Eopluralism: Andrew S. Mcfarland
Eopluralism: Andrew S. Mcfarland
Eopluralism: Andrew S. Mcfarland
NEOPLURALISM
Andrew S. McFarland
Political Science Department, University of Illinois at Chicago, Chicago, Illinois 60607;
email: [email protected]
INTRODUCTION
“Neopluralism” has several overlapping meanings. The term can refer to one of
several models of power in a local, national, or policy system: elitism, pluralism,
neopluralism, corporatism, statism, clientelism, consociationism. The term can
focus on the pluralist theory of political power as set forth by Robert A. Dahl
in Who Governs? and hence refer to revived formulations of this outlook, setting
forth more sophisticated methods and conclusions. Neopluralism more specifically
can refer to the observation that Dahl’s (1961) formulation of theoretical and
methodological elements, known as pluralist theory, has been used in modified
forms by researchers in the areas of public policy making, urban politics, and
interest groups ever since the publication of Who Governs? in 1961.
Accordingly, this essay begins with an analysis of Dahl’s pluralist theory. It
then reviews the challenge to pluralist theory as set forth by Lowi (1964, 1969,
1979), Olson (1965), and others in the viewpoint variously described as theories
of subgovernments, clientelism, and interest group liberalism, although I use the
term multiple elitism. Next, the essay proceeds to the challenge posed to multiple
elitism termed neopluralism, which only partially resembles Dahl’s pluralism.
Then I examine characteristics of neopluralism that make it something more than
just another model in the line-up of models of power. A major conclusion is that
1094-2939/07/0615-0045$20.00 45
1 Apr 2007 12:22 AR ANRV312-PL10-03.tex XMLPublishSM (2004/02/24) P1: KUV
46 MCFARLAND
this sequence of scholarship proceeding from Dahl provides the basis for a general
theory of the political process.
To prevent confusion, one must first point out that there are no fewer than five
usages of the term pluralism in the literatures of the social sciences and philosophy.
As used herein, pluralism refers to the most common usage by political scientists
since 1961, that is, referring to the theory of political power set forth by Dahl in
Who Governs?. Dahl’s usage was emulated by numerous political scientists until
this pluralist theory came under serious criticism at the end of the 1960s. The
usage referring to Dahl’s theory differs from reference to the group theories of
Truman (1951) and other political scientists in the 1950s, who stressed the pri-
macy of interest groups in determining policy outcomes in American politics. A
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2007.10:45-66. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org
common error among scholars not very familiar with this literature is to assume
that Dahl was also a pluralist in the group theory sense, but in truth, he was not (see
Access provided by 180.190.39.18 on 09/10/20. For personal use only.
below). Truman’s group theory was dubbed pluralism because it was an empirical
theory that stressed the role of groups, as had the political theory of the British
philosopher Harold Laski a generation earlier (Laski 1921). Laski downgraded
the normative role of state sovereignty in comparison to the importance of social
groupings, and his theory was called pluralism (although Laski himself later be-
came a leading Marxist). Sociologists also use the term pluralism when referring
to social diversity, such as in reference to pluralist societies, perhaps containing
many ethnic and religious groups. Sociologists sometimes use the term in referring
to social theory that stresses the significance of social groups, as did Tocqueville.
Finally, during the past 20 years, “pluralism” has come to mean political theo-
ries that emphasize the value of promoting distinctive gender and ethnic identity,
implying that public policies should promote such pluralism as social diversity
(Connolly 2005). Having pointed out these sources of confusion, I reiterate that
pluralism and neopluralism in this essay refer to the pluralist theory of political
power set forth by Dahl and to revisions of Dahl’s theory by a generation of research
successors.
Power as Causation
A definition of power was a key element in Dahl’s construction of pluralist
theory. With the definition of power as causation, Dahl brought together two
strands of academic discussion during the 1950s. The Power Elite by Mills (1956)
1 Apr 2007 12:22 AR ANRV312-PL10-03.tex XMLPublishSM (2004/02/24) P1: KUV
NEOPLURALISM 47
argued that America is ruled by three connected elites: the executives of the largest
corporations, those at the top of the executive branch of the U.S. government,
and leading officers of the U.S. military. This book immediately was assigned
in many undergraduate classes and was widely read by intellectuals outside of
academia. A few years earlier, social science leaders Harold Lasswell (Lasswell
& Kaplan 1950) and Herbert Simon (1953) had put forth a definition of power
intended to serve as a basis for a more analytical political science discipline. Dahl
picked up the Lasswell-Simon definition of power as causation and made it a
basis of his Who Governs? study, the pluralist alternative to Mills’ power-elite
study.
The definition of power as causation states that A has power over B to the
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2007.10:45-66. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org
extent that A causes changes in B’s behavior in the direction of A’s intentions. For
instance, when Dahl studied the urban renewal decision-making process he found
Access provided by 180.190.39.18 on 09/10/20. For personal use only.
that the New Haven mayor tended to realize his intentions by getting other actors
to do what he wanted. Dahl (1961) defines this as political power. Power here is
seen as causing changes in the behavior of others. Clearly the role of intentions
is a sticky issue. Actor A might cause changes in the behavior of others simply
by acting, but those changes might not be the ones A favors. In such cases, most
would speak of A exercising “influence” by causing changes in behavior, even if
A opposed those changes. But it seems, following Max Weber, that it is best to
use “power” to refer to changes intended by the actor, and to reserve “influence”
to refer to any behavioral change. Lasswell, Simon, March, and Dahl introduced
the causal definition of power to American politics researchers without at first
making a distinction between power and influence. Dahl and others later came to
see the distinction as necessary (Weber 1946; Lasswell & Kaplan 1950; Simon
1953; March 1955; Dahl 1957, 1961, 1968; McFarland 2004).
The definition of power as causation is certainly not universal. Structural theo-
rists tend to use “power” to refer to the control of resources, such as money and
property (Polsby 1980), or, in the realm of international relations, military and
economic capability (Morgenthau 1964). However, pluralists refer to these items
as “resources” to be used in the pursuit of power; for example, military capability
might be a resource used by one nation-state to threaten an opposing nation-state
and make it comply with the policy of the first.
48 MCFARLAND
of law and constitutional traditions, description of the legal forms of state institu-
tions, and philosophical inquiry into the nature of justice and other social values.
Accordingly, two leading American exponents of empiricism in political science,
Arthur F. Bentley and David B. Truman, entitled their major works The Process of
Government and The Governmental Process, respectively (Bentley 1967 [1908],
Truman 1951). During the 1950s, Truman’s book was often regarded by schol-
ars as the leading theoretical work on American politics, and political scientists
of that era often used the term “process” in book titles and course descriptions.
Dahl adopted the basic Bentley-Truman model of the political process but did not
adopt the more extreme assertions of this model, in which process was claimed to
be everything, and in which institutions, laws, and political culture were viewed
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2007.10:45-66. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org
processes, but he viewed political institutions and political culture as more fixed
and as responding to social changes such as economic and technical changes, cul-
tural factors, and demography. Moreover, even within such areas as public policy
making and elite bargaining, Dahl rejected the extreme Bentley-Truman viewpoint
that political groups could be assumed to be the most important variable in caus-
ing outcomes, as, for instance, individual voting decisions might play an important
role in elections.
Nevertheless, the political process model is a basic concept of Dahl’s pluralism.
Following Bentley and Truman, this model is characterized by a combination of
the following elements:
1. Empirical observation indicates agents acting within a policy system.
2. These agents are seen as groups and individuals representing group interests.
3. The agents interact and affect one another’s behavior.
4. The agents pursue their interests, defined according to the agents’ own def-
initions of interest, although sometimes these must be inferred from their
behavior.
5. Interests frequently change in the process of interaction among the agents
over time.
6. Implicit in the foregoing, empirical observation should continue over a period
sufficient to understand fluctuations in power, interest groups, and policy-
making activities.
As Polsby (2006) notes, pluralist research usually tries to trace events back in
time to decide who caused what to happen in the search for power. The political
process model is normally complex; it normally has many units, many interrela-
tionships that shift over time, and interests (goals) that are frequently redefined by
the interacting agents. In some cases, however, there might be only a few agents,
as for instance, it might be observed that one group consistently defeats a second
group or just a few groups. The existence of a power elite can be empirically
observed, if one group consistently defeats other groups.
1 Apr 2007 12:22 AR ANRV312-PL10-03.tex XMLPublishSM (2004/02/24) P1: KUV
NEOPLURALISM 49
pattern of power and process, but someone sometime had to do an empirical study
Access provided by 180.190.39.18 on 09/10/20. For personal use only.
50 MCFARLAND
powerful in all three of them. There was not a single Millsian power elite. On the
other hand, the urban political system was not authoritarian, because the mayor
Access provided by 180.190.39.18 on 09/10/20. For personal use only.
was checked by voters, who could eliminate his power in competitive primary
and general elections. Accordingly, the mayor was accountable to the voters and
was checked by the need to anticipate the opinions of the voters. One could then
conclude that power in New Haven is not held by a power elite but is “pluralist.”
In other words, power is fragmented, although sometimes partially concentrated
in the hands of the mayor, who is, however, held accountable through competitive
elections.
Thus Dahl established this pluralist research procedure, implying the impor-
tance of doing case studies of the political process. Political issues are identified
as those important to the people being studied. Power as causation implies the
necessity of observing a flow of events or reconstructing a history of past events.
Power is seen as divisible by issue area and so cannot be generalized from one
issue area without empirical confirmation.
The techniques for case studies of politics were straightforward. Essentially,
the scholar assembled a history of a sequence of political events. To do a history,
one interviewed participants, collected documents issued by political participants,
read newspapers and official records, and, if possible, directly observed political
meetings and other events that were part of the history. The concern about causation
did not rule out the communication of the ambience of political events; good writing
and readability were valued.
Pluralists sometimes conducted relatively simple surveys about political par-
ticipation and elections in local communities. Following Dahl, pluralists tended to
pay special attention to individual politicians, their motivations, and their political
strategies. Presidents, mayors, members of the U.S. Congress, state legislators, and
bureaucrats were studied as political entrepreneurs assembling political resources
to gain power, often to please constituents and thus to keep their jobs. City and
town political organizations were another favorite topic of study; these were re-
garded as organizational entrepreneurs assembling resources to gain support and
to win elections, sometimes thereby representing the working classes and assim-
ilating immigrants into the American system (Wildavsky 1964a; Polsby 1971,
1980).
1 Apr 2007 12:22 AR ANRV312-PL10-03.tex XMLPublishSM (2004/02/24) P1: KUV
NEOPLURALISM 51
Such methods and concepts could be applied to most sectors of political life in
America. There were pluralist studies of cities, local communities, and different
issue areas both nationally and locally (Polsby 1980). Pluralist studies of the pres-
ident and of mayors sometimes found them to be powerful, yet contained within a
bureaucratic system of politics (Allison 1971). Political party organizations were
studied in pluralistic terms (Greenstein 1963). Congress and other legislatures were
studied in terms of centralization and decentralization of power (Polsby 1971). In
studying federalism, pluralists assumed a political process divided into issue ar-
eas and conducted an empirical study of the relative power (causation) of central
government versus state and local governments (Grodzins 1960). Pluralists stud-
ied attempts to centralize power in administrative management systems: planning,
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2007.10:45-66. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org
This pluralist theory of power did achieve some apparently permanent success.
For the next 30 years, political scientists eschewed elitist or power-elite explana-
tions of political processes. Power-elite theories of community power have been
supplanted. Those interested in social elites started in the 1970s to analyze elites
in terms of network theory, based on aggregating the frequency of communication
among individuals or units, and then depicting such communication networks as
a mathematical theory of social structure (Laumann & Knoke 1987).
MULTIPLE-ELITE THEORY
Although Dahl’s pluralist theory had several major problems, most have been dealt
with in subsequent neopluralist and political process research (see below). One
problem in Dahl’s work provided an opening for what I term “multiple-elite the-
ory.” Dahl found fragmented power in the three issue areas of Who Governs? except
that the mayor exercised some power in all three issue areas. In turn, the mayor was
controlled by voters in competitive elections. But could there not be policy systems
in which a few persons or groups exercised power without any higher democratic
authority to check them? Could not a particular group or coalition rule a specific
issue area to the exclusion of higher democratic authority, such as chief executives,
legislatures, or even higher courts? Moreover, a political system might have com-
petitive elections for its chief executive and for its legislature, but such officials,
selected by the entire citizenry, might lack control over some particular policy areas.
This was the argument made by multiple-elite theorists. Such writers sided
with Dahl against Mills; they seldom observed single power elites in the United
States. However, they differed from Dahl in arguing the general significance of
multiple independent elites, each particular to specific policy areas, within the
fragmentation of power found by Dahl. Multiple-elite theorists normally argued
that this fragmentation of power led to unrepresentative government of special
interests, controlling policy in a particular area to the detriment of diffused public
interests.
1 Apr 2007 12:22 AR ANRV312-PL10-03.tex XMLPublishSM (2004/02/24) P1: KUV
52 MCFARLAND
NEOPLURALISM 53
Besides islands of oligarchy, another major new idea put forth by multiple-
elite theory was Olson’s (1965) logic of collective action. Olson’s was the best
single theory to explain the existence of islands of oligarchy. Olson based collective
action theory on the sort of economic theory just considered. Oligopolies produce
a collective benefit for constituent units (although not for the public), as a few units
cooperate to restrict production and raise prices. But as the number of producer
units increases, it becomes more difficult to collude to restrict production, because
some firms will leave the production restriction to others and produce more to
obtain higher profits for themselves in the short run. Similarly, Olson reasoned, a
few units will contribute to support a political lobby, but as the number of units
increases, they will all try to be free riders, and the lobby will get no contributions.
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2007.10:45-66. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org
Olson concluded that a lobby with a large number of units could exist only if an
interest group offered benefits that were restricted to its members— for example,
Access provided by 180.190.39.18 on 09/10/20. For personal use only.
54 MCFARLAND
with the public philosophy of interest group liberalism, not in the sense of the
Democratic Party, but in the sense of political philosophy. In its academic usage,
“liberal” refers to scholars who define democracy according to some process of
decision making, rather than referring to standards of justice in the substance of
government action. Lowi argued that interest group liberalism in the process sense
had come to permeate the values of legislative, executive, and judicial decision
makers in American government, so that laws were written and interpreted without
useful reference to clear standards of justice and administration. He argued that,
as a consequence, lower-level executive decision makers interpreted the practical
meaning of legislation after a process of bargaining with organized interest groups,
thereby forming a special interest policy-making coalition specific to a particular
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2007.10:45-66. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org
area of public policy. Consequently, American public policy making is rife with
particularistic policy coalitions, forming multiple elites within the overall system.
Access provided by 180.190.39.18 on 09/10/20. For personal use only.
NEOPLURALISM 55
Beer (1976), Haider (1974), and others described the phenomenon of governments
lobbying other governments—associations of cities, counties, and so forth lobby-
ing in Washington and elsewhere. Walker (1983) and his collaborators (Gais et al.
1984) found a great increase in lobbying by nonprofit organizations (e.g., churches,
hospitals, and colleges); by professions, especially groups of government employ-
ees; and by ideological cause groups. Schlozman & Tierney (1986, pp. 55–57)
found a great increase in government lobbies since 1960, although they argued
that this did not substantially decrease the business domination of other lobbies.
Neopluralists thus observed a complex welter of group participation in pub-
lic policy making (Jordan 1981, Jordan & Maloney 1996, Gray & Lowery 2004,
Lowery & Brasher 2004). Within a single issue domain such as air pollution regu-
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2007.10:45-66. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org
lation, one might find producers of electricity, coal mining companies, auto man-
ufacturers, the United Auto Workers, railroads (carriers of coal), environmentalist
Access provided by 180.190.39.18 on 09/10/20. For personal use only.
groups, the American Lung Association, the American Public Health Association,
various state governments, the association of state public utility regulators, and
probably other groups. Neopluralists would expect to observe this situation in nu-
merous issue areas at the national level, rather than to observe a narrow coalition
of an interest group, government agency, and legislative committee.
Concomitant with this finding of a complexity of groups active in national policy
domains was the need of explaining why such groups mobilized and maintained
themselves in light of Olson’s persuasive theory of collective action, which stated
that lobbies make public goods (public policies) available even to groups and
individuals who do not contribute to the lobby and thereby act as free riders.
As mentioned above, Olson posited that groups would organize if they provided
selective benefits to contributors, benefits available only to members, such as the
Farm Bureau providing insurance and fuel discounts to its farmer members. But
the concept of selective benefits did not provide a persuasive explanation for the
existence of the full panoply of interest groups.
Why did so many interest groups exist despite the logic of collective action?
Political scientists made this question a priority, particularly during 1970–1990.
A number of answers received widespread acceptance and were incorporated into
neopluralist views of the policy-making process.
First, a few years after the publication of The Logic of Collective Action,
Chamberlin (1974) and Frohlich et al. (1971) pointed out that interest groups
can be started and maintained by political entrepreneurs, to use economic lan-
guage. One or more individuals take it upon themselves to start a group and to
bear the time costs of organizing and doing the necessary fund-raising. Walker’s
(1991) surveys found that about half of the interest groups responding had been
organized by such political entrepreneurs.
Walker then extended this mode of thought by demonstrating the key role of
patrons in organizing interest groups. Patrons were particularly helpful in under-
standing the organizing of citizen groups, in which members contributed to lobby-
ing for public policy issues even when such policies did not have a great immediate
impact on the members’ own pocketbooks. Patrons are seen as providing money
1 Apr 2007 12:22 AR ANRV312-PL10-03.tex XMLPublishSM (2004/02/24) P1: KUV
56 MCFARLAND
and other resources to the entrepreneurs who do the organizing. Patrons include
wealthy individuals, foundations, other organizations (creating spin-off groups,
for instance), and governments, particularly the federal government. Walker em-
phasized the government as a patron, noting that the federal government actually
played a key role in organizing several major groups, such as the Farm Bureau, the
U.S. Chambers of Commerce, and the National Organization of Women (Walker
1983, 1991; McFarland 2004, pp. 44–45).
A third source of interest groups is social movements. Although they use non-
institutionalized tactics, social movements eventually encompass supporters who
prefer to work within established political institutions to attain movement goals,
thus forming lobbies for large but seemingly diffused groups, such as women,
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2007.10:45-66. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org
DC around 1970. Although efforts have been made to explain social movements
using a rational choice framework similar to that of Olson’s collective action theory
(Chong 1991, Lichbach 1995), most writers emphasize a variety of causes for so-
cial movements (McAdam 1982, Costain & McFarland 1998), thereby employing
variables outside of Olson’s theory.
A fourth theory addressing the proliferation of interest groups was provided
by policy theorist Hugh Heclo (1978), whose concept of “issue networks” found
immediate, widespread acceptance among political scientists. Heclo observed that
although the particularistic coalitions described by multiple-elite writers do indeed
exist, they are only part of a complex network of communication and interaction
within some issue domain. Heclo termed such an overall network an “issue net-
work.” He argued that the subgovernments or little governments of multiple-elite
theory existed in only a minority of cases, and that ordinarily such limited coali-
tions, only part of an issue network, are checked by other actors within the issue
network (sometimes called a “policy network”). In addition, from the standpoint
of collective action theory, the issue network provides a basis for mobilizing lob-
bies to represent interests more diffuse than the oligopolistic coalitions implied by
Olson’s theory.
For instance, in the case of air pollution policy, there is a potential subgov-
ernment consisting of eastern coal mining businesses; eastern miners; legislators
representing Kentucky, Ohio, Illinois, and West Virginia; and the Department of
Energy. Such a subgovernment would favor the use of high-sulfur coal, which
would require the purchase of expensive emissions-scrubbing equipment or regu-
latory variation to meet the requirements of air pollution legislation. But in addition
to the electric utilities directly affected, there exists a network of communication of
political, economic, and technical information within this issue area. The federal
Environmental Protection Agency and state EPAs regularly communicate about
air pollution issues, as do university researchers, environmental group personnel,
recreation industry personnel, American Lung Association staff, journalists, fed-
eral and state legislators specializing in environmental legislation, and the staffs of
such legislators. Because of the overall issue network, the potential high-sulfur coal
1 Apr 2007 12:22 AR ANRV312-PL10-03.tex XMLPublishSM (2004/02/24) P1: KUV
NEOPLURALISM 57
58 MCFARLAND
more likely to design and execute policy reflective of professional norms, such as
those of lawyer, economist, educator, or biologist (Wilson 1980; McFarland 2004,
p. 48). More groups lead to more autonomy for government agencies (controlled
in varying degrees by executive or legislative officials).
Countervailing group power is related to the theory of advocacy coalitions,
as set forth by Sabatier & Jenkins-Smith (1993). In the history of international
relations, one refers to bipolar systems; in American domestic politics, one fre-
quently observes competing advocacy coalitions, such as competition between
environmentalists and development interests in Western communities. An advo-
cacy coalition is a stable alliance, probably lasting ten years or more, among actors
within a policy network, including individuals representing government agencies
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2007.10:45-66. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org
at all levels of federalism. The concept of advocacy coalition within a policy net-
work, often in competition with each other, has proved useful in scores of studies
Access provided by 180.190.39.18 on 09/10/20. For personal use only.
CHARACTERISTICS OF NEOPLURALIST
POLITICAL PROCESS
The basic meaning of neopluralism is a finding about power structure within the
framework of four assumptions underlying Dahl’s theory of political power (pro-
cess, power as causation, domains, subjective definition of interests). Using these
and perhaps other assumptions, political science has set forth seven findings about
power structure: power elite theory, Dahl’s pluralist theory, multiple-elite theory,
neopluralism, corporatism (Schmitter 1974), statism (Krasner 1978), and conso-
ciationism (Lijphart 1969). Neopluralism was derived from a research sequence
that started with Mills versus Dahl and proceeded through multiple-elite theory,
finally resulting in neopluralism.
Explicitly or implicitly, these seven research findings can be based on the use
of Dahl’s concepts and methods. Dahl (1958) criticized Mills for not using these
methods, but a scholar can readily find a single elite ruling a single issue domain,
a community, or even a nation by using Dahl’s methods and arguing that the
same group controls the core of public policy. The multiple-elite theorists did
this in respect to single policy domains. Neopluralism is thus a type of finding
in research about political power. But it is more than this; neopluralism can be
called a theory, because researchers assuming neopluralist power domains have
begun to make other theoretical observations about political and policy-making
processes.
As of 2006, according to my reading of the literature, most political scientists
and other public policy researchers assume a condition of neopluralism in the
policy domains they study. Dahl’s pluralist theory and multiple-elite theory are
normally seen to be dated as general theories, although they might provide accu-
rate explanations for outcomes in a minority of policy domains. Disproving the
existence of a power elite or a state of Dahl’s pluralism within a policy domain
1 Apr 2007 12:22 AR ANRV312-PL10-03.tex XMLPublishSM (2004/02/24) P1: KUV
NEOPLURALISM 59
power and more interest in analyzing other questions regarding the political pro-
cess, the theory of political power is becoming embedded in an emerging theory
Access provided by 180.190.39.18 on 09/10/20. For personal use only.
60 MCFARLAND
generation, stated that there are more than 400 policy niches in national agricultural
policy making.
At about the same time, Gray & Lowery (1996) stressed “interest group niches”
and “group niche behavior” in their data-rich study of interest group systems and
lobbying in fifty state governments. They put forth the ecological model of interest
group systems. Because groups compete with one another, it is rational and “eco-
logical” for interest groups to occupy a piece of the policy-making turf that has
little or no competition from other groups trying to mobilize resources in the same
policy-making space. In their study of 137 representative national policy domains,
Baumgartner & Leech (2001, p. 1201) found 17 domains in which >200 groups
were interested to lobby, whereas in 23 domains only a single group was interested
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2007.10:45-66. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org
groups are often mobilized in power domains with the multiple elitists’ finding
that sometimes only a single group is significant within a domain. However, neo-
pluralism states that the observation of a multiplicity of groups is the more general
research finding.
Lipsky (1970), and perhaps a few other scholars, anticipated neopluralist con-
clusions but did not frame them in the debate about the extent of multiple-elitism.
Lipsky’s widely read Protest in City Politics: Rent Strikes, Housing and the Power
of the Poor (1970) presented a neopluralist study ten years ahead of its time. Study-
ing the nationally famous Harlem rent strike of 1963–1964, Lipsky used methods
similar to those of the pluralists by focusing on a case study of a political process
within a single domain, while assuming Dahl’s definition of political power by
referring to “protest as a political resource” rather than protest as “power” itself.
Lipsky observed that the economic stakeholders normally were powerful in the
domain of city housing rent regulation, but he found that a social movement could
form organizations to challenge economic power. Such organizations, however,
were quickly subject to processes of decay. In this case, collective action was fur-
thered by a movement entrepreneur, who found the costs of organization lessened
by the proximity of supporters living in the same building.
NEOPLURALISM 61
of accepting this argument were not very clear. Polsby (1980 [1963]) soon pointed
out that the two-faces-of-power argument was an injunction to study “nonissues,”
and that this was not an empirical endeavor, being subject to the interpolation of a
scholar’s values in choosing which nonissues were important. But Polsby could not
persuade most political scientists about the invalidity of the two-faces-of-power
argument.
Bachrach & Baratz’s concern about power over the agenda applies to the range
of studies that accept Dahl’s four assumptions in the study of power, including
multiple-elite and neopluralist studies. Actually, two faces of power also applies
to other theories of power insofar as such theories are based on observations of
who wins and loses on certain political issues. Following the two-faces-of-power
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2007.10:45-66. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org
argument, some might say that neopluralism as a theory might as well be ignored.
Yet researchers into power and the political process have shed much light on power
Access provided by 180.190.39.18 on 09/10/20. For personal use only.
62 MCFARLAND
private interests, such as in determining the private use of public lands for grazing,
forestry, and mining (Klyza 1994).
Since the mid 1990s, there has been much interest among social scientists, not
just political scientists, in the concept of issue framing (Benford & Snow 2000).
Calling a tax a “death tax” rather than an “estate tax” can make a big difference
in the policy-making process; the first issue frame emphasizes intervention of big
government into private affairs and making money from death, whereas the issue
frame of “estate” emphasizes the idea of taxing the wealthy. The examination
of issue framing is a valuable addition to the study of political agendas because
framing the agenda in one way or another affects political outcomes. Successful
issue framing says something important about political power.
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2007.10:45-66. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org
Bachrach & Baratz made their point with “The Two Faces of Power,” but we
must now acknowledge the succeeding 40 years of research about political agendas
Access provided by 180.190.39.18 on 09/10/20. For personal use only.
NEOPLURALISM 63
or it might emerge over generations in a research sequence, such as the one pro-
ducing neopluralism. In other words, a general theory of political process has been
evolving.
ACKNOWLEDGMENT
Limited portions of this chapter previously appeared in my book Neopluralism:
The Evolution of Political Process Theory and are used with permission of the
University Press of Kansas.
LITERATURE CITED
Ackerman B, Hassler WT. 1981. Clean enue sharing: a case study in public sector
Coal/Dirty Air. New Haven, CT: Yale Univ. politics. Public Policy 24:127–95
Press Benford RD, Snow DA. 2000. Framing pro-
Allison G. 1971. Essence of Decision. Boston: cesses and social movements: an overview
Little, Brown and assessment. Am. Rev. Sociol. 26:611–39
Bachrach P, Baratz M. 1962. Two faces of Bentley AF. 1967 (1908). The Process of Gov-
power. Am. Polit. Sci. Rev. 56:947–52 ernment. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of
Balbus ID. 1971. The concept of interest in Harvard Univ. Press
pluralist and Marxian analysis. Polit. Soc. Bernstein M. 1955. Regulating Business by
1:151–78 Independent Commission. Princeton, NJ:
Baumgartner FR, Jones BD. 1993. Agendas and Princeton Univ. Press
Instability in American Politics. Chicago: Berry JM. 1977. Lobbying for the People.
Univ. Chicago Press Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ. Press
Baumgartner FR, Leech BL. 2001. Interest Braybrooke D, Lindblom CE. 1963. A Strategy
niches and policy bandwagons: patterns of of Decision. New York: Free
interest group involvement in national poli- Browne WP. 1990. Organized interests and
tics. J. Polit. 63:1191–1213 their issue niches: a search for pluralism in a
Beer SH. 1976. The adoption of general rev- policy domain. J. Polit. 52:477–509
1 Apr 2007 12:22 AR ANRV312-PL10-03.tex XMLPublishSM (2004/02/24) P1: KUV
64 MCFARLAND
NEOPLURALISM 65
Laski HJ. 1921. The Foundations of Sovereignty McConnell G. 1966. Private Power and Amer-
and Other Essays. New York: Harcourt, ican Democracy. New York: Knopf
Brace McFarland AS. 1984. Common Cause: Lob-
Lasswell HD, Kaplan A. 1950. Power and So- bying in the Public Interest. Chatham, NJ:
ciety. New Haven, CT: Yale Univ. Press Chatham House
Laudan L. 1984. Science and Values: The Aims McFarland AS. 2004. Neopluralism: The Evo-
of Science and Their Role in Scientific De- lution of Political Process Theory. Lawrence:
bate. Berkeley: Univ. Calif. Press Univ. Press Kansas
Laumann EO, Knoke D. 1987. The Organiza- Michels R. 1959. Political Parties. New York:
tional State: Social Choice in National Policy Dover
Domains. Madison: Univ. Wisc. Press Mills CW. 1956. The Power Elite. New York:
Lichbach MI. 1995. The Rebel’s Dilemma. Ann Oxford Univ. Press
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2007.10:45-66. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org
Arbor: Univ. Mich. Press Mitchell RC. 1984. Public opinion and envi-
Lindblom CE. 1965. The Intelligence of ronmental politics in the 1970s and 1980s.
Access provided by 180.190.39.18 on 09/10/20. For personal use only.
66 MCFARLAND
Polsby NW. 2006. Remarks for 2006 Southern Stone CN. 1989. Regime Politics: Governing
Political Science Association Roundtable. Atlanta, 1946–1988. Lawrence: Univ. Press
Typescript, Inst. Gov. Stud., Univ. Calif., Kansas
Berkeley Stone CN. 2006. Power, reform, and urban
Redford E. 1969. Democracy in the Adminis- regime analysis. City Community 5:23–38
trative State. New York: Oxford Univ. Press Truman DB. 1951. The Governmental Process.
Sabatier PA, Jenkins-Smith HC, eds. 1993. Pol- New York: Knopf
icy Change and Learning: An Advocacy Vogel D. 1980/1981. The public interest move-
Coalition Approach. Boulder, CO: Westview ment and the American reform tradition.
Sabatier PA, Jenkins-Smith HC. 1999. The Polit. Sci. Q. 95:607–27
advocacy coalition framework: an assess- Walker JL. 1983. The origins and maintenance
ment. In Theories of the Policy Process, of interest groups in America. Am. Polit. Sci.
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2007.10:45-66. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org
Sayre WS, Kaufman H. 1960. Governing New America. Ann Arbor: Univ. Mich. Press
York City. New York: Russell Sage Found. Weber M. 1946. Class, status, party. In From
Schlozman KL, Tierney JT. 1986. Organized Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, ed./transl.
Interests and American Democracy. New HH Gerthe, CW Mills, pp. 180–95. New
York: Harper & Row York: Oxford Univ. Press
Schmitter P. 1974. Still the century of corpo- Wenner LM. 1982. The Environmental Decade
ratism? Rev. Polit. 36:85–131 in Court. Bloomington: Univ. Indiana Press
Scott JC. 1990. Domination and the Arts of Re- Wildavsky AB. 1964a. Leadership in a Small
sistance. New Haven, CT: Yale Univ. Press Town. Bedminister, NJ: Totowa
Selznick P. 1953. TVA and the Grass Roots. Wildavsky AB. 1964b. The Politics of the Bud-
Berkeley: Univ. Calif. Press getary Process. Boston: Little, Brown
Simon HA. 1953. Notes on the observation and Wildavsky AB. 1979. Speaking Truth to Power:
measurement of power. J. Polit. 15:500–16 The Art and Craft of Policy Analysis. Boston:
Stigler GJ. 1975. The Citizen and the State: Es- Little, Brown
says on Regulation. Chicago: Univ. Chicago Wilson JQ. 1980. The Politics of Regulation.
Press New York: Basic Books
P1: JRX
April 9, 2007 10:54 Annual Reviews ANRV312-FM
CONTENTS
STATE REPRESSION AND POLITICAL ORDER, Christian Davenport 1
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2007.10:45-66. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org
v
P1: JRX
April 9, 2007 10:54 Annual Reviews ANRV312-FM
vi CONTENTS
INDEXES
Cumulative Index of Contributing Authors, Volumes 1–10 391
Cumulative Index of Chapter Titles, Volumes 1–10 394
ERRATA
An online log of corrections Annual Review of Political Science chapters
(if any, 1997 to the present) may be found at http://polisci.annualreviews.org/
Annu. Rev. Polit. Sci. 2007.10:45-66. Downloaded from www.annualreviews.org
Access provided by 180.190.39.18 on 09/10/20. For personal use only.