Religious Experience
Religious Experience
Religious Experience
Abstract
The paper aims at studying the nature and problems of religious experience. Religious
experience is defined as a subjective experience which is interpreted in religious circle as an
encounter with God or gods or higher order realities. The researcher identifies the features
of religious experience, and various activities that can enhance its manifestations. The
philosophical problems of religious experience are also discussed. Despite the challenges of
religious experience, the writer concludes that the experiences cannot be totally disregarded,
but have to be examined discreetly in order not to be deceived, as faith without reasoning
leads one to errors, deceptions and wrong belief. The work is a qualitative research and the
method used is philosophical analysis.
Introduction
However, Charlesworth (1988) argued that most of these experiences can be produced under
drug and alcoholic influences. His argument is true as we know that drunkard and those under
the influence of drugs like cocaine, Indian hemp and even the mad do have similar
experiences. It becomes difficult to differentiate between real religious experiences and drug
influences, but obviously, drug and alcoholic influences are not religious experiences. How
can we differentiate religious experiences from drug and alcoholic influences? What are the
characteristics of religious experience? Can we accept religious experiences as truth and
reliable phenomenon? In the first place, the argument of Charlesword can easily be
dismissed, as according to Habel’s definition of the concept, any experience outside the
religious context cannot be qualified as religious experience. Nonetheless, we need to
highlight qualities of religious experience, activities that enhance manifestations of such
experiences and challenges to its credibility.
Moore and Habel (1982) identified two classes of religious experience: the immediate and
mediated forms of religious experience. Mediated experiences are those situation whereby
the believer experiences the sacred through mediators as prophets, seers, totemic objects,
symbols or the natural world. Immediate experiences, on the other hand, are where the
2
encounter comes to the believer directly without any intermediary or mediator. Religious
experiences are more impactful when the believer is directly involved. William James
highlights four characteristics of religious experience as transient, ineffable, noetic and
passivity. To these, we add numinon and ecstasy.
Religious experience is not intentionally or consciously induced by the subject but certain
religious activities can facilitate it. What are these activities? We may not exhaust them,
but highlight the commonest ones among them:
1. Extended Religious Exercise: Various religious sects gather to worship, pray, listen
to their doctrinal teachings, and have communion. When such fellowship is extended,
many religious encounters become feasible. This is very common in Christian religion
where gathering like camp, crusades and set apart become avenues for diverse
miracles, healings and prophecies. This is because of what is called ‘cooperate
anointing’ and mortifying of the fresh through such long fellowship.
2. Mortification of the Fresh: Man is made up of body and soul. The soul is very
powerful but is caged in the body with various bodily desires. The more one indulges
in satisfying the desires of his body, the more powerful the fresh becomes while the
spirit weakens. The beginning of man’s self-realization is mortification of the fresh.
Once one mortifies his bodily desires especially the desires for sex, eating, drinking
and worldly enjoyment, his soul gets more power over the fresh. In that state, the
person becomes susceptible to diverse religious experiences.
3. Praying: Prayer is defined as a “mediums through which man empresses his desires
and needs to his maker, while the maker speaks to him through the scripture”
(Akudolu, 2018:22). Akudolu gives instances of those that lived lives of prayer and
their lives characterised by miracles and diverse religious experiences. Prayer is very
effective, but sins, unbelief and wrong motive militate against its efficacy.
4. Fasting: Similar to prayer is fasting, where one forbids food and stays in prayer.
Lives of many religious leaders were extraordinary because of fasting and prayer.
Think of Jesus Christ, Mohammed, Moses and others. Fasting mortifies the fresh and
empowers the spirit, making it easy for it to have access to spiritual realities.
4
5. Singing and Dancing: Music is very powerful. Religious songs and dancing are
known for long as means to receiving religious experiences and miracles as its opens
the spiritual door of a man. Similar stories of religious experiences coming as
consequence of singing and dancing abound in the Holy Bible, Holy Quran, Bhagavad
Gita and other Holy Writs.
6. Meditation: Meditation may be scriptural meditation, where one gives deeper
thought to the contents of the scripture; it may be yoga meditation, focused attention
meditation, transcendental meditation, mental or any form as we have many forms of
it according to various religious traditions. Meditation of any kind can calm the mind
and spirit and makes it susceptible to various religious experiences.
Religion has been a problem since time immemorial. This is because religion centres on
God who is invisible. Most of religious issues are spiritual and abstract and this elicits lots
of challenges to its claims. Problems of religious language are more of epistemological
issues. Here, we shall arrange them into five headings for easy comprehension and clarity.
insists that religious experience are in the domain of the spiritual and should not be
judged with the instrumentality of the senses. The problem with this is that everybody
is not spiritual and therefore cannot understand the religious experience.
2. Problem of Religious Diversities with conflicting Religious Experiences: In
sensory experience, there is similarity in what people observe but in religious
experience, there is a wide range of differences in what people claim to have seen,
even within the same religious group. I cannot forget my experience in one prayer
team where a lady started speaking in tongues. At the end, she prophesied to one
brother, “The Holy Spirit says that you must marry me”. The brother started his own
speaking tongues and ended with this prophecy, “Sister, Holy Spirit says I must not
marry you”. Which of these two prophecies is to be accepted as true? The problem of
conflicting religious experience becomes worse with the existence of diverse religious
sects. What a particular religious group believe in is quite different from the other.
How can we reconcile this? In response to this, John Hick(1989, 2006) adopted
Kantian phenoumena and noumena. Kant (1970) has said that the phenoumena is the
reality as people see it but noumena is the reality as it is which is incomprehensible.
According to him, how people experience the reality may differ because of certain
factors, but that does not make the reality non-existent. Truly, people perceive
realities in diverse ways. Human frailty, condition of the mind, aspiration, background
and difference in belief can affect how people perceive and interpret issues. The work
of philosophers are therefore to search out the truth uncorrupted. In addition to this,
Alston (1991) and Plantiga (1981, 2000) argued that each religious tradition has its
epistemic resources. Members within that particular religious circle understands the
experience within the circle. They do not require epistemic resources outside their
circle. Those within that circle understands their religious experiences, but those
outside may not understand it. Therefore, religious experience is meaningful within a
particular circle. But the problem remains unsolved: How can they help others outside
their religious circle to understand their religious experiences? How can they, within
the same circle reconcile their conflicting ideas since within a particular circle,
conflicting experience do happen? The case of “The Holy Spirit says you must marry
me” is a typical example. More so, our society is characterised by many religious
sects, how can we reconcile their conflicting views (which are products of their
diverse experiences) to have a harmonious and peaceful society? These are serious
challenges indeed!
6
necessitate belief? Even within the same religious circle, there are conflicting
experiences and doubts as we have noted. Some, like Oakes (1976) claim that it is
epistemologically possible to form a belief based on such experiences, but you may
also be justified in not forming a belief. According to them, if we can believe the
testimonies of others concerning event that happened when we are not there, why not
religious experience. It depends on whether the testimony is compelling enough for us
to believe it or not. In that case, we have to evaluate the contents of what is said, the
coherency and logicality, epistemological and mental situation of the speaker, and
then the context. Though, these may be acceptable criteria, they are not so reliable as
we are aware of fraudulent activities and deceits going on in various religious circles,
nowadays.
5. Linguistic Problem: Another problem of religious experience is its language. The
positivists, in their verifiability principles, hold that language must picture reality; for
a proposition to be true, it must be verified; and it can also be falsified. Exception to
these rules are analytic statements where the subject is contained in the predicate.
Example of such statements is “A bachelor is unmarried man”. Here ‘bachelor’ means
‘unmarried man’. Such statement is always true. Religious language does not pass any
of these test and therefore regarded as meaningless. In response to this, Akudolu
(2019) and Okoro (2014) hold that verifiability principles of logical positivists and
empiricists are not verifiable and therefore fall victim to its claims. Religious
experience is spiritual experience and should not be judged with empirical tools. This
is the main emphasis of Wittgenstein’s language game (Wittgenstein, 1978).
Language is like a game, every game has its language and can be judged within that
context. Therefore, religious experience and language can only be judged in a
religious and spiritual context.
Conclusion
From what we have done so far, we can affirm that religious experiences are subjective
experiences which can have meaning within religious context. It includes experiences like
prophecy, revelation, trance, dream, speaking in tongue, charismatic display, falling under
anointing and similar claims as we have in many religions. These experiences are divinely
inspired but can be enhanced through certain religious practices. Transience, ineffability,
noetic, passivity, numinous, and ecstasy are common features of such experiences. Religious
experiences are highly valued in religious circle but have some epistemological and linguistic
8
challenges, which we have examined. We therefore hold that despite all these challenges,
religious experiences cannot be totally disregarded, but we need to examine and judge them
with maturity in order not to be deceived. Faith without reasoning leads one to errors,
deceptions and wrong belief.
References
Akudolu, L.O. (2018). Moving the Heart of God. Nigeria, Onitsha: Perfect Image Publishers.
Akudolu, L.O. (2019). Understanding the Nature and Problems of Metaphysics. Nigeria,
Awka: Valid Publishers.
Ellwood, R. S. (1999). Mysticism and Religion. New York: Seven Bridges Press.
Freud, S. (1927). “The Future of an illusion”. In The Future of an Illusion, Civilization and
its Discontents, and other Works (Vol. xxi, the Standard Edition of the Complete
Psychological works of Sigmund Freud). London: Hogarth Press, pp.1-55.
Guthrie, S.E. (1995). Faces in the Clouds: A new Theory of Religion. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Habel, N. et al (1993). “Religious Experiences”. In Myth, Ritual and the Sacred: Introducing
the Phenomena of Religion. Underdale: University of South Australia.
Hornby, A.S. (2015). Oxford Advanced Learner’s Dictionary. Uk, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Kant, Immanuel (1970). Critique of Pure Reason (Trans. Norman K. Smith). London:
Macmillan and Co. Ltd.
9
Moore, B. and Habel, N. (1982). Appendix 1, When Religion Goes to School. Adelaide:
SACAE, pp. 184-218.
Oakes, R.A. (1976). “Religious Experience and Rational Certainty”, Religious Studies, 12
(3), pp.311-318.
Otto, R. (1923).The Idea of the Holy, trans. John Harvey. London: Cambridge University
Press.
Plantinga, A. (1981). “Is Belief in God properly Basic?”, Nous, 15, pp.41-51.
------------ (2000). Warranted Christian Belief. New York: Oxford University Press.