Badiou On Deleuze

Download as docx, pdf, or txt
Download as docx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 6

Deleuze always paid tribute to Sartre as the figure who, during the thirties and forties, woke

French philosophy from its academic slumbers. He considered the 1937 article, 'The
Transcendence of the Ego', the origin of everything: why? It is because, in this text, Sartre
proposes the idea - I am citing Deleuze - of 'an impersonal transcendental field, having the form
neither of a personal synthetic consciousness nor subjective identity-the subject, to the contrary,
always being constituted.' I want to emphasize this remark of Deleuze's all the more insofar as
the motif of an impersonal transcendental field is dominant throughout my Greater Logic,
where it is effectuated, in the finest technical detail, as a logic of appearance or worlds.

Deleuze remarked also that Sartre had been prevented from thinking all of the consequences of
his idea because he had attached the impersonal field to a (self)-consciousness. This is
absolutely correct. We could also say: Sartre continued to believe in an auto-unification of the
transcendental. He did not expose the subject to the alea of a pure Outside. Now, one of the
names of the Outside is 'event'. This is why the event, as that to which the power (puissance) of a
thought is devoted, and/ or that from which this power proceeds, has, after Sartre, become a
common term for the greater number of contemporary philosophers. Other than through the
critique of the phenomenology of consciousness, this term has been transmitted to us, on the
side of truth-procedures, by the lasting fragment-in the 20th century-of four entangled motifs:
that, in politics, of Revolution; in love, of erotic liberation; in the arts, of performance; and in the
sciences, of the epistemological break. In philosophy, it can discerned as well in Wittgenstein
('The world is everything which happens') as in Heidegger (being as being-on-the-
way, Ereignis).

The idea is central in Deleuze, as it is in my own enterprise-but what a contrast! The interest of
this contrast is that it exposes the original ambiguity of the idea itself. It effectively contains a
dimension of structure (interruption as such, the appearance of a supernumerary term) and a
dimension of the history of life (the concentration of becoming, being as coming-to-self,
promise). In the first case, the event is disjoined from the One, it is separation, assumption of the
void, pure non-sense. In the second case, it is the play of the One, composition, intensity of the
plenum, the crystal (or logic) of sense. The Logic of Sense is the most considerable effort on the
part of Gilles Deleuze to clarify his concept of the event. He does so in the company of the
Stoics, they for whom the 'event' must be integrated into the inflexible discipline of the All,
according to which Stoicism orients itself. Between 'event' and 'destiny', there must be
something like a subjective reciprocation.

I will extract from The Logic of Sense what I will call the four Deleuzean axioms of the event.

Axiom 1: "Unlimited becoming becomes the event itself."


The event is the ontological realisation of the eternal truth of the One, the infinite power
(puissance) of Life. It is in no way a void, or a stupor, separated from what becomes. To the
contrary, it is the concentration of the continuity of life, its intensification. The event is that
which donates the One to the concatenation of multiplicities. We could advance the following
formula: in becomings, the event is the proof of the One of which these becomings are the
expression. This is why there is no contradiction between the limitless of becoming and the
singularity of the event. The event reveals in an immanent way the One of becomings, it makes
becoming this One. The event is the becoming of becoming: the becoming(-One) of (unlimited)
becoming.

Axiom 2: "The event is always that which has just happened and that which is about to happen,
but never that which is happening."

The event is a synthesis of past and future. In reality, the expression of the One in becomings is
the eternal identity of the future as a dimension of the past. The ontology of time, for Deleuze as
for Bergson, admits no figure of separation. Consequently, the event would not be what takes
place 'between' a past and a future, between the end of a world and the beginning of another. It
is rather encroachment and connection: it realises the indivisible continuity of Virtuality. It
exposes the unity of passage which fuses the one-just-after and the one-just-before. It is not 'that
which happens', but that which, in what happens, has become and will become. The event as
event of time, or time as the continued and eternal procedure of being, introduces no division
into time, no intervallic void between two times. 'Event' repudiates the present understood as
either passage or separation; it is the operative paradox of becoming. This thesis can thus be
expressed in two ways: there is no present (the event is re-represented, it is active immanence
which co-presents the past and the future); or, everything is present (the event is living or
chaotic eternity, as the essence of time).

Axiom 3: "The event is of a different regime than the actions and passions of the body, even if it
results from them."

Whether thought of as the becoming of becomings, or as disjunctive eternity, the event


intensifies bodies, concentrates their constitutive multiplicity. It would therefore be neither of
the same nature as the actions and the passions of the body, nor supervene on them. The event
is not identical to the bodies which it affects, but neither is it transcendent to what happens to
them or what they do, such that it cannot be said any longer that they are (ontologically)
different to bodies. It is the differenciator of actions and passions of the body as a result. What
then is an immanent One of becomings, if not Becoming? Or difference, or Relation (other
Deleuzean terms)? However, Becoming is not an idea, but what becomings become. Thus the
event affects bodies, because it is what they do or support as exposed syntheses. It is the coming
of the One through them that they are as distinct nature (virtual rather than actual) and
homogenous result (without them, it is not). This is the sense that must be given to the formula:
'The event is coextensive with becoming'. The event of Life will be thought as the body without
organs: of a different regime than living organisms, but uniquely deployed or legible as the
result of the actions and passions of these organisms.

Axiom 4: "A life is composed of a single and same Event, lacking all the variety of what
happens to it."

What is difficult here is not the reiteration of the One as the concentrated expression of vital
deployment. The three preceeding axioms are clear on this point. The difficulty is in
understanding the word 'composed'. The event is what composes a life somewhat as a musical
composition is organised by its theme. 'Variety' must here be understood as 'variation', as
variation on a theme. The event is not what happens to a life, but what is in what happens, or
what happens in what happens, such that it can only have a single Event. The Event, in the
disparate material of a life, is precisely the Eternal Return of the identical, the undifferentiated
power (puissance) of the Same: the 'powerful inorganic life.' With regard to any multiplicity
whatsoever, it is of the essence of the Event to compose them into the One that they are, and to
exhibit this unique composition in a potentially infinite variety of ways.

With these four axioms, Deleuze reveals his response to evental ambiguity: he chooses for
destiny. The event is not the risky (hasardeux) passage from one state of things to another. It is
the immanent stigmata of a One-result of all becomings. In the multiple-which-becomes, in the
between-two of the multiples which are active multiples, the event is the destiny of the One.

It is enough to invert these four axioms-here as in Book II (of Logiques des mondes), 'inversion'
reveals negations-in order to obtain a quite good axiomatic of what I call 'event', that which is a
site, appearing in maximal intensity, and equally capable of making absolute its own
inexistence in apparition (l'apparaître).

Axiom 1. An event is never the concentration of a vital continuity, or the immanent


intensification of a becoming. It is never coextensive with becoming. It is, on the contrary, on the
side of a pure break with the becoming of an object of the world, through the auto-apparition of
this object. Correlatively, it is the supplementation of apparition (l'apparaître) by the emergence
(surgissement) of a trace: what formerly inexisted becomes intense existence.
There is, with regard to the continuity in the becomings of the world, at once a lack (the
impossibility of auto-apparition with the interruption of the authority of the mathematical laws
of being and the logical laws of appearance) and an excess (the impossibility of the emergence
of a maximal intensity of existence). 'Event' names the conjunction of this lack and this excess.

Axiom 2. The event would not be the inseperable encroachment of the past on the future, or the
eternally past being of the future. It is, to the contrary, a vanishing mediator, an intemporal
instant which renders disjunct the previous state of an object (the site) and the state that follows.
We could equally say that the event extracts from a time the possibility of an other time. This
other time, whose materiality envelops the consequences of the event, deserves the name of a
new present. The event is neither past nor future. It makes us present to the present.

Axiom 3. The event would not be the result of the actions and passions of a body, nor does it
differ in nature from them. To the contrary, an active and adequate body in a new present is an
effect of the event, as we have seen in detail in Book IV (of Logique des mondes). We must here
reverse Deleuze-in the sense in which, after Nietzsche, he himself wanted to reverse Plato.
These are not the actions and passions of the multiples which are, under the title of an
immanent result, synthesised in the event. It is the blow of an evental One which animates
multiplicities and forms them into a subjectivisable body. And the trace of an event, which is
itself incorporated in the new present, is clearly of the same nature as the actions of this body.

Axiom 4. An event does not make a composite unity of what is. There is, to the contrary, a
decomposition of worlds by multiple evental sites.

Just as it performs a separation of times, the event is separated from other events. Truths are
multiple, and multiform. They are exceptions in their worlds, and not the One which makes
them converge. Deleuze often adopts the Leibnizian principle of Harmony, even as he defends
the idea of divergent series and incompossible worlds. The eternal and unique Event is the focal
point at which the ingredients of a life converge. Beyond the 'chaosmos' in which the divergent
series and heteroclite multiplicities are effectuated, 'nothing but the Event subsists, the Event
alone, Eventum Tantum for all contraries, which communicates witih itself through its own
distance, resonating across all its disjuctions.' No, this 'resonance' does not attract me. I propose
rather a flat sound, without resonance, which in no way modifies the the apparition of a site,
and nothing is disposed in harmony-or in disharmony-either with itself (considered as
subsisting solitude) or with others (considered as the reabsorption of contraries). There is not-
there cannot be-a 'Unique event of which all the others are shreds and fragments.' The one of a
truth is initiated on the basis of the without-One of the event, its contingent dissemination.
This dispute is without a doubt, as Lyotard would say, a differend, since it bears on the
fundamental semantic connection of the word 'event': with sense for Deleuze, and with truth for
me. Deleuze's formula is without apology: 'The event, which is to say, sense.' From the
beginning of his book, he forges what is for me a chimera, an inconsistent neologism: the 'sense-
event.' Such a claim communicates with the linguistic turn of the great contemporary sophists,
much more than Deleuze would have wished. In maintaining that the event belongs to the
register of sense, the entire project finds its ground on the side of language. Consider: 'The event
is sense itself. The event belongs essentially to language, it is in an essential rapport with
language.' It would be necessary to detail the dramatic reactive consequences of this kind of
statement, and of many others: for example, '[The event] is the pure expressed in what happens
which makes us signify.' Here is the kernel of the aestheticisation of everything, and the
expressive politics of the 'multitudes', in which the compact thought of the Master is today
dispersed. Insofar as it is the localised disfunction of the transcendental of a world, the event
does not have the least sense, nor is it sense itself. If it only remains as trace, it can in no way be
supported on the side of language. It only opens a space of consequences in which the body of a
truth is composed. Like every real point, as Lacan saw, it is absolutely on the side of this
unsensed which by itself can only maintain a rapport with language by making a hole in it. And
nothing sayable, nothing of the order of the transcendental laws of language (du dire), can fill
this hole.

Like all philosophers of vital continuity, Deleuze cannot abide any division between sense, the
transcendental law of appearance, and truths, eternal exceptions. He even seems sometimes to
identify the two. He once wrote to me that he 'felt no need for the category of truth. He was
certainly justified in such a claim: sense is a name sufficient for truth. There are, however,
perverse effects of this identification. Vitalist logic, which submits the actualisation of
multiplicities to the order of the virtual One-All, overlooks the fact that, in the simultaneous
declaration that events are sense, and that they have, as Deleuze proclaims, 'an eternal truth,'
we find religion in its pure state. If sense has in effect an eternal truth, then God exists, having
never been anything other than the truth of sense. Deleuze's idea of the event would have had
to convince him to follow Spinoza to the end, he who Deleuze elects as 'the Christ of
philosophers,' and convince him to name 'God' the unique Event in which becomings are
diffracted. Lacan knew well that to deliver that which happens over to sense is to work towards
the subjective consolidation of religion, since, as he wrote, 'the stability of religion is provided
by sense, which is always religious.'

This latent religiosity is all too apparent in the disciples eager to praise the supposed inverse
and constituant moment of an unbridled Capital, the 'creativity' of the multitudes: those who
believe they have seen-or what they call seeing-a planetary Parousia of a communism of 'forms
of life' in the anti-globalisation demonstrations in Seattle or Genoa, in which disaffected
(désoeuvrée) youths participate in their own way in the sinister meetings of the financial
establishment. Deleuze, often sceptical towards the formulations of those concerned with
political matters, would have, I believe, laughed to himself about such pathos. Having openly
conceptualised the place of the event in the multiform procedures of thought, Deleuze had to
reduce this place to what he called 'the ideal singularities which communicate in a single and
same Event.' If 'singularity' is inevitable, the other terms are of dubious value. 'Ideal' could be
taken as 'eternal' if Deleuze was not overly obsessed with the real of the event. 'Communicate'
could be taken as 'universal' if Deleuze did not interdict any interruption of communication
which would immediately connect any rupture to transcendental continuity. Of the 'single and
same,' I have already noted its unfortunate nature: the effect of a One, on bodies, of an evental
blow (frappe) is necessarily transformed by the absorption of the event by the One of life.

Deleuze has very strongly marked the nature of the philosophical combat in which the destiny
of the word 'event' is played out: 'A double struggle has as its object the prevention of every
dogmatic confusion between event and essence, and also every empiricist confusion between
event and accident.' There is nothing to add. Except that, when he thinks the event as intensified
result and continuity of becoming, Deleuze is an empiricist (which he, in any case, continually
proclaimed). And that, when he reincorporates it into the One of 'the unlimited Aion, the
Infinitive in which it subsists and insists', into the always-there of the Virtual, he is tendentially
dogmatic.

To break with empiricism, the event must be thought as the advent of what is subtracted from
all experience: the ontologically un-founded and the transcendentally discontinuous. To break
with dogmatism, the event must be released from every tie to the One. It must be subtracted
from Life in order to be released to the stars.

You might also like