Nietzsche On Ressentiment and Valuation
Nietzsche On Ressentiment and Valuation
Nietzsche On Ressentiment and Valuation
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at .
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ips. .
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
International Phenomenological Society is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.
http://www.jstor.org
Philosophyand Phenomenological
Research
Vol. LVII, No. 2, June 1997
The paper examines Nietzsche's claim that valuations born out of a psychological
condition he calls "ressentiment" are objectionable. It argues for a philosophically
sound construal of this type of criticism, according to which the criticism is directed at
the agent who holds values out of ressentiment, ratherthan at those values themselves.
After presentingan analysis of ressentiment,the paper examines its impact on valuation
and concludes with an inquiry into Nietzsche's reasons for claiming that ressentiment
valuation is "corrupt."Specifically, the paper proposes that ressentiment valuation
involves a form of self-deception, that such self-deception is objectionable because it
undermines the integrity of the self, and that the lack of such integrity ensnares the
agent in a peculiar kind of practical inconsistency. The paper ends with a brief review
of the problems and prospects of this interpretation.
I. INTRODUCTION
In a well-known passage of the Preface to On the Genealogy of Morals,
Nietzsche writes that the book aims to answer two questions: "underwhat
conditions did man devise these value judgments good and evil? and what
value do they themselves possess?" (GM, Preface, 3).1 He also insists that
determiningthe origin of moral values is only a "means"to addresshis "real
concern," namely, "the value of morality"(GM, Preface, 5; cf. 6). In other
1
I will use the following standardabbreviationsto refer to Nietzsche's works:
A = TheAntichrist
BGE = Beyond Good and Evil
D = Daybreak
EH = Ecce Homo
GM = On the Genealogy of Morals
GS = The Gay Science
HTH = Human,All Too Human
WP = The Will to Power
Z = Thus Spoke Zarathustra
All the translationsare Walter Kaufmann's, except The Antichrist and Daybreak trans-
lated by R. J. Hollingdale.
6 This is notably true, for example, of the judgment that compassion is good: it might ex-
press genuine "nobility" (GM, I, 10) or "richness of personality" (WP, 388) or, on the
contrary, "ressentiment" (GM, III, 18; WP, 373), self-contempt (Z, II, 16) or the self-in-
terest of the weak (BGE, 260). For a general statementof this ambiguity,see BGE, 293.
I. RESSENTIMENT
1. Mastersand Slaves
Nietzsche startshis analysis of ressentimentby refininga distinctionbetween
the types of the "master,"or "noble,"and the "slave"which he introducedand
developed in works priorto the Genealogy (HTH, 45; BGE, 260). We know
from these early descriptionsthat the good life as the noble mastersconceive
of it includes "political superiority":"the noble felt themselves to be men of
a higher rank"(GM, I, 5; cf. also 6; BGE, 257-58). Nietzsche's use of the
notions of "(noble) master"and "slave" is ambiguous. They are now socio-
political categories, and now charactertypes. The noble mastersvalue politi-
cal supremacy qua noble in the socio-political sense, but we will see that
their valuing political power is not essential to their possessing a noble char-
acter. Nietzsche makes clear that nobility as a type of character is "the case
that concerns us here"(GM, I, 5; cf. 6).7 Accordingly, I will consider the cat-
egories of "noble"and "slave"in theirsocio-political sense as elements in the
illustration of an essentially psychological view which makes use of the
same notionsto denote specific charactertypes.
To the fundamentaldistinction between noble and slaves, the Genealogy
adds a new crucial refinement:it suggests that, within the noble class, two
subgroups compete for political superiority, namely the "knights"and the
"priests."Leaving aside the question of the historical plausibility of this ex-
ample (Nietzsche alludes to the war between the Romans ("knights")and the
Jewish ("priestly")people [GM, I, 16]), I want to draw out some of its psy-
chological lessons. The importantfact is that the priests, who are physically
"weak" and "unhealthy,"are defeated by the "powerful physicality" and
"overflowing health" of the knights, and consequently develop a pervasive
7 One consequence of this fact is worth noting. The socio-political predicament of the
agent who exemplifies a character-typemight (but need not) contributeto his developing
a characterof that type. A slave from the socio-political standpointmight well develop a
noble character.
NIETZSCHE
ONRESSENTIMENT
ANDVALUATION 285
sense of "impotence"(GM, I, 6-7). Some featuresof the example need to be
emphasized.
First, the salience of physical strength and weakness is a purely contin-
gent aspect of Nietzsche's example. The weakness of the priests creates their
feeling of impotence only because they hold it responsible for the loss of
their political supremacy.The noble knights seem to be generally intellectu-
ally deficient, in any case inferior in that respect to their rivals, the priests
(GM, I, 7). But this does not spawn a feeling of impotence because they do
not see this deficiency as the incapacityto realize theirvalues-indeed they do
not seem to regard it as a weakness at all. But there is no reason to think
that,in differentcircumstances,the feeling of impotencewould not be created
by intellectual,ratherthanphysical, weakness.8
Second, the feeling of impotence is not a temporarystate of mind caused
by an accidentalreversal of fortune.It must ratherhave become an essential
featureof one's self-assessment:the agent sees himself as irremediablyweak,
instead of temporarilylacking the strengthhe customarilyhas. Though Niet-
zsche is unclear on this issue, his analysis of ressentiment(as I understandit
here) presupposes that the priest believes he has tried everything he could
thinkof to regain power and failed. Accordingly,he does not see his defeat as
a fluke, but as evidence of his constitutional impotence (GM, I, 6), which
appearsto be, for that very reason, "incurable"(see GS, 359). It thereforein-
hibits any furtherattemptto recoverpolitical power.
Finally, the priest evidently refuses to accept, or resign himself to, his
impotence. The priest's sickliness does not eradicate his "lust to rule," but
only makes it "moredangerous"(GM, I, 6). Furthermore,ratherthan subsid-
ing, as it would in the case of resignation, the hatred the priest harborsto-
wards his victorious rivals, the knights, "grows to monstrous and uncanny
proportions"(GM, I, 7).
From this overview of Nietzsche' s example, we can derive the
fundamentalfeaturesof ressentiment.It is a state of "repressedvengefulness"
(GM, ibid.) which arises out of the combination of the following elements.
First, the "manof ressentiment"desires to lead a certainkind of life, which
he deems valuable: thus the priest, a member of the nobility, values a life
that includes political supremacy. Second, he comes to recognize his
2. Resignation,reflectiverevaluationand ressentiment
First of all, the agent who is convinced of his impotence could simply resign
himself to it. Such a resignationwould have to be quite radical:it would not
simply consist in relinquishingone way of life he values but feels incapable
of living to adopt anotherwhich he finds just as valuable. It is ratherthe re-
nunciationof the kind of life he values most and the acceptanceof the unre-
deemable shame which goes with global failure. This alone would offer a
formidableincentive to resist resignation.
Nietzsche suggests that, in addition, an importantfeature of the priest's
predicamentmakes resignation to political inferiority all but impossible. As
a member of the nobility, the priest expects to enjoy political superiority.
Expectations, as I understandthe notion in this context, are essentially rela-
tive to the agent's estimation of himself. An agent might believe that a cer-
tain sort of life is worth living and yet not expect to be able to live it because
he has a very low estimationof himself, of his abilities and standing. Such is
the attitude of the slave: "not at all used to positing values himself, he also
attached no other value to himself than his masters attachedto him" (BGE,
261). Thus the slave accepts his masters' high estimation of the noble life
and theirlow estimationof himself, and thereforenever even forms the expec-
tation to live the life his mastersvalue. The attitudecharacteristicof the slave
is his resignationto a worthless way of life.
The situationis quite differentwith the priests who belong-and we must
underlinethis fact-to the nobility (GM, I, 6-7). The noble, it should be re-
memberedfeel "themselvesto be of a higherrank"(GM, I, 5). Like other no-
ble, but unlike the slaves, the priests fundamentallyexpect to live the sort of
life they find valuable, which is, in Nietzsche's example, a life that includes
political superiority.Accepting their impotence and inferiorityis all but im-
in opposing their enemies and conquerors were ultimately satisfied with nothing less than a
radical revaluationof their enemies' values, that is to say, an act of the most spiritual revenge.
For this alone was appropriateto a priestly people, the people embodying the most deeply re-
pressed priestly vengefulness. (GM, I, 7)
9 The notion of expectation is introducedto explain why the priest and the slave react dif-
ferently to their inability to satisfy a desire they nonetheless share. The agent's estimation
of himself, which fosters or undermines expectations, must be understoodin terms of a
feeling of entitlement which is related to a general conception of an "orderof things."
The priest expects to share in the attributes of nobility because it is somehow in the
"order of things" that he should. The slave does not develop such an expectation pre-
cisely for the same reason, since he accepts the noble conception of the "order of
things." Unfortunately,Nietzsche offers no account of the origin of this feeling of enti-
tlement: he only distinguishespsychological types in terms of its presence or absence.
288 BERNARDREGINSTER
So, the "manof ressentiment"has recourseto a quite peculiarform of revalu-
ation which I will call 'ressentimentrevaluation.'
Before I turn to the analysis of ressentiment revaluation, I should offer
some supportfor my claim that Nietzsche's "priest"is the personificationof
the "man of ressentiment."This is controversialbecause, on more than one
occasion, Nietzsche appears to maintain that ressentiment revaluation is a
"slave revolt" (e.g., GM, I, 10). Nevertheless, I believe that Nietzsche saw a
profound affinity between the "priestlytype" and ressentimentfor a number
of reasons of which I will mention only the most importantones.
First, in Beyond Good and Evil, Nietzsche had alreadyoffered an account
of master and slave moralities from which both the notion of ressentiment
and the type of the priest are conspicuously absent (BGE, 260). These two
notions are introducedtogether in the account of the Genealogy, which sug-
gests thatNietzsche sees an intimateconnectionbetween them.10
Ressentiment revaluationcannot be the work of the slaves, for, as Niet-
zsche repeatedly insists, the slave does not create values, a privilege which
belongs exclusively to the masters(cf. BGE, 261). The slave, Nietzsche sug-
gests, blindly accepts his masters' values-and this is, arguably,what makes
him a "slave" (in the psychological sense) in the first place. The so-called
"slave morality"is not the system of values which the slave does create, but
which he would create, on the mere "supposition"he were capable to do so
(BGE, 260).
Ressentimentrevaluationis a "slave revolt" not because it was fomented
by the slaves, but because it consists in negating "noble values" (see GM, I,
7-8), and so presumablyfavors the "slave"or the "commonman."But there
is abundantevidence that the revolt was in fact lead by the (Jewish) priests,
whom Nietzsche describes as a segment of nobility, albeit an essentially
"unhealthy"one (GM, I, 6-7).11
10 Nietzsche describes the account of master and slave moralities he offers in Beyond Good
and Evil as a "typology" (BGE, 186), and not a "genealogy": it merely records the dif-
ferences between the two moralities, but does not explain their origin, in particularthe
origin of slave morality.It is thus very temptingto considerthat both the notion of ressen-
timent and the type of the priest are introducedprecisely to provide such an explanation.
The choice of the Jewish people as a paradigmaticinstance of a "priestlypeople" makes
the connection between priestliness and nobility particularlyevident. The Jewish people
share the noble feeling "to be of a higher rank"since, after all, they regard themselves
as the "chosen people."
1. Ressentimentand 'sourgrapes'
At first glance, ressentiment revaluationmight seem akin to the revaluation
illustratedby Aesop's famous fable of the fox and the sour grapes.12 Unable
to reach the grapes it covets, the fox attemptsto get rid of its feeling of frus-
trationby persuadingitself that the grapes were sour and so were not what it
wantedanyway. Nietzsche's emphasison the spiritualcharacterof the priest's
revenge might suggest that he imitates the fox. He might tell himself that
the military superiorityof the knights and their physical power do not consti-
tute genuine power. "I do not wage war," we might imagine him proclaim-
ing, "becausethe physical power which sustains military superiorityis not a
markof real power:real power lies exclusively in spiritualachievements."
In this case, the priest would not change his values, nor would he believe
he cannot, ultimately,realize them. His revaluationwould only concern what
will bring about that realization: as not all grapes are sweet, so not every
form of power is 'real' power. Thoughhe is not deceived aboutwhat desire he
wants to satisfy, he is deceived about what will and will not satisfy it.
But in fact the priest's revaluationis far more radical than the fox's. As a
result of his defeat at the hands of the warriors,he denies the value of politi-
cal supremacyaltogether. And by the same token he condemns all the atti-
tudes that help to secure and sustainit, namely the lust to rule, arrogance,ha-
tred, envy, revengefulness,and the like. In otherwords, the values themselves
2. Ressentimentrevaluationand reflectiverevaluation
Unlike reflective revaluation, ressentiment revaluationis not motivated by
the recognition that certain attributes,like political supremacy,really do not
have the value that was hithertoattributedto them. Ressentimentrevaluation
is ratherdriven by the way in which the "manof ressentiment"relates to the
attributeswhose value he ostensibly denies: he still values them, but feels
unable to acquire them, and yet he refuses either to give up his desire for
them or to accept his inability to acquire them. Nietzsche's central insight
consists in seeing ressentiment revaluation as the eminently paradoxical
attemptto accommodatethis twofold refusal.
On the one hand, the revaluationaccommodatesthe feeling of impotence
of the "manof ressentiment"by exempting him from the pursuit of an ideal
he regardshimself unableto realize:
When the oppressed, downtrodden,outraged exhort one anotherwith the vengeful cunning of
impotence: "let us be different from the evil, namely good! And he is good who does not out-
rage, who harmsnobody, who does not attack, ..."-this, listened to calmly and without previ-
ous bias, really amountsto no more than: "we weak ones are, after all, weak; it would be good
if we did nothingfor which we are not strong enough"(GM, I, 13).
292 BERNARDREGINSTER
those desires: "these weak people-some day or other they too intend to be
strong, there is no doubt of that, some day their kingdom too shall come"
(GM, I, 15). Ressentiment revaluation is thus the priest's way of securing
the satisfaction of his desire in spite of his conviction that he does not have
what it takes to satisfy it.
Nietzsche's central insight about ressentiment valuation is perhaps best
summarizedin the following text: "Masterstroke:to deny and condemn the
drive whose expression one is, to display continually, by word and by deed,
the antithesis of this drive-" (WP, 179). The "man of ressentiment" pro-
fesses to act accordingto some ideals but he is in fact motivatedby desires he
regards as incompatible with the realization of those ideals. Such a discrep-
ancy between the values that appearto the agent to motivate him and the de-
sires that really do need not be a manifestationof ressentiment:it could just
as well be the result of psychological inertia, or of weakness of will. A brief
comparativeanalysis of these phenomenashould strengthenour grasp of the
distinctive featuresof ressentiment.
14 For example, in his Confessions (Trans. R.S. Pine-Coffin [Penguin Books, 1961]), Saint
Augustine recounts his efforts to strike down his pride in orderto devote himself humbly
to the love of God. Acutely aware of the difficulties of any such conversion, he observes
for example that "even when I reproach myself for it, the love of praise tempts me.
There is temptationin the very process of self-reproach,for often, by priding himself on
his contempt for vainglory, a man is guilty of even emptierpride"(Book X, 38). As I un-
derstandit, the crucial featureof Augustine's example is that the reprehensiblemotive of
personal glory, however powerful, is only residual. It is not a case of ressentiment insofar
as the very valuation of humility is not motivated by pride, though the effort to become
humble always risks being recuperatedby it.
15 The agent will also react very differently to the disclosure of his motivational deception.
The reflective agent (leaving aside the special case of the agent who takes excessive
pride in his moral achievements) will accept the disclosure without difficulty. It is merely
a mistake or an accidental relapse which he will not see as evidence of an essential
weakness, but rather as the natural resistance of old habits to new ways. The "man of
ressentiment," by contrast, will refuse, "as a matterof principle"(WP,179), to acknowl-
edge that his actual motivation is not his professed one. I have already pointed out that
this self-deception is indeed essential to the success of the implicit project of his revalua-
tion: it still covertly aims to realize the values it denies in spite of the agent's conviction of
his inabilityto do so.
5. Ressentimentand resentment
The English 'resentment'can be used to refer to the phenomenonNietzsche
calls 'ressentiment.' However, it is also used in a more restricted moral
sense. 16 Moral resentmentmust be distinguishedfrom Nietzschean ressenti-
ment since the latteris introducedto explain the origin of the morality which
the formerpresupposes.I believe we should distinguishthem as follows.
If the priests truly believed that the political superiorityof the warriorsis
'evil,' then the treatmentinflicted on them by the warriorsshould provoke
their indignation, or their resentmentin the restrictedmoral sense. Political
power would not be something they value so that lacking the ability to se-
cure it would not be cause for shame. On the contrary, they might rather
judge the unbridledaggressiveness of the warriorsa markof moral weakness
(see GM, I, 13 & 14).
But indignationand resentmentare by no means the first reactions of the
man of ressentiment to his defeat: shame and self-contempt are (GS, 359).
His defeat causes him shame because his fundamentalaspirationsinclude en-
joying the political supremacyachieved by his victors (see GM, I, 15). It is
because political power mattersto them thattheir defeat arouses ressentiment
in the priests, and not just indignationor (moral)resentment.
In other words, the fundamentaldifference between ressentimentand re-
sentment is that resentment appears to presuppose the condemnation of its
object and constitutes a reaction of disapproval to its occurrence, whereas
ressentiment rests on the implicit endorsement of the very values embodied
by those towards whom it is directed. Among the affects associated with
ressentiment, Nietzsche attaches a particular importance to vengefulness
16
Notably, this is how the notion is used in the discussion of "reactiveattitudes"initiatedby
Peter Strawson in his "Freedomand Resentment"in Proceedings of the British Academy,
vol. xlviii (1962), pp. 1-25.
1. Theproblem of self-deception
Nietzsche's most common objection to ressentiment revaluation is that it
involves "falsification,""lie," "mendaciousness"or "counterfeit"(GM, I, 10,
14, 15; II, 11; III, 19; see also, e.g., EH, Preface, 2-3; IV, 7; and more). But
Nietzsche also believes that all these cases of deception are in fact cases of
"self-deception" (see especially GM, I, 10, 13; see also III, 13 for the
particular case of "ressentiment against life"; cf. A 55). I have already
suggested that the "manof ressentiment"is self-deceived aboutthe values he
ostensibly embraces. Thus, 'deep down,' the priest really values and desires
the political power which his rivals the knights monopolize, but winds up
convincing himself that it is not desirableafter all.
Some of Nietzsche's texts might suggest the following objection to my
interpretation(e.g., GM, III, 15; A, 26). In these texts, the priest seems quite
clear about what he wants, namely political power. Accordingly, the revalua-
tion of noble values, which includes the denial of the value of political
power, is but the central piece of a cunning strategy to confound his oppo-
nent-a strategywhich, moreover, turnsout to be largely successful (GM, I,
16). There is no self-deception involved here, and no reason to reproachthe
priest for having recourse to deception:it is a meansjustified by his ultimate
end, political supremacy.
The scenario underlyingthis objection, however, leaves out ressentiment
altogether.If the revaluationis a piece of fully controlledself-conscious strat-
egy, it is not clear that the priest ever lost confidence in his abilities, or the
sense of his own power. But the feeling of impotence is an essential ingredi-
ent of ressentiment. Hence, the objection fails to establish that a valuation
motivatedby ressentimentdoes not involve self-deception.
A more serious difficulty arises from Nietzsche's use of self-deception as
the basis of his objection.The readerof Nietzsche who learns, first in Beyond
Good and Evil, then again in the closing sections of the Genealogy, that de-
ception is not necessarily harmful (BGE, 1; GM, III, 24-27), that it might
even be a "conditionof life" (BGE, 4), is bound to be profoundlyperplexed
by the scathing indictment of self-deception in the latter book's first essay.
Two observationsshould overcome this difficulty.
First, a brief examinationof Nietzsche's critique of the value of truthre-
veals that its aim is less to show that deception is good than to question our
The noble type of man experiences itself as determiningvalues; it does not need approval;it
judges, "whatis harmfulto me is harmfulin itself'; it knows itself to be that which first'accords
honor to things; it is value-creating.(BGE, 260)
19 These ideas cut to the heart of Nietzsche's philosophical psychology. In Daybreak, pub-
lished some seven years before the Genealogy, he already introducedand developed the
distinction between values that are merely "adopted" and those that are truly one's
"own" or "original," as well as the idea that to create and live by values that are
genuinely one's own is most demandingand consequently very rare (see D, 104 ff.). The
question of what makes a valuationgenuinely one's own is extremely complex. I am here
considering only one necessary condition of it which self-deceived agents cannot meet.
20 The acceptance condition does not necessarily eliminate all conflict between values and
desires, but it demands a particularattitudetowards it. We have genuinely endorsed our
professed values if a conflict between them and incompatible desires results in a self-
conscious control of the latter,ratherthan in their repression.Nietzsche explicitly distin-
guishes between the cases where the values bring about the "control"of the desires, and
the cases where the values "inhibit"or "extirpate"the desires. See, e.g., WP, 384, 870, &
928.
21 This view is articulated, for example, in Daniel Conway, "Genealogy and Critical
Method" in Nietzsche, Genealogy, Morality, R. Schacht ed. (U. of California Press:
Berkeley, Los Angeles, London, 1994), pp. 318-33. Though I believe that Nietzsche's
psychological critiqueis 'internal,'I do not think it can be so for the reasons advancedby
Conway (and, frequently, by others as well). I discuss this point in my "Review of Niet-
zsche, Genealogy, Morality" in Ethics, Vol. 6, 2, January 1996, and in more detail in
"Perspectivism,Criticism,and SpiritualFreedom"(forthcoming).
24 As I use the terms here, a desire is 'satisfied' when the state of affairs it intends comes to
obtain. This satisfaction is, in turn, 'enjoyed' when the agent experiences pleasure at the
state of affairs that has come into existence.
25 The phrase is Nietzsche's: see, e.g., WP, 135.
28 Alexander Nehamas, in op. cit., ch. 6, draws that very sort of connection, and offers a
detailed examinationof it..
29 In writing this paper, I benefited from the comments and suggestions Alexander
Nehamas, GarrettDeckel, Jay Wallace and Louke Van Wensveen Siker made on earlier
drafts. I also wish to thank Lanier Anderson and Wolfgang Mann, as well as audiences at
Columbia University's BarnardCollege and Brown University, for helpful discussions on
various aspects of the paper.