morality is primarily a pre-college
enterprise; my concern here is teaching ethics in college, graduate
departments, and professional schools. Second, the literature on using
cases to teach ordinary morality is substantial, including a good deal of
empirical evidence that it works. I have little to add here.26 Third, much I
shall say about teaching special standards applies to teaching ordinary
morality as well. So, little, if anything, is lost by not dealing further with
the teaching of morality as such.
I do, however, want to say a little about the use of cases in teaching
philosophical ethics. What is important for us is that such teaching uses
cases in two ways different from the use of traditional examples.
First, there is a pedagogical use. So, for example, one might begin a
course in ethical theory with an ethics case rather than a theory to help
students see the point of theories: theories should help us solve problems
like this.
Second, there is a theoretical use. One can, during the semester, bring
various theories to bear on this or that case, asking which theory gives us
the most insight. This use of cases, though close to the use of traditional
examples (and counter-examples) differs in one important way. Examples
are chosen because they are “clear,” that is, because we agree on what
the right answer is; the theory is tested against the example. Cases, in
contrast, are chosen because they are “hard,” that is, because we disagree
about what the right answer is. Cases help us to probe the theory, to
162
CASE METHOD
compare one theory with another, to gauge their power. Theories do not
pass or fail depending on whether they give the right answer to a case.
The case has a right answer, of course, perhaps even more than one. But,
insofar as we have chosen the case because it is hard – that is, because
we do not agree on what the right answer is – we cannot test the theory
against the case in the way we can test a theory against an example.27
This theoretical use of ethics cases resembles the business school
use of business cases in at least two ways. First, a philosophy instructor
can use a case while claiming not to know what the right answer is (how
a problem should be resolved or whether a character in a story did what
she should). Second, a philosophy instructor cannot use cases to test
moral theories to destruction. Examples, not cases, test theories to
destruction.
This theoretical use of ethics cases does, however, resemble the use
law schools make of legal cases rather than the use business schools
make of business cases in at least one way. In a course in moral theory, the
instructor uses cases to build an argument against one theory or in favor
of another. The cases are not offered simply to train judgment.
That is enough about courses in moral theory. Courses in moral theory,
however they use cases, are not courses in practical ethics.28 What then
is a course in practical ethics? We may distinguish at least three kinds:
social issues courses, professional ethics courses, and institutional ethics
courses. A course in social issues takes up controversial questions of
social policy: abortion, euthanasia, war, terrorism, and so on.29 It seeks to
clarify the issues, to evaluate arguments, and (if all goes well) to justify
adoption of certain social standards.30 A course in professional ethics
focuses on the special standards of a profession rather than on general
social standards (special standards that do or should exist): nursing ethics,
police ethics, accounting ethics, engineering ethics, or the like. A course
in institutional ethics focuses instead on special standards of an institution
(those that do or should exist): academic ethics, business ethics, criminal
justice ethics, research ethics, or the like.
The distinction between professional and institutional ethics, though
not important here, is worth recalling for clarity’s sake. Physicians, for
example, both belong to a profession (medicine) and work in an institution
(the health care system). It is therefore at least theoretically possible for
“medical ethics” (in the sense of the special standards physicians as a
group apply to themselves as individuals) to conflict with “medical ethics”
163
CASE METHOD
(in the sense of the special standards that the health care system applies
to anyone providing health care). Indeed, such conflicts explain why
many courses in “medical ethics” include both professional and
institutional ethics.
A course in practical ethics (of whatever kind) is concerned not with
moral theory as such but with special standards of conduct that apply, or
might apply, to members of a certain group. The same is true of a course
on some other subject (Thermodynamics, say) in which a segment is
devoted to practical ethics. A practical ethics course, or practical ethics
segment of some other course, can have at least four purposes (all quite
different from the purposes of a course in philosophical ethics):
First, the course might seek to raise the ethical sensitivity of students.
That is, the course might try to teach students to recognize that some
professional, institutional, or other special standard may be relevant to a
decision. The study of cases is an obvious way to raise sensitivity.
Students may, for example, read a case, see no ethical issue, and come to
class wondering what the point of the case was. If, during class, the
instructor (whether by lecture, by “Socratic” questioning, or by some
other method) helps students see that the case raises several issues they
missed, the students should be more likely to see those issues next time
they read a similar case – and probably the next time they are in a situation
resembling the case. This use of cases is analogous both to the law
school’s use of legal cases to teach students to identify legal issues and
to the business school’s use of business cases to teach students to
identify business issues.
A second purpose a course in practical ethics might have is increasing
the ethical knowledge of students. The course might try to add to what
students know about the special standards in question, not only their
content, interpretation, and application, but also the resources available
to help realize them in practice. A case can contribute to this purpose
either by itself containing the information (as some business and law
school cases do), by providing an occasion for the instructor to provide
the information, or by providing an occasion for the students to seek the
information, in their texts, in the library, or in the world.
A third purpose a course in practical ethics might have is improving
the ethical judgment of students. The course might, that is, try to increase
the likelihood that students who apply what they know about ethics to a
decision they recognize as ethical will get the right answer. All university
courses teach judgment of one sort or another. Most find that discussing
164
CASE METHOD
165
CASE METHOD
The previous section drew a sharp line between philosophical ethics and
practical ethics, and between the way cases would be used in one or the
other of those courses. Yet many texts in practical ethics begin with a long
section discussing moral theories, and many teachers of practical ethics
feel obliged to introduce a good deal of moral theory into their practical
courses. While the line between philosophical ethics courses and practical
ethics courses need not be as sharp as I have drawn it, I think there are at
least four good reasons to avoid the use of moral theory in courses that
really are in practical ethics, reasons which become decisive when the
question is not a course but a segment of a course or when the instructor
does not in fact know much about moral theory.
One reason not to teach moral theories in a course in practical ethics
is that moral theories are complicated. Teaching one theory in a reasonably
sophisticated form can take several weeks, pass over the heads of most
students, and consume time better used for the substance of a course.
Teaching a theory in simplified form, while avoiding most of these
disadvantages, has another: it tends to reduce the theory to caricature,
leaving students to wonder why anyone would want to hold such a view.
A second reason not to teach moral theories in a course in practical
ethics is that (explicit) theories are generally unnecessary for good
decision-making. What a teacher of practical ethics needs is some
framework for orderly discussion of ethics cases, one including the
substance of common sense. While a moral theory can provide such a
framework, there are many other frameworks. Here is one I use.
166
CASE METHOD
Step 4, “Test options,” uses ideas from various moral theories (harm,
reversibility, and so on) to evaluate options. The tests are not necessarily
decisive; they are supposed to call attention to relevant considerations.
In this way, the core of most moral theories can be brought into decision
making in an uncontroversial form (that is, without the exclusiveness and
technical paraphernalia of explicit moral theory).
A third reason not to use moral theories in a course in practical ethics
is that in practice people seldom explicitly appeal to moral theories. They
may do so “implicitly,” that is, by saying something that can be understood
as appealing to one moral theory rather than another. But telling them that
they are so relying is seldom an effective way to get them to think sensibly
about the practical problem before them. Indeed, thinking explicitly with
theory is a special skill, one few have and perhaps not many more can
develop. Even many philosophers are not competent to do justice to a
moral theory. Given how short a single course in practical ethics is, its
time seems better used dealing with practical ethics directly. Insofar as
167
CASE METHOD
students need a framework for dealing with practical problems (as they
certainly do), the best framework would seem to be one – like the seven
steps – that both has a theoretical foundation (however implicit) and
guides reasoning in ways likely to convince those to whom the reasoning
is addressed.
A fourth reason not to use moral theories in a course in practical
ethics is that different people tend to prefer different theories as soon as
they understand them well enough to see the differences. Getting
agreement on a particular course of action, even in a relatively hard case,
is usually much easier than getting agreement on which moral theory to
apply. In this respect, moral theories resemble religions; their explicit use
in practical decisions tends to be divisive.
These four reasons are all practical. They do not establish that moral
theories are useless in principle or that they should never be used in a
course in practical ethics. Together, the four establish no more than a
general presumption against moral theories in courses in practical ethics,
a presumption that can be overcome where time, the preparation of
students, the skill of the instructor, and the specific question under
consideration together create circumstances making the introduction of
theory clearly helpful. However that may be, neither these reasons nor my
own experience suggests that instructors may not benefit from reading
theoretically informed work in practical ethics, from applying theory in
their own thinking about hard cases, or from using theory to organize
what they do in class.
168
CASE METHOD
169
CASE METHOD
170
CASE METHOD
171
CASE METHOD
172
CASE METHOD
3. Look at ethics cases in textbooks in the field (if there are any).
4. Ask practitioners what comes up when they do work of this sort.
Many good ideas can be picked up at what would otherwise be dull
parties.
5. Think about writing a report on research, design work, or evaluation
of the material you are teaching: what problems arise in reporting
technical results? What should be put first? What put last? What
buried in a footnote? What left out? Why?
6. Ask your students to identify ethical issues related to work of this
sort.
7. If all else fails, ask how someone using what you are teaching could
harm someone or embarrass members of your profession (or theirs).
Once you have identified an issue, you are ready to go looking for a
case. Often, identifying an issue will also give you one or more cases. So,
for example, practitioners will seldom give you an ethical issue without
describing one or more times when they themselves faced that issue. If,
however, identifying an issue has not given you a suitable case, you
should begin looking for one in a file you should have been keeping. This
file would contain newspaper stories raising ethical issues relevant to
your course, parts of novels or short stories raising such issues, cases
out of text books, cases your colleagues have given you, cases students
have given you (and given you permission to use), cases you developed
for other purposes, and so on. If all else fails, start asking colleagues,
students, and practitioners if they know of a case raising the issue. If this
fails to identify a suitable case, perhaps the issue you have identified is
not live; and so, not worth discussing.
Once you have identified a “case,” you must still put it in a form
suitable for use in class. Case writing becomes easy pretty quickly, but it
is no more a science than writing a paper is. The first step is to draft the
case so that it seems to do what you want it to do. When your draft is
done, you should be able to answer yes to the following four question:
173
CASE METHOD
If you cannot answer yes to all four, you should keep revising until you
can. Once you do answer yes, you should put the draft aside for a few
days. That should be enough time to see room for improvement. Make the
improvements and then let a student or colleague read the case. A second
reader generally uncovers a number of points in need of clarification by
addition, subtraction, or word-smithing. Rewrite accordingly and then
use in class. Classroom use usually reveals a whole new set of
imperfections. Rewrite accordingly.
Like a paper, a case is never really finished. But, at some point, we
decide that the improvements that may be possible are no longer worth
the effort necessary. That is the point at which to stop rewriting and to
declare the case finished (for now).
174
9
A MORAL PROBLEM IN
THE TEACHING OF
PRACTICAL ETHICS
175
A MORAL PROBLEM TEACHING PRACTICAL ETHICS
The problem
176
A MORAL PROBLEM TEACHING PRACTICAL ETHICS
A utilitarian objection
My students will have had a course in business ethics. Most other
applicants for a job probably will not. My students will therefore be more
likely to be morally sensitive than other applicants. All else equal, the
more morally sensitive employees are more likely to identify moral problems
that the rest would not and more likely to resolve well the problems they
identify.3 Probably no organization is all bad; even the worst will sometimes,
perhaps often, respond to moral objections by changing policy.
Whistleblowing may be relatively rare in part because one common
response to internal dissent in most organizations is to try to find an
alternative that satisfies dissenters. If morally sensitive employees can
make a difference even in organizations that are morally relatively
insensitive, my students can do something to improve the moral
performance of such organizations and thereby make society better than
it would otherwise be.
The reverse, however, is not true. The morally better an organization,
the more likely it is to provide its own ethics training, to encourage its
employees to discuss moral problems as they arise, and otherwise to raise
the moral sensitivity of employees. The better an organization, the less
need it has of the moral sensitivity that my students would bring to their
work. The better the organization, the more likely it is to generate that
sensitivity itself. So, insofar as what I teach leads my students to take
jobs in morally better organizations, the effect of my teaching is to assure
that the organizations most in need of morally sensitive employees will
not get them. I am contributing to the moral insensitivity of those
organizations. The overall effect of that cannot be good.
Like most utilitarian arguments, this one rests on a good number of
shaky empirical assumptions (for example, that morally sensitive people
put in a morally insensitive environment will maintain their sensitivity
long enough to make a difference).4 Still, even putting doubts about those
assumptions aside, the argument seems morally unattractive. It recognizes
no special responsibility to my students. They are treated as only so
many opportunities that I have to benefit society. They have (according
177
A MORAL PROBLEM TEACHING PRACTICAL ETHICS
178
A MORAL PROBLEM TEACHING PRACTICAL ETHICS
employees. They would either have to improve the way they do business
or cease to exist. Can I will that consequence? Certainly. Indeed, I would
welcome it. On the other hand, I could not universalize a maxim allowing
me to withhold information from students for the purpose of raising social
utility at their expense. I would not want teachers to treat me (or those I
care about) that way.
These typical Kantian arguments are, however, not quite on point.
They ignore too much of what we know, the smoke and sludge of an
imperfect world. My problem arises precisely because few others are
teaching what I teach (or, at least, because I believe that). My students
can shift the moral burden of working in bad organizations to others in
part at least because the others do not know what my students know. I
would not have a problem if my students could not shift the moral burden
in this way. I therefore need to consider what my duties are in world where
“bad organizations” (or, at least, the relatively bad) will probably always
be able to find enough employees among the morally insensitive (but
otherwise competent). The maxim I must be willing to universalize is
therefore (something like) this: Serve your own students even if, by doing
so, you both help them to shift moral burdens to strangers and help to
make society as a whole somewhat worse.
Here we have a Kantian version of the utilitarian objection discussed
earlier. The maxim forces a choice between the good of my students and
that of others (both the good of particular strangers and of society as a
whole). If I cannot will that maxim, then (assuming it is the maxim of my
act) I cannot go on teaching as I have. Can I will that maxim? I shall need
the rest of this chapter to answer.
This Kantian objection plainly has a power the corresponding utilitarian
objection lacked. Why? In part, what explains the objection’s power is a
certain conception of the relationship between teachers and students.
Teaching is conceived as somehow different from, for example, selling
gasoline to motorists. Teaching is not the mere transmission of information,
skills, understanding, or the like from one intelligence to another. The
teacher bears some responsibility for what students do with what is taught
to them (in a way a gas station attendant need bear no responsibility for
what a customer does with the gasoline pumped by the former into a gas
tank).5 Without such a conception of a teacher’s responsibility, it makes
no sense to include in my maxim anything about what I “help” my students
do. I should instead think of my teaching as merely transmitting
information, knowing that it might be used for any number of purposes,
179
A MORAL PROBLEM TEACHING PRACTICAL ETHICS
180
A MORAL PROBLEM TEACHING PRACTICAL ETHICS
181
A MORAL PROBLEM TEACHING PRACTICAL ETHICS
courage in this way is teaching only in the sense a parent may be said to
teach a child swimming by throwing the child into the water and letting
the child sink or swim.
So, we cannot condemn what I teach simply because I teach cloistered
virtue rather than moral courage. Indeed, the foregoing argument suggests
a defense of what I do. By providing my students information about how
to avoid the need to blow the whistle, I give the chance to show moral
courage in their choice of job. They need not avoid the organizations I
hope they will avoid. What I teach frees them to choose knowingly between
entering the morally risky environment of a bad organization and the
morally safer environment of a good organization. Those who choose the
morally risky environment knowingly (and for the right reasons) thereby
show moral courage (as those who choose blindly do not). Insofar as the
practice of moral courage is part of learning moral courage, they would be
farther along in learning moral courage than students who have blindly
stumbled into a job where they will need such courage. In the sense in
which a parent teaches swimming simply by throwing the child into the
water, I am teaching moral courage by teaching the students how to avoid
the need to blow the whistle. I am giving them an opportunity to choose
courageously, an opportunity that they would not otherwise have had;
and I am giving it to them earlier than if I withheld the information in
question.
However, as I said, I hope my students will avoid the morally risky
environment, even if the effect of my teaching is only to let them know
what they are getting into. I cannot so easily escape the charge that I am
at least trying to harm my students. Nor need I. The claim that teaching
cloistered virtue rather than moral courage harms students rests on the
assumption that having moral courage is morally better than having
cloistered virtue. That assumption seems, in turn, to rest on another, that
virtue is an individual strength, like good teeth or endurance. If I act
honestly thanks only to social arrangements, I am not really honest. I
only appear to be because I have not yet been put to the test.
This is a common assumption, but not a necessary one. We are, after
all, social beings, not isolated individuals. Without the social world we
take for granted, most of us would quickly starve, lonely and terrified.
Those who survived might well envy the baboons in their troop. Since we
are social beings, why not think of the virtues, especially the moral virtues,
primarily as expressions of social arrangements? Why not, for example,
say I am honest if, thanks to social arrangements that protect me from
most temptations, I in fact act honestly? Why demand instead that I
182
A MORAL PROBLEM TEACHING PRACTICAL ETHICS
satisfy some individualistic ideal in which one is not “truly” honest unless
that honesty would endure even the ring of Gyges? The virtue that shuns
ease and demands thorny paths seems a romantic invention more
appropriate to the knights of Malory’s Morte Arthure than to the business
people of today. Why make a fetish of that ideal, seeking test after test
until we die or are defeated? What is wrong with cloistered virtue so long
as we have in fact chosen a cloistered life? There is no virtue in looking
for trouble.
Of course, all else equal, it would be better to be able to resist temptation
within any social carapace rather than only within some. I do not deny
that. What I deny is much more limited, that is, that such an ability is of a
different order from the ability to pick a carapace where the need to exercise
that other ability becomes unnecessary. Cloistered virtue is not less a
virtue than moral courage nor inherently inferior to it. It is, at worst, a
virtue more easily developed because its range is correspondingly narrow.
How we rate the two virtues will depend on our assessment of the
environment in which the possessor is likely to have to operate.
While this defense of cloistered virtue is hardly decisive, it is, I think,
strong enough to leave the problem intact. We have reason enough to
believe that teaching students how to avoid having to blow the whistle
benefits them.8
The discussion so far allows us to see that the problem has two parts.
The first is the teacher’s responsibility for what a student does with what
is taught. Without that responsibility, a Kantian objection to what I teach
seems unlikely. However, given that I am responsible for what my students
do with what I teach them, our problem has a second part, showing that I
am entitled to benefit them even at the cost both to strangers (burdened
with choices they would rather avoid) and to society (made worse overall
by what my students do). We must, then, turn to the question of
responsibility. What is my responsibility for what my students do with
what I teach?
183
A MORAL PROBLEM TEACHING PRACTICAL ETHICS
clear (as I try to do) that they are to weigh my reasons, not bow to my
authority.
However, if my students cannot shift moral responsibility to me, what
responsibility can I have for what they do? The answer seems to be: quite
a bit. I could not, for example, both teach students how to burgle and
deny responsibility if they then commit burglaries. Transmitting that
technical skill is not a morally neutral act. The reason is not that the skill
can only be put to a bad use or even that its primary use is bad. Most
teachers would, I think, still feel shame (or at least embarrassment) if a
student got into trouble using a socially approved skill they had taught,
such as computer programming. Something similar is true of praiseworthy
acts. We do not think it odd for a teacher to take pride in the
accomplishments of a student, moral as well as technical, so long as the
virtue the student thereby revealed has some connection with what the
teacher in fact taught. But how can such an attitude be justified?
The attitude makes no sense if we think of teaching as morally neutral,
the mere transmitting of information, skill, understanding, or the like. If
that were all teaching is, we could take pride in our students’ technical
achievements but not in their moral achievements. We would also have
no reason to feel shame when students misused the information, skill,
understanding, or the like that we successfully imparted to them. Indeed,
insofar as they used what we taught effectively, we should feel pride, not
shame, at the evidence of our (technical) success.
So, teaching must have a moral structure, a context of presuppositions
justifying such pride and shame. Among these presuppositions, the most
important is probably that the teacher recognizes the student as a person,
a being who can reason and whose acts can be guided by reasons,
including reasons of the sort the teacher gives. The teacher–student
relation requires the teacher to know something the student does not. In
this respect, the relationship is necessarily unequal. That technical
inequality is, however, consistent with a deeper equality among rational
agents. Here, then, is one difference between teaching and mere training
or indoctrination. Teaching can of course address far more than a student’s
reason (it is a poor teacher who ignores a student’s interests, prejudices,
or emotions). But, strictly speaking, we do not teach unless we address as
well the student’s reason. A student is not a mere pupil or trainee. A
teacher cannot simply transmit knowledge, skill, judgment, or
understanding by some mechanical means (“drum it into the student’s
head,” as we might say); the teacher must actually win the student’s faith
184
A MORAL PROBLEM TEACHING PRACTICAL ETHICS
185
A MORAL PROBLEM TEACHING PRACTICAL ETHICS
learns will serve the student’s purposes (even while recognizing that a
student’s purposes – like her teacher’s – are often inchoate, partially
inconsistent, and otherwise in need of rational revision). The teacher
cannot try to benefit the student in ways contrary to the student’s own
purposes without treating the student as a mere pupil; nor teach what he
thinks will not be useful to a student without becoming a mere pedant;
nor declare indifference to how a student uses what is taught without
ceasing to be a benefactor. The teacher, as such, is always trying to help
the student do something the student could not otherwise do. A teacher
is always co-conspirator in the student’s plans, however little of the details
the teacher knows.
Character therefore limits what we can teach (as well as what we will
teach). We cannot (literally) teach what we think it wrong to use. For
example, a teacher of burglary would have to think knowing how to burgle
is itself good for the student. A criminal might well think that. Knowing
how to burgle gives options the student would not otherwise have. The
student will now be able to supplement earnings in a way she could not
otherwise. For the criminal teacher, then, seeing the skills that were taught
put to such a use should be a source of pride. Such use shows the
teachers has done the job well.
If, however, the teacher is a morally decent person, he cannot think in
this way. A morally decent person cannot view helping someone become
a criminal (or helping him commit new crimes) as benefiting him. Helping
someone become a criminal is – except under the most unusual
circumstances – corrupting him. A morally decent person could, of course,
teach skills useful to a burglar – but only as part of teaching something
other than burglary, for example, a course for homeowners in how to
protect against burglars.
A morally decent person also cannot teach burglary as a “mere means.”
No one can. Means are always means to something. Part of being a teacher
is taking an interest in the ends one’s student is pursuing, for the means
should be appropriate to those ends. Students who cannot benefit from
what is being taught, even if only by way of simple edification or harmless
diversion, cannot strictly speaking be taught, although they might still be
trained or indoctrinated. So, for morally decent people, teaching burglary
as such (or not caring what they teach) can only be teaching with scare
quotes, teaching’s counterfeit.
We can now understand why a teacher properly feels shame when a
186
A MORAL PROBLEM TEACHING PRACTICAL ETHICS
student misuses what was taught. Shame is proper when we fall short of
what we should be, when we are weak when we should be strong, foolish
when we should be wise. While the teacher is not responsible for what
the student did, he can recognize their own failure in what the latter did.
He can see that he did not do his job as well as he should have. He may,
for example, have harmed the student by unintentionally helping her to
get into trouble. Doing that may, under the circumstances, have been
excusable; perhaps only a brilliant teacher would have done better. The
failure is none the less a cause for shame. We do not need excuses where
we have been as good as we should be.
The shame the teacher feels may be moral, but it need not be. Shame
is still appropriate where the failing is one of technical skill or knowledge;
where, for example, we have simply not shown as much insight as a good
teacher would. We are not necessarily criminals because our students
turn to crime. We must none the less view ourselves as failures insofar as
they use what we taught them to commit crimes. A better teacher would
have withheld the knowledge, skill, judgment, or understanding to prevent
its misuse, or found a way to help the student see how it should be used,
or refused to be that student’s teacher.
If (as I have argued) my responsibilities as a teacher include providing
my student with what we can both recognize as benefits, it may seem that
we have a solution to our problem: I cannot morally offer myself as a
teacher while withholding knowledge, skill, judgment, or understanding
(relevant to the course of study) for any reason but the student’s good.
To “teach” what I do not think will help a student, especially if I teach it in
place of what will help, is, strictly speaking, not teaching at all but its
perversion. It is a perversion of teaching even if I do it to be just to others
or to benefit society overall. By offering myself as a teacher, I invite my
students to believe I intend to benefit them. If, lacking that intention, I still
offer to teach them, I deliberately mislead them. I merely pretend to be
their teacher.
Though this argument may seem decisive, it is not. We all recognize
certain limits on what a teacher must reveal in class, however relevant to
the course and useful to the student. For example, we expect the teacher
to respect the privacy of others. (Indeed we expect the teacher to respect
his own privacy also.) Insofar as we believe our teachers to be morally
decent persons, we, as morally decent persons ourselves, understand
that there are limits on what they can properly do in teaching (beyond the
187
A MORAL PROBLEM TEACHING PRACTICAL ETHICS
188
A MORAL PROBLEM TEACHING PRACTICAL ETHICS
189
A MORAL PROBLEM TEACHING PRACTICAL ETHICS
190
A MORAL PROBLEM TEACHING PRACTICAL ETHICS
191
A MORAL PROBLEM TEACHING PRACTICAL ETHICS
192
A MORAL PROBLEM TEACHING PRACTICAL ETHICS
Conclusion
We can now understand what is wrong with the maxim formulated early
on; and what made the objection resting on it seem so powerful. The
choice is not (as the objection requires) between (a) serving my students
even when, by doing so, I help to shift moral burdens to strangers and
make society a somewhat worse place overall and (b) protecting society
at my students’ expense. In this world, I never face that choice. Since I,
like other teachers, am fallible, the choice I in fact face is whether to teach
a student what I know even when I believe doing so will have bad effects.
I am prepared to say that I should teach what will benefit my students
even at the risk of putting others at a disadvantage or making society as
a whole worse off. Indeed, I am willing to allow all teachers to do that. I am,
in short, willing to rely on the division of moral labor, imperfect though it
is, rather than take on myself responsibility for setting things right. I have
no reason to believe that, working alone and in the dark, I would do better
than others have, working together in relatively good light. I am unwilling
to pretend to more knowledge than I have.
193
A MORAL PROBLEM TEACHING PRACTICAL ETHICS
194
10
SEX AND THE
UNIVERSITY
195
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
“gender politics.”2 What I shall argue here is that this reassignment is not
helpful, that the questions gathered into that large category will be easier
to resolve if redistributed to their former homes and dealt with there one at
a time. Questions of sexual ethics have much less in common than a
common category suggests.
Insofar as questions of sexual ethics do not have much in common,
any survey of them must be a ramble. I shall try to keep from rambling too
much both by only sampling the questions and by imposing a rough
order. I shall begin by placing today’s questions in historical context,
then deal with them in three clumps: (1) questions of sexual equality, (2)
questions of sexuality, and (3) questions of sexual identity. Throughout I
shall be on the lookout for help formulating a response to my student’s
use of “broad.”
196
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
The belief that sex does not, or at least should not, matter much in the
university may also seem out of keeping with what I said in Chapter 2.
After all, Chapter 2 argued that while scholars as such may be without
race or history, the humans who people any university are not. But, just
as each scholar arrives at the university with an historically determined
race, including complicated attitudes toward members of that race and
others, so each arrives with a body of determinate sex, with views, habits,
and expectations about physical contact between that body and others,
and (generally) with a strong interest in such contact. Indeed, to compare
sex to race as I just have is to understate the importance of sex. We
recognize race as a social construction. We can imagine a day when race
no longer matters. We may even be able to identify societies present or
past in which race does not, or did not, matter. However, we know of no
society in which sex does not, or did not, matter. Sex, if not itself a vocation,
is much more than a mere socially constructed inconvenience for
education.4 A university that does not take account of sex merely closes
its eyes to danger.
Universities have, I think, never done that. They have, however,
responded to sex in different ways at different times. Until the nineteenth
century, universities generally excluded women from their classrooms.
This helped to make the classroom relatively “sex free.” Those universities
providing residences for students could also exclude women from much
of the rest of a student’s life, even forbidding a student to marry before
graduation. Those universities not providing residences might seek to
regulate student conduct “in town” or simply leave such regulation to the
civil magistrate.5
Until the nineteenth century, the university’s regulation of relations
between the sexes was part of a larger ascetic discipline, especially in the
United States. Students might also be forbidden to play ball, to drink
alcoholic beverages, to form secret societies, or to read outside the
curriculum. They might be required to follow a set schedule, rising every
morning at a certain hour, going together to chapel for prayers, taking
breakfast together, going to class together, and so on until “lights out.”
That discipline slowly crumbled during the nineteenth century. In the
United States, universities let in sports, converted the forbidden “secret
societies” into social fraternities, scheduled parties, allowed students to
drink, and even yielded to students control over what, when, and how
they studied.
Letting women into the classroom may seem a natural part of this
general loosening up, but it was something more. Much of the loosening
197
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
198
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
Perhaps the most basic question of sexual ethics under discussion today,
though certainly not the most important, is the status of the remaining
sexually segregated universities. Recently, the United States Supreme
Court forced Virginia to allow women into state-supported military college.
One interpretation of the Court’s decision is that sexually segregated
schools are, like racially segregated schools, inherently unequal in a society
where those excluded are also those rare in positions of power.7 That
interpretation assumes, probably correctly, that a university is a place not
only of education but to make the social contacts that give one a head
start in life. Because women are not generally in positions of power, the
contacts made in a women’s college (largely with other women) tend to be
less useful in life than similar contacts made with men. Women may
individually choose to give up the advantage of being educated with men
for many reasons, but (if otherwise qualified) they should not be forced to
give it up. So (the argument runs), an exclusively women’s university
might be morally permissible, if the women there have chosen to give up
the head start they would have acquired had they gone to a co-educational
university, but an exclusively men’s university would not be, since it
denies women the head start they might otherwise get there.
This rationale for sexual integration raises serious questions about
the moral permissibility of much sexual segregation remaining in
universities. Consider, for example, the exclusively male dormitory or
fraternity (where residence or membership is entirely voluntary). Dormitories
and fraternities are, beside residences, places to make contacts that could
give one a head start in life. While dormitories seldom stress this advantage
199
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
200
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
they may think bought at too high a price. As with paternalism generally,
so here: there is (a) a set of empirical claims about benefits and burdens,
(b) an evaluative claim about what it would be rational to choose, and (c)
a moral claim about the permissibility of making that choice for an unwilling
rational agent. The paternalistic argument fails if the needed empirical
claims cannot be proved (or at least made plausible enough), or if the
evaluative claim is controversial, or if the person to be treated
paternalistically does not fit any of the categories permitting such treatment.
Interestingly, the paternalist defense of sexual segregation we are
now considering seems to fail in all three ways. Consider, first, just one of
the empirical claims on which the defense sometimes relies. Are women
living in sexually integrated dormitories or fraternities more likely to be
raped than women living in sexually segregated dorms or sororities, less
likely to be, or just as likely to be? I know of no empirical study answering
that question. Is the claimed safety none the less plausible? Yes, but no
more plausible than the opposite. Even if women were, for the reason
given, less likely to be raped in their residence if men cannot reside there,
the absence of men in the residence may still lead women to go elsewhere
to meet men, places less safe than a sexually integrated dormitory or
fraternity, making the overall risk of rape higher rather than lower.
Consider, next, the question of how to balance the risks and benefits.
Does reason require the choice that paternalism would force on an unwilling
woman? It seems not. True, reason requires that, all else being equal, a
woman (or man) not risk being raped. But all else may not be equal if the
cost of avoiding the risk is a cramped social life, putting off until later
learning how to avoid rape in one’s residence, or just reduced opportunity
to learn how men act when they are at home rather than on a date. A
woman might, it seems, rationally choose to risk rape to avoid such costs.
Last, consider whether the woman in question belongs to a category
allowing others, those knowing what is best for her, to pre-empt her
choosing otherwise. Why, in other words, not just give the information to
the woman in question and let her decide for herself? To answer that
question, the paternalist must claim (a) that the woman is not mature
enough to make the decision, or (b) that she is not (and cannot reasonably
be made) well-informed enough to make the decision, or (c) that she is in
some other way unfit to make the decision on her own (for example,
because the decision requires coordination that individuals cannot manage
201
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
202
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
Second is fairness. If women were allowed to try out for the men’s
teams, then men should be allowed to try out for the women’s teams. But,
in some sports, such as basketball (where height is important) or football
(where sheer mass is), allowing men to try out for the “women’s team”
might well mean the end of women on the “women’s team.” Such problems
might be resolved by sex-neutral regulations, for example, a height limit in
“women’s basketball” or weight limit in “women’s football” (as we now
have weight limits for wrestling and boxing). Having such limits might
have a different effect, however. If, as is widely believed, women of the
same height and weight as men do not perform as well in most sports
because they lack the (sexually related) upper body strength of men,
setting weight and height limits might simply give men of oriental or
Mediterranean ancestry something like an equal chance to play basketball
or football, something they do not now have because they are, on average,
so much smaller than the blacks and blonds who dominate those sports.
Women might still find themselves largely excluded. We would then have
two integrationist options.
One is simply to let the chips fall where they may (as we now do for
height in basketball or weight in football). Women may compete with men
in any intercollegiate sport, but if they fail to make the team, so be it. The
resulting segregation, if any, would be de facto but not de jure.
The other integrationist option is to abolish the scarcity of
intercollegiate spaces so that everyone who wants to play a certain
intercollegiate sport can. One way to do that is to have a series of graded
teams (much as some schools have several bands): a “varsity team” (with
the best players), a “B team” (for players not good enough for the A
team), a “C team” (for players not good enough for the B team), and so on
until everyone who wants to play that sport on an intercollegiate team
can. The varsity team might turn out to be all male, but need not. The B, C,
or D team might turn out to be all female, but need not. Again, any resulting
segregation would be merely de facto.
One objection to multiplying teams in this way is easily disposed of.
The objection is that such multiplication is too expensive. The obvious
response is that it need cost nothing. It only requires spreading the same
amount of money over more teams, ending support of less popular sports,
or both. There are at least two reasons why the fact that universities
might be forced to cut the budget of relatively rich teams or end support
of relatively less popular sports cannot provide an argument against this
203
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
204
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
example, for one boy to hit another, even if the one hit is smaller, is at
worst “bullying”; for the same boy to hit a girl is much worse, even if she
is bigger: it is “unmanly.” To ask men so raised to compete against women
is to give the women an unfair advantage. So, for example, a “real man”
cannot tackle a woman with the same assurance he would another man.
He must “pull his punches” or appear unchivalrous (to himself if not to
the world). There is a corresponding problem about women on one’s own
team. A “real man” would not feel right putting a woman where she could
be hurt; he would feel called upon to do things to protect her that he
would not feel called upon to do for a male teammate.
Of course, the premise of the argument from chivalry is a pair of sex
roles the movement for women’s equality has been trying to end. So, the
obvious response is, “Too bad if men are at a disadvantage; it’s about
time they learned to treat women as their equals.” But, though obvious,
the response is not altogether satisfactory. On the one hand, we recognize
that football, basketball, or indeed almost any sport would suffer if men
treated chivalrously the women on their own team or those competing
against them. On the other hand, we also recognize athletic chivalry as an
expression of decency, however misguided. We do not, all else equal,
want people to act in ways they consider unchivalrous; we do not want
them to violate their own integrity. So, we have some reason to segregate
women, if only to preserve the excellence of the sport and the integrity of
those who play it.
If we consider athletics, even varsity sports, unimportant, we will
assign the argument from chivalry little weight and have no trouble putting
women on previously all-male teams, forcing the males to be unchivalrous,
redefine their notions of chivalry, or leave the team. That the sport will
suffer for a time, or forever, will not deter us. If, however, we consider
athletics important as such, we are likely to prefer, for now at least, sexually
segregated teams. Are athletics important? Does it matter whether a team
wins or not, just so long as everyone has fun? Because I am of the “fun
school” of athletics, I am regularly surprised to hear students,
administrators, alumni, and even some faculty talk about this or that team
as if it were the university’s equivalent of a nation’s military, an entity
upon the success of which much depends. I am less surprised, and more
impressed, by those whose concern is aesthetic, not winning but breaking
records or some other form of excellence. For them, basketball, football,
tennis, and so on are arts. To let just anyone play varsity sports would be
like letting just anyone exhibit her paintings in an art museum. To force
205
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
good players into situations where they cannot play well would be like
forcing great artists to paint blindfolded and then exhibit the results beside
their best work.
Here, then, the question of sexual segregation within the university
merges into another question, one long debated in the United States; the
role of athletics in the university.10 Because that question is beyond the
subject of this chapter, we must leave it for other questions of sexual
ethics.
Sexuality
206
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
Since insurance is a gamble, those who can easily control the risks insured
against are most likely to win, that is, to pay less in premiums than they
take out in benefits; or, at least, to take out proportionately more in benefits.
Those who cannot control the risks are more likely to lose. Federal law
forbids insurance companies to take sex into account when setting
premiums. Two people, differing only in sex, must pay the same premium.
So, unless we assume that copulation is, like driving a car or playing
sports, “normal risk-taking” – that is, risky behavior we cannot reasonably
expect people to forgo – extending health insurance coverage to birth
control and abortion unfairly burdens male students. Men have no special
health needs corresponding to birth control or abortion.11
This question of fairness has, however, had nothing to do with
controversy over extending health insurance coverage to birth control or
abortion. That may be because insurance rates for students are relatively
low, birth control is cheap (so whether a woman is covered for it or not is
not a great matter), and abortions among students are rare enough and
cheap enough not to have much effect on the cost of insurance. The
controversy over such coverage has, instead, simply reflected wider social
debates. So, for example, Catholic universities have a religious commitment
making abortion seem the moral equivalent of murder. For them, the
question of abortion coverage is primarily one of complicity in moral
wrongdoing of the most serious sort. Naturally, they choose not to be
implicated, leaving their students to find coverage for abortion under
their parent’s policy, to avoid the need for abortion, or to find the few
hundred dollars an abortion would cost.
For similar but less decisive reasons, Catholic universities (and those
with similar views about copulation) are not inclined to cover birth control.
They have, however, no such compunctions about covering the costs
associated with childbirth. They do not even have compunctions about
covering those costs when the birth occurs outside marriage. That seems
significant. For the purposes of insurance, at least, even Catholic
universities now seem to view copulation, whether within marriage or
outside, as normal risk-taking, though their principles still say something
else. Even Catholic universities no longer expect students to live like
nuns or monks. We are a long way from the ascetic ideal of earlier centuries.
Student medical care is likely to generate many of the same questions
as student health insurance. For example, should universities provide
abortions or even abortion counseling at the student health service?
207
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
Such questions invite no new arguments; but others do. Consider, for
example, whether the university’s health service should have enough
female doctors on staff so that every woman who wants a doctor of her
own sex can have one. If the university did that for women, should it do
the same for men, assuring that every man who wants a male doctor can
have one? Providing every woman who wants a female doctor with one
may seem like a return to sexual segregation of the sort discussed in the
last section. I do not think it is.
Why would a woman want a female doctor? One reason may be
modesty, especially now that there are enough female doctors that a
woman might grow up without having a male doctor. A woman may feel
more comfortable having another woman examine her body than having a
strange man do it. Certainly many male students feel that way about a
female doctor examining them (in part, no doubt, because they have had
no earlier experience of a woman examining them in that way). The other
reason for providing a female doctor for those who want one – the more
important, I think – is that a female doctor is (it is thought) more likely to
understand the special medical problems of a woman better than a male
doctor. A male doctor knows the problems from the outside; a female
doctor knows them from the inside as well. Male doctors may not
appreciate the sensitivity of specifically female organs, causing more
discomfort than an otherwise similarly qualified woman would, and so on.
While the facts are probably less clear than these two arguments
require, and may change as women become a larger part of the medical
profession and medical education itself changes, what is important now
is that these two arguments are (a) unconnected with the power arguments
discussed in the last section, (b) nearly parallel for men and women, and
(c) not such as to require segregation de jure (though allowing students
to choose doctors by sex might produce segregation de facto). They are
merely arguments for trying to accommodate the demand for the most
appropriate doctor. These arguments would, no doubt, have little appeal
where accommodating demand would disadvantage female doctors, a
group we suppose already to be relatively disadvantaged. But, given the
proportion of women to men in most universities, and the proportion of
female to male doctors, accommodating the demand for doctors of one’s
own sex is likely to increase the demand for the underrepresented sex in
208
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
medicine, thus contributing to equality between the sexes rather than (as
with sexual segregation in the last section) working against it.
Though students are by far the largest part of the university, they are
not the only part. As well as students, there are faculty and staff. Faculty
and staff are employees. In the United States, health insurance normally
comes through one’s employer. Universities therefore have to make
decisions about employee health insurance similar to those they have to
make for student health insurance. They also have to decide at least one
question student insurance has not yet raised, although it can; that is, the
question of recognizing the enduring but not legally recognized sexual
partners of the primary insured, for example, by granting the same
dependent health benefits to such partners as are currently granted to a
legal spouse.
Until well into this century, most universities, especially in the United
States, would have had little trouble with this question, should anyone
have thought to raise it. Sex inside marriage was all right; sex outside was
not. Living with someone in the manner of husband and wife but without
legal sanction was “living in sin,” a scandal. Providing benefits to the
other partner in such circumstances would have meant condoning “an
affair.” No university could do that. Indeed, the standard response of a
university to an affair would have been to fire the faculty or staff member
involved for “moral turpitude.” Even tenure was no defense.
Today few universities seek to prevent all copulation outside marriage.
Some universities try to be neutral on the sexual conduct of their staff,
faculty, and students and leave to the criminal law and public opinion the
enforcement of today’s standards of sexual conduct, standards which are
now much different from those of even a half century ago. But mere
neutrality is difficult. For example, in the United States, universities receiving
federal money must have a policy for dealing with sexual harassment. The
law forbids simple neutrality (while also forbidding any distinction in
treatment based merely on sex). Everywhere public opinion still demands
that the university do something about certain forms of sexual conduct
(though the conduct in question has changed somewhat over the years).
Some universities have responded by re-enacting parts of the criminal
law. For example, IIT explicitly prohibits “harassment and/or hazing in all
forms.” It then defines harassment in terms of battery or assault: “striking,
laying hands upon, intimidation, threatening with violence, or offering to
do bodily harm to another person.”12 Taken literally, the policy would
prohibit not only many forms of sexual harassment, including some too
209
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
210
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
have sex with me?’ is not enough.”16 The policy is entirely neutral
concerning what sexual acts are agreed to. While the policy has been
mocked for intellectualizing sex, that is actually its strength.17 It discourages
the brute groping that constitutes so much of sexuality, rewarding instead
articulate agreement and the reflection necessary to achieve it. What
institution, except the university, puts as much of life as possible into
words, formulas, and other linguistic entities, even when doing so has no
practical result beyond the pleasure of doing it well? Antioch’s policy
tries to bring sex into the university on the university’s terms.
What effect such a policy will have on conduct remains to be seen.
For now, the policy’s appeal is its intentions, not its actual consequences.
Indeed, if interpreted too strictly, the policy has some strange
consequences. For example, suppose that I want to ask you for a date.
Asking for a date is sexual conduct in a relatively straightforward, if
preliminary, sense. (If this seems a stretch, you need only suppose that
we are of the same sex to see how sexual my asking you for a date is.) So,
presumably, I should, under the Antioch policy, have your explicit consent
to ask such a question before I ask you for a date. But I cannot simply ask
consent to ask you a question. “May I ask you a question?” is not specific
enough. It gives no hint that sexual conduct is to follow. Yet, if I ask,
“May I ask you a sexual question?” I have already asked a sexual question.
Hence, I have already engaged in sexual conduct without consent; and I
cannot avoid doing so, except by staying off the subject of sex altogether.
That is certainly not what Antioch intends.
Antioch might avoid this paradoxical consequence by distinguishing
between “conduct” and “mere words.” That would be a mistake. The
distinction between conduct and mere words seems even more difficult to
make for sexual conduct than for other conduct. Much sexual harassment
consists of nothing but words. The only sensible way to avoid the paradox
is, I think, to interpret the policy as assuming certain “ground level”
sexual questions which, by definition, are not offensive, however offensive
they may sometimes be (for example, “May I ask you a sexual question?”).
A “no” might be understood to forbid a similar question for a certain time
– a week, a month, or forever – or until there is an explicit invitation.
Antioch’s sexual offense policy may seem to answer a number of
related questions about sexual conduct, for example, whether sexual
relations between a faculty member and a student are permissible, whether
211
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
She, not the faculty member, was the prime mover in the sexual relation.
For her, seducing faculty was a way of giving herself the confidence to
“presume she had something to say worth saying.”19 So, it seems, some
copulating between faculty and students might serve education. Here,
perhaps, is the place to recall those relations, praised in Plato’s Symposium,
in which a youth pairs up with an older man. The youth learns what the
man has to teach, mostly about matters unrelated to sex; in return, the
man finds “love,” whether a mere sexual outlet, a divine passion, or an
enduring friendship. Whether either youth or man exploits the other
depends on the particular relationship, not on any general feature. The
same may be true of Gallop’s causal sex with her teachers.
Such relationships within a university are none the less troubling for
at least two reasons. The first is that the student has already entered into
the teacher–student relationship when, having paid the fees, he signs up
for the class. From that moment, as argued in Chapter 9, the teacher has an
obligation to try to benefit the student. The student does not owe his
teacher anything in return (apart from fulfilling the requirements of the
course), and certainly not a sexual relation. Plato’s bargain is foreclosed.
212
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
The Platonic analogy therefore identifies the problem with the relationship,
even as it helps us to understand its good side. The problem is that the
student–teacher relation is a general feature of such sexual relationships.
Any justification of them must take that into account.
We have reached the fundamental objection to even the sexual
relationships Gallop describes. The faculty of a university are never just
teachers; they are also administrators. They must apportion their time
between a number of students, must treat each student fairly, and judge
each, embodying that judgment in a final grade affecting both the student
in question and all those in competition with her. Are there any faculty
who could copulate (or even have a “less serious” sexual relation) with a
student and still treat her with the same impartiality as other students? A
few perhaps, those with the passions of a lizard, but even they could not
prove their impartiality to those who, knowing their own passions, doubt
that anyone else could be so different. Even the cold-blooded few cannot
avoid a well-founded suspicion of their impartiality. So, a faculty member
who has sexual relations with a student cannot serve the university or the
students as they are supposed to serve them. The fundamental problem
with the relationship is just what it would be if the student were not the
faculty member’s sex partner but his father or daughter: conflict of interest.
We can often avoid conflicts of interest. When we can, we should, if
the cost is not too high. Avoiding sexual relations with students in our
classes costs us relatively little. Avoiding all sexual relations with students
in our university costs us more, especially if the university is distant from
any substantial town and we are young and single. Avoiding all sexual
relations with anyone who might some day be a student costs more still.
Few of us are good at guessing the future. So, the only (morally permissible)
way to be sure that no sex partner of ours will ever become one of our
students is to have no sex partners.20
One alternative to this absolute ban on sex is to make it clear in
advance – Antioch style – that the sexual relation will foreclose the normal
classroom relation. The best way to make that clear is a university
regulation announced loudly and often. Leaving it to individual faculty to
adopt such a policy has many risks. If the faculty member waits to announce
the policy until the sexual relation has begun, she denies the student the
opportunity to choose to have the faculty member as a teacher rather
than as a sexual partner. And, of course, waiting until the student shows
up in class is worse yet; it may force the student into a last-minute scramble
for a substitute course, deny her a course she needs for graduation, or
213
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
otherwise harm her.21 When a former sexual partner turns up in class even
though we told her about the conflict of interest before the sexual relation
began, we can still escape the threat to judgment by getting the student
to transfer to another class or, when transfer is impossible or would harm
the student, by having a colleague do the grading for that student.
Because this alternative is not altogether satisfactory, some may think
the best policy is simply to prohibit faculty to have sexual relations with
students in their university, whether the student is enrolled in their class
or not. This flat prohibition, though of course preferable to a total ban on
sex, is, I think, none the less both unwise in practice and unjustified in
principle.
The flat prohibition is unwise because it demands too much of faculty
who are also human beings living in a society in which sexual relations
seem to be relatively central to life. In most universities, especially those
in small towns, most of the potential sexual partners of most faculty,
especially younger faculty, are students. A flat prohibition is likely to be
breached often enough to come into disrepute.
The flat prohibition is also unjustified. The prohibition’s purpose,
preserving the impartiality of faculty judgment, can be achieved about as
well merely by prohibiting faculty to have a sexual relation with a present
student or to take a former sexual partner as a student. Indeed, this more
limited prohibition is extensive enough to prevent even the appearance
that a faculty member has used the power to grade to force a student into
a sexual relation. The prohibition none the less leaves faculty and students
relatively free to interact in ways that, as Gallop reminds us, are not
necessarily bad for students or faculty. A prohibition limited to one’s own
students does not impose an unreasonable burden on faculty.
Sexual identity
214
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
215
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
216
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
217
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
still predominated in the canon, would not the women having voted more
or less as the men did vouch for that predominance? Do we worry about
the outcome when we trust the procedure?
Since the canon is set by university faculty, underlying the dispute
about the canon’s representativeness may be questions about hiring,
promotion, and tenure of female faculty. Clearly, even today women are
decidedly in the minority among faculty. Are they therefore
underrepresented (because there are improper obstacles to their becoming
more numerous)? Or adequately represented (because their number is the
result of a fair procedure)? Or even overrepresented (because even their
small number is the result of procedures unfairly rigged against men)?
The assumption today – and it is, I think, still not much more than that –
is that women are underrepresented, that under fair conditions women
would constitute about half the faculty in every department at every rank.
The problem is to identify the conditions that have brought about the
underrepresentation and rectify them.
Yet, even assuming underrepresentation, there is much room for
disagreement concerning both the cause of underrepresentation and the
moral permissibility of the means of rectification. For example, some might
argue that tenure policies are inherently unfair to women because they
emphasize publication over teaching, and women, more interested in caring
relationships than men, naturally prefer to teach rather than publish. Others
might explain women’s relative lack of publications as a byproduct of the
distribution of responsibilities in the wider society. Because women have
a larger part in the care of children and aged parents, they often cannot
devote as much time to research and writing as can otherwise similarly
qualified men.
Those two analyses, while attributing the dearth of tenured women to
their lack of publications, disagree on the cause of that dearth. Agreeing
on the cause will, however, not foreclose disagreement on the means of
rectification. One way to rectify the dearth of tenured women may be to
grant women publication handicaps so that men and women in the
university have an equal chance of tenure. However, such handicaps
require taking into account sexual identity rather than the actual domestic
burdens under which the scholar operates. That may seem unfair even to
some who agree that unfair distribution of domestic burdens causes
“underpublication” and underpublication causes underrepresentation.
Another way to rectify the dearth of tenured women is to treat the sexes
218
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
I divided the category of sexual ethics into three parts – sexual equality,
sexuality, and sexual identity – primarily for coherence of exposition. As
should be clear by now, the differences between problems grouped
together in any of these subdivisions can be as great as differences
between problems in one subdivision and another. My purpose
throughout was in part to make clear how diverse the problems assigned
to the category of sexual ethics can be. In part, too, my purpose was to
show how little guidance understanding any of the large problems so
assigned would give in dealing with the student comment with which I
began this chapter. Like many problems now assigned to the category of
sexual ethics, this one has more to do with teaching than with sex. Let me
make that point by completing my story.
As I looked over the class, I was pretty sure that “broad” did not
offend the women there, or even surprise them. They certainly did not
219
SEX AND THE UNIVERSITY
look offended or surprised, and after three or four years at IIT, where they
constituted a relatively small minority (about 20 percent of students),
they should, I thought, be “battle hardened.”
What was chiefly wrong with my student’s use of “broad,” I thought,
was that it was his way of distancing himself from Cecily’s position. He
might not be able to dismiss her concerns so easily if he thought of her as
an engineer, that is, as a member of a profession bound by a code of
ethics. After all, he too was an engineer. So, my initial response was,
“That’s no broad, that’s an engineer.” He looked a bit shaken, but didn’t
respond. I had intended to add something about the origin of “broad”
(pregnant cow). Giving the origin of a word often makes students more
careful in their use of it. But before I could slip into that digression,
another student broke in, taking discussion in another direction. We never
got back to “broad.”
Until near the end of the class hour, I thought my response had failed.
Then the student, long silent, announced that he had changed his mind:
Cecily was doing what an engineer with her opinion should do; the manager
should respect her judgment, but he should also “shop around” for another
engineer to sign off on the revised assessment.25 I heard nothing more of
“broad” that semester.
By responding to the student’s thoughtlessness, his failure to think
of Cecily as an engineer, I also responded to the question of sexual ethics
that thoughtlessness seemed to raise. I believe that most practical questions
of sexual ethics in the university are best handled in some such way as
this, taking care of education and letting the sex take care of itself; or, at
least, are best so handled when the standard in question is more or less
settled. Where the standard is not yet settled, we should continue the
discussion, treating our disagreements about ethics as we should treat
other academic disagreements, that is, as disputes about arguments,
evidence, and procedure. We should take most care to remain civil with
those we think most confused or ignorant, to assume mistake rather than
malice – as I have tried to do throughout this book.
220
NOTES
Early versions of this chapter were presented to the Chicago Chapter of the
America Society for Public Administration, 22 June 1989; the Western Michigan
Chapter of the American Society of Fund Raising Executives, Grand Rapids, 21
September 1989; the Southwestern Section of the Michigan Society of Professional
Engineers, Kalamazoo, 3 October 1989; and the Center for Ethics Studies,
Marquette University, Milwaukee, Wisconsin, 27 October 1989. I should like to
thank those present, and my colleagues at IIT, especially, Sohair ElBaz and Jing
Li, for helping me to fit the pieces together.
1. The first recorded use of “medical ethics” in this sense (or any other) seems to
be the title of Thomas Percival’s 1803 text, Medical Ethics.
2. I give priority to the very successful Samuel Gorovitz et al. (eds), Moral
Problems in Medicine, Englewood Cliffs, N.J., Prentice, 1976. But, in fairness,
I should mention two other texts that appeared the same year: another
philosophical anthology, James M. Humber and Robert F. Almeder (eds),
Biomedical Ethics and the Law, New York, Plenum P., 1976; and a survey by
Howard Brody, Ethical Decisions in Medicine, Boston, Little, 1976. Several
more texts appeared the following year. Medical ethics had come of age.
3. See, for example, the famous exchange beginning with Monroe Freedman,
“Professional Responsibility of the Criminal Defense Lawyer,” Michigan
Law Review, 1966, vol. 64, pp. 1,469–84. The philosophically sophisticated
literature – much of it the work of philosopher-lawyers – was only beginning
to appear the year I first taught legal ethics. See, for example, Richard
Wasserstrom, “Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues,” Human Right,
1975, vol. 5, pp. 1–24.
4. The best of these, Vern Countryman and Ted Finman (eds), The Lawyer in
Modern Society, Boston, Little, 1966, begins with the observation that “law
teaching focuses on law almost to the exclusion of the lawyer.” I used instead
Maynard E. Pirsig (ed.), Professional Responsibility, St. Paul, West, 1970 – a
text going back to 1949 – because it had been revised for the new code. None
221
NOTES
222
NOTES
223
NOTES
224
NOTES
225
NOTES
226
NOTES
3. Having equated ethics both with the study of morality (“critical morality”)
and with morality itself (note the parentheses containing “or morals”), Ladd
can only contrast law’s imposition of standards with morality’s “discovery”
of standards by “argument and persuasion.” (Moral standards, being universal,
can only be discovered.) Ladd wholly misses the possibility of local (morally
binding) standards that can be “recreated, changed, or rescinded” through
“argument and persuasion.” Ladd has, in other words, ruled out professional
or applied ethics as it seems to have developed rather than argued against it
possibility.
42. See, for example, entry 3c under “ethics” in The Oxford English Dictionary
(1933): “The rules of conduct recognized in certain associations or departments
of human life.” Though the first example under this definition is 1789
(Bentham’s distinction between “private ethics” and the “art of legislation”),
the first use in the sense of local rules is 1864; the first involving a profession
is 1884 (from Australia!): “Ethics, medical, the laws of the duties of medical
men to the public, to each other, and to themselves in regard to the exercise of
their profession.” Curiously, there is no reference to Percival’s 1803 text.
Marcus Singer seems to have been the first philosopher to note in print this
new sense. See his “Recent Trends and Future Prospects in Ethics.”
Metaphilosophy, 1981, vol. 12, pp. 207–23. I should like to thank William
Starr for calling my attention to Singer’s paper.
227
NOTES
228
NOTES
Tenured Radicals: How Politics Has Corrupted Our Higher Education, New
York, Harper and Row, 1990; Dinesh D’Souza, “Illiberal Education,” Atlantic
Monthly, 1991, vol. 267, pp. 51–79; and, of course, Allan Bloom, The Closing
of the American Mind, New York, Simon and Schuster, 1987. These works,
though numerous, do not, strictly speaking, constitute a literature (hence my
scarce quotes). A literature is cumulative, participants acknowledging one
another’s work, whether to draw on it, refute it, or improve it. Usually, a
contribution to the “literature” of homily presents itself as a lone voice crying
in the desert.
7. See, for example, the exchange between two Stanford professors, Charles R:
Lawrence III, “Acknowledging the Victim’s Cry,” and Gerald Gunther,
“Freedom for the Thought We Hate,” in Academe, 1990, vol. 76, pp. 10–4.
For thoughtful defense of treating questions of academic freedom as questions
of ordinary workplace rights, see Robert Ladenson, “Is Academic Freedom
Necessary?” Law and Philosophy, 1986, vol. 5, pp. 59–87.
8. Edward Shils, The Academic Ethic: Report of a Study Group of the International
Council on the Future of the University, Chicago, University of Chicago Press,
1983. Among important examples of earlier work in this category, I would
put the following: Academic Freedom: The Scholar’s Place in Modern Society,
Hans Baade and Robinson Everett (eds), Dobbs Ferry, N.Y., Oceana
Publications, 1964; Academic Freedom and Tenure: A Handbook of the
American Association of University Professors, Louis Joughin (ed.), Madison,
WI, University of Wisconsin Press, 1969, especially the essays collected at
the back; The Concept of Academic Freedom, Edmund L. Pincoffs (ed.),
Austin, TX, University of Texas Press, 1972; and many of the papers in The
Ethics of Teaching and Scientific Research, Sidney Hook, Paul Kurtz, and
Miro Todorovich (eds), Buffalo, N.Y., Prometheus Books, 1977. On the
other hand, I would not put in that category Morality, Responsibility, and the
University: Studies in Academic Ethics, Steven M. Cahn (ed.), Philadelphia,
PA: Temple University Press, 1990. Cahn the editor has made a significant
contribution to academic ethics, as I use that term here, even if Cahn the
writer has not. Much will be learned from comparing the papers in his collection
with earlier work. Other recent contributions to the still tiny literature include:
Louis G. Lombardi, “Character v. Codes: Models for Research Ethics,”
International Journal of Applied Philosophy, 1990, vol. 5, pp. 21–8; John
Martin Rich, Professional Ethics in Education, Springfield, I.L., Charles C.
Thomas, 1984; and Mary Ellen Waithe and David T. Ozar, “The Ethics of
Teaching Ethics,” Hastings Center Report, 1990, vol. 20, pp. 17–21.
9. Shils, The Academic Ethic, p. 12.
10. AAUP Policy Documents and Reports, Washington, D.C., American Association
of University Professors, 1984, pp. 135–36, reprinted from Academe, 1969,
vol. 55, pp. 86–87. Why this date for a code of ethics? Other professions that
organized about the same time as the AAUP published a code decades earlier.
11. This judgment is, however, not universal. See, for example, Page Smith, Killing
the Spirit: Higher Education in America, New York, Viking, 1990. Curiously,
thoughtful defenses of the academy (more or less) as it is are rare. One
229
NOTES
possible example, though quite old, is Carl L. Becker, “The Cornell Tradition:
Freedom and Responsibility,” in his Cornell University: Founders and the
Founding, Ithaca, N.Y., Cornell University Press, 1943, pp. 193–204. (I owe
this reference to Kevin Harrington.) The only recent defense I have found is
Mortimer R. Kadish, The Ethic of Higher Education, Palo Alto, C.A., Stanford
University Press, 1991. Kadish finds a principled place for much of what
American universities do and offers a vocabulary adequate for discussing
how much room to make for artists, poets, football players, and the like. But
even Kadish’s defense includes a sustained (and powerful) critique of recent
developments.
12. Paragraph II of the AAUP Statement (the one concerned with teaching) does
say that “[a professor] demonstrates respect for the student as an individual.”
This can be read as prohibiting Professor B’s conduct. But I think that reading
strained. Given the spirit of the Statement, the respect due to students as
individuals can only mean respect-as-individual-searchers-after-knowledge,
not respect in any sense sufficient to condemn what Professor B did. And,
indeed, the very sentence in which this reference to respect appears, continued:
“and adheres to his proper role as intellectual guide and counselor.” AAUP
Policy Documents, p. 135 (italics added).
13. Discriminary Conduct Policy: Regent Resolution, Racism and Discriminatory
Conduct,” October 1988, UMF Fac. Doc. No. 1670, Milwaukee: University
of Wisconsin, 11 January 1990, p. 1. This policy applies to faculty as well as
students. Most of the policies I have examined (Stanford, Michigan, and so
on) apply only to students. Why?
14. UW, “Discriminatory Conduct Policy,” p. 2.
15. Bernard Shaw, The Doctor’s Dilemma, Baltimore, M.D., Penquin Books,
1954, p. 40. I am, of course, rejecting something like the “separatist thesis”
defended, for example, in Benjamin Freedman, “A Meta-Ethics of Professional
Morality,” Ethics, 1978, vol. 89, pp. 1–19. Few, if any, writers on professional
ethics still think that professional status can exempt one from the requirements
of ordinary morality. For some of the reasons, see my “Moral Authority of a
Professional Code”; Alan Gewirth, “Professional Ethics: The Separatist
Thesis,” Ethics, 1986, vol. 96, pp. 282–300; or David Luban, “The Adversary
System Excuse,” in The Good Lawyer: Lawyers’ Roles and Lawyers’ Ethics,
Totowa, N.J., Rowman and Allanheld, 1984, pp. 84–113. The argument for
institutional ethics would be much the same.
16. Compare Kadish, The Ethic of Higher Education, for example, pp. 109–10
(concerned with how to respond to an incident in which two drunken fraternity
men accosted two black co-eds):
230
NOTES
This chapter began as a talk presented to Annual Spring Meeting of the Illinois
Conference, American Association of University Professors, Chicago, 1 April
1989. I should also like to thank that audience of alert academics, as well as my co-
panelist, Louis Lombardi, and my colleagues, Warren Schmaus and Vivian Weil,
for helpful comments.
1. My italics.
2. By “recent,” I mean “since 1982” (for reasons I explain in Section II below).
Perhaps it is worth pointing out that engineering has not always been separated
in this way. Consider, for example, Charles E. Reagan, Ethics for Scientific
Researchers, 2nd edn., Springfield, IL, Charles C. Thomas, 1971, in which
engineering examples do appear. Note too that, unlike his scientific examples,
his engineering examples carry citations, indicating a pre-existing literature.
That suggests yet another question I shall ask only to put aside: Why were
the engineers so far ahead of the scientists in thinking about research ethics?
3. See, for example, Russell Jacoby’s comments on David Abrahams in The Last
Intellectuals, New York, Basic Books, 1987, p. 128.
4. See, for example, “Head of College Quits under Fire: Texan’s Dissertation
Was Found to Resemble Wife’s,” New York Times, 20 April 1969, p. 64. The
historian in question, a friend of Lyndon Johnson, had just completed a term
as an undersecretary at HEW. When I checked my memory of this case, I was
surprised to learn that the Attorney General of Texas eventually ruled that
the University of Texas could not revoke his doctorate, plagiarism or no. See
“Ruling in Doctorate Dispute,” New York Times, 16 September 1969, p. 26.
5. For example, one “model” for institutional policies defines “research fraud”
as “a form of scientific misconduct involving deception.” “Scientific” is nowhere
defined. Association of American Universities, National Association of State
Universities and Land-Grant Colleges, and Council of Graduate Schools,
Framework for Institutional Policies and Procedures to Deal with Fraud in
Research (4 November 1988), p. 2
6. Note that (as defined here) research ethics is not a mere department of academic
ethics. Many researchers – perhaps half of all Ph.D.s – now work outside the
academy. Why then have we so far had no research scandals involving non-
academic researchers? Another question I ask only to put aside.
7. See, for example, Max Weber, Wissenschaft als Beruf, München, Duncker und
Humblott, 1921; Robert Merton, “The Normative Structure of Science,” in
The Sociology of Science: Theoretical and Empirical Investigations, Norman
W. Storer (ed.), Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1973, pp. 267–78;
231
NOTES
232
NOTES
Hospital rather than submit to those procedures. Belmont soon rehired him.
Harvard did not. My impression is that Harvard overreacted – in part perhaps
to compensate for earlier failures to react enough but in part too because no
one involved had a clear idea how to gauge the seriousness of Frazier’s
wrongdoing. (I owe this point to Carl Cohen.)
21. For a useful introduction to punishment theory, see my How to Make the
Punishment Fit the Crime, Boulder, CO, Westview Press, 1992.
22. Perspectives on the Professions, Chicago, Center for the Study of Ethics in
the Professions, Illinois Institute of Technology, 1989, vol. 8, pp. 4–5. That
issue also includes a paper by Dow Woodward describing a course in bioethics
he teaches in Stanford’s Biology Department. For some other examples of
courses in research ethics, see Professional Ethics Report, a Newsletter of the
American Association for the Advancement of Science, Committee on Scientific
Freedom and Responsibility, Professional Society Ethics Group, Washington,
D.C., AAUP, 1989, vol. 7, p. 7.
23. For a theoretical justification of this commonsensical claim, see my “Explaining
Wrongdoing,” Journal of Social Philosophy, 1989, vol. 20, pp. 74–90.
24. Harvard has in fact adopted such a procedure. See Paul Strohm, “Professional
Ethics and Scientific Misconduct,” Footnotes, a publication of the American
Association of University Professors, 1988, vol. 6, p. 1.
Versions of this chapter have been presented to: the Philosophy Colloquium,
Illinois Institute of Technology, 30 September 1992; the Wingspread Conference
on Knowledge and Responsibility: The Moral Role of Scientists, Racine, Wisconsin,
9 October 1992; and the Philosophy Department, Wayne State University, 19
November 1992. I should like to thank those present, especially Bruce Russell,
my commentator at Wayne, for many helpful comments. I should also like to
thank the participants in the Wingspread conference for provoking the first draft
and helping me to refine several of its successors; and to the editors of Professional
Ethics for helping to give it its penultimate form.
1. Stanley Joel Rosen and Ruth Ellen Bulger, “The Social Responsibilities of
Biological Scientists,” Science and Engineering Ethics, 1997, vol. 3, pp. 137–
44.
2. Albert H. Teich and Mark S. Frankel, Good Science and Responsible Scientists
(Washington, DC, Directorate for Science and Policy Programs, American
Association for the Advancement of Science, 1992, p. 15. “Stem” is, of
course, ambiguous. It could mean “derives,” or it could mean some weaker
relation (for example, “is made reasonable by”). Perhaps much talk that
sounds like arguments attempting to derive special moral responsibility from
what scientists are is, in fact, too loose to be counted in that category. Certainly,
many of the examples scientists give of their special responsibilities, for
example, not faking data, seem to be no more than requirements of ordinary
233
NOTES
234
NOTES
10. Lawyers and philosophers will be aware of H.L.A. Hart’s extensive discussion
of four senses of “responsibility” in Chapter IX of Punishment and
Responsibility, New York, Oxford University Press, 1968. I am here interpreting
“responsibility” in the first of Hart’s four senses (that is, as “role-
responsibility” rather than “causal-responsibility,” “liability-responsibility,”
or “capacity responsibility”). I have, however, taken for granted some
connections between these four senses: in particular, that where one has a
role-responsibility (a domain of duties or assigned tasks) for such-and-such
and one is causally responsible for an unfavorable outcome, one may have to
bear liability or blame for the outcome. For a less familiar analysis of
responsibility, but one more useful for our purposes, see Kenneth Kipnis,
“Professional Responsibility and the Responsibility of Professions,” in Profits
and Professions: Essays in Business and Professional Ethics, edited by Wade
L. Robinson, Michael Pritchard, and Joseph Ellin (Humana Press: Clifton,
N.J., 1983), pp. 9–22. Having noted that a responsibility is always a matter
of concern, he goes on to define carrying out one’s “substantive responsibility”
as “[giving] these matters all the attention they are due” (suggesting a principle
rather than a rule), p. 10. But subsequent discussion finds him very soon
talking in terms of duties, obligations, and rules. I therefore take his initial
formulation to be provisional.
11. How might we derive the rule “Parents, care for your children”? Why not
from the rule of individual responsibility (discussed under arguments from
complicity below)? “Care for your children” seems to be no more than a
special case of going out of your way to help someone when, however
inadvertently, you have put them in need of help.
12. Compare, for example, Peter Singer, “Famine, Affluence, and Morality,”
Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1972, vol. 7, pp. 229–43; Alan Gewirth, Reason
and Morality, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1978, pp. 217–30; Joel
Feinberg, “The Moral and Legal Responsibility of the Bad Samaritan,”
Criminal Justice Ethics, 1984, vol. 3, pp. 56–66; Patricia Smith, “The Duty
to Rescue and the Slippery Slope Problem,” Social Theory and Practice,
1990, vol. 16, pp. 19–41; John M. Whelan, “Charity and the Duty to Rescue,”
Social Theory and Practice, 1991, vol. 17, pp. 441–56; David Copp,
“Responsibility for Collective Inaction,” Journal of Social Philosophy, 1991,
vol. 22, pp. 71–80; and Alison McIntyre, “Guilty Bystanders? On the
Legitimacy of Duty to Rescue Statutes,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1994,
vol. 23, pp. 157–91. The equivalent rule for the Good Samaritan argument
would be something like: Go out of your way whenever, without breach of an
important duty or great loss to yourself, you can substantially help someone in
great need. As a rule, this is quite demanding. For example, given how many
needy people there are in the world, and how easily I could help them, this
rule would seem to require me to forego every luxury, sending the money so
saved to one or another philanthropic organization (and Singer actually so
argues).
13. For some idea of the dynamics of this, see my “Avoiding the Tragedy of
235
NOTES
236
NOTES
our purposes require. There are good reasons to reject the rule of individual
complicity here even in the vaguer (and therefore less demanding form) I have
given it. For more on such rules, see my “Famous Violinists, Foetuses, and
the Right to Continued Aid,” Philosophical Quarterly, 1983, vol. 33, pp.
159–78; and “Strasser on Dependence, Reliance, and Need,” Philosophical
Quarterly, 1986, vol. 36, pp. 384–91.
24. I owe this version of the argument from individual complicity to Francis
Slakey (or, rather, to my initial misunderstanding of his argument for collective
responsibility to organize as a profession discussed in the next note).
25. Francis Slakey has suggested that scientists individually might have a moral
obligation to establish an organization to prevent the misuse of the knowledge
they individually produce. This seems to be another version of the argument
from individual complicity (though one reminding me of Kant’s justification
of the state). While I think scientists have many good reasons to want such an
organization, I don’t see any reason to believe that they are morally required
to form one. This version of the argument seems even less plausible than
those allowing individuals more freedom in the choice of means to accomplish
the end in view. I have therefore felt free to dismiss it in a mere note rather
than in the text.
26. There is one important exception to this rule. Those who benefit, however
unwillingly, from a wrong may have to compensate the wronged party – with
the limit of liability being the value of the benefit in question. The theory
seems to be one of unjust enrichment rather than tort. I ignore this exception
here because I cannot see how to turn it into an argument for special
responsibility relevant to “my” case.
27. There are, however, a few exceptions to this rule (or, to save the thesis, a few
hybrids) – most notably, the American Psychological Association and the
American Institute of Chemists. These have codes of ethics, disciplinary
committees, and the like just as (other) professional societies do. They are
both technical and professional. I should perhaps add that, while a scientific
society can be professional and still be scientific (because concerned with
science as such), not all organizations of scientists are scientific societies.
Consider, for example, a mutual insurance company organized to provide life
or health insurance only to scientists; or a pension fund run for, and by,
scientists.
28. I believe this conclusion, however surprising to some, is consistent with the
way much of the its membership views the IEEE.
29. The APS’s “Guidelines for Professional Conduct” (3 November 1991) seems
instructively confused about its status. The first paragraph identifies its
audience as “Society members” and the code following as mere “guidelines”
(making the document sound like the advice a technical society would give its
members). But the third paragraph begins “Each physicist” (not “each member
of the Society”) and declares the rules following to be “minimal standards”
(even though they are stated with the “should” of principle or ideal rather
than the “shall” of rule). It even declares the standards as critical to the
“physics profession.” The Guidelines conclude, “Physicists have an individual
237
NOTES
238
NOTES
the volume’s other contributors wrote, not my response to what the other
panelists said.
3. D. Blumenthal, M. Gluck, K.S. Louis, M. Sotto, D. Wise, “University-
Industry Research Relationships in Biotechnology: Implications for the
University,” Science, 1986, vol. 232, pp. 1,361–6, at p. 1,364.
4. I am, by the way, far from being the only philosopher who thinks applied
ethics has done much for theory (and for philosophy generally). See, for
example, S. Toulmin, “How Medicine Saved the Life of Ethics,” Perspectives
in Biology and Medicine, 1982, vol. 25, pp. 736–50.
I should like to thank Herman Berg for calling my attention to his case (when he
cornered me after my session with Nader), for providing all the documents cited
in the text, for telling me what he remembered of events where no documents
existed or where they gave only an incomplete picture, for reading and commenting
on many drafts of this chapter, and correcting many errors. While he has done
enough to be listed as co-author of this chapter, I have (with his permission)
chosen to take full responsibility for what is written here so that I would be free
of the constraints of dual authorship.
1. Actually, the letter’s fame is a bit more complicated. Strictly speaking, not the
French version but an 1843 retranslation into English is famous. This first
appeared in a translation (by the Countess of Lovelace) of Menabrea’s paper
on the Analytical Engine. It was in this version that the Babbage letter became
famous. See The Works of Charles Babbage, Martin Campbell-Kelly (ed.),
New York, New York University Press, 1989, vol. 1, p. 25.
2. According to Berg, the purpose of this letter was not so much to inform HSS
of his discovery as to inquire whether the discovery merited a prize or, at
least, a letter of praise he might use to strengthen his claim that the Annals
should publish a report of it.
3. Why did Berg not simply publish his discovery elsewhere? He tried, but there
are not many journals in the history of computing. Those he wrote advised
him that the Annals was the appropriate place for a note correcting a claim
made in Van Sinderen’s article.
4. Berg always admitted that it was possible that between March 1984 and early
1989 the Quetelet letter was moved to the Royal Library (and then back to
the Royal Academy), but he could find no one who knew of such a move.
Recently J.A.N. Lee, “On ‘Babbage and Kings’ and ‘How Sausage Was Made’:
And Now the Rest of the Story,” IEEE Annals of the History of Computing,
1995, vol. 17, pp. 7–23, only added to the mystery. One Mme. Wellens-De
Donder informed him, through a third party, that the letter was in the Royal
Library from 1964 to 1985 (where Berg’s letter should have found it) and
then moved to the Royal Academy (Lee, “And Now,” pp. 15–6). Though
Berg has a document purporting to come from the Royal Academy, it must
239
NOTES
have come from the Royal Library (using Royal Academy stationery?).
5. Only three of the eleven paragraphs Berg had before him – that is, the minute’s
introductory paragraph and two concluding paragraphs – were independent
of his discovery.
6. See Campbell-Kelly, Works of Babbage, vol. 1, pp. 22–7. He has since denied
responsibility for such details (Lee, “And Now,” p. 18).
7. Berg considered the phrase in quotes to be a smoking gun. The exact words
appear in the version of Babbage’s letter Berg discovered but not in any of the
others. Since Bromley did not suggest that he had already discovered the
original letter on his own (or knew of it in some other way), that phrase
demonstrates that his first knowledge of it must have come from Berg.
8. But see Lee, “And Now,” p. 19 (Campbell-Kelly’s description of how editorial
work was done).
9. Lee, “And Now,” p. 20.
10. For a somewhat better experience with the AHA, see Stephen Nissenbaum,
“The Plagiarists in Academe Must Face Formal Sanctions,” Chronicle of
Higher Education, 28 March 1990, p. A52.
11. Out of desperation, or whimsy, Berg went even farther afield in search of a
forum, but with no more success. The International Court of Justice at the
Hague told him they had no jurisdiction (22 March 1990), as did the
International Criminal Police Organization (2 July 1992). On the assumption
that religions might be concerned with a violation of the Commandment
“thou shalt not steal,” Berg wrote a number of religious organizations. Some
did not write back. Those that did – the Rabbinical Council of America (5
November 1990), the Church of Jesus Christ of Latter-Day Saints (11 March
1991), Bob Jones, Chancellor of Bob Jones University (23 June 1992), the
Archbishop of Detroit (6 July 1992), the Archbishop of Milwaukee (23 July
1992), and even the Papacy (14 June 1991) – all declined to get involved.
12. For their own attempts to explain the silence (long after the events), see the
letters of Bromley and Campbell-Kelly in Accountability in Research, 1994,
vol. 3, pp. 282–9. While the question of motive is probably impossible to
settle on the basis of the information we have or are likely to get, it is, of
course, crucial to the amount of blame we assign in individual cases; and, for
an institution, to designing means of prevention as well. For my own articles
on the subject, see Michael Davis, “Of Babbage and Kings: A Study of a
Plagiarism Complaint,” Accountability in Research 2, Spring 1993, pp. 273–
86, and Michael Davis, “Righting the History of Mathematics,” Mathematical
Intelligencer 16, Fall 1994, pp. 21–6.
13. After I published my first article on this case, the other side began to respond
in print. Though adding many interesting details, the response is most
interesting for what it reveals about how intelligent people can back themselves
into a bad situation without realizing what they are doing. See especially Lee,
“And Now.”
14. What might that other side be? A curator at the British National Museum of
Science and Industry ends a long friendly letter to Berg (23 June 1990) with
the observation: “My knowledge of Prof. Allan Bromley, Dr. Martin
240
NOTES
Campbell-Kelly and [one more] makes it inconceivable that any one of them
would actively repress any due acknowledgement. I feel sure that there is
some simple explanation that does not impugn them and at the same time
duly puts the record straight. However, I remain handicapped by the lack of
any hard facts about the discovery.” After receiving copies of the relevant
documents, he wrote Berg again (4 November 1991): “I remain convinced
that you are a casualty of a number of factors that have combined and that
there is an explanation that does not impugn the integrity of the scholars
associated with the field.” Unfortunately, he could not say what that
explanation might be. He had to wait another four years before the principals
bothered to provide what his faith hoped for.
15. Bromley was quite explicit while explaining why he was not responsible for
failing to credit Berg (even though Bromley’s name was prominent both in the
Collected Works and in advertisements for it): the letter had been located
independently by Jim Roberts, an independent scholar in London, who knew
nothing of either Berg’s discovery or Bromley’s possession of a copy of it.
Roberts goes unacknowledged anywhere in the Collected Works, even though
he did an extensive and careful study of all the available Babbage
correspondence. Why? The reason, according to Bromley, is that it “never
crossed my mind to name the many people I knew to have seen or studied
these archives.” Lee, “And Now,” p. 18. For how this looks to another
academic, see C. Muses, “The unique reach of cybernetics in our Fin-de-
Siecle,” Kybernetes, 1995, vol. 24, no. 7, pp. 6–20, especially pp. 16–8.
16. I must admit to having little sympathy for this view. It seems to narrow the
definition of scholarly plagiarism to what can be prosecuted in court as
plagiarism (essentially, a violation of copyright). For courts, “plagiarism” is
a technical term. Much that academics might consider plagiarism (for example,
copying a method of tabulating data or using information another develops)
receives legal protection through the law of patent, trade secrets, or the, like;
or none at all. In any case, the narrow definition seems wrong as a matter both
of usage and of scholarly policy. “Plagiarism” comes (according to my
dictionary) from the Latin word for kidnapping (or plundering, especially the
taking of someone’s “slaves”). “Ideas” as well as “original words or writing”
can be plagiarized. Talk of “plagiarizing discoveries” seems to stretch ordinary
language not at all (though perhaps “plagiarizing an invention” does). More
important, in the commerce of scholarship, one’s discoveries are at least as
important as one’s writing and, as Berg’s story makes clear, just as susceptible
to being plundered (that is, used without the customary payment). Most,
perhaps all, arguments against plagiarism in the narrow sense seem to be
arguments against plagiarism in a sense broad enough to include using another’s
discovery without giving credit. The issue is not what plagiarism “is” so
much as what forms of conduct (plagiarism or not) should be subject to
formal disciplinary procedures, or at least embodied in explicit rules, and
which should be left to the less formal procedures of the research community
(as much promise breaking is).
17. This letter (18 May 1989) does not in fact refer to the Works but to Berg’s
241
NOTES
242
NOTES
5. For a good critique of the honors system, see the entire January issue of
Perspectives on the Professions, 1995, vol. 14.
6. I have said nothing about team-taught courses because they seem to me not to
get ethics into class in a way at once economical, permanent, and distinct
from those ways already discussed. In theory, team-teaching seems to be an
extended guest lecture (who the guest is depending on how the course is listed
or packaged). Having a guest around all term may solve the problem of limited
time, testing, and grading, but still seems likely to leave the impression that
professional ethics is optional. Why else would technical faculty need someone
outside the profession to teach the profession’s ethics? In practice (at IIT),
on the other hand, team-taught courses have often served the same purpose
as a workshop. Faculty teach a course together for a time. Once each has
learned enough from the other to teach on his own (a year or two), the team
dissolves. Team-teaching a particular course seldom lasts long (in part, no
doubt, because using two faculty to teach one course strikes most
administrators as inefficient).
7. See, for example, Richard A. Matasar, “Teaching Ethics in Civil Procedure
Courses,” Journal of Legal Education, 1989, vol. 39, pp. 587–607. Though
he became dean of IIT’s law school, Matasar was at the University of Iowa’s
College of Law when this article was published.
8. Chicago Tribune, February 15, 1987. But see Terrence R. Bishop, “Integrating
Business Ethics into An Undergraduate Curriculum,” Journal of Business
Ethics, 1992, vol. 11, pp. 291–9.
9. Arne P. Vesilund, “Rules, Ethics, and Morals in Engineering Education,”
Engineering Education, February 1988, vol. 77, pp. 289–93.
10. See, for example, my “Explaining Wrongdoing,” Journal of Social Philosophy,
1989, vol. 20, pp. 74–90.
11. Because even our NSF reviewers took some convincing on this point, it may
be worth quoting in full the argument we made:
243
NOTES
244
NOTES
were assigned.
16. ”Co-leader” is purposefully vague. While we had proposed a workshop in
which Vivian Weil, CSEP Director, and I would be co-leaders, she was on
leave in Washington when the first workshop was given. Patricia Werhane,
Philosophy, Loyola University of Chicago, replaced her (bringing considerable
experience with the workshops sponsored by Arthur Anderson for business
school faculty interested in teaching business ethics). The second and third
year went as originally proposed. The three workshops were otherwise so
alike that I shall ignore most differences here.
17. Michael Davis, “The Ethics Boom: What and Why?,” Centennial Review,
1990, vol. 34, pp. 163–86 (a version of chapter 1); a part of William F. May’s
“Professional Ethics: Setting, Terrain, and Teacher,” from Ethics Teaching in
Higher Education, Daniel Callahan and Sisela Bok (eds), New York: Plenum
Books, 1980, pp. 212–9.
18. See works cited above.
19. This case is a slightly revised version of the first part of “Falsifying Data?,”
from Michael Pritchard, Teaching Engineering Ethics: A Case Study Approach,
Kalamazoo, Center for the Study of Ethics in Society, Western Michigan
University, 15 June 1992, pp. 276–9, included as well in Charles E. Harris, Jr.
et al., Engineering Ethics: Concepts and Cases, Belmont, CA, Wadsworth,
1995, pp. 80–3.
20. See Chapter 8 for one version of the seven-step method.
21. Actually, this occurred only the first year. In the second and third years the
case discussion ran over and crowded out this preview.
22. Rachels, Elements, pp. 79–103 (Mill), 104–123 (Kant), and 12–24 (relativism).
After the first year, we used the second edition (1991). Rachels’ book
(whatever the edition) received many compliments.
23. This is my reconstruction of the test. Neither of my co-leaders presented it
this formally, and each gave it a somewhat different emphasis.
24. Bernard Gert, Morality: A New Justification of the Moral Rules, New York:
Oxford University Press, 1988, especially pp. 284–5 (for the two lists).
25. John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press,
1971; and David Gauthier, Morals By Agreement, Oxford, Clarendon Press,
1986.
26. Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue, Notre Dame, IN, University of Notre Dame
Press, 1984; and Lawrence C. Becker, Reciprocity, London, Routledge &
Kegan Paul, 1986.
27. Michael Davis, “Thinking like an Engineer: The Place of a Code of Ethics in
the Practice of a Profession,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1991, vol. 20,
pp. 150–67; and David Luban, “The Structure of Role Morality,” from
Lawyers and Justice, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press, 1988, pp.
128–47. The assigned reading also included a continuation of “Catalyst B.”
28. I owe this idea to Jean B. Hunter, assistant professor, Bioprocess Engineering,
Cornell University.
29. James Rest, “Can Ethics Be Taught,” Easier Said Than Done, 1988, vol. 1,
pp. 22–6; Thomas Lickona, “What Does Moral Psychology Have to Say to
245
NOTES
the Teacher of Ethics?,” from Callahan and Bok, Ethics Teaching and Higher
Education, pp. 103–32, 1980, and Davis, “Who Should Teach Workplace
Ethics?”
30. For more on these issues, see Chapter 9.
31. Caroline Whitbeck, “Teaching Ethics to Scientists and Engineers: Moral Agents
and Moral Problems,” Science and Engineering Ethics, 1995, vol 1, pp. 299–
308.
32. My “Explaining Wrongdoing,” Journal of Social Philosophy, 1989, vol. 20,
pp. 74–90; and John D. Arras, “Getting Down to Cases: The Revival of
Casuistry in Bioethics,” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 1991, vol. 16,
pp. 29–51.
33. Scheduling difficulties the first year forced us to break the group into two
parts for these later sessions (each group about eight). Each group met twice
(with some people switching from one group to another between the first and
second meeting). Since even these small groups took most of the day to make
their presentations, answer questions, and receive comments, we divided the
group in subsequent years even when there were no scheduling problems.
34. Some faculty have experimented with having students sign off on each problem.
If they sign off and the answer is right, they get a little extra credit. If the
answer is wrong, they get no credit. They are advised that, if they are not sure
they are right, they should not sign off. They will then be given partial or full
credit, as appropriate, but no extra credit. In this way, students are forced to
consider how reliable their work is. Some faculty like to tell students what
would happen in real life if they were wrong. Donald Gotterbarn, not a
workshop graduate but the one from whom I got the idea of signing off, likes
to tell his students what the effect of an error in their work would be.
35. Would we have had greater attendence at the continuing seminar the first
semester had we had someone talk about grading ethics in, say, an engineering
course? Perhaps. It would certainly have been worth a try. Unfortunately,
that idea did not occur to us the first year (and we would not have known who
could have given it). By the second year, faculty seem to have had colleagues
with whom they could discuss their worries.
36. The first year’s fifteenth official participant, the chair of Civil Engineering,
became seriously ill a week before the workshop began.
37. Question 3 similarly asked about increased knowledge; Question 5 asked
about increased ability to deal with ethical issues.
38. Compare FIN 525 (4 of 7 yes to question 1) and CE 340 (18 out of 23). The
only real exception to this favorable pattern was Applied Thermodynamics
(MAE 301). The same instructor who got a good response from his basic
Thermodynamics students (MAE 205), 15 yeses to 5 noes (with 2 neutrals)
to question 1, got only 9 yeses to 12 noes (and 1 neutral) for Applied
Thermodynamics. The instructor’s analysis of this outcome is worth quoting:
246
NOTES
8 CASE METHOD
This chapter began as a session I gave at the Rocky Mountain Workshop for
Teaching Ethics in Research, University of Wyoming, 12 July 1996. It then
became a paper presented at a Philosophy Colloquium, Illinois Institute of
Technology, on 15 October 1996; and then an article in Teaching Philosophy,
1997, vol. 20, pp. 353 – 85. I should like to thank my “students” in Laramie both
for assuring me that what I said was helpful and for adding significantly to what
I had to say; my colleagues in Chicago for confirming most of what I thought I had
observed and for correcting a few errors; and the editor of Teaching Philosophy for
suggesting further improvements.
1. For a good summary of that literature, with lots of references, see Bruce A.
Kimball, The Emergence of Case Method Teaching, 1872–1990s: A Search
for Legitimate Pedagogy, Bloomington, IN, The Poynter Center for the Study
of Ethics and American Institutions, Indiana University, April 1995. For a
sampling of the vast literature on case method in business, see Hans E. Klein
(ed.), Case Method Research and Case Method Applications: Selected Papers
of the Sixth International Conference on Case Method Research and Case
Method Applications, Waltham, MA, Bentley College, 22–4 May 1989.
2. See, especially, Albert R. Jonsen and Stephen Toulmin, The Abuse of Casuistry:
A History of Moral Reasoning, Berkeley, University of California Press,
1988; John D. Arras, “Getting Down to Cases: The Revival of Casuistry in
Bioethics,” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 1991, vol. 16, pp. 29–51;
and Christopher Miles Coope, “Does Teaching Cases Mislead Us About
Morality?,” Journal of Medical Ethics, 1996, vol. 22, pp. 46–52.
3. The best discussions of how to use cases to teach practical ethics I have come
across are: John B. Matthews, Kenneth E. Goodpaster, and Laura L. Nash,
Policies and Persons: A Casebook in Business Ethics, 2nd edn, New York,
McGraw-Hill, 1991, pp. 1–7; Tom L. Beauchamp, Case Studies in Business,
Society, and Ethics, 3rd edn, Englewood Cliffs, NJ, Prentice-Hall, 1993), pp.
1–13; and Charles E. Harris, Michael S. Pritchard, and Michael J. Rabins,
Engineering Ethics: Concepts and Cases, Belmont, CA, Wadsworth, 1995,
pp. 125–44.
4. Indeed, there is little more than the few remarks in Caroline Whitbeck,
“Teaching Ethics to Scientists and Engineers: Moral Agents and Moral
Problems,” Science and Engineering Ethics, 1995, vol. 1, pp. 299–308.
5. For some idea of this criticism, especially in the legal case method’s early
247
NOTES
years, see William P. LaPiana, Logic and Experience: The Origin of Modern
American Legal Education, New York, Oxford University Press, 1994,
especially pp. 132–47.
6. See, for example, Harvard Case Histories in Experimental Science, vol. I,
edited and with forward by James Bryant Conant, Cambridge, MA, Harvard
University Press, 1957.
7. For more on this, see Stephen Toulmin, “How Medicine Saved Ethics” in New
Directions in Ethics, edited by Joseph P. DeMarco, New York, Routledge,
1986, pp. 265–81; and Chapter 1.
8. Some, however, are quite elaborate. See, for example, the “famous violinist” in
Judith Jarvis Thomson, “A Defense of Abortion,” Philosophy and Public
Affairs, 1971, vol. 1, pp. 47–66. Theologians have a comparable tradition of
“parables.” What connection does that tradition have with the development
of the case method in practical ethics?
9. While physicians seem to have used medical cases (both living patients and
published reports) for teaching centuries before Harvard’s law school coined
the term “case method,” physicians cannot claim to have invented the case
method (any more than they can claim to have coined the term). Until the last
few decades, physicians did not use cases as the standard method of instruction.
Instead, they relied primarily on lecture, textbook, and laboratory, reserving
the study of cases for the last stage of medical education, that is, for clinical
training just before or after the MD. There is, however, some connection
between the physician’s use of clinical cases and the law school’s case method,
an analogy which (along with the scientific laboratory) seems to appear
regularly in early defenses of the method.
10. What connection is there between the lawyer’s use of “case” and the
physician’s? Probably no more than etymology. A case is literally a box, file,
or other container; and, by extension, whatever it holds. No doubt both
lawyers and physicians kept records of their work, organized by the individual
served and then by the individual’s problem, in containers of some sort, that
is, in “cases.” Hence, it would be only natural for both lawyers and physicians
to refer to one of these records – and, by extension, to the events it described
– as “a case.”
11. Michael Davis and Frederick A. Elliston (eds), Ethics and the Legal Profession,
Buffalo, NY, Prometheus Books, 1986.
12. Another piece of evidence that the business school’s case method is not
“natural” is that there exist dozens of books for business students on how to
learn by the case method. See, for example, J. Kenneth Matejka and Thomas
J. Cosse, The Business Case Method: An Introduction, Richmond, VA, Robert
F. Dame, 1981, especially the fourteen questions “students may have,” pp.
39–48, and the bibliography (with a list of other books of the same type).
Vivian Weil recalls that Prof. X had his own explanation of what went wrong:
“This works with cynical business students” (in effect, that the problem was
not that we academics were unfamiliar with the business school’s case method
but that we were not sufficiently cynical).
13. Compare, for example, the relatively long cases in Tom L. Beauchamp’s
248
NOTES
casebook, Case Studies in Business, Society, and Ethics, 3rd edn, Englewood
Cliffs, NJ, Prentice Hall, 1993, with the relatively short cases in the anthology
which he edited with Norman Bowie, Ethical Theory and Business 4th ed.,
Englewood Cliffs, NJ, Prentice Hall, 1993.
14. Lon Fuller, “The Case of the Speluncean Explorers,” Harvard Law Review,
1949, vol. 62, pp. 616–45.
15. A case which includes a descriptive commentary is often called “a case study”
to distinguish it from a mere case. For an example of a descriptive commentary,
see Paula Wells, Hardy Jones, and Michael Davis, Conflict of Interest in
Engineering, Dubuque, IA, Kendall/Hunt, 1986.
16. This rule is, I am afraid, only formally true. Some stories, though they can be
turned into problems (in a sense), cannot be turned into problems successfully.
In famous cases, students may recognize the story behind the problem, adding
the ending themselves. The problem will then behave exactly like a story.
17. Whitbeck, “Moral Agents,” p. 300: “The judgments offered as responses to
intellectual puzzles are…just the ‘kibitzing’ of a critical spectator.”
18. Compare Whitbeck, “Moral Agents,” p. 302: “Of course, the best problem is
an actual problem that a student is experiencing.... Problem statements may,
if carefully crafted, simulate many features of an actual ethical problem
however.” The best problem is an actual problem only if all else is equal, that
is, if the problem is on the right subject, does not involve too much risk, is of
manageable size, and so on. Generally, all else is far from equal. Whitbeck is,
I think, in effect wishing the classroom were the clinic.
19. Kohlbergian experiments with enhancing moral judgment, both his experiments
and those of most of his successors, were done using relatively unrealistic
hypotheticals. Only Muriel Bebeau has published much in which the cases
used were real. And she has, I believe, done no comparison of results obtained
for hypotheticals with results obtained from real (or at least realistic cases).
See, for example, Muriel Bebeau, “Designing an Outcome-Based Ethics
Curriculum on Moral Reasoning: Strategies and Evidence of Effectiveness,”
Journal of Moral Education, 1993, vol. 22, pp. 313–26; or Muriel Bebeau,
“The Impact of a Dental Ethics Curriculum on Moral Reasoning,” Journal of
Dental Education, 1994, vol. 58, pp. 684–92. There is, then, no scientific
evidence for the claim that real cases are better for teaching moral judgment
than hypothetical cases. The alleged superiority of first-job over top-level
cases rests on even less evidence than that. Because it is generally unwise to
claim to know (in advance) what experiment will show, I do not think we
should accept Whitbeck’s claim that one sort of case is better than another
unless she can offer unusually powerful arguments. She has yet to offer
anything of the sort (and, given the great variety of ways in which students
learn, I doubt she ever will).
20. For a collection of cases, many of which are multi-stage, see Michael S.
Pritchard (ed.), Teaching Engineering Ethics: A Case Study Approach,
Kalamazoo, MI, Center for the Study of Ethics in Society, Western Michigan
University, 15 June 1992. Pritchard’s suggestions on how to use his cases,
pp. 1–22, include several useful insights into the case method.
21. Based on case developed in P. Aarne Vesilund, Introduction to Environmental
249
NOTES
250
NOTES
see Donn B. Parker, Susan Swope, and Dr. Bruce N. Baker, Ethical Conflicts:
Information and Computer Science, Technology, and Business, Wellesley,
MA, QED Information Sciences, Inc., 1990. I owe this reference to Jack
Snapper.
34. For more on ethics bowl, see “Ethics Bowl at Annual Meeting,” Speaking
Ethically, 1996, vol. 5, p. 4, or contract the inventor, Robert Ladenson, Center
for the Study of Ethics in the Professions, Illinois Institute of Technology,
Chicago, IL 60616; phone 312–567–3474, fax 312–567–3016, or e-mail
[email protected].
251
NOTES
252
NOTES
even in Harvard’s first decades, the president’s wife had an important place in
the economy of the institution. Frederick Rudolph, The American College
and University, New York, Alfred A. Knopf, 1962, pp. 26–7.
6. The parenthesis is meant to remind us of the great gap that separates us from
early supports of higher education for women. So, for example, were Ezra
Cornell to visit the university to which he admitted women in 1872, he could
not be happy with the “masculine” manners of today’s female students, their
“masculine” dress, or even their “masculine” participation in sport. That was
precisely what he had to be assured would not happen. Rudolph, American
College, 316–7.
7. United States v. Virginia, 116 S. Ct. 2254 (1996). So, for example, the majority
opinion notes (at 2273): “The VMI Alumni Association has developed a
network of employers interested in hiring VMI graduates. The Association
has agreed to open its network to VMIL graduates [the women’s equivalent
of VMI]…but those graduates will not have the advantage afforded by a VMI
degree.”
8. Another weakness, no doubt, is the assimilation of university action (when it
establishes a dormitory or recognizes a fraternity) to the private action of
students (for example, when they club together to rent an apartment in the
open market). Like individual faculty, universities as a whole have special
obligations to students, obligations beyond the fair dealing every seller in the
market has to every buyer. I ignore those obligations here because I have, I
think, said enough about them in Chapter 9 to make a similar discussion here
unnecessary.
9. How, for example, are we to balance the advantage to women of having
women’s universities that would seek out female faculty members, thus
assuring more jobs of women with PhDs, against the advantage to women of
integrated universities in which they would study under the best people in
their field (most of whom might be men)?
10. Though the demands of women certainly have given that debate new life, their
demands are not the only ones that have done that. The demands of the
handicapped for teams of their own have added another dimension, forcing us
to consider even more carefully than women’s sports do what sports do for
a university.
11. I ignore both vasectomies and condoms here because vasectomies are rare
among students and condoms cost so little. I also ignore the birth control and
abortion a male student may have to buy for his sexual partner, in part
because most male students are not married (or otherwise committed to
sharing such costs), but in part too because I consider the university’s
responsibility for sexual partners later.
12. 1996–97 Student Handbook, Chicago, Illinois Institute of Technology, 1996,
p. 72.
13. ibid.
14. IIT Handbook, p. 87.
15. Appendix 1, Date Rape: Feminism, Philosophy, and the Law, edited by Leslie
Francis, University Park, PA, Pennsylvania State University Press, 1996, p.
139.
253
NOTES
254
BIBLIOGRAPHY
255
BIBLIOGRAPHY
256
BIBLIOGRAPHY
257
BIBLIOGRAPHY
258
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Evans, William M. (1962) “Role Strain and the Norm of Reciprocity in Research
Organizations”, American Journal of Sociology, vol. 68, no. 3, pp. 346–54.
Feinberg, Joel (1984) “The Moral and Legal Responsibility of the Bad Samaritan,”
Criminal Justice Ethics, vol. 3, Winter/Spring, pp. 56–66.
Francis, Leslie (1996) Date Rape: Feminism, Philosophy, and the Law, University
Park, PA, Pennsylvania State University Press.
Freedman, Benjamin (1978) “A Meta-Ethics of Professional Morality,” Ethics,
vol. 89, October, pp. 1–19.
Freedman, Monroe (1966) “Professional Responsibility of the Criminal Defense
Lawyer,” Michigan Law Review, vol. 64, June, pp. 1469–84.
Fuller, Lon (1949) “The Case of the Speluncean Explorers”, Harvard Law Review,
1949, vol. 62, February, pp. 616–45.
Fullinwider, Robert K. (1989) “Moral Conventions and Moral Lessons,” Social
Theory and Practice, vol. 15, Fall, pp. 321–38.
Futurecraft v. Clary Corp., 205 C.A. 2nd 279 (1962).
Gallop, Jane (1995) Feminist Accused of Sexual Harassment, Durham, NC, Duke
University Press.
Gauthier, David (1986) Morals By Agreement, Oxford, Clarendon Press.
Gert, Bernard (1988) Morality: A New Justification of the Moral Rules, New York,
Oxford University Press.
Gewirth, Alan (1978) Reason and Morality, Chicago, University of Chicago Press.
—— (1986) “Professional Ethics: The Separatist Thesis,” Ethics, vol. 96, pp.
282–300.
Glass, Bentley (1965) “The Ethics Basis of Science”, Science, vol. 150, pp.
1254–61.
Goldman, Alan (1980) The Moral Foundations of Professional Responsibility,
Totowa, NJ, Littlefield Adams.
Gorlin, Rena A. (ed.) (1986) Codes of Professional Responsibility, Washington,
DC, Bureau of National Affairs, Inc.
Gorovitz, Samuel et al. (eds) (1976) Moral Problems in Medicine, Englewood
Cliffs, NJ, Prentice.
Gunther, Gerald (1990) “Freedom for the Thought We Hate,” Academe, vol. 76,
December, pp. 10–2.
Harris, Charles E., Michael S. Pritchard, and Michael J. Rabins (1995) Engineering
Ethics: Concepts and Cases, Belmont, CA, Wadsworth.
Hart, H.L.A. (1968) Punishment and Responsibility, New York, Oxford University
Press.
Hastings Center Staff (1980), “The Teaching of Ethics in American Higher
Education: An Empirical Synopsis,” in Daniel Callahan and Sissela Bok (eds),
Teaching Ethics in Higher Education, New York, Plenum Press, pp. 153–70.
259
BIBLIOGRAPHY
“Head of College Quits under Fire: Texan’s Dissertation Was Found to Resemble
Wife’s,” New York Times, 20 April 1969, p. 64.
Hearnshaw, L. S. (1981) Cyril Burt – Psychologist, New York, Random House/
Vintage Books.
Hixson, Joseph (1976) The Patchwork Mouse, Garden City, NJ, Anchor/
Doubleday.
Hook, Sidney, Paul Kurtz, and Miro Todorovich (eds) (1977) The Ethics of
Teaching and Scientific Research, Buffalo, NY, Prometheus Books.
Humber, James M. and Robert F. Almeder (eds) (1976) Biomedical Ethics and the
Law, New York, Plenum Press.
Hunt, Morton (1989) “Did the Penalty Fit the Crime?” New York Times Magazine,
May 14, pp. 36ff.
Illinois Institute of Technology (1996) 1996–97 Student Handbook, Chicago,
Illinois Institute of Technology.
Jacoby, Russell (1987) The Last Intellectuals, New York, Basic Books.
Johnson, Henry C. (1964) “On Avoiding ‘Single Vision and Newton’s Sleep’:
Sketches From an Unorthodox Moral-Education History,” in Morality, Moral
Behavior, and Moral Development, William M. Kuntines and Jacob L. Gewirtz
(eds), New York, John Wiley, pp. 381–99.
Jonsen, Albert R. and Stephen Toulmin (1988) The Abuse of Casuistry: A History
of Moral Reasoning, Berkeley, CA, University of California Press.
Joughin, Louis (ed.) (1969) Academic Freedom and Tenure: A Handbook of the
American Association of University Professors, Madison, WI, University of
Wisconsin Press.
Kadish, Mortimer R. (1991) The Ethic of Higher Education, Palo Alto, CA,
Stanford University Press.
Kadish, Mortimer R. and Sanford H. Kadish (1973) Discretion to Disobey: A
Study of Lawful Departures from Legal Rules, Stanford, CA, Stanford
University Press.
Kant, Immanuel (1990) Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. by
Lewis White Beck, New York, Macmillan/Library of Liberal Arts.
Kimball, Bruce A. (1995) The Emergence of Case Method Teaching, 1872–1990s:
A Search for Legitimate Pedagogy, Bloomington, IN, The Poynter Center for
the Study of Ethics and American Institutions, Indiana University.
Kimball, Roger (1990) Tenured Radicals: How Politics Has Corrupted Our Higher
Education, New York, Harper & Row.
Kipnis, Kenneth (1983) “Professional Responsibility and the Responsibility of
Professions” in Wade L. Robinson, Michael Pritchard and Joseph Ellin (eds)
Profits and Professions: Essays in Business and Professional Ethics, Clifton,
N. J., Humana Press.
Klein, Hans E. (ed.) (1989) Case Method Research and Case Method Applications:
260
BIBLIOGRAPHY
261
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Mallon, Thomas (1989) Stolen Words: Forays into the Origins and Ravages of
Plagiarism, New York, Ticknor & Fields.
Martin, Theodore Day (1931) Instruction in Professional Ethics in Professional
Schools for Teachers, PhD dissertation, Columbia University.
Martin, T.R. (1981/82) “Do Courses in Ethics Improve the Ethical Judgment of
Students?”, Business and Society, vol. 21–22, Winter–Spring, pp. 17–26.
Matasar, Richard A. (1989) “Teaching Ethics in Civil Procedure Courses,” Journal
of Legal Education, vol. 39, December, pp. 587–607.
Matejka, J. Kenneth and Thomas J. Cosse (1981) The Business Case Method: An
Introduction, Richmond, VA, Robert F. Dame, Inc.
Matthews, John B., Kenneth E. Goodpaster, and Laura L. Nash (1991) Policies
and Persons: A Casebook in Business Ethics, 2nd edn, New York, McGraw-
Hill.
May, William F. (1980) “Professional Ethics: Setting, Terrain, and Teacher”, in
Ethics Teaching in Higher Education, Daniel Callahan and Sisela Bok (eds),
New York, Plenum Books, pp. 205–41.
Medawar, Peter B. (1975) “The Strange Case of the Spotted Mice,” The New
York Review of Books, 15 April, p. 8.
Merton, Robert (1973) “The Normative Structure of Science,” in Norman W.
Storer (ed.), The Sociology of Science: Theoretical and Empirical Investigations,
Chicago, University of Chicago Press, pp. 267–78.
Mill, John Stuart (1956) On Liberty, Indianapolis, IN, Library of the Liberal Arts.
—— (1957) Utilitarianism, Indianapolis, IN, Library of the Liberal Arts.
Mooney, Carolyn J. (1990) “N.Y. City College Panel Weighs Academic Freedom,
Inflammatory Racial Views of 2 Faculty Members,” Chronicle of Higher
Education, 23 May, p. A13 ff.
Muses, C. (1995) “The Unique Reach of Cybernetics in Our Fin-de-Siécle”,
Kybernetes, vol. 24, no. 7, pp. 6–20.
Nissenbaum, Stephen (1990) “The Plagiarists in Academe Must Face Formal
Sanctions”, Chronicle of Higher Education, 28 March, p. A52.
Parker, Donn B., Susan Swope, and Bruce N. Baker (1990) Ethical Conflicts:
Information and Computer Science, Technology, and Business, Wellesley,
MA, QED Information Sciences, Inc.
Parsons, Talcott and Gerald M. Platt (1973) The American University, Cambridge,
MA, Harvard University Press.
Pincoffs, Edmund L. (ed.) (1972) The Concept of Academic Freedom, Austin,
TX, University of Texas Press.
Pirsig, Maynard E. (ed.) (1970) Professional Responsibility, St. Paul, MN, West.
Pritchard, Michael S. (ed.) (1992) Teaching Engineering Ethics: A Case Study
Approach, Kalamazoo, Center for the Study of Ethics in Society, Western
Michigan University.
262
BIBLIOGRAPHY
263
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Smith, Patricia (1990) “The Duty to Rescue and the Slippery Slope Problem”,
Social Theory and Practice, vol. 16, Spring, pp. 19–41.
Sobel, Alan (1997) “Antioch’s ‘Sexual Offense Policy’: A Philosophical
Exploration”, Journal of Social Philosophy, vol. 28, Spring, pp. 22–36.
Sperber, Murray (1990) College Sport, Inc.: The Athletic Department vs. the
University, New York, Henry Holt.
Strohm, Paul (1988) “Professional Ethics and Scientific Misconduct,” Footnotes,
a publication of the American Association of University Professors, vol. 6,
Fall, p. 1.
Sykes, Charles J. (1988) ProfScam: Professors and the Demise of Higher Education,
Washington, DC, Regnery Gateway.
Teich, Albert H. and Frankel, Mark S. (1992) Good Science and Responsible
Scientists, Washington, DC, Directorate for Science and Policy Programs,
American Association for the Advancement of Science.
Thomson, Judith Jarvis (1971) “A Defense of Abortion”, Philosophy and Public
Affairs, vol. 1, Fall, pp. 47–66.
Toulmin, Stephen (1982) “How Medicine Saved the Life of Ethics,” Perspectives
in Biology and Medicine, vol. 25, Summer, pp. 736–50.
—— (1986) “How Medicine Saved Ethics” in New Directions in Ethics, Joseph
P. DeMarco (ed.), New York, Routledge, pp. 265–81.
United States v. Virginia, 116 S. Ct. 2254 (1996).
U.S. Department of Commerce, Bureau of the Census (1976) Historical Statistics
of the United States: Colonial Times to 1970, Part 1, (Bicentennial Edition).
U.S. Department of Justice, Bureau of Justice Statistics (March 1989) Report to
the National on Crime and Justice, Second Edition, Washington, DC.
U.S. National Criminal Justice Information and Statistics Service (1980) Sourcebook
of Criminal Justice Statistics, Washington, DC.
van der Waerden, B.L. (1968) “Mendel’s Experiments,” Centaurus, vol. 12, March,
pp. 275–88.
Veatch, Robert M. (1979) “Professional Medical Ethics: The Grounding of its
Principles,” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, vol. 4, March, pp. 1–19.
Vesilund, P. Arne (1988) “Rules, Ethics, and Morals in Engineering Education”,
Engineering Education, vol. 77, February, pp. 289–93.
—— (1997) Introduction to Environmental Engineering, Boston, PWS Publishing
Co.
Waithe, Mary Ellen and David T. Ozar, (1990) “The Ethics of Teaching Ethics,”
Hastings Center Report, vol. 20, July/August, pp. 17–21.
Wasserstrom, Richard (1975) “Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues,”
Human Right, vol. 5, Fall, pp. 1–24.
Wells, Paula, Hardy Jones, and Michael Davis (1986) Conflict of Interest in
Engineering, Dubuque, Iowa, Kendall/Hunt.
264
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Whelan, John M. (1991) “Charity and the Duty to Rescue”, Social Theory and
Practice, vol. 17, Fall, pp. 441–56.
Whitbeck, Caroline (1995) “Teaching Ethics to Scientists and Engineers: Moral
Agents and Moral Problems”, Science and Engineering Ethics, vol 1, July,
pp. 299–308.
Wilshire, Bruce (1989) The Moral Collapse of the University: Professionalism,
Purity and Alienation, Albany, NY, State University of New York Press.
Weber, Max (1921) Wissenschaft als Beruf, München, Duncker und Humblott.
Woodward, Dow (1989) “The Challenge of Understanding and Teaching Broad
Aspects of Bioethics Principles”, Perspectives on the Professions, Chicago,
Center for the Study of Ethics in the Professions, Illinois.
265
INDEX
266
INDEX
267