The American Society For Aesthetics, Wiley The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism
The American Society For Aesthetics, Wiley The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism
The American Society For Aesthetics, Wiley The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
http://www.jstor.org/stable/425882?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
The American Society for Aesthetics, Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
VOL. IX MARCH, 1951 NO3.
THE JOURNAL OF
THOMAS MUNRO
1. Internationalism.
During the last few years, even under war conditions, there has been a nota-
ble growth of interest in aesthetics in the United States. One indication of this
is the establishment in 1941 of the Journal of Aesthetics, and of the American
Society for Aesthetics in the following year. College courses and published
articles in the field are increasing in numbers. But unsettled conditions, at
home and abroad, are slowing the advance. High printing costs obstruct the
publication of scholarly books and magazines, and college students are under
strong pressure to study practical, vocational subjects.
In spite of these obstacles, leaders in various countries are reviving com-
munication, and making aesthetics once more an international subject. Im-
portant publications in each country are noted elsewhere, and international
meetings are again being held. A new generation of American scholars is taking
an active part in the revival of aesthetics on a world scale. Cooperation is es-
pecially active between the American and French groups, now that the latter
has revived its own Societ6 d'Esth6tique, and begun publication of its Revue
d'Esth~tique.
The past leadership of Germany in aesthetics was outstanding, from the
first recognition of the subject as a branch of philosophy in the early 18th century,
down almost to 1939. It was ably carried on by such contemporary figures as
Max Dessoir, Emil Utitz, and Richard Mfiller-Freienfels, in the rich pages of the
Zeitschrift fur Asthetik und allgemeine Kunstwissenschaft, and in an output of
books and articles on the subject which overshadowed that of all other countries
put together. Under these twentieth-century leaders, a series of international
congresses on aesthetics was held in Germany and France, including one in
* Part of this article was published under the title "Present Tendencies in American
Esthetics" in the volume of essays entitled Philosophic Thought in France and the United
States, edited by Marvin Farber and published in 1950 by the University of Buffalo, Buffalo,
New York. This volume provides the basis for a detailed comparison between French and
American philosophy. Thanks are extended to Professor Farber and the publishers for
permission to print the complete article herewith. I have added a few incidental compari-
sons between American and French aesthetics; also some bibliographical notes. These are
merely illustrative and not intended as a selection of the most important writings in either
language. Professor Farber's volume (which appeared also in a French edition) contains
a valuable article by Raymond Bayer of the Sorbonne on "Recent Esthetic Thought in
France," and critical notes by Andr6 Lalande on the portion of my article which appeared
in the book. I recommend the entire volume, comparing present French and American
philosophy in detail, to readers of the present article. The book was reviewed in this Journal
for September 1950, p. 60, by Campbell Crockett.
161
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
162 THOMAS MUNRO
Paris in 1937. Since the recent war, the leadership has passed to France and the
United States. There has been little activity in aesthetics in the British Isles
since World War II, in spite of some excellent work in collateral fields.
In the United States, the subject is still at a rudimentary stage of develop-
ment, by comparison with prewar Germany and with other branches of philoso-
phy in America.' We have produced some important writings on the philosophy
of art from Emerson to Dewey, but with little continuity in research or discus-
sion. No American university has taught it long and steadily, so as to build up
a cumulative tradition of interest and achievement. It is usually taught, if at
all, as an advanced elective course in the philosophy department; less often in
the fine arts, music, English, or psychology department, by some teacher who
happens to be interested in theory. But it is seldom regarded as necessary, even
in a liberal, humanistic curriculum.
Isolationism is slowly giving way to extensive cooperation in aesthetics and
related fields. But American writers still tend to quote chiefly from other Ameri-
cans, while the English quote English sources, the French quote French ones,
and the Germans those in their own language. Reading books on aesthetics
from any of these countries, one is led to imagine a separate line of succession
there, owing little to outside influence; its own writers always leading the way.
This is partly due to national pride; partly to lack of facilities for quick transla-
tion and exchange of ideas.
Complacent isolationism exists also in each specialized branch of scholarship
in the arts. The literary critics have their own little cliques for mutual admira-
tion and quotation, each discussing the other's latest essay as if it were vastly
important and original, requiring only one or two small corrections. Thus each
new generation of sophisticated critics, many of them unfamiliar with philo-
sophical aesthetics, revives in slightly altered wording the ancient perennial
arguments about standards of value, as if they had discovered something radically
new. As in the so-called "New Criticism" of literature, proud claims to origi-
nality are made with slight justification.2 In science, a new demonstration or
discovery is quickly made common property, and used as a starting-point by
later scientists. In aesthetics and criticism, one cannot hope that yesterday's
conclusions will be accepted as final. But there is unnecessary waste of effort
and lack of cumulative progress, when important work in each generation is
almost ignored by the next, and its unfinished researches dropped in the scramble
to appear up-to-date and to quote only the newest, most fashionable authorities.
Recent French and German writings on aesthetics and related subjects have
been little read in the United States.3 A reading knowledge of French and German
has been none too common among our college graduates and artists. The influence
1 Munro, T., "Aesthetics and Philosophy in American Colleges," JAAC (Journal of
Aesthetics and Art Criticism), Vol. IV, No. 3, March 1946, pp. 180-186.
2 "The New Criticism is a very old criticism . . . explication du texte," (Malcolm Cowley
in "The New Criticism," American Scholar, Winter 1950-51, p. 88).
3 For an introduction to recent French aesthetics, see the special issue of this Journal
for June 1949, with articles by Lalo, Souriau, Bayer, Rudrauf, and others, in addition to
biographical and bibliographical notes.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SCIENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 163
4Thorpe, C. D., The Aesthetic Theory of Thomas Hobbes, Ann Arbor, Michigan, 1940.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
164 THOMAS MUNRO
Working in this philosophical tradition, the author of the present essay pro-
posed in 19285 a scientific, descriptive, naturalistic approach to aesthetics; one
which should be broadly experimental and empirical, but not limited to quanti-
tative measurement; utilizing the insights of art criticism and philosophy as
hypotheses, but deriving objective data from two main sources-the analysis
and history of form in the arts, and psychological studies of the production,
appreciation, and teaching of the arts. An empirical, relativistic approach to
aesthetic valuation and value standards was also outlined. The analysis of form
was broadly conceived, not as limited to the mere skeleton or external shell of
the work of art, but as covering the organization of suggested meanings, emo-
tions, and other components.
In 1928, the time was not yet ripe for concerted action along such lines in the
United States; it had to wait another fourteen years.6 Several writers had already
attempted, in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, to establish
aesthetics as an important subject in American scholarship. William Knight's
Philosophy of the Beautiful, a history of aesthetics published by a Scottish writer
in 1891-93, found much of interest in American writings on the subject from
1815 down to Ladd, Scott, Gayley, and the youthful John Dewey. Santayana's
Sense of Beauty was a notable step toward a naturalistic, psychological orienta-
tion in 1896; it still retains considerable vitality. Max Dessoir presented a
forward-looking paper on the "science of art" and its problems in St. Louis in
1904.7 It has been almost completely ignored. Hugo Minsterberg made valiant
efforts, in the early 1900's, to introduce German ideas on the psychology and
teaching of art. They came to grief in 1914. Each similar attempt has suffered
a setback, in part through wars and depressions; in part because conditions had
not yet produced a widespread intellectual need for aesthetics in this country.
That need is now arising, because of events to be described in the next section.
Before long, the history of aesthetics will have to be completely rewritten
from a much more cosmopolitan point of view. It will have to include a great
deal of important art criticism and aesthetic psychology, hitherto ignored in
histories of criticism. Instead of following a single line of apostolic succession
from Plato through Kant and Hegel to Croce and Bosanquet, it will have to
consider much wise theorizing about the arts from China,8 India,9 Japan,'0 the
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SCIENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 165
Near East, Russia, and other cultures besides our own. Knight's Philosophy of
the Beautiful, in 1891, was much more international in scope than either of the
two large histories of aesthetics which have appeared in English since then. It
contained chapters on the beginnings of aesthetics in prehistoric and Egyptian
culture; on the classical and medieval periods; and on modern aesthetics in
Germany, France, Italy, Holland, Britain, America, Russia, and Denmark. By
contrast, Bosanquet's History of Aesthetic, which appeared in London in 1892
and has been scarcely altered since, is narrow and biassed ignoring not only
American contributions but almost everything outside the German transcenden-
talist tradition which Bosanquet admired. Dull and stodgy in treatment, it
persistently omits the vital, stimulating, and colorful aspects of its subject-
matter, the discerning comments of great writers on art and artists, to plod
through the endless course of pedantic speculation about the nature of Beauty.
For the past five decades it has served as a wet blanket, to dampen the interest
of students in aesthetics.
In view of all that had happened since 1892, there was even less excuse in
1939 for Gilbert and Kuhn's History of Esthetic to neglect or misrepresent
American contributions to the field and all attempts at scientific method in
aesthetics. Strongly German and anti-scientific in bias, it condescendingly
dismisses not only American but French and British writings in the evolutionary,
naturalistic tradition (e.g., Herbert Spencer and Grant Allen) with a few com-
pletely inadequate sentences. Santayana and Dewey together are given a total
of four lines (p. 554). Prall gets six words as a mere follower of the German
formalists. Lalo, DeWitt Parker, Dessoir, Basch, and Delacroix are disposed of
together in four and a half lines (p. 554). Dessoir and the whole "general science
of art" movement receive another four lines on page 527. Utitz and Miller-
Freienfels are not mentioned. Thus even German writers unsympathetic to the
authors' point of view are neglected, in spite of world-wide recognition else-
where. Obviously, the history of aesthetics has still to be written, with due
consideration of different schools of thought, and of different national contribu-
tions.
In spite of obstacles, aesthetics as a whole is steadily becoming more inter-
national in scope. It has never been pervaded by narrow chauvinism or blindly
worshipful patriotism. Its leaders have been, on the whole, philosophers with a
broadly humanistic attitude. The few exceptions, as in certain 'Nazi and Soviet
pronouncements on art, are taken seriously only as examples of political propa-
ganda. But one could easily cite examples of leading art historians and philoso-
phers of history, whose racial and national pride has led them to exaggerate
the importance of their own cultural background. If they were Germans, it has
led them to regard all Gothic culture, or all modern western, "Faustian" culture,
as somehow peculiarly German in spirit. There have been Italian scholars, so
York 1912. Coomaraswamy, A., The Mirror of Gesture, New York 1936. Mukerjee, R., The
Social Function of Art, Bombay 1948.
"I Okakura, K., The Book of Tea. Anesaki, 'I., Art, Life, and Nature in Japan, Boston
1932. Binyon, L., The Flight of the Dragon, London 1911.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
166 THOMAS MUNRO
dazzled by the wealth and beauty of their own culture, with its roots in the
classical past, as to ignore or minimize others. Such bias can produce a distorted
view of art history and world civilization, in which one's own spiritual ancestors
are constantly brought to the center of the stage.
All aesthetic theory before the late nineteenth century was cramped and
distorted by ignorance of exotic and primitive styles of art. In Renaissance
humanism and by Winckelmann, it was based largely on the late Greek and
Roman traditions in visual art and literature, and on the Renaissance styles
which carried them on. Hegel regarded the art of advanced oriental civiliza-
tions condescendingly and superficially. Theories of the ideal and beautiful in
art were founded mainly on late Greek principles of naturalistic representation,
balance, and proportion. Gothic art was imitated at times, but was on the whole
compared unfavorably with the classic. While there was so little to compete
with classical art for admiration, one could easily erect it into an absolute norm
of all that was good and beautiful; one could interpret all art history as a process
of groping ascent from the "crude ugliness" of tribal and archaic art to the
pinnacle of neo-classic refinement.
The enlargement of cultural horizons in the late nineteenth and twentieth
centuries has produced a revolutionary effect on recent aesthetics, making it
not only international but intercultural in scope. The data for its generaliza-
tions are coming to be drawn from the artistic products and experiences of all
peoples. We are rapidly losing the complacent assumption that western styles
of art are necessarily the best in all respects. In interpreting these data-for
example, the significance of a Hindu statue-we are learning not to judge every-
thing through modern western eyes, but to understand what the statue meant
to the culture which made it."1
One effect, inevitably, is to make aesthetic theory more relativistic. It seems
more and more unreasonable to appraise the tremendous variety of styles by
any one simple rule or fixed standard. More and more styles of art, which do
not conform to strict neoclassical rules, are becoming accepted by critics,
historians, art museums, and the public. It seems increasingly evident that
each great historic style of art, however strange and repellent it may seem at
first to untrained western eyes, had its own functions and values-perhaps its
own type of beauty-in its own cultural setting. Perhaps all these types of
aesthetic value can be reduced to some one formula; if so, it will have to be an
extremely broad and flexible one. For the present, there is more interest in
observing and describing the infinite variety of ways in which art can be pro-
duced, used, regarded, and evaluated in different cultures.
It is interesting to compare the United States with France as to the relations
between nationalism and internationalism. In some ways, France is highly
cosmopolitan. As the capital of a colonial empire, and as the world's traditional
artistic capital, Paris has long been a center for exotic arts and customs; a
meeting-place of foreign artists and intellectuals. The Mus6e Guimet presents
11 As in A. Coomaraswamy's The Dance of Siva, New York 1924; Elements of Buddhist
Iconography, Cambridge, Mass. 1935; H. Zimmer, Myths and Symbols in Indian Art and
Civilization, New York 1946.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SCIENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 167
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
168 THOMAS MUNRO
tions may suffer accordingly; but at least a few important examples are at
hand for direct study. Not only finished works of art are there, but living artists
in every medium. Art is, and has been for centuries, a vital activity, by which
people earn their living. The practice, enjoyment, and discussion of art have
long been taken seriously as a valuable part of community life. All this provides
an excellent foundation for aesthetic theory.
In America, most of the fine arts have been on a small scale until recent
decades. The American artist in a visual medium had little opportunity to see
great works of art in his own field, except through an occasional trip to Europe,
or in mediocre reproductions. Writers were much less cut off from the great
traditions in their craft; Whitman could read the King James Bible. Even music
scores could be easily imported, though orchestras were few. Today, though the
fine arts are not yet part of the American scene as they are of the European, a
tremendous advance has been made. Museums have multiplied in American
cities, even the smaller ones, and stocked themselves with the world's treasures,
expertly selected and exhibited, so as to astonish the foreign visitor. Motion
picture films, radio, and television bring us music and drama (good and bad in
quality), along with colorful scenes of foreign architecture, costume, and cere-
monial. Books, public libraries, illustrated magazines, bring us literature for
every taste and age-level, with photographic reproductions of the world's art.
We design gardens, watch ballets, join amateur dance or handicraft clubs.
Mass production brings good copies of museum pieces of furniture, pottery, and
painting into modest homes. We are producing some original art, as in the film
and architecture; how much or how good, it is hard for us to say. But all the
principal arts of western civilization are now active here; their products are
available for everyone to enjoy and study. We spend enormous sums on them,
and multitudes of people make a living from them. As a result, the American
critic, historian, and philosopher can now find concrete materials at hand for
researches into the nature of art and artists. For the first time, aesthetics and
art history can be studied in America, not in a purely bookish way, but through
direct observation of a wide range of original works of art.
One accompaniment of the growth of art in America has been the growth of
art education;'2 of instruction in all the arts, both in formal schools and courses,
and in popular articles and lectures. These follow several different lines of ap-
proach. One emphasizes technical training in the practice of the arts; learning
to be an artist. This includes all manner of schools, courses, and treatises in-
tended to help one become a creative painter, sculptor, designer, architect,
short story writer, playwright, actor, composer, or performer of music. Another
type of education emphasizes the appreciation, enjoyment, and understanding
of the arts. To satisfy this demand, museums establish gallery talks, courses,
and public lectures; in print and over the radio, critics explain current tend-
encies in the arts. A third type emphasizes history and chronological develop-
ment; the characteristics of art in successive periods, and the contribution of
individual artists, writers, or composers. Systematic study of this type reaches
12 Whipple, G. (ed.) Art in American Life and Education: 40th Yearbook of the National
Society for the Study of Education, Bloomington, Ill. 1941.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SCIENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 169
a comparatively small audience, mainly on the college level. Still another type
emphasizes educational methods; it seeks to prepare teachers of a certain art.
Ordinarily, such a course of study includes the philosophy and psychology of
education, classroom management, and a little about the school curriculum on
various levels, in addition to the practice and history of the art concerned. The
training of a prospective college instructor usually differs from one on the
secondary level, in bringing in more history of the art and less educational
method. It differs from that of an artist, in having less intensive training in the
technical use of the medium.
3. Specialization and synthesis.
All these various approaches to the arts tend to be highly specialized in
America today, and on the whole, increasingly so. Above the early, elementary
level, the arts are divided into separate courses and departments, with little
cooperation between "art" (i.e., the visual arts), music, and literature. Literature
is minutely subdivided according to language, nationality, and period, with
little study of comparative literature aside from introductory courses on "world
masterpieces." Specialization is least on the lowest grades of school, where one
teacher often teaches all subjects. It is increasingly sharp from junior high
school onward, where rigid departmentalization occurs. It is often extreme on
the college and post-graduate levels, where the idea persists that one cannot be
genuinely scholarly without narrowing down his interests, not only to a single
subject such as the English novel, but to some narrow chronological and geo-
graphical subdivision within it. Advanced students are persistently discouraged,
by the regulations for degrees and by faculty advisers, from trying to study the
arts in a broad, comprehensive way, in relation to philosophy, psychology, so-
ciology, and other subjects which might throw light upon them.
Most theoretical discussion of art is still limited by our compartmental system
to a single art. This is true not only of education but of criticism, on both schol-
arly and journalistic levels. Music is considered by itself, theater by itself,
painting by itself, and literature by itself. The results are often expert, and
significant volumes on the aesthetics, psychology, or formal structure of a
particular art are produced.'3 There are many advantages in such limits, but
no art can be thoroughly understood in isolation. By seeing how they interact
in every period, and how all spring from the same human nature, the same
social settings, we can see more clearly the distinctive features of each. When
the theory of each art proceeds along a separate line, ignoring the rest, it tends
to develop its own jargon, its own inbred provinciality. This may go on for
generations without ever approaching a philosophic conception of the arts.
In some ways, the French educational system is even more deeply and rigidly
specialized than ours, with ancient walls dividing it into compartments. There is
little art or music in the liberal arts curriculum, even on the lower levels, and
that little tends to be stiffly conventional. The idea of giving all students a basic
13 Pratt, C. C., The Meaning of Music, New York 1931. Mursell, J. L., The Psychology of
Music, New York 1937. Haydon, G., Introduction to Musicology, New York 1946. Dudley, L.,
The Study of Literature, Boston 1928. Wellek, R., and Warren, A., Theory of Literature.
New York 1942. Daiches, D., A Study of Literature, Ithaca 1948.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
170 THOMAS MUNRO
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SCIENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 171
14Balet, L., "The History of Art of the Future," JAAC, Fall 1941, pp. 42-62. Winternitz,
E., "Overspecialization and Art Education," Assn. of American Colleges Bulletin, Vol.
XXVIII, No. 2, May 1942, pp. 276-282.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
172 THOMAS MUNRO
cerning the nature of art, beauty, and aesthetic value. Aesthetics of this narrow,
traditional sort has always failed to interest many college students, or to satisfy
the inquiring layman. They find in it, not a unifying approach to the arts, but
another highly specialized little subject, off in a corner by itself, devoted to
endless debate over small technicalities.
To be sure, there is room in aesthetics for intensive researches as well as
general syntheses. But the latter are most urgently needed at present, in liberal
education and by the general public. They are needed especially in the English-
speaking countries, because of the extreme pluralism and disunity of our intel-
lectual life. Reacting against grandiose aesthetic systems of the German type,
we have gone to the opposite extreme, avoiding even that minimum of broadly
systematic thinking which is essential to a rational world view, and which has
been philosophy's distinctive contribution in the past. In a period of rapid
cultural change and mixture, when science is discovering particular facts at
unparalleled speed, there is urgent need for the large-scale, organizing phase
of philosophic thinking.
Much that passes for philosophy today, and that is written by professional
philosophers, does not deserve the name because of its minute specialization.
It should be classed rather as science or historical scholarship. There is need
for intensive, semantic researches on the meanings of "beauty," but these are
not a substitute for the vitally needed, comprehensive interpretation of the
arts. One school of philosophy in American universities is now attempting an
approach to aesthetics in terms of semantics and semiotics.'5 So far, it has been
narrowly preoccupied with a few selected aspects of art: especially its relation
to other kinds of symbol, sign, and meaning. Important conclusions may emerge.
But obviously, this so-called "philosophical" approach is only one more highly
specialized inquiry, concerned with certain abstract characteristics of thought
and communication. It makes no attempt to deal philosophically with the
whole realm of art and aesthetic experience, or with the central, distinctive
problems arising therein.
In the twentieth century, Santayana is the only American philosopher who
has produced any approach to a full-scale philosophic system with a place for
the arts, and he has written little about them since Reason in Art appeared in
1905. Literature is the only art about which he has written with assurance.
Dewey, our other front-rank philosopher, has consciously avoided system-build-
ing. In Experience and Nature and Art as Experience, his far-ranging commentary
on human life was extended, late in his own life, to deal with the aesthetic
realm. He praises the concrete, specific approach in philosophy, but most of his
comments on the arts are abstract and general. In the present generation, we
have produced no comprehensive examination of the arts which is comparable
in scope to G. F. Raymond's huge series on comparative aesthetics, written at
Princeton during the nineties. Obsolete in many respects today, it still sets an
example as a. large-scale application of theory to copious illustrations from the
arts. T. M. Greene's substantial volume on The Arts and the Art of Criticism
(1940) is one of the few recent attempts in America at a large-scale, philosophical
15 Rieser, M., "Brief Introduction to an Epistemology of Art," Jl. of Philosophy, No-
vember 23, 1950, Vol. XLVII, No. 24, p. 695.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SCIENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 173
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
174 THOMAS MUNRO
explain phenomena from widely distant fields. In the nineteenth century "evo-
lution" was such a key idea, and much of the world's best philosophizing on art
and other matters was linked up with it. It served to stimulate and suggest
inquiry in every subject. Today, no single concept holds so central a place in
our thinking, but certainly that of symbolism is near the focus. As Susanne K.
Langer"9 has pointed out, it has important bearings in contemporary logic,
semantics, language, psychology, religion and ritual, visual art, literature,
music, and ethics. Thinkers in fields as remote as psychoanalysis, ethnology,
and the history of Renaissance painting (as in the Warburg Institute researches)
find themselves organizing their discoveries in terms of symbols and mean-
ings-individual and cultural, conscious and unconscious, words and concrete
images. Philosophical synthesis can be exercised with such new tools, on a
moderate scale: e.g., by combining the insights of psychoanalysis and art history
or literary scholarship on the symbolism of a single work of art, such as Hamlet
or Ulysses, Diirer's Melancolia, or Goya's Foolish Fury.20 Such cooperation is
welcomed, not by aesthetics alone, but by each cooperating specialist. The
psychoanalyst today looks to the arts as a rich source of data for understanding
the human mind, but he cannot exploit it without some help from experts in
the field of art.
Every job of synthesis well done has far-reaching repercussions. For example,
it was mentioned above that recent art and art criticism had shown a tendency
to specialize on "pure form"-i.e., on the visual or auditory aspects of painting,
music, or poetry; and to disparage "sentimental associations." This was a
fruitful temporary line of experimentation. But now, we are discovering that
art can have a wealth of other, unsuspected meanings, of many different kinds.
This in turn affects the kind of art produced. Surrealists and other modernists
are trying to exploit such meanings (e.g., unconscious, dream symbolism) as a
source of interest and emotional power.
4. The joining of several streams of thought in present aesthetics.
There has been a marked change in American aesthetics in recent years. It is
branching out vigorously, to include more study of the arts themselves, as well
as of theories about them. It is now commonly conceived as the subject which
seeks to describe and explain, in a broadly theoretical way, the arts and related
types of behavior and experience. It considers the aesthetic experience of nature
and of other types of object in addition to works of art. It is no longer a mere
branch of speculative philosophy, since it incorporates many data and methods
from the sciences, as well as from direct observation of aesthetic phenomena.
It has not abandoned the traditional, philosophical approach, emphasizing
beauty and value; but it also takes in what Dessoir and his associates called
allgemeine Kunstwissenschaft, or general science of art.2" This comprises the more
19 Langer, S. k., Philosophy in a New Key, a Study in the Symbolism of Reason, Rite and
Art, Cambridge, Mass. 1942. Bernheimer, R., "Concerning Symbols," Art: a Bryn Mawr
Symposium, Bryn Mawr, Pa. 1940.
20 Wight, F. S., "The Revulsions of Goya: Subconscious Communications in the Etch-
ings," JAAC, Vol. V, No. 1, September 1946, pp. 1-28.
21 Dessoir, M., Aesthetik und allgemeine Kunstwissenschaft, Enke, Stuttgart 1906, 1923.
Cf. Ducasse, C. J., "Aesthetics and the Aesthetic Activities," JAAC, Vol. V, No. 3, March
1947, pp. 165-177.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SCIENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 175
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
176 THOMAS MUNRO
nized as a class apart, philosophers discussed them in a general way. Plato and
Aristotle both discussed the functions, values, good and bad effects, which music
could have in society, and advanced criteria for judging music to be good or
bad. Beauty and sensuous pleasure were considered, among other effects of art
such as the moral and intellectual. St. Augustine feared the moral and spiritual
dangers of sensuous beauty in art.
Such philosophizing involved some factual description of the general charac-
teristics of the arts and of certain styles, such as the "soft Lydian airs" of music.
It also involved the evaluation of art as good or bad, and the setting up of
general norms. It involved penetrating insights into the psychology of art pro-
duction and aesthetic experience, as in the theories of catharsis and divine
madness. This too was mixed with dogmatic appraisals of different kinds of
artist and mental attitude as good or bad. There was no systematic attempt,
until modern times, at objective, factual accounts of art or aesthetic psychology,
which would avoid evaluative judgments. Philosophers rationalized their ap-
praisals in accordance with their religious, metaphysical, and moral assumptions.
Nevertheless, we now see that these appraisals were all conditioned by the
cultural environment in which the philosopher lived, and by his individual
personality. For example, Plato's philosophy was conditioned by the small,
city-state culture of his time, and by the fact that his beloved teacher was
executed by the Athenian populace. His greatness enabled him to rise above
local, temporary conditions more than most other men have, so that his judg-
ments are often acceptable to people in other cultures; they seem perennially
enlightening whether one agrees with them fully or not.
Plato's meditations, and those of other great philosophers of art, are important
for aesthetics today in two principal ways: (a) as historical and psychological
phenomena; as evidence of ways in which the arts were regarded in different
cultures, and by different types of individual; (b) as hypotheses to guide further
investigation; the insights of early wise men being often far ahead of science in
certain respects, suggesting theories which science later verifies in part.
The development of a scientific approach to art and aesthetics, as described in
this article, does not mean that the philosophical approach is becoming outmoded
or unnecessary. The two are and should be supplementary. But the highly
abstract, speculative approach has too long monopolized the field of aesthetics;
it must now make room for others. It is only the a priori, dogmatic, and tran-
scendentalist schools of philosophy, which scorn to cooperate with natural science,
that are becoming obsolete. Between scientific aesthetics and a naturalistic,
empirical philosophy of art, there is no quarrel whatever. For example, the
influence of Dilthey's empiricism and his theory of world-views, which coincide
in many ways with the teachings of John Dewey, is increasing in American
aesthetics.22
In America, George Santayana's Reason in Art and Dewey's Art as Experience
both belong in the category of "philosophy of art," rather than in "science of
art." They are full of philosophical wisdom and insight; they discuss the varieties
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SCIENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 177
of form and experience in the arts with some fullness, instead of confining them-
selves to empty generalities about beauty. In such discussion, they constantly
blend evaluation with description of observable facts. Their methods are those
of the philosopher and not of the scientist, with many sweeping statements which
appeal to the reason and cultivated taste of the reader, but do not attempt
demonstration through detailed experiment or specific evidence. At the same
time, they incorporate some of the scientific information of their day, about the
psychology and sociology of the arts.
It is comparatively easy to work out a broadly synthetic theory of the arts on
a personal, subjective basis; that is, for the philosopher to say what the arts mean
to him. Much past philosophy of art has really been of this type, although put
forward as objectively true. It is a harder task to work one out on a more objective
or intersubjective basis, through coordinating recent scientific knowledge and
theory from a great variety of sources. Most American writing in aesthetics is
still somewhere between the two; rather personal and dogmatic in attitude, yet
with some effort to apply the latest scientific concepts. Many readers are satis-
fied with this informal combination. Some prefer the frankly personal expression,
the "adventures of a soul among masterpieces." Others wish to see aesthetics
become still more scientific and objective, even though it cannot be completely
so.
23 Farber, M. (ed.), Philosophic Thought in France and the United States, p. 272.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
178 THOMAS MUNRO
literary aestheticism." Clever, casual essay-writing about art can achieve fine
literary art in its own right, with occasional deep insights, but not the continuous
development of tested knowledge. When the aesthetician tries to create art at
the same time that he explains it, he risks doing neither very well. He must be
ever watchful of his style and cleverness, ever careful not to be dull or boresome
for a moment. Unfortunately, science often has to be dull and boresome in its
endless scrutiny of details, its dogged pursuit of a single train of thought far
beyond the point where it ceases to be amusing. Masquerading as aesthetic
science, urbane and witty generalities about art and artists often tend (as in
France today) to conceal the absence of genuine scientific inquiry in the field.24
The latter must follow its own more sober course if it is to get anywhere.
Again, this is not to say that aesthetics should sever all relations with art
criticism or with literary discussions of art. It will always find there valuable
data for analysis, in the shape of recorded experiences with art, individual and
cultural attitudes toward art, the processes of forming, applying, and revising
standards of value. More and more critics today approach their problems in a
partly scientific spirit, with some awareness of theoretical advance in fields
related to their own. With these aesthetics will continue to cooperate.
7. Aesthetics in the narrow sense, as theory of beauty.
Through a series of technical discussions in eighteenth and early nineteenth
century German philosophy the word "aesthetics" came into use, derived from
the Greek word for "perception." Originally referring to sensuous knowledge, it
came to signify a branch of philosophy concerned with beauty, especially in the
fine arts, but also in nature.
In the works of some philosophers, "aesthetics" covered a wide field, identical
with "philosophy of art" as just described; that is, it considered the particular
arts. Hegel made it cover a philosophy of art history. On the whole, however, the
tendency was to narrow "aesthetics" down to the single problem of beauty and
aesthetic value;2" to the question of whether judgments of value and claims to
superior taste in art have any objective basis, or rest on mere personal preference;
also to the relations between aesthetic value, moral value, and metaphysics.
Whereas the philosophy of art had included much theorizing on the facts of art,
aesthetics in this narrow sense became largely normative, neglecting problems
of art history and psychology. Theories of beauty and aesthetic value ranged
from extreme absolutism and religious dogmatism to extreme relativism and
naturalism. Leaders in the naturalistic approach, especially in England, were
mostly hedonists, emphasizing sensuous pleasure as a standard of value. In
Germany, the leading philosophers were mostly idealists, emphasizing the role
of art as an expression of the cosmic mind.
8. So-called "experimental aesthetics"; the laboratory or psychometric approach
to the psychology of beauty and aesthetic preference.
24 Malraux's Psychology of Art has many merits, but is not a psychology of art.
26 Andr6 Lalande, in his widely-used Vocabulaire technique et critique de la philosophie
(Paris 1947, p. 291) repeats the traditional definition of esthetique as "Science ayant pour
objet le jugement d'appr6ciation en tant qu'il sapplique A la distinction du Beau et du
Laid. "
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SC IENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 179
This branch of aesthetics has also been largely concerned with the nature of
beauty, sensory pleasantness, and aesthetic evaluation. But its methods have
been more descriptive, factual, empirical, and quantitative. As a rule, it does not
make or defend evaluative judgments about art, but observes and describes
certain external aspects of evaluation. It tries to ascertain in an open-minded
way what people actually consider beautiful. Occasionally, evaluative assump-
tions are concealed in a mass of statistical details. This occurs when the investi-
gator assumes that majority preference actually makes a thing more beautiful;
or when he assumes that certain "experts" really know what is best, and then
judges people's taste as good or bad, according to whether they agree with the
experts.
Psychometric aesthetics (a more exact term than "experimental") follows the
lead of Fechner whose Vorschule der Aesthetik in 1876 helped bring about the
experimental approach to general psychology. It emphasizes statistical studies
of aesthetic preference, especially of what kinds of visible shape, proportion, and
color combination are considered most beautiful or pleasing by the greatest
number of persons. The objects to be judged are usually not complete works of
art, but simple geometrical figures, arrangements of dots or strips of color, etc.
Hence this approach is, in its own way, almost as abstract as the philosophical
theories of beauty. Supposedly, Fechner's approach was "from below," or from
empirical data; but in practice it has paid little attention to the complex types
of form which are actually encountered in art and nature. Its data consist rather
in certain behavioristic responses, expressions of preference by the persons tested.
In the early 20th century, Fechner's approach was actively pursued in the
United States by Witmer and others. It has weakened in recent years. In ex-
perimental psychology, now a huge, diversified science, quantitative researches
are still occasionally done on problems related to art and aesthetic preference.26
The psychometric approach is only one small element in the contribution of
psychology to modern aesthetics, and in the scientific approach to aesthetics.
9. Tests and measurements in the field of art.
A special application of the psychometric approach is that of standardized test
devices which claim to measure and rate the individual's taste or judgment of
values in art, or even his aptitude for becoming a creative artist.27 They are
especially popular in American education, where standardized tests of intelli-
gence, aptitude, and achievement in other fields have been used with some
success. There is continuous demand for them in art education, and new ones
are constantly appearing on the market. In general, Americans have great faith
in standardized mass-production methods, in applied science, and in anything
presented with imposing claims to scientific, mathematical accuracy, however
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
180 THOMAS MUNRO
superficial that scientific air may be. Such tests usually present the subject
with pairs of pictures or other art works (garments, room interiors, etc.), and
ask him to tell which he prefers, or which is "better." The test assumes that one
of each pair is objectively better, and that a subject who prefers the other is
"wrong" or has inferior taste. Supposedly correct choices are obtained as a rule
from a consensus of supposed "experts" selected by the author of the test, or
by taking well-known pictures, passages of music, etc., and altering them to
produce a "spoiled" version. Sometimes vague, high-sounding "art principles"
such as unity, balance, and rhythm are invoked, with no recognition of the
problems involved in applying them concretely. The usual effect of such tests is
to penalize all deviation from adult, conventional norms of taste in that par-
ticular environment, since the student who prefers the "right" examples gets a
high grade. The relativity of aesthetic values is ignored, no allowance being
made for legitimate differences in taste and style (e.g., for variations according
to age and cultural background), or for the fact that different art forms may
be desirable under different circumstances. Some credulous teachers use them
with harmful results for students; others become skeptical about all attempts
at measurement in the aesthetic field.
When less exaggerated claims are made, statistical methods can be used to
advantage in analyzing tastes and works of art. Unwarranted claims to appraise
art ability, taste, or value in general can and should be avoided. Instead, the
test can deal with more specific, factual matters: e.g., differences in taste with-
out inferring that some are "better" than others; specific effects of altering a
work of art in various ways; specific abilities such as "absolute pitch" and
power to perceive and remember visual patterns. In addition, the techniques of
educational measurement can be used to aid the teacher in making his admittedly
subjective, arbitrary judgments (as in the necessary grading of students' work)
a little more clear and careful, with explicit recognition of debatable criteria,
and no claims to absolute finality.
10. Kunstwissenschaft; science or knowledge of art.
This movement has consisted largely in historical studies of the visual arts.
It includes such related subjects as determining the authenticity, date, and
provenance of a work of art. It differs from "philosophy of art" not only in being
thus restricted, but in being more neutrally descriptive in aim; it seeks to ascer-
tain the facts, rather than to appraise them. As distinguished from the earlier
art history and from art criticism, it aims at objectivity and generalization,
describing styles as historical facts without assuming or arguing that one is
better than another. Much of it has been minutely specialized art history, devoted
to ascertaining and recording particular facts, such as the date and origin of a
certain work of art. There is no clear distinction between Kunstwissenschaft and
Kunstgeschichte, and many scholars in art prefer the latter name.28 Scientific
methods can be used, of course, in discovering particular facts, as well as general
28 The Reportorium far Kunstwissenschaft began publication in 1876 in Stuttgart, under
the editorship of Franz Schestag, a Vienna museum curator, as an outgrowth of the first
congress on Kunstwissenschaft, held in Vienna in 1873. Its pages have been devoted more to
specialized history than to theory.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SCIENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 181
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
182 THOMAS MUNRO
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SCIENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 183
concerned with factual, scientific studies of the arts from many points of view-
psychological, sociological, religious, and other-whether it be distinguished from
aesthetics or included in a broader concept of aesthetics."'
The French society, which was organized before the second world war as
L'Association pour l'tude des Arts et les Recherches relatives a la Science de l'Art,
was dormant during the war. It was revived in 1945 under the simple title,
Socigtg Frangaise d'Esthetique. Its quarterly magazine began publication in 1948
under the title Revue d'Esthetique. The list of topics discussed by both the
French and the American Society and periodical makes it clear that "science of
art" is now covered by the single word "aesthetics." The term allgemeine Kunst-
wissenschaft and its English translation, "general science of art," have never
found much favor in the United States. They are cumbersome and raise un-
necessary controversy over whether there can be a "science" of art, strictly
speaking. Some prefer "philosophy of art," but that term suggests the old,
restricted status of the subject as a branch or application of philosophy. It seems
to deny the subject's modern aspiration to be a distinct, major field of investi-
gation, based on observation of the arts rather than on deduction from
philosophical principles, and cooperating with the sciences quite as much as
with specialized philosophy.
The very fact that aesthetics as a subject has been so undeveloped in America
has prevented its name from acquiring the definite meaning, restricted to the
philosophy of beauty, which Dessoir and his friends found obstructive. It is
correspondingly easier, for those who now seek to establish it as an important
subject in American higher education, to give the word "aesthetics" the newer,
broader interpretation. Only a few American writers3' have sought to preserve
the sharp distinction between aesthetics and the science or philosophy of art.
Of course, if we could start with a clean slate, it would not be hard to find a
better name than "aesthetics," with its many confusing associations. But it is
fairly well established in the broader sense, and a new name would be hard to
substitute.
Flexibility in changing the names and scope of academic subjects is charac-
teristic of the American educational system. In Germany and France, where
universities have long been under strongly centralized, state control, such changes
are more difficult. Here it is comparatively easy to establish a new subject,
department, or professorial chair, or to work out informal, cooperative courses
between different departments. In Germany, where aesthetics had considerable
academic prestige, it was usually taught by a full professor, as a branch of system-
atic philosophy. Special courses on it were usually given by instructors of
lower rank. Little or no recognition was given to allgemeine Kunstwissenschaft as
a definite university subject. In spite of the great theoretical advances made by
Dessoir and his group, and their success in building up a miscellaneous public
interested in the "general science of art," neither they nor the French had gone
very far before World War II, in establishing it as a major academic subject.
12. French and English contributions.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
184 THOMAS MUNRO
It would be going too far to give the Germans full credit for it, or for the
scientific, naturalistic approach to aesthetics. French, English, and American
scholars during the past seventy-five years have done a tremendous amount of
objective research in the history of all the arts, and in the description of styles,
which parallels the Kunstwissenschaft movement in Germany. The French have
their own scientific tradition in aesthetics, stemming largely from Comte, Taine,
and V6ron. Taine stated its objectives clearly in the first of his lectures on The
Philosophy of Art, delivered in 1864, and thus antedating the German leaders in
Kunstwissenschaft.32 Hennequin, Galabert, and others in the nineties outlined
further approaches to scientific aesthetics, such as esthopsychologie, or aesthetic
psychology: "the science of works of art considered as psychological documents
concerning their authors or the public which admired them."33 Paul Val6ry and
Victor Basch, on the eve of World War II, opened the Second International
Congress on Aesthetics and the Science of Art by pointing out the ways in which
aesthetics can make use of scientific aid in attacking its own central problems,
such as the nature and conditions of aesthetic pleasure, and the "laws" or re-
currences in art history.34 Charles Lalo had discussed the methodology of a
broadly scientific aesthetics in 1908, with a review of previous German, French,
and English work, and had then proceeded into many fields--especially music
and literature-with his penetrating psychological and sociological analyses.A5
Etienne Souriau in 1929 outlined a future course for scientific aesthetics.36
Monod-Herzen, Lehel, and Lucien Rudrauf attempted the morphology or struc-
tural analysis of artistic forms.37 Boug1s's Evolution of Values placed the sub-
ject of aesthetic value in a context of naturalistic sociology. France has had many
first-rate cultural historians and analysts of style, such as Male in the medieval,
32 The aim was "defining the nature and marking the conditions of existence of each art. "
Such a study "imposes no precepts, but ascertains and verifies laws." It "Considers human
productions, and particularly works of art, as facts and productions of which it is essential
to mark the characteristics and seek the causes, and nothing more. . . . Science neither
pardons nor proscribes; it verifies and explains. It does not say to you, despise Dutch art
because it is vulgar, and prize only Italian art. . . . Science has sympathies for all the
forms of art, and for all schools, even for those most opposed to each other. . . . It accepts
them as so many manifestations of the human mind. . . . It is analogous to botany, which
studies the orange, the laurel, the pine, and the birch with equal interest; it is itself a
species of botany, applied not to plants, but to the works of man. By virtue of this it keeps
pace with the general movement of the day, which now affiliates the moral sciences with the
natural sciences."
33 Lalande, Vocabulaire, p. 291. Hennequin, E., La Critique scientifique, Paris 1888.
Galabert, E., Les fondements de l'esthetique scientifique, Paris 1898; Revue Internationale de
Sociologie, 1898, pp. 1-15.
34Discours liminaires by Paul Val6ry and Victor Basch, in Deuxibme Congrbs Interna-
tional d'Esthetique et de Science de l'Art, Paris 1937, pp. XII, LI. Basch was appointed in
1918 as the first professor of aesthetics and science of art at the Sorbonne.
36 L'esthetique experimentale contemporaine, 1908; Les sentiments esthetiques, 1910;
L'art et la vie sociale, 1921; E19ments d'une esthetique musicale scientifique, 1939; L'esthe'tique
du rire, 1949, and others.
36 L'avenir de l'esth~tique: essai sur l'objet d'une science naissante.
3 Monod-Herzen, E., Principes de Morphologie gen&ale, 1927; Marguery, E., L'oeuvre
d'art, 1929; Lehel, F., Morphologie comparee des arts, 1930; Rudrauf, L., L'Annonciation,
1943.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SCIENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 185
and Grousset in the oriental field. Henri Focillon, in his essay on The Life of
Forms in Art and in his lectures at Yale and other universities, made a notable
contribution to the "general science of art" in America. He disliked "aesthetics,"
in the old sense, but was a leader in scientific aesthetics nevertheless from his
vantage point as an art historian.
In England, Grant Allen's Physiological Aesthetics (1877) was a landmark in
the scientific approach. Banister Fletcher's monumental History of Architecture
on the Comparative Method first appeared in 1896. It gives a comparative analysis
of the Gothic, Classic, and Renaissance styles in regard to general plans, walls,
openings, roofs, columns, mouldings, and ornament, with many concrete examples
and a discussion of geographical, geological, climatic, religious, social, and his-
torical influences on style. Works of this type qualify as Kunstwissenschaft and
as aesthetics in the broad present sense, whether or not their authors so labelled
them. But in the English-speaking world of recent years, theoretical studies
within a single art have not been linked up systematically with those in other
arts, or with philosophic aesthetics. This is true of many important British
studies in special fields related to aesthetics, such as those of Frazer in cultural
anthropology and folklore, of Havelock Ellis on the dance and on the psychology
and literature of sex, of R. G. Moulton on literary form,38 of Donald Tovey on
music analysis, of Roger Fry and Herbert Read on visual art. The ingredients
for scientific aesthetics are present, but more thorough synthesis is needed.
The time is overdue for bringing these ingredients together, first of all through
a large-scale program of bibliographies, translations, critical summaries, and
publications in different languages; second, through more thoroughly integrated,
original syntheses. For this purpose, a clear conception of the new and broad
extent of aesthetics is essential. Much of the writing, now accepted by aestheticians
as important for their subject, is not so labelled. An author, with the old concep-
tion of "aesthetics" in mind, may even deny that he is writing about it, or has
any interest in it. Many such reluctant collaborators are being claimed by
aesthetics, willy-nilly. This makes it hard to survey current trends in the sub-
ject. It would be easy to limit one's account to the few recent publications, most
of them highly specialized, which are explicitly classed as aesthetics. But that
would give a very inadequate picture of what is happening on a larger scale.
In saying that aesthetics is expanding to include "general science of art," we
do not, then, refer only to the work of German aestheticians, psychologists, and
art historians. To Dessoir belongs the chief credit for publicizing the need of
cooperation between philosophical aesthetics and empirical studies of the arts.
He advanced the subject more by promoting cooperation among different groups
of scholars, and by combining their contributions, than by any particular new
discovery or theory of his own. The German-writing school of cultural historians,
from Burckhardt through Fiedler, Riegl, Wlfflin, Dilthey, Cassirer, Hermann
Schneider, Spengler (in spite of his many errors), Leichtentritt, Sachs, Panofsky,
and others, have made great indirect contributions to aesthetics through show-
ing the role of the arts in the history of civilization. Important supplementary
38 The Ancient Classical Drama, Oxford 1890; The Modern Study of Literature, Chicago
1915, etc.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
186 THOMAS MUNRO
work is coming from other countries and other subjects: especially psychology,
anthropology, and the cultural history of the orient. Thus we have seen, flowing
into contemporary aesthetics, many streams of thought and investigation which
had nothing directly to do with the German "science of art" movement, even
though they can be broadly grouped under that heading.
13. Can aesthetics be a science? Criteria of scientific status.
There has been a good deal of argument as to whether aesthetics is a science,
or can ever become one. The answer depends, first, on what we include within
the field of aesthetics; and, second, on the definition of "science" we accept.
There are several correct ones, according to the dictionaries.
In the narrow sense, which emphasizes exact measurement, aesthetics is not a
science and will not become so in the near future. A small amount of measure-
ment is being done in aesthetics, of works of art and related psychological
phenomena. Works of art can be measured in some respects with considerable
accuracy: for example, as to the dimensions of buildings and vases, the shape
and placing of lines in a picture, the sequences of rhythmic and pitch variations
in music.39 Overt behavior can be statistically measured, as in votes of preference
or other expressions of opinion, and in popular demand for this or that kind of
art.40 But many deeper phases of art and aesthetic experience e.g., the specific
emotional suggestiveness of music, painting, and poetry-are far too complex
and variable to be measured accurately at present. The scope for significant
measurement in aesthetics is gradually increasing, and will continue to increase.
But there is much spade-work to be done in the preliminary grouping, analysis,
and interpretation of phenomena before exact methods will be of major impor-
tance-
Exact quantitative laws and formulas are seldom attained outside the realm
of physical science. Economics uses them increasingly; anthropology and political
science, comparatively little. Even in biology, where exact methods have grown
considerably since Mendel, there is a great deal of important investigation which
cannot be stated in precise quantitative terms. Croce is right in charging that
"the inductive aestheticians have not yet discovered one single law." But "laws"
in the old-fashioned, absolutistic sense of invariable uniformities in nature are
scarcer than we used to think, even in the physical sciences. Instead, the scien-
tist now talks rather in terms of averages, correlations, and over-all trends.
These emerge gradually out of the multiplicity of data in all realms. We do not
measure them exactly, all at once, but gradually refine our quantitative esti-
mates.
It is misleading to restrict the concept of science to fields where measurement
is highly developed, as many physical scientists insist on doing. It seems to
relegate all humanistic investigation to the outer darkness of mere guesswork.
It obscures the important relative differences, in degree of development along
3Y Vitruvius, De Architectura, Bk. III. Birkhoff, G. D., Aesthetic Measure, Cambridge,
Mass. 1933. Hambidge, J., Dynamic Symmetry in Composition, Cambridge, Mass. 1923.
Schillinger, J., The Schillinger System of Musical Composition, New York 1941.
40 Farnsworth, P. R., Trembley, J. C., and Dutton, C. E., "Masculinity and Femininity
of Musical Phenomena," in this issue.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SCIENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 187
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
188 THOMAS MUNRO
make mistakes, but on the whole they make their living by guessing correctly as
to what people of different kinds will like enough to pay for, in the realm of art.
Educational experiment with the use of different kinds of art is constantly in-
creasing our understanding of what effects each type will have on the thoughts,
emotions, and abilities of different types and ages of student. Organized religion
and government have used art since prehistoric times to influence the feelings,
thoughts, and actions of the public. Greater understanding of the psychological
means of such control leads to greater power in exercising it. The results of such
practical observation and experiment do not often get into textbooks on aes-
thetics; they are more likely to appear in a book on the psychology of adver-
tising. Such dissociation among the various approaches to understanding the
arts is characteristic of this transitional period.
There is no reason why science should limit its experimental study of control
through art to the often trivial concerns of advertising and the often harmful
aims of political propaganda. It can examine the power of art to produce any
kind of effect, desired or undesired; individual or social; aesthetic or practical;
sensuous, emotional, intellectual, or spiritual. It can study the effects of varying
any type of artistic stimulus in relation to the other variable factors concerned.
There are many ways in which prediction, or estimate of probability, is be-
coming an important task of aesthetics. Some are concerned with appreciation,
taste, preference, enjoyment, liking, and so on. The problem may concern a
particular individual at a particular time: what will be his response to a particular
work of art? It may be hard or impossible to predict it, because of the many
variable factors (e.g., transitory moods and attitudes) within him which are
inaccessible to view. If the problem concerns a large group of persons belonging
to a well-defined type, over a long period of time, prediction becomes more
dependable, as in actuarial science; the minor variations and momentary devia-
tions cancel out.
Another type of prediction in aesthetics is concerned with the production of
art. What types of art will be produced in the near and far future? Here again it
is hard to tell in a particular case: what kind of picture will a certain boy draw
tomorrow, if left to himself? One can predict only in certain general charac-
teristics normal to his age-level, etc. The larger inquiry takes us into the realm
of art history: of styles and style trends. We are just beginning to discern the
main outlines of the past history of styles in each art, and in art as a whole:
the broad inclusive trends, such as the alternation of classic and romantic,
Apollonian and Dionysian, throughout the world. As we learn to plot the curves
of past and recent tendencies, we naturally speculate about the future: can one
prolong or project a certain curve into the next quarter century? Will a certain
basic cycle recur, as it has many times before? Similar questions arise in economics
and other social sciences. One is never quite sure; unforeseen factors may break
in; but the margin of error is progressively reduced. Already, in art, there is a
great deal of trained guesswork as to future trends in production: especially in
a1 Munro, T., "Knowledge and Control in the Field of Aesthetics," JAAC, Vol. I, No. 1,
Spring 1941, p. 1. Frank, L., "The Integrative Role of the Arts in Personality." Eastern
Arts Ass'n Yearbook, 1950, p. 17.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SCIENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 189
the realm of fashions in clothing. Science can gradually increase their dependa-
bility. Trends in production and in taste or appreciation are of course intimately
connected: each influences the other; they never diverge very far.
We owe largely to Auguste Comte the idea that the sciences develop in a
certain order, the earlier ones providing necessary means or foundations for the
later ones. Mathematics, he pointed out, first entered the "positive" stage; then
astronomy, physics, chemistry, biology, sociology. The advance has been from
simple to complex: the earlier sciences describing the world in respect to a few
comparatively simple and constant characteristics such as number, magnitude,
and mass; the later ones describing more and more complex and variable phe-
nomena such as those of human society. Each science presupposes its prede-
cessors. Comte did not envisage psychology as a special science, but divided its
phenomena between biology and sociology. His theory was incorrect in some
respects, but on the whole it has been confirmed by later events. Mathematics
employs logic. The physical sciences depend to a large extent on mathematics.
Biology, which made a decisive step toward science in the 18th century with
the logical classifications of Linnaeus, Cuvier, and others, now uses mathematics
and chemistry to an increasing extent. The social sciences, which advanced
toward scientific status in the early 19th century, use the concept of evolution
and other tools derived from the biological, physical, and mathematical sciences.
Next to achieve scientific status was psychology, formerly "the philosophy of
mind," which adopted experimental methods in the late 19th and early 20th
centuries, through the efforts of such men as Helmholtz, Fechner, Wundt, and
William James. Their observation was partly in the laboratory, partly clinical
(as in the case of Charcot and Freud), partly in the outside world of human
behavior. It was heavily indebted to previous biological work on the anatomy,
physiology, and pathology of the brain and nervous system. Psychology is still
learning how to make full use of the social sciences, such as anthropology, with
their information on the varieties of psychic phenomena in different cultures.
These general facts about the history of science apply significantly to the
present situation in aesthetics. No subject can become a full-fledged science
until the prerequisites have been provided by the older sciences. Before then, it
may have individual pioneer steps, brilliant anticipations, but no concerted,
systematic procedure along scientific lines. Attempts to introduce the latter before
the prerequisites are available will be premature and disappointing. This occurred
in aesthetics in 1876, when Fechner tried to introduce laboratory measurement.
He did not then succeed in making aesthetics scientific, because the chief pre-
requisites were not yet in existence. Without them, the central phenomena of
art and aesthetic experience were inaccessible and mysterious. Indirectly, Fechner
helped to provide the necessary tools; through helping to establish the new,
experimental psychology, he did much to lay the foundation for scientific aes-
thetics in the twentieth century.
14. Development of the prerequisites for scientific aesthetics.
To an extent not commonly realized, the necessary tools and materials for
scientific aesthetics have been developed since 1900. Let us briefly summarize
three groups of them, in particular.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
190 THOMAS MUNRO
In the first place, a sufficient amount and variety of works of art are now avail-
able, to allow generalization about the arts of mankind on a broad scale. For the
first time, we now have a fair sampling of the chief art products of all the prin-
cipal civilizations, nationalities, and stages of development. There are still large
gaps in our knowledge, but we can see world art as a whole in a way impossible
as late as 1900. This applies to the visual arts, where our data for comparison
include a much wider sampling of oriental, archaic, and primitive arts.42 This is
due in part to archeological excavation; in part to exploration, travel, commerce,
museum techniques, and improved methods of reproduction, as in color-prints
and casts. It applies to world literature, where improved translations and new
editions are now available on a much greater scale. It applies to music, where
new phonograph and sound-film recordings are bringing us exotic music such as
that of India, Java, and the African tribes, as well as much unfamiliar European
music of the Baroque, Renaissance, and Middle Ages.43
In the second place, the social sciences have cooperated to document these
works of art for us historically and culturally: to help us understand them by
seeing them, not merely as museum exhibits, but in their cultural setting." They
show us the status and functions of art and artist in various times and places.
Anthropology and ethnology are showing us the meaning of primitive and
oriental arts, in relation to the entire culture-pattern in which they were pro-
duced, including religious, social, economic, moral, technological, and other fac-
tors. Slowly, this approach is being extended to the complex and diversified
higher civilizations of east and west.45
In the third place, recent psychology has given us a general, naturalistic
description of human nature; of its physiological basis, its animal origin, its inborn
mechanisms, powers, and processes of learning; its cycle of growth and senescence
in personality and mental abilities. We are given an account of such basic func-
tions as visual and auditory perception, emotion, and conation. Psychoanalysis
and depth psychology have explored the life of fantasy in its conscious and un-
conscious levels; the nature of emotion and motivation. All these have a direct,
obvious bearing on the arts.4" The processes and mechanisms involved in the
creation and appreciation of art are now seen to be, not fundamentally unique
or separate, but special applications of those which occur in all other main realms
of human activity.47 Before scientific psychology had given us this general frame-
work of human nature, it was impossible for aesthetics to lift itself, by its own
bootstraps, into an understanding of art.
42 Boas, F., Primitive Art, Cambridge, Mass. 1927. Linton, R., and Wingert, P. S., Arts
of the South Seas, Museum of Modern Art, New York 1946.
43 E.g., the phonograph albums Musik des Orients, African Native Music, and
L'Anthologie Sonore: this last with program notes by Curt Sachs.
44 Kroeber, A. L., Configurations of Culture Growth, Berkeley, Calif. 1944; Anthropology,
New York 1923, 1948. Sorokin, P. A., Social and Cultural Dynamics, New York 1937, Vol. I.
Mumford, L., The Culture of Cities, New York 1938. Mead, M., "The Role of the Arts in a
Culture." Eastern Arts Ass'n. Yearbook, Kutztown, Pa., 1950. p. 10.
41 Benedict, R., Patterns of Culture, Boston 1934; The Chrysanthemum and the Sword,
Boston 1946. Mumford, L., Technics and Civilization, New York 1934.
46 Schneider, D., Psychoanalysis and the Artist, New York 1950.
47 Art in American Life and Education, Ch. XXIV.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SCIENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 191
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
192 THOMAS MUNRO
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SCIENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 193
66 Heyl, B. C., New Bearings in Esthetics and Art Criticism, New Haven, Conn. 1943.
Morris, C., Signs, Language, and Behavior, Prentice-Hall, New York 1946. "Aesthetics and
the Theory of Signs," Jl. of Unified Science, Vol. VIII, 1939, pp. 131-150. Hess, M. W.
"Symbolic Logic and Aesthetics," Jl. of Philosophy, Vol. 37, 1940, pp. 579-581. Creed, I. P.,
"Iconic Signs and Expressiveness," JAAC, Vol. III, No. 11-12, pp. 5-14. Amyx, C., "The
Iconic Sign in Aesthetics," JAAC, Vol. VI, No. 1, September 1947, pp. 54-60.
56 Kahn, S. J., "Psychology in Coleridge's Poetry," in this issue.
57 Kardiner, A., and others, The Psychological Frontiers of Society, New York 1945.
Linton, R., The Cultural Background of Personality, New York 1945. Bateson, G., and
Mead, M., Balinese Character, N. Y. Academy of Sciences, New York 1942. Kluckhohn, C.,
and Murray, H. A., (eds.) Personality in Nature, Society, and Culture, New York 1949.
Haring, D. G. (ed.), Personal Character and Cultural Milieu, Syracuse, New York 1948.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
194 THOMAS MUNRO
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SCIENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 195
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
196 THOMAS MUNRO
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SCIENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 197
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
198 THOMAS MUNRO
63 George Santayana, in a letter to the author from Rome, recalling the latter's enthu-
siasm for primitive Negro sculpture, added, "There is a theme for your Society to investi-
gate philosophically and scientifically. I am glad that you are approaching the vast subject
of the arts from that side, rather than from that of precepts and taste. The philosophers
have written a good deal of vague stuff about the beautiful and the critics a good deal of
accidental partisan stuff about right and wrong in art. If you will only discover why and
when people develop such arts and such tastes, you will be putting things on a sounder
basis." (JAAC, Vol. IV, No. 2, December 1945, p. 131.)
64 Dewey, John, Theory of Valuation, Chicago, Ill. (Reprint from International Encyclo-
pedia of Unified Science, Vol. II, No. 4) 1939, 1943.
65 Lepley, R. (ed.) Value, A Cooperative Inquiry, New York 1949. Hilliard, A. L., The
Forms of Value, New York 1950.
66 Chambers, F. P., Cycles of Taste, Cambridge, Mass. 1928; The History of Taste, New
York 1932. Allen, B. S., Tides in English Taste, Cambridge, Mass. 1937. Schucking, L. L.,
The Sociology of Literary Taste, London 1944.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SCIENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 199
with what results;67 their relation to other cultural factors; how they express
different attitudes, culture-patterns, motivations, and stages in social develop-
ment; what ends and functions art has served, both consciously and uncon-
sciously; what effects each type of art tends to have on and for different types of
person under different conditions.68 The functions and experiences thus examined
include both instrumental and immediate or consummatory, utilitarian, and
aesthetic; perceptual, emotional, cognitive, and other.
Much that was formerly expressed in terms of value is now expressed in more
descriptive terms. For example, one can state that a certain kind of art is con-
ducive to certain specific ends which are approved by certain groups or types
of person in a certain culture and period, one's own or another. Such generaliza-
tions tend to be explicitly limited and relative in scope, as a correlation between
specific variables; they do not assert that something is good or bad in general.
Particular styles of art, or characteristics of art, are recognized as conducive to
particular kinds of aesthetic effect, so that the artist can use them as means to
that end if he so desires; but this is not to say that they are always right. Past
rules and precepts for good art, formerly regarded as universally true, are now
regarded as expressions of a certain temporary cultural attitude, associated
with the production of a certain style of art. They suggest possible means and
ends to the modern artist, showing him how to produce many different effects,
and they help us understand the motivation of past styles. Standards and
judgments of value are recognized as open to criticism and correction in some
respects:69 e.g., as involving verbal ambiguities or logical fallacies in reasoning,
or as based on misconception of the facts. They may assume a false belief as to
the effect of certain kinds of art on health or moral conduct; e.g., the effect on
children of films dealing with crime. Also, one may recognize that a certain kind
of taste is motivated by juvenile attitudes, limited experience, neurotic conflict,
or temporary passion inconsistent with the individual's more stable character
configuration. This does not mean that it is bad taste, but it helps one to under-
stand it, and to work out one's own tastes and standards in the light of this
knowledge.
Much aesthetic evaluation can be descriptively expressed as (a) a prediction
as to the probable future effects of a work of art, immediately, instrumentally,
or both; (b) an estimate as to the relation between such probable effects and the
set of aesthetic and moral standards accepted by the individual or group, as
conforming or conflicting with them. The work of art can be described, after
investigation, as conducive or non-conducive to certain effects; hence, perhaps,
as successful or unsuccessful in achieving a certain end which the artist aimed
at, or which the observer expects and desires in works of this type.
67 Boas, G., A Primerfor Critics, Baltimore 1937. Munro, T., "The Verification of Stand-
ards of Value," Ji. of Philosophy, May 25,,1922. Hungerland, H., "Suggestions for Procedure
in Art Criticism," JAAC, Vol. V, No. 3, March 1947, pp. 189-195. Leichtentritt, H., "Aes-
thetic Ideas as the Basis of Musical Styles," JAAC, Vol. IV, No. 2, December 1945, pp.
65-73. Cazden, N., "Musical Consonance and Dissonance: a Cultural Criterion," JAAC,
Vol. IV, No. 5, September 1945, pp. 3-11.
68 Schoen, M. (ed.), The Effects of Music, New York 1927. Wells, K. M., "The Fugue as
an Expressive Vehicle," JAAC, Vol. VI, No. 4, June 1948.
49 Santayana, G., Reason in Art, Ch. X, "The Criterion of Taste," New York 1905.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
200 THOMAS MUNRO
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SCIENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 201
Science can never prove that an individual ought to like or desire something
which his entire personality structure, his innate endowment, and cultural
conditioning impel him to detest. Modern occidental culture cannot prove to a
primitive, ecstatic, thaumaturgic culture that its own rational, practical, extro-
verted aims are best. But for those who already accept its general aims and
premises with regard to the values of life and the trustworthiness of logical,
empirical reasoning, science offers help in achieving those values more fully and
effectively through art. It may hope to show, for example, how mental and
physical health, social cooperation, earthly happiness and pleasure, the growth
of perceptual, imaginative, and intellectual powers, variety and richness of
experience, can be most effectively achieved through the arts if one wants to
achieve them. Such techniques can never be reduced to a simple, static formula.
The most effective means will vary too much in relation to individual differences
and changing conditions. But they will not vary completely. Human nature and
its environing conditions also display much that is similar, enduring, or recurrent.
Therein lies the hope for generalized, flexible, relativistic value-standards which
will express more than an individual's passing fancy. Though not eternal or
universal, they will express fairly widespread, enduring tendencies in specific
age, sex, and personality types and in large cultural groups, Thus they will
offer help in making both social and individual evaluation more informed and ra-
tional, for those who wish it to become so.
Investigation is producing a multitude of tentative generalizations, subject to
change with increasing knowledge, as to the tendency of certain types of art to
fulfill iertain functions or lead to certain consequences, depending on the per-
sonalities and circumstances involved. They vary greatly in degree of generality:
some attempting to show that certain tendencies hold true for human nature on
the whole, or at least for all adult, civilized humanity, as constant behavior-
traits underlying all cultural variation. However, philosophy is not limited to
generalizations of maximum breadth, which are often so abstract as to have
little importance in theory or practice. There is need for more studies of inter-
mediate breadth in aesthetics.
There is also need for scientific help in the practical work of evaluating art.
While philosophers debate interminably over the theoretical possibility of value-
judgments, these are being made on every hand without much help from science
or philosophy. Teachers of the arts have to grade their students' work and
award prizes and scholarships.70 Historians praise some artists and ignore
others. Critics are paid to advise us -what plays to see, what music to hear, and
what books to read. Official commissions pass on plans for public parks and
buildings. Museum officials purchase works of art. There is too great a gap
between this practical, everyday work of aesthetic evaluation and the ab-
stractions of philosophic value-theory. The latter could help to make evaluation
more informed and intelligent, more conscious of its standards and the reasons
for them, more specific as to means and ends. At the same time, it could learn
something about evaluation from observing and cooperating in this work.
70 Art in American Life and Education, Bloomington, Ill. 1941, Chs. XXIII (Munro),
XXVII (Faulkner), XXX p. 599 (Patzig). Beverley, F., "The Art Teacher and Evaluation,"
in Art Education, Today, New York 1949-50, p. 85.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
202 THOMAS MUNRO
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SCIENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 203
73 Reid, J. R., A Theory of Value, New York 1938, Ch. VIII, "Naturalistic Standards."
Cf. Aiken, H. D., "Criteria for an Adequate Aesthetics," JAAC, December 1948, pp.
141-148, with discussion by Boas, Ducasse, and Pepper.
74 Rau, C., "The Aesthetic Views of Jean-Paul Sartre," JAAC, December 1950, p. 139.
Ames, V. M., "Existentialism and the Arts, " in this issue.
7 Coomaraswamy, A., The Transformation of Nature in Art, Cambridge, Mass. 1934.
Morey, C. R., Christian Art, New York 1935.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
204 THOMAS MUNRO
This is not the place to debate religious or metaphysical issues. But one or
two points should be clarified in passing. It goes without saying that aesthetics
in a democracy, such as France or the United States, is a field in which radically
different beliefs and approaches can flourish. Its professional societies and
journals in both countries have explicitly welcomed such difference of opinion.
The pragmatist will look to see what fruits are produced by each school of
thought; if ancient schools, now out of fashion, can be fruitfully revived, so
much the better for everyone. But it is sometimes hard to tell what creed should
get the credit for a particular achievement. People are never quite consistent,
and a philosopher may be a supernaturalist in some respects, a naturalist in
others. There are many possible areas of agreement and cooperation between
persons whose beliefs on metaphysical ultimates are at opposite poles. Disagree-
ments often turn out to be partly verbal.
Vigorous proponents of supernaturalism and transcendentalism, in one form
or another, have not been lacking in our time. Croce was a doughty fighter in
his recent attack on Dewey's aesthetics.76 Maritain and other Neo-Thomists
have recalled to many Americans that medieval Catholicism had a definite
philosophy of art, surprisingly flexible in relation to post-impressionist experi-
mentation.77 The late Ananda Coomaraswamy stoutly belabored modern natural-
ism in art and art theory, while defending the so-called Philosophia Perennis,
which, he believed, had been shared by all true philosophers of east and west.
"Mr. Coomaraswamy's bate noire," writes Katharine Gilbert,78 "is aesthetics.
Since he fixes the meaning of the term by its etymology, and does not believe in
progress, it would seem futile, for one who believes in the history of aesthetics
as precisely the progressive enrichment of understanding in matters relating to
art, to argue with him." Many of the faults for which he berates aesthetics have
long been attacked and discarded by modern aestheticians; many of the things
he urges have long been done. Holding a narrow definition of aesthetics, and a
false conception of modern art as concerned only with sensuous appearances and
pleasures, he ignores the tremendous amount of work which has been done in
recent aesthetics on the moral, intellectual, and cultural significance of art.
Nevertheless, his own interpretations of oriental art and the oriental philosophy
of art have been eagerly accepted by aestheticians, critics, and historians of all
schools. They are invaluable aids in freeing modern aesthetics from occidental
provincialism, and giving it the international, cosmopolitan scope described in
the first section of this article. Coomaraswamy's anti-empiricist doctrine seldom
interfered with his keen, visual observation of works of art. His historical at-
tributions, his generalizations on styles in Indian art, are objective Kunstwissen-
schaft of a rigorous type. On the whole, his work is among the most valuable of
76 Croce, B., "On the Aesthetics of Dewey," JAAC, Vol. VI, No. 3, March 1948, pp. 203-
207. Dewey, J., "A Comment on the Foregoing Criticisms," Ibid., pp. 207-209.
77 Maritain, J., Art and Scholasticism, New York 1930. Chapman, E., "Some Aspects of
St. Augustine's Philosophy of Beauty," JAAC, Spring 1941, pp. 46-51. Hart, C. A., "The
Place of Aesthetics in Philosophy," JAAC, No. 6, 1943, pp. 3-11. Callahan, L., A Theory of
Esthetic According to the Principles of St. Thomas Aquinas, Washington 1947.
78 Gilbert, K., Review of Coomaraswamy's "Why Exhibit Works of Art?" Art Bulletin,
Vol. XXX, No. 2, June 1948, p. 157.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SCIENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 205
all American contributions to the subject he denounced. Aside from his rather
naive and misinformed attacks on modern western art, science, and culture, it
is acceptable to scholars of all philosophical creeds. Likewise, one can disagree
with the basic principles of a St. Thomas, a Hegel, a Marx, an Emerson, or a
Spengler, and yet find much to admire and accept in their incidental observations
and comments by the way.79 Some supernaturalists remain forever rapt in
contemplation of the Absolute, or of a personal deity; others descend from time
to time into the world, and have mundane experiences in common with other
mortals. They can talk of art in its phenomenal aspects, and find a common
ground of discourse with men of other creeds. It is only when they denounce
and try to obstruct what men of other creeds are doing and believe important,
that serious clashes arise. Naturalism in aesthetics has no quarrel with the various
current brands of mysticism, supernaturalism, and immanent pantheism, except
when they seek to obstruct and discourage all approaches but their own. It
welcomes their positive contributions, which are many and rich, to the under-
standing of religious art and of aesthetic and mystical experience as actual
phenomena of human life. They explain phenomena and point out values which
are often ignored by occidental science and lost in modem life. To what extent
these can be achieved along with naturalistic beliefs and attitudes is a question
for the future.
The attacks of such men as Croce80 and Coomaraswamy on naturalism are
based on constant misrepresentation of it, in distorted summaries and quotations
out of context. Naturalism is persistently identified with crass materialism, with
devotion to the crudely sensual and sordid, with antagonism to "the spirit" and
to all the finer things of life, with the idea that art is "entirely physical," and
with every mistaken theory of history and psychology advanced by Victorian
evolutionists. Moderate attitudes are distorted into extreme ones. Any defense
of scientific method in aesthetics is construed as a rejection of all philosophical
aesthetics, or as a belief that beauty can be measured, or that aesthetic values
can be decided by majority votes. Such misinterpretation has been heard less
frequently in recent years.
If and when aesthetics becomes a full-fledged science, it will not cease to be
philosophical.8" It may not be formally classed as a branch of philosophy. Those
working in it may prefer, like present-day psychologists, to have their field
classed as a separate field of investigation, and not as "philosophy of art." But
such divisions are merely for convenience. Every science today still retains
connections with philosophy, its ancient ancestor; it contains areas of com-
paratively philosophical thinking. Those physicists who analyze basic physical
concepts and assumptions such as matter, space, and energy; those who systema-
79 See H. D. Aiken's review (Jl. of Philosophy, August 25, 1948, p. 500) of Cory, H. E.,
The Significance of Beauty in Nature and Art, Milwaukee 1947.
80 Croce, B., "Aesthetics," Encyclopedia Britannica, 14th ed. He speaks of "a hopeless
attempt to solve the problems of aesthetics, which are philosophical problems, by the
methods of empirical science." For Croce's other work, see Roditi, E., "The Growth and
Structure of Croce's Philosophy," JAAC, Spring 1942, pp. 14-29.
81 Edman, I., "The Challenge of the Arts to Philosophy," Jl. of Philosophy, Vol. XLIV,
1947, pp. 407-413.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
206 THOMAS MUNRO
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
AESTHETICS AS SCIENCE: ITS DEVELOPMENT IN AMERICA 207
types and historic styles of art. In the logical and semantic approaches to aes-
thetics, emphasis is usually placed on the verbal and other forms in which
concepts, propositions, and inferences about aesthetic phenomena-e.g., value
judgments-are expressed. In the sociology, anthropology, and ethnology of art,
or in approaches to aesthetics from those standpoints, attention is divided
between art products and the human individuals, groups, and activities related
to them. The anthropologist is careful not to regard works of art as museum
specimens, detached from their life contexts; whereas the morphological approach
must do so to some extent, just as biologists bring plants and animals to the
laboratory for comparative analysis of their structure. Aesthetic morphology,
however, is not to be understood as limited to the dead, static aspects of struc-
ture; it includes dynamic aspects analogous to the life activities of the plant
or animal, as described by physiology and etiology.
In aesthetic value-theory, attention is distributed rather evenly between works
of art, human beings, and verbal or other expressions of evaluation. It is con-
cerned, not only with the apperceptible characteristics of works of art, but with
human feelings, desires, emotions, as aroused by them and directed toward
them. It is concerned with standards and judgments of value as phenomena of
individual and social behavior toward works of art. It is concerned with how
works of art fit into various culture-patterns of organized motives, interests,
goals, and moral standards, as more or less conducive or non-conducive to
approved ends.
Neither the psychological nor the philosophical approach is limited to any
one branch of aesthetics. In every branch, psychology is used. In all, there
are comparatively philosophical areas, and comparatively specialized, or super-
ficial ones.
There are many ways of thinking about art which can be roughly grouped
as applied aesthetics. All are still embryonic as subjects, though often energetic
and influential. They apply current knowledge and theory in the practical
management and use of the arts. These include, first, the practice of art; the
use of aesthetics in the production and performance of the arts. It is a disputed
question, how much the artist can and should use aesthetic theory, or learn
about it. Much depends on the type of artist, and also on the type of theory.
In the past, it has not been of much direct help; it may obstruct the imagination,
and it is often ultra-conservative, lagging behind art movements. But artists
use aesthetic theories more than they realize, usually in a careless, uncritical
way. Perhaps the new kind of aesthetics will be of more use to them.
Other lines of practical activity in which aesthetics is being increasingly
applied are education in the arts, and the arts in general education; therapeutic
uses of the arts, especially in psychopathology; the industrial management of
the arts, as in the theatrical, concert, publishing, and building industries; social
and political uses of the arts, for constructive ends in the achievement of social
welfare. Such applications of aesthetic ideas contribute to aesthetic theory itself,
by the experimental testing out of hypotheses, and the gathering of data through
experience.
This content downloaded from 194.27.18.18 on Wed, 13 Apr 2016 06:05:06 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms