Fuller Science Studies Non Critical
Fuller Science Studies Non Critical
Fuller Science Studies Non Critical
Fuller / SCIENCE
OF STUDIES
THE SOCIAL
ANDSCIENCES
SCIENCE / March 2000
Why Science Studies
Has Never Been Critical of Science
Some Recent Lessons on How to Be a
Helpful Nuisance and a Harmless Radical
STEVE FULLER
University of Warwick
Research in Science and Technology Studies (STS) tends to presume that intel-
lectual and political radicalism go hand in hand. One would therefore expect
that the most intellectually radical movement in the field relates critically to its
social conditions. However, this is not the case, as demonstrated by the trajec-
tory of the Parisian School of STS spearheaded by Michel Callon and Bruno
Latour. Their position, “actor-network theory,” turns out to be little more than a
strategic adaptation to the democratization of expertise and the decline of the
strong nation-state in France over the past 25 years. This article provides a pre-
history of this client-driven, contract-based research culture in U.S. sociology of
the 1960s, followed by specific features of French philosophical and political cul-
ture that have bred the distinctive tenets of actor-network theory. Insofar as
actor-network theory has become the main paradigm for contemporary STS
research, it reflects a field that dodges normative commitments in order to main-
tain a user-friendly presence.
There are many ironic features about the development of the inter-
disciplinary field of Science and Technology Studies (STS). Perhaps
most ironic of all is the field’s handling of its own history. STS treats its
past unproblematically, always tracing its proper origins to the Edin-
burgh School after having paid tribute to Thomas Kuhn as the mythi-
cal progenitor. (This is true even of such well-informed “second gen-
eration” texts as Golinski 1998.) Indeed, in classic Kuhnian fashion,
STS is prone to conceptualize its own history as an evolving response
to theoretical and methodological issues surrounding the nature of
science that transcend national boundaries. Yet, even a cursory
understanding of the different post–World War II science policies
pursued in the founding nations of STS—the United Kingdom, the
requires breaking with its letter; hence, they call for a generalized
application of SSK’s symmetry principle. The complexity of techno-
scientific networks revealed in their studies cannot be accounted for
simply by invoking social factors, however “symmetrically” they are
applied to successful and failed courses of action. Natural factors need
to be invoked as well—and just as symmetrically. Not surprisingly,
scientists (e.g., Labinger 1995) who follow the STS literature have wel-
comed the Parisian turn, since it clearly reopens the door to tradi-
tional, even commonsensical, explanations of science that incorpo-
rate both social and natural factors “interacting” to produce, say, an
experimental outcome. It would seem, then, that we have reached one
of those all too familiar Molierean moments in academic life when a
move that appears radical within the terms of a paradigm is equiva-
lent to the prose that everyone else outside the paradigm has been
always speaking (albeit now with a French accent).
The impasse between Collins and Latour is symbolized by the
Janus-faced character of STS’s much vaunted case study methodol-
ogy. On the one hand, in Collins’s view, case studies create intellectual
entitlements for the STS practitioner that effectively restrict the “com-
munity of inquirers” simply to those with similar training and experi-
ence. On the other hand, in Latour’s view, because case studies are
typically evaluated merely in terms of their descriptive adequacy
(“Does it tell a good story?”), and not some larger normative context,
they can be of potential use to a wide range of users, most notably
those who do not share the STS researcher’s personal or professional
commitments. But regardless of whether Collins’s or Latour’s view
prevails, the dynamic spirit of critical inquiry loses.
On the surface, Collins and Latour appear to be arguing about the
future of a specialized field of inquiry called “Science and Technology
Studies,” but in fact their attitudes reflect a fundamental disagree-
ment about the prospects of their own knowledge production site, the
university. Collins has steered clear of collaborating with the state and
industry, whereas Latour has been housed in an institution that has
had to develop such networks in order to sustain its research pro-
grams. There is nothing especially mysterious about this difference.
Their respective national academic contexts largely explain it (Fuller
2000, chap. 7). But the difference also reflects an emerging schism,
namely between what fashionable science policy theorists call
“Mode 1” and “Mode 2” conceptions of knowledge production. (For
the provenance of this jargon, see Gibbons et al. 1994.) Collins repre-
sents the Mode 1 conception of university-protected, paradigm-
Fuller / SCIENCE STUDIES AND SCIENCE 9
CAPTURE OR BE CAPTURED:
A SOCIAL EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE PARIS SCHOOL OF STS
the most basic level, university enrollment grew threefold from 1960
to 1970, and then doubled again by the end of the 1980s. The number
of universities and research clusters, although still concentrated in
metropolitan Paris, has increased, thereby reducing the public image
of academic leaders from trusted mandarins to feuding warlords. (In
the field of STS alone, there are at least six research units in the Paris
area.) But most significantly, les grandes ecoles have been forced to
change their mode of domination in French society. While the admis-
sions policies of these institutions are no less elite than in the past, the
power their graduates exert in French society has generally declined,
and the locus of power has shifted from the humanities and public
administration schools to those like L’Ecole des Mines, devoted to
applied science, technology, and business (Bourdieu [1989] 1996).
To be sure, Mitterand had failed in the 1980s to democratize entry
into les grandes ecoles. Nevertheless, the value of professional
degrees in engineering declined with the expansion of less prestig-
ious engineering schools. This has had profound implications for STS,
and sociology more generally, in France. First, it drove home a point of
logic: it is possible for most top managers to be drawn from elite
schools, while the likelihood of an elite graduate becoming a top man-
ager diminishes. This is possible in a society where the elite can con-
trol only entry into its own immediate ranks but not the constitution of
the field of play, which may include additional competitors who bring
other qualities that alter the criteria of, say, leadership potential. Per-
haps the most important intellectual legacy of this shift has been
Pierre Bourdieu’s ([1979] 1984) concept of “symbolic capital” as a
form of knowledge-based power that is only partially determined by
“cultural capital” (e.g., the quality of one’s upbringing and training)
yet potentially convergent with “economic capital” (e.g., where com-
petition for top posts approximates a free market).
Considering Bourdieu’s largely antagonistic stance to the actor-
network approach, it is ironic that his conceptual innovation was
introduced to the anglophone world by Latour and Woolgar (1979,
esp. chap. 5). Bourdieu and Latour can be seen as trying to capture the
same transformation from opposing perspectives: Bourdieu, the
director of the leading state-supported research institute in the social
sciences, critiquing the ways the state has buckled under external eco-
nomic pressures; Latour, the resident sociologist at a leading benefici-
ary of the emerging neoliberal order, denying that the state ever had
much control in the first place.
Fuller / SCIENCE STUDIES AND SCIENCE 17
2. Argue that the special talk surrounding science may have no binding
force on the actions performed at the research site but does constrain
the possibilities for action in administrative and educational settings,
where the appeal to science serves a more explicitly legitimatory func-
tion. In that case, those interested in witnessing the distinctive power
of science would do better focusing their attention on these distribu-
tion points rather than the original “hands-on” sites of production.
3. Somehow try to regiment scientific discourse to live up to its own nor-
mative ideals by subjecting scientific claims to greater scrutiny than
one would ordinarily claim. This would entail a level of suspicion and
discipline that would effectively undermine the so-called tacit dimen-
sion that has traditionally conferred on scientific knowledge its status
as expertise.
If these courses of action are so “obvious,” why are they not cur-
rently pursued by STS researchers? An important part of the answer
lies in the aversion or inability of STS researchers to adopt a perspec-
tive independent of either those under study or, more saliently, those
for whom the study is done. Latour (1997) illustrates the lengths that
some STS researchers will go to pursue the autonomy of scientific
practice from science critique. He argues that critique is morally ob-
jectionable because it presupposes a low opinion of scientific practi-
tioners, whose alleged self-deception provides the only opportunity
for the critic to practice her own trade. Critics treat practices as mere
means to their own ends, while failing to recognize that the most per-
fect constructions are ones whose handiwork is hidden and, hence,
without need of critical improvement.
Latour’s etiology of the critic’s craft is based largely on Bachelard’s
defense of scientific labor from philosophical exploitation, as dis-
cussed in the previous section. However, Latour’s equation of normal
scientific practice with seamless construction harkens to a version of
the theological argument from design, namely, the postulation of a
deus absconditus—a God who builds the world so well that his services
are no longer required. Thus, science works so well that its con-
structed character does not matter, and philosophers are invited to
take leave. The STS researcher, then, is like the Wittgensteinian who
refuses to revise, let alone improve, our understanding of the world,
but merely holds a mirror to it. In this respect, the epistemological
chicken debate discussed in the first section of this article does not go
very deep at all: both Collins and Latour are beholden to the late Witt-
genstein’s normative quietism.
I wish to recover what lies outside the Wittgensteinian horizons of
what Latour (1993, 1997) himself positively dubs “acritical” STS. This
30 PHILOSOPHY OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCES / March 2000
REFERENCES
Ashmore, Malcolm, and Stella Harding, eds. 1994. Humans and others: The concept of
agency and its attribution [Special issue]. American Behavioral Scientist 37:731-856.
Becker, Howard. 1967. Whose side are we on? Social Problems 14:239-47.
Bourdieu, Pierre. [1979] 1984. Distinction. Reprint, Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univer-
sity Press.
. [1989] 1996. The state nobility. Reprint, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Callon, Michel. 1986. Some elements of a sociology of translation: Domestication of the
scallops and the fishermen. In Power, action, and belief, edited by J. Law, 196-229. Lon-
don: Routledge.
. 1987. Society in the making. In The social construction of technological systems,
edited by W. Bijker, T. Hughes, and T. Pinch, 83-106. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Callon, Michel, and Bruno Latour. 1981. Unscrewing the Big Leviathan. In Advances in
social theory and methodology, edited by K. Knorr-Cetina and A. Cicourel, 277-303.
London: Routledge.
Callon, Michel, John Law, and Arie Rip. 1986. Mapping the dynamics of science and technol-
ogy. London: Macmillan.
Castells, Manuel. 1996-98. The information age. 3 vols. Oxford: Blackwell.
Collins, Harry, and Steven Yearley. 1992. Epistemological chicken. In Science as practice
and culture, edited by A. Pickering, 301-27. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Crawford, Hugh. 1993. An interview with Bruno Latour. Configurations 2:247-69.
Fuller, Steve. 1988. Social epistemology. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Fuller / SCIENCE STUDIES AND SCIENCE 31
. 1992. Social epistemology and the research agenda of science studies. In Science
as practice and culture, edited by A. Pickering, 390-428. Chicago: University of Chi-
cago Press.
. 1993. Philosophy, rhetoric and the end of knowledge. Madison: University of Wis-
consin Press.
. 1996. Talking metaphysical turkey about epistemological chicken. In The dis-
unity of science, edited by P. Galison and D. Stump, 170-88, 468-71. Palo Alto, CA:
Stanford University Press.
. 1999a. The governance of science: Ideology and the future of the open society. Milton
Keynes: Open University Press.
. 1999b. Making the university fit for critical intellectuals: Recovering from the
ravages of the postmodern condition. British Education Research Journal 25:583-96.
. 1999c. Review of Castells (1996-8). Science, Technology & Human Values
24:159-66.
. 2000. Thomas Kuhn: A philosophical history for our times. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Gibbons, Michael, C. Limoges, H. Nowotny, S. Schwartzman, P. Scott, and M. Trow.
1994. The new production of knowledge. London: Sage.
Gildea, Robert. 1996. France since 1945. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Glaser, Barney, and Anselm Strauss. 1967. The discovery of grounded theory: Strategies for
qualitative research practice. Chicago: Aldine.
Golinski, Jan. 1998. Making natural knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gouldner, Alvin. 1968. The sociologist as partisan: Sociology and the welfare state.
American Sociologist 3:103-16.
Grint, Keith, and Steve Woolgar. 1995. On some failures of nerve in constructivist and
feminist analyses of technology. Science, Technology & Human Values 20:286-310.
Hughes, Thomas. 1987. The evolution of large technological systems. In The social con-
struction of technological systems, edited by W. Bijker, T. Hughes, and T. Pinch, 51-82.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Knorr-Cetina, Karin. 1999. Epistemic cultures. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Krause, Elliott. 1996. Death of the guilds: Professions, states, and the advance of capitalism,
1930 to the present. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Labinger, Jay. 1995. Out of the petri dish endlessly rocking. Social Studies of Science
25:341-48.
Latour, Bruno. 1987. Science in action. Milton Keynes: Open University Press.
. 1988. The pasteurization of France. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
. 1993. We have never been modern. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
. 1995. Mixing humans and non-humans together: The sociology of the door-
closer. In Ecologies of knowledge: Work and politics in science and technology, edited by
S. L. Star, 257-89. Albany: State University of New York Press.
. 1996. Aramis. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
. 1997. A few steps toward an anthropology of the iconoclastic gesture. Science in
Context 10:63-83.
Latour, Bruno, and Michel Callon. 1992. Don’t throw the baby out with the Bath School!
In Science as practice and culture, edited by A. Pickering, 343-68. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Latour, Bruno, and Steve Woolgar. 1979. Laboratory life: The social construction of scientific
facts. London: Sage.
32 PHILOSOPHY OF THE SOCIAL SCIENCES / March 2000