Classical Political Economy: Heinz D. Kurz
Classical Political Economy: Heinz D. Kurz
Classical Political Economy: Heinz D. Kurz
2 (2019)
Heinz D. Kurz
Department of Economics and Graz Schumpeter Centre, University of Graz, 8010 Graz,
Austria. [email protected]
Abstract: The paper discusses the approach to political economy of the classical
economists from Adam Smith to David Ricardo; the reasons why it was
prematurely abandoned and replaced by marginalist economics; and why a
logically coherent version of it elaborated by Piero Sraffa puts into sharp relief the
difficulties affecting the latter and especially its concept of capital as a magnitude
that can be ascertained prior to and independently of the rate of profits and relative
prices. It is argued that the classical approach does not stand or fall with the labour
theory of value, which was adopted by classical authors only as a makeshift
solution since they were not possessed of the mathematics of simultaneous
equations needed to deal with an economic system characterised by a social
division of labour. It is shown that the general rate of profits and relative
competitive prices are fully determined in terms of the data of the theory, i.e., the
system of production actually in use and real wages. The paper then deals with the
determination of real wages; the role of natural resources; technical and
organisational progress; money and banking; foreign trade; government and state.
JEL Codes: B12, B40, B51, D33, D46, D82, E23, H10, J31, P16
1 It deserves to be mentioned that marginalist theory is also known under the name
of “neoclassical economics,” a term coined by Thorstein Veblen in 1900. Veblen
responded to Alfred Marshall’s claim that marginalist theory consisted simply in
the further cultivation of the seed planted at the time of the classical authors, thus
the name neoclassical. However, Veblen saw that the neoclassical school had very
little in common with other schools, including the classical one.
Heinz D. Kurz: Classical Political Economy 19
Clearly, demand and supply play some role in every kind of economic
analysis, classical, marginalist, Marxist, Austrian or other. The question is:
precisely which role? We shall see that in this regard there are fundamental
differences between the classical authors and the marginalists. (See on this
Kurz (2016: chaps 2 and 4).) These differences have their roots in
fundamentally different methodological outlooks on the subject. Most
importantly, the classical economists took the socio-economic system as
they found it, stratified in social classes – workers, landowners and
capitalists – who perform different roles in the process of the production,
distribution and use of commodities and the wealth of a nation. In the
tradition of Aristotle’s zoon politicon (ζώον πολιτικόν), individuals are
seen as social beings whose motivations, aspirations, capabilities and so on
are largely shaped by society or the milieu from which they come.
Another characteristic feature of the classical authors is their objectivist
point of view. This was most effectively expressed by William Petty, who
advocated a “physician’s outlook” on economic problems and decided to
express himself “in terms of Number, Weight, or Measure ... and to
consider only such Cases, as have visible Foundations in Nature, leaving
those that depend upon the mutable Minds, Opinions, Appetites, and
Passions of particular Men, to the Consideration of others.” Interestingly,
the alternative he described fits rather well marginal utility theory and thus
an important pillar of marginalism (the other one being marginal
productivity theory). In a similar vein, James Mill, a friend of Ricardo (and
the father of John Stuart Mill), put forward the remarkable proposition:
“The agents of production are the commodities themselves ... They are the
food of the labourer, the tools and the machines with which he works, and
the raw materials which he works upon” (Mill 1926: 165). Production,
these authors insisted, is a process of “productive consumption,” in which
various commodities (means of production and means of subsistence of
workers) have necessarily to be “destroyed,” in order to get some other
commodities, and the amounts that have to be destroyed reflect the
“difficulty” of getting them.
20 Munich Social Science Review, New Series, vol. 2, 2019
man has almost constant occasion for the help of his brethren, and it
is in vain for him to expect it from their benevolence only. He will be
more likely to prevail if he can interest their self-love in his favour,
and shew them that it is for their own advantage to do for him what
he requires of them. Whoever offers to another a bargain of any
kind, proposes to do this. Give me that which I want, and you shall
have this which you want, is the meaning of every such offer; and it
is in this manner that we obtain from one another the far greater part
of those good offices which we stand in need of. (WN I.ii.2)
3 There has been a controversy about whether Smith’s two major works are
compatible with one another, known as “Das Adam Smith Problem.” There is now
widespread agreement that they are, with the two works emphasizing different
aspects of human nature and the particular situations in which they come to the
fore.
24 Munich Social Science Review, New Series, vol. 2, 2019
from their regard to their own interest. We address ourselves, not to their
humanity but to their self-love, and never talk to them of our own
necessities but of their advantages” (WN I.ii.2). Finally, he also saw the
division of labour – which in his view is the main source of material
opulence – rooted in the propensity under consideration: “it is this same
trucking disposition which originally gives occasion to the division of
labour” (WN I.ii.3).
Hence, Smith established two crucial axioms upon which his analytical
edifice rests:
Smith’s economic agent is a homo mercans and homo laborans, but she is
also a homo inventivus. Smith emphasized: “the desire of bettering our
condition ... comes with us from the womb, and never leaves us till we go
into the grave” (WN II.iii.28). It prompts people to save and accumulate
capital, expand markets, deepen the division of labour and carry out
“improvements” in each and every sector of the economy. It makes them
invent machines to abbreviate the toil and trouble of work and to increase
the social productivity of labour. In short, it makes them innovate and
revolutionize production processes and economic organisation.
5. Socio-economic classes
and retrench the dark sides of selfishness. This will stimulate diligence,
industry and creativity. The “science of the legislator,” Smith elaborated,
was designed to show the way to good government. He left no doubt that
the regulatory task cannot be accomplished once and for all, because self-
seeking agents will always try to find ways to circumvent them. What is at
stake is a race between the cleverness of legislators and the cunning of
business people.
The classical economists were well aware of conflicts of interest
between different classes and groups of people. The view that they saw
society to be harmonious amounts to a travesty of facts. They also
identified the sources of conflict and the potential causes of economic
malfunctioning or crises and proposed policy measures to mitigate their
destructive effects.
the whole seignorage charged” (Works I: 353). Hence the value of gold (of
a given weight and fineness) and the value of money will differ and the
difference will depend on the quantity of money provided. Ricardo was
concerned with proposing an ideal monetary system, which he defined in
the following way: “A currency is in its most perfect state when it consists
wholly of paper money, but of paper money of an equal value with the
gold which it professes to represent.” (Works I: 361). Hence the quantity of
paper money in circulation “should be regulated according to the value of
the metal which is declared to be the standard” (Works I: 354). This does
not require that paper money should be payable in specie to secure its
value. It suffices that “paper might be increased with every fall in the value
of gold, or, which is the same thing in its effects, with every rise in the
price of goods” (Works I: 354). According to Ricardo the increase in the
price level during the suspension of the convertibility of bank notes
between 1797 and 1821 was first and foremost the result of printing too
much money and thus of disregarding the role of the monetary standard.
Deleplace (2015: 355) concluded: “Ricardo’s concept of monetary
standard … had a revolutionary content, which put it far ahead of its time.”
According to Bonar (1923: 298), Ricardo’s Ingot Plan “was to be the
euthanasia of metal currency.” This is perhaps expressed too strongly,
because in Ricardo’s view gold was to preserve both its role as domestic
monetary standard and at the same time (as bullion) to serve as the means
of settlement of international debts.
In Ricardo we encounter the purchasing power theory of exchange rates
and the theory of a gold currency including the mechanism that is seen to
bring about an equalisation of the balance of payments. In the Bullion
controversy, which generated important insights into the functioning of a
monetary system without convertibility, Ricardo fought on the side of the
“bullionists” who argued in favour of a swift return to the gold standard.
An increase of the domestic relative to the foreign price level leads via the
flow of commodities and capital to a falling external value of the domestic
currency and thus prompts a tendency towards the parity of its purchasing
power at home and abroad.
explain the sharing out of the product amongst the various claimants
(workers, capitalists and landowners) and which system of relative prices
supports this distribution. Notwithstanding important differences between
different authors, close scrutiny shows that the unifying element is that
they all deal with the problem essentially in the same way: they explain the
general rate of profits in the economy, the rents paid to the proprietors of
the different types of land and the ordinary or “natural” prices ruling in
markets at a given time and place in terms of the following givens or
independent variables (see Sraffa 1951, 1960):
From equation (1) we get the already known r = 0.25. Plugging this in
equation (2) allows us to determine the price ratio of the two commodities,
The price ratio determined in (3) reflects what Adam Smith and David
Ricardo called “natural”, “normal” or “ordinary prices” and Ricardo,
Robert Torrens and Karl Marx called “prices of production.” The
characteristic feature of these prices is that they reflect the permanent and
systematic forces at work in competitive conditions and cover costs of
production of the various commodities plus a uniform rate of profits on the
capitals invested. “Actual” or “market prices” are in addition subject to a
multiplicity of “accidental” and “temporary” factors interfering with the
fundamental forces. By their very nature, markets prices defy an
explanation that is sufficiently general. The classical economists’ therefore
focused on the determination of prices of production.
The uniformity of the rate of profits reflects the successful working of
competitive forces. The natural price, Smith insisted, is
them suspended a good deal above it, and sometimes force them
down even somewhat below it. But whatever may be the obstacles
which hinder them from settling in this center of repose and
continuance, they are constantly tending towards it. (Smith, WN
I.vii.15)
While every man is free to employ his capital where he pleases, he will
naturally seek for it that employment which is most advantageous; he
will naturally be dissatisfied with a profit of 10 per cent, if by removing
his capital he can obtain a profit of 15 per cent. This restless desire on
the part of all the employers of stock [capital], to quit a less profitable
for a more advantageous business, has a strong tendency to equalize the
rate of profits of all, or to fix them in such proportions, as may in the
estimation of the parties, compensate for any advantage which one may
have, or may appear to have over the other. (Ricardo, Works I: 88-9)
vc = 2.5,
that is, 2.5 man years are needed altogether to produce a ton of corn (2
man years are needed directly and 0.5 years indirectly via the used-up
input of corn in corn production.) As regards whisky production, the
following labour value accounting applies:
vw = 6.
Comparing equations (3) and (6) shows that relative competitive prices
deviate from relative labour values: In price terms, whisky is more
expensive relatively to corn than in labour value terms, i.e., 2.5 vs. 2.4.
The reason for this is that whisky is produced with relatively more indirect
labour, incorporated in the capital good corn, than corn itself. Put
differently, the ratio of corn input to direct labour input in whisky
production is larger than in corn production: 4.000 corn/20.000 labour =
1/5 > 20.000 corn/200.00 labour = 1/10. The difference between 2.5 and
2.4 expresses the compound interest effect of discounting forward wages
paid in a more or less distant past.
Ricardo was clear that the labour theory of value does not completely
correctly determine relative prices, but he felt that it provided an
approximation that was good enough to adopt it as a simplifying device or
makeshift solution.4 He therefore in the Principles of Political Economy
We now have to bring natural resources and the scarcity of land(s) into the
picture. Smith had argued in accordance with the physiocrats that ground
rent was an expression of the “fertility of nature.” Nature was taken to
cooperate with man for free and increase man’s productivity. This is also
the reason why Smith was of the opinion that agriculture was more
productive than manufacturing. Ricardo strongly opposed this view: rent is
an expression of how nature is “niggardly”! If land of the best quality and
location were available in unlimited quantity, he insisted, there could be no
ground rent, because cost-minimizing producers would be able to meet
society’s need for corn at every level by using only the best kind of land.
But because this kind of land is not available in abundance but becomes
scarce at some point as production increases, it is necessary to meet
effectual demand by also cultivating inferior lands, which exhibits higher
unit costs of production, or by cultivating the best quality of land more
intensively, which is also only possible at rising unit costs. As a result,
returns fall either extensively or intensively, leading to extensive or
intensive rents.
If, for example, demand is large and cultivation is expanded on plots of
inferior land, production costs per quarter of corn will be higher. In order
for the larger quantity to be brought forth the corn price will have to rise.
The higher price for corn enables the owners of the superior quality of land
– who continue to produce at lower unit cost – to collect a rent from their
tenants, which is just large enough to result in equal costs (inclusive of
rent) on both qualities of land. In this new situation, no rent is paid on the
inferior land, which is not scarce and which represents what later was
called “marginal” land in the given situation. Ground rent is therefore a
differential rent attributable to differences in production costs per quarter
of corn. To Ricardo, trained in the financial markets, the connection
between the annual rent per hectare of a piece of land of given quality m,
qm, and the land price per hectare, pm, was clear. If one discounts all future
annual rent payments at the prevailing interest rate i in order to get their
Heinz D. Kurz: Classical Political Economy 39
so-called present or capital value, one arrives at the formula for the eternal
rent: pm = qm/i. If the lease is, for example, £100 and the interest rate 5 per
cent (or 0.05), the price per hectare of that land amounts to £2.000.
With society’s growing need for corn, and setting aside technological
progress, the unit cost of corn would rise, as would the price of corn, the
money wage rate (to keep real wages constant) and ground rents on all
cultivated lands. Therefore, for a given real (and rising money) wage rate
and a decreasing fertility of marginal land, there would necessarily ensue a
falling tendency of the rate of profits for producers in agriculture and, via
the mobility of capital, in the economy as a whole. This was Ricardo’s
explanation of the tendency of the rate of profits to fall. Such a tendency
was the logical outcome in the hypothetical case where there was no
technological progress. But since there typically is technological progress,
Ricardo insisted: “it is difficult to say where the limit is at which you
would cease to accumulate wealth, and to derive profit from its
employment” (Works IV: 179). The widespread view (see, for example,
Rostow 1990: 34, 87; Blaug 2009; Solow 2010) that Ricardo saw the
stationary state lurking around the corner therefore cannot be sustained. It
mistakes Ricardo’s method of counterfactual reasoning – What would
happen, if there were no technical progress, but capital accumulated and
the population grew? – for a statement about actual economic
development. Yet Ricardo clearly was no Horseman of the Apocalypse as
his intellectual counterpart Thomas Robert Malthus, who saw mankind
forever exposed to misery and deprivation. Despite clear evidence to the
contrary, Ricardo is frequently taken to share Malthus’ pessimism. Nothing
could be further from the truth. (See also below the section on the “law of
population”.)
Ricardo was able to put this rent theory to lucrative use: he took a large
part of the fortune he had gained at the stock exchange after the defeat of
the Napoleonic troops in the Battle of Waterloo in 1815 to buy land and
become one of England’s wealthiest landowners. He understood: should
the accelerating accumulation of capital and the ensuing shortage of lands
following Waterloo mean that the lease on the land in the above-mentioned
example rose to £180, and the interest rate (as a result of the tendency of
the rate of profits to fall) sink to 3 per cent (or 0.03), the price of land
would treble and rise to £6.000. Not a bad deal at all! While Ricardo
rejected Smith’s theory of rent, he confirmed the latter’s dictum that
landlords “love to reap where they never sowed” (WN I.vi.8): when land is
40 Munich Social Science Review, New Series, vol. 2, 2019
getting more and more scarce, ground rents and land prices will rise.
Landlords are the lucky beneficiaries of a development of the economy to
which they contributed nothing.
If capital accumulates and the population grows, less and less fertile lands
have to be cultivated. With a fairly constant real wage rate, the rate of
profits is bound to fall. Since capital accumulation is closely related to the
rate of profits,5 a fall in the latter entails a fall in the former: the system
tends towards a stationary state, economic growth comes to a standstill.
Ricardo saw technical and organizational change as a factor that
countervails the niggardliness of nature.
For Adam Smith, the division of labour was the most important engine
of economic growth and lever of increases in labour productivity and per
capita income. Initially, he argued, there was a division of labour within
and then between firms and regions in a given country, and finally between
countries. The division of labour (i) yields gains from specialization, (ii)
saves time that is lost in changing from one task or job to another, and
most importantly, (iii) promotes the development of machinery. Labour
power is replaced by machine power, and production is mechanized – a
process for which there is no end in sight.
Interestingly, Smith anticipated the emergence of a sector of the
economy that today is known as research and development (R&D). He
referred to new trades and occupations, including “that of those who are
called philosophers or men of speculation [i.e. scientists], whose trade it is,
not to do any thing, but to observe every thing; and who, upon that
account, are often capable of combining together the powers of the most
distant and dissimilar objects. In the progress of society, philosophy or
speculation becomes, like every other employment, the principal or sole
trade and occupation of a particular class of citizens.” (WN I.i.9) The new
knowledge that is systematically produced enables “improvements” in
production and organization. Two centuries before the emergence of the
concept of a “knowledge society,” Smith had already explicitly identified
the “quantity of science” as the foundation of society’s productive powers.
5 In a fully classical spirit, Karl Marx was to call the rate of profits “the stimulus of
Heinz D. Kurz: Classical Political Economy 41
_______________________
capitalist production and condition as well as driver of accumulation.”
42 Munich Social Science Review, New Series, vol. 2, 2019
the insight that these forms may affect employment, income distribution
and other important economic magnitudes in very different ways. In the
chapter on machinery, added to the third edition of the Principles (1821),
Ricardo discussed a particular form of technical progress, which, he
insisted, “is often very injurious to the interests of the class of labourers”
(Works I: 388). The case under consideration is “the substitution of
machinery for human labour” that reduces the gross product. It is
characterised by an increase both in labour productivity and in the capital-
to-output ratio, and thus a decrease in the maximum rate of profits: it is
both labour saving and (fixed) capital using. The gross-produce reducing
mechanization entails what was later called “technological unemploy-
ment,” which will typically exert a downward pressure on real wages, viz.
its injurious effect on workers.6
Ricardo argued that foreign trade increases the set of commodities and
methods of production to which a country has access via imports bought
with exports, and therefore can be expected to affect income distribution
and relative prices via the channels mentioned above. He also had a clear
understanding of induced technical change: A newly invented machine,
for example, may not be introduced by cost-minimizing producers, because
at the given real wage rate and prices it would not be profitable to do so: it
has been born into an environment that is inimical to it. In Schumpeter’s
words, it would be an “invention,” but would not (immediately) become an
“innovation,” because the new knowledge would not be applied. However,
as capital accumulates and the population grows, wages and prices
typically change, which may eventually render the invention profitable (see
Kurz 2015: section 7).
It is interesting to note that Ricardo even contemplated the limiting case
of a fully automated system of production and pointed out: “If machinery
could do all the work that labour now does, there would be no demand for
labour. Nobody would be entitled to consume any thing who was not a
capitalist, and who could not buy or hire a machine” (Works VIII: 399f).
He thus anticipated in an extreme form the trend towards automation
which advanced economies are currently experiencing. And he saw that
6In Marx we encounter Ricardo’s case as the allegedly dominant form of technical
progress in capitalism, characterized by a growing “organic composition of
capital” and thus a falling maximum rate of profits, which will eventually, Marx
was convinced, also force the actual rate of profits to fall.
Heinz D. Kurz: Classical Political Economy 43
product (Works I: 48). If this were the case for a prolonged period of time,
a sort of ratchet effect may be observed: the higher real wages become
customary and define a new level of “natural” wages. As early as in the
Essay on Profits, Ricardo stressed that “it is no longer questioned” that
improved machinery “has a decided tendency to raise the real wage of
labour” (Works IV: 35; see also VIII: 171).
It follows that the concept of “natural wages” in Ricardo is defined with
reference to the wealth of a society and the growth regime it experiences
and must not be interpreted as indicating a given and constant real wage
rate – nothing of this sort. An implication of this is that Ricardo felt the
need to replace the real (that is, commodity) wage rate by a share concept,
or “proportional wages” (Sraffa 1951: lii), that is, “the proportion of the
annual labour of the country … devoted to the support of the labourers”
(Works I: 49). It was on the basis of this wage concept that he asserted his
fundamental proposition on distribution: the rate of profits depends
inversely on proportional wages (see Gehrke 2011).
To conclude, the classical surplus explanation of profits applies both in
a regime, in which the law of population holds, and in a regime, in which it
doesn’t. Ricardo’s main concern was clearly with the latter.
Assume that the money prices of the quantities of cloth and wine in the two
countries are proportional to the quantities of labour spent in producing
them, and assume for simplicity that the numbers are the same, the only
difference being that now, instead of Portuguese and English labour, we
have reals and pounds (Table 1).
Table 1:
One can easily see that trade would be favourable to merchants of both
countries. (In the following, for simplicity, we set aside transportation
costs.) Take the case of an English merchant. He may buy for £100 a given
quantity of cloth, ship it to Portugal, and sell it there for 90 reals. With this
sum of money he may then buy wine from a Portuguese wine grower and
get altogether 90/80 = 9/8 units of wine, where one unit costs 80 reals.
This quantity of wine he then ships to England and sells for 9/8 × £120 =
£135. He thus yields a profit of £135 – £100 = £35 or a rate of profit of 35
per cent on an investment of £100 over the time it took to export cloth and
import wine. (It deserves to be noted that the English merchant can use the
same ship to export and import goods from and to England.) A similar
consideration applies to a Portuguese merchant.
The remarkable fact here is (as opposed to the previous explanation
with gold as the universal means of payment) that while commodities are
exported and imported, the currencies of the two countries do not cross
borders: they stay in the countries of origin; there are no flows of money
into and out of a country.
What applies to specialization between countries also applies to trade
between people. The happy message of Ricardo’s finding is this: whoever
is inferior to another person in everything can nonetheless become
involved in a division of labour that is mutually advantageous. In this way,
Ricardo added an important verse to Adam Smith’s hymn of praise on the
beneficent effects of the division of labour.
Heinz D. Kurz: Classical Political Economy 47
References
Gehrke, C. and H.D. Kurz (1995), “Karl Marx on Physiocracy,” The Euro-
pean Journal of the History of Economic Thought 2: 54-92.
Gehrke, C. and H.D. Kurz (2006), “Sraffa on von Bortkiewicz: Re-
constructing the Classical Theory of Value and Distribution,” History of
Political Economy 38, 91-149.
Kurz, H.D. (2002), “Surplus, Abstinenz, und Lohnfonds: John Stuart Mill
zur Theorie der Einkommensverteilung,” in: E.W. Streissler (ed.), Stu-
dien zur Entwicklung der ökonomischen Theorie XIX. John Stuart Mill,
Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, pp. 253-280.
Kurz, H.D. and N. Salvadori (1995). Theory of Production. A Long-Period
Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kurz, H.D. and N. Salvadori (eds.) (1998), The Elgar Companion to
Classical Economics, two vols, Cheltenham and Northampton: Edward
Elgar.
Malthus, T.R. ([1820] 1989), Principles of Political Economy, Variorum
edition, 2 vols, edited by John Pullen, Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press.
Malthus, T.R. ([1827] 1971), Definitions in Political Economy. Preceded
by an Inquiry into Rules That Ought to Guide Political Economists in
the Definition and Use of their Terms; With Remarks on the Deviations
from These Rules in Their Writings. Reprint 1971, New York: A. M.
Kelley.
Marx, K. ([1859] 1970), A Contribution to the Critique of Political
Economy, New York: International Publishers.
Marx, K. ([1861-63] 1988), Theories of Surplus Value, 3 vols, Moscow:
Progress Publishers.
Marx, K. ([1867] 1954), Capital. A Critique of Political Economy, vol. I,
Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Mill, J. ([1844] 1965), Elements of Political Economy, Third edition, Re-
print 1965, New York: A.M. Kelley.
Mill, J. S. ([1848] 1965), Principles of Political Economy with Some of
their Applications to Social Philosophy, Toronto: University of Toronto
Press.
O’Brien, D.P. (1975), The Classical Economists, London: Oxford Uni-
versity Press.
O’Brien, D.P. (2004), The Classical Economists Revisited, Princeton and
Oxford: Princeton University Press.
Heinz D. Kurz: Classical Political Economy 51