Dystopia (N) Matters
Dystopia (N) Matters
Dystopia (N) Matters
Dystopia(n) Matters:
On the Page, on Screen, on Stage
Edited by
Fátima Vieira
Dystopia(n) Matters: On the Page, on Screen, on Stage,
Edited by Fátima Vieira
All rights for this book reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system,
or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or
otherwise, without the prior permission of the copyright owner.
Acknowledgements .................................................................................... ix
Introduction ................................................................................................. 1
Fátima Vieira
Dystopias Do Matter.................................................................................. 40
Lucy Sargisson
Intermezzo
Dystopia on Screen
Dystopia on Stage
FÁTIMA VIEIRA
Dystopias do matter
In 2005 I edited, along with Marinela Freitas, a book entitled Utopia
Matters (Porto, Editora UP, Perspective Series). The book was divided
into two parts: the first was composed of statements by reputed scholars
from the field of utopian studies, who explained why utopias really matter.
The second part of the book, which in fact corresponded to its subtitle,
dealt with “utopian matters” and was in turn divided into three parts:
Theory, Politics, and Literature and the Arts.
This new book published by Cambridge Scholars replicates the
structure of the book of 2005, but it now gravitates around a topic which
one would expect to find at the other end of utopia. However, as is made
clear by all the texts included in the first part of the volume, there are more
affinities binding utopia and dystopia together, with regard to their aims
and objectives, than differences setting them apart.
As in 2005, the contributors to the first part of this volume are reputed
scholars who were asked to make a statement explaining why dystopia
matters; they were given complete freedom as to the way they would deal
with the topic – the only exception was the limit of the number of words.
Some chose to address the issue by attempting to offer a definition of
dystopia, to trace its history and its kinship with utopia; others resorted to
dystopian texts to exemplify the relevance of their perspective; and a third
group presented very personal testimonies on their discovery of dystopia
and on their disappointment with regard to the way it has invaded the
political dimension of many countries in the world. In any case, the links
between utopia and dystopia were described as if they were almost
correlative in their function: to begin with, “every utopia contains
dystopia” (Ribeiro); rather than being the negation of utopia, dystopia may
paradoxically be its essence (Claeys); dystopia can well be seen as the
“shadow of utopia” as it emerged in the wake of the latter (Kumar); or we
can think of it as the alter ego of utopia, always “pull[ing] its dreamy
companion back to earth” (Davis).
2 Introduction
In one way or another, the need for dystopia is recognised by all the
contributors. In fact, if “the name of this world is dystopia” (Moylan), we
need it not only because it is a way of “exorcis[ing] one’s ghosts”
(Gallardo), but also because it “reminds us that our dystopia could get
worse” (Sargent), because it makes us think (Sargisson), because it is “a
form of resistance in and for our times” (Baccolini), because it may well
be “a necessary step towards a better world” (Ashworth).
The final idea, then, is that dystopia is as needed as utopia; in spite of
the “overwhelmingly individualistic focus of many dystopias” (Balasopoulos)
– as happens in fact with many utopias – despite our awareness of “[h]ow
difficult it is to make utopian progress” (Arnold), human beings will
always find “ways of coping with (…) dystopia” (Blaim), as there will
always be a “tiny element of hope (…) glimmering, that the forces of
dystopia will inspire in some part of humanity” (Davidson). Dystopia is no
doubt relevant if we think of it as a “concerted, strategic and practically
oriented reflection on a future” (Ferreira). This is, in the end, the way we
are bound to live: “fearing for the worst, hoping for the best, with a
perennial oscillation between ‘if’ and ‘but’” (Geoghegan), and cautiously
proceeding in the construction of our future.
Intermezzo
“Hell upon a Hill” is a well-informed and intelligent reflection by Artur
Blaim on the concepts of anti-utopia and dystopia, which suitably bridges
the first and the second parts of the volume and thus constitutes a
convenient intermezzo.
Fátima Vieira 5
apocalyptic ending. At last, Hande Tekdemir examines the way the epic
cycle of sixteen short plays Shoot/Get Treasure/Repeat, by Mark
Ravenhill, has been staged in Turkey by theatre director Murat Daltaban
and how this has contributed to the creation of a new language which
posits what Tekdemir calls a “theatrical utopia”.
* * *
DYSTOPIA MATTERS
DO DYSTOPIAS MATTER?
I must admit that I have always been more interested in good places
(eutopias) than bad places (dystopias). I have been told that that was
because I could not deal with the “real world”, and my response has
always been “Who wants to?” Given our real world, who needs dystopias?
At the same time, while I have always been attracted to the pleasure-
oriented Cockaigne version of the eutopia, I have always thought of
eutopia as a statement about desirable change rather than escape, perhaps
because too many colleagues, friends and students who tried to escape into
the drug culture (“Reality is for those who can’t do drugs” was a slogan of
the times) sank into that culture and either never resurfaced or resurfaced
damaged. Thus, dystopia has for me always had a strong connection to the
“reality” I wanted to avoid, a “reality” that to me needed eutopia to change
it.
At the same time, doing the bibliographic work that I do, it has always
been clear that the dystopia has been the dominant form of utopianism
since around World War I. Some of this is simply because, as Arthur C.
Clarke once said on a panel I was on, the dystopia is more interesting to
write since it gives the writer an almost automatic entry to conflict that can
drive a story. But also with World Wars I and II, Korea, Vietnam, the
various revolutions both successful and suppressed, the struggles against
colonialism that only succeeded after very high costs were paid, racism,
sexism, homophobia, etc., etc., the twentieth century has quite correctly
been called the dystopian century, and the twenty-first century does not
look much better, although as I write Egyptians are in the streets hoping to
topple a dictator just as their neighbours had done in Tunisia. But the
problem is what to do after the dictatorship and its supportive apparatus
go, and that is where we need eutopia. What can dystopia contribute?
To answer that question, I need to go back to the beginning. When
Thomas More coined the word “utopia” he also played on the word
“eutopia”, and no place became the non-existent good place. As far as we
currently know the word “dystopia” or “bad place” was coined in 1747,
Lyman Tower Sargent 11
and although it was used from time to time, it did not catch on until well
into the twentieth century.1 Since then utopia has included both eutopia,
unfortunately spelled “utopia”, and dystopia.
Of course, the concepts utopia and dystopia are not that simple. The
terms “critical utopia” introduced by Tom Moylan and “critical dystopia”
later introduced by Moylan and Raffaella Baccolini (see Moylan, 1986 and
2000; and Baccolini, 2000) mix the two together. The “critical dystopia”
in particular suggests that the possibility of eutopia exists within some
dystopias, but the problem is how to actualise the eutopia and get rid of the
dystopia. Neither the standard dystopia, where some hero or heroine is
needed, nor the “critical dystopia”, where no such change takes place, is
reassuring on this problem.
One of the first utopias I ever read, I and many others thought of as a
dystopia, while the author and many others were quite clear that it was a
eutopia. That book was B.F. Skinner’s Walden Two (1948), and even
though I read it negatively, I had to admit that Skinner saw it positively,
and he said so many times. As a result, it is clear from both internal and
external evidence together with the fact that a number of people decided to
establish intentional communities modelled on Skinner’s vision as
expressed in the book that a book could be both a eutopia and a dystopia
depending on the reader (on Walden Two communities, see Kuhlman).
A similar issue is seen in some of the novels of Aldous Huxley. Brave
New World (1932) is explicitly an extrapolation into the future of trends
that he saw in his present, trends that he said in a “Foreword” written in
1946 and in Brave New World Revisited (1957) were coming to fruition
even faster than he had expected. Between these two books, Huxley had
written that he believed that he should have given the Savage another,
better option, and, of course, later Huxley spelled out a positive vision in
Island (1962) that has many features in common with Brave New World.
But Island is clearly a eutopia rather than a dystopia. Thus, Brave New
World was a warning, the 1946 “Foreword” and Brave New World
Revisited are statements that the world depicted in Brave New World is
fast approaching, and Island at least suggests that a better alternative might
be possible, although its ending implies that Huxley was not very
optimistic that “the people” would change their ways.
But of course it is not quite that simple. When I read Walden Two I had
never heard the word “eutopia” and had no real knowledge of the utopian
tradition in its various manifestations. I thought Walden Two would be a
terrible place to live, and others thought it would be a good place to live,
so good that they tried to create it. To really complicate matters I also
disliked one aspect of Island, the manipulation of people who were “little
12 Do Dystopias Matter?
Note
1
On the history of the word, see Budakov, 2010.
Lyman Tower Sargent 13
Works cited
Baccolini, Raffaella (2000), “Gender and Genre in the Feminist Critical
Dystopias of Katharine Burdekin, Margaret Atwood, and Octavia
Butler”, in Marleen S. Barr (ed.), Future Females, the Next
Generation: New Voices and Velocities in Feminist Science Fiction
Criticism, Lanham, MD, Rowman and Littlefield, pp. 13-34.
Bercovitch, Sacvan (1978), The American Jeremiad, Madison, U of
Wisconsin P.
Budakov, V[esselin] M. (2010), “Dystopia: An Earlier Eighteenth-Century
Use”, Notes and Queries, vol. 57, nr. 1, March, pp. 86-8.
Kuhlmann, Hilke (2005). Living Walden Two: B.F. Skinner’s Behaviorist
Utopia and Experimental Communities, Urbana, U of Illinois P.
Moylan, Tom (1986), Demand the Impossible: Science Fiction and the
Utopian Imagination, London, Methuen.
—. [Thomas Patrick] (2000), Scraps of the Untainted Sky: Science Fiction,
Utopia, Dystopia, Boulder, CO, Westview.
Polak, Fred[erick] L[odewijk] (1961), The Image of the Future:
Enlightening the Past, Orientating the Present, Forecasting the
Future, trans. Elise Boulding, 2 vols., Leyden, The Netherlands, A.W.
Sythoff/New York, Oceana Pub. [Originally published as De Toekomst
is verleden tijd: Cultuur-futuristische verkenningen, 2 vols., Utrecht,
The Netherlands, W. de Haan, 1955.]
Sargent, Lyman Tower (1994), “The Three Faces of Utopianism
Revisited”, Utopian Studies, vol. 5, nr. 1, pp. 1-37.
—. (2010), Utopianism: A Very Short Introduction, Oxford, Eng., Oxford
UP.
THREE VARIANTS ON THE CONCEPT
OF DYSTOPIA
GREGORY CLAEYS
What kind of concept is “dystopia”,1 and how does it differ from that of
“utopia”? Dystopia is popularly supposed to be an inverted, mirror,
negative version of utopia. Unlike “utopia”, however, in the first instance,
“dystopia” is evidently a much younger concept, dating only from the late
nineteenth century, and one moreover not linked to a single text or
discernable tradition. Prima facie, of course, there is no difficulty viewing
these concepts as synchronised or symmetrical: if “utopia” entails the
depiction of any kind of idealised society regarded as superior to the
present by its author, “dystopia” implies its negation, or any kind of
society regarded as inferior by its author. The problems commence when
we acknowledge that utopianism is not a purely literary tradition and that
“utopia” may be defined in a number of other ways. Indeed while we may
generally concede that the common language definition of utopia describes
any variety of “ideal” society, the term itself only becomes historically and
analytically interesting when we refine this definition. In particular, when
we associate “utopia” with the tradition established by Thomas More’s
famous text of 1516, we are presented with a variety of interesting
questions which have a bearing upon the definition of any negation or
inversion of the concept.
The tradition associated with Thomas More, then, may be described in
terms of an adherence to a communal regime in which private property
generally is restricted and public life is given priority over individualism.
Such a definition is clearly problematic: it does not purport to describe all
the texts written in imitation of More, in particular, and it acknowledges
that the road to Utopia in More’s own account is paved with unclear
intentions at best. But it does take into account the fact that utopianism,
taken more broadly, clearly does consist of three facets: a literary tradition,
an ideology or ideologies, and a tradition of communal living and
organisation. The question, then, is what bearing a more refined definition
of utopia of this type has for the definition of dystopia and whether it
Gregory Claeys 15
renders the latter concept distinctly asymmetrical: that is, not usually a
mirror negative image of utopia at all.
But there are problems even with the idea of dystopia as the negative
of “ideal” societies. Clearly just as one person’s freedom fighter is
another’s terrorist, one person’s utopia is another’s dystopia. Dystopia, in
other words, rather than being the negation of utopia, paradoxically may
be its essence. Any privileging of the communal over the individual will
for some have dystopian overtones. Writ large, in this view, utopia is the
predecessor of totalitarianism, particularly of the Marxist type; such was
the essence of the enormously influential Talmon-Popper line of the late
1940s and 1950s, which, though it has nineteenth-century roots, notably in
the work of Gustave Le Bon, is today most often associated with Norman
Cohn’s classic study, The Pursuit of the Millennium. (Lately John Gray
has notably taken up this particular cudgel.) In this interpretation modern
utopianism is quintessentially an extension of the millenarian thrust of the
Judaeo-Christian tradition. History possesses a particular telos, which is
some form of salvation, and culminates in some variation of its secular
realisation. In socialism, this consists essentially in the recapturing and/or
realisation of some form of social essence, or primeval sociability. For
Marx this was early on described in Ludwig Feuerbach’s concept of
species-being, which was repackaged as a plea for “human emancipation”
or “universal emancipation”. Utopianism, in other words, is secular
perfectibility. (One of many paradoxes here, of course, is that as we have
seen Marx did not view himself as a utopian – and in this sense he was
correct: he was not a utopian but a perfectibilist.) Realising the essence of
the communal involves the suppression of the individual: the family and
private life are sacrificed to or subsumed under the greater identity of the
society, state, party and/or nation. Students of twentieth-century history, in
particular, will have little difficulty assembling a teleological construction
of dystopia in which the origins of modern totalitarianism lie in something
like the vision described by Thomas More (whether the latter approved of
this or not of course remains contentious). Despite Marx and Engels’s own
famously caustic comments on “utopian” socialism, many Marxists have
lent credence to this intellectual chronology, without of course intending
such portrayals to show the social and economic system described in a
negative light. Utopia is here not dystopia, because the demands it makes
respecting the suppression of individuality are justified by the ends
achieved in terms of a more just, fair and equal society. To its opponents,
however, such a view eventuated in Stalinism in all its manifold forms, in
the hyper-politicisation of individual and social relations, in the privileging
of conformity over dissent, in leader-worship as a quasi-religious
16 Three Variants on the Concept of Dystopia
Notes
1
This essay builds upon arguments presented in my (2010) “The Origins of
Dystopia: Wells, Huxley and Orwell”, in Gregory Claeys (ed.), The Cambridge
Companion to Utopian Literature, Cambridge UP, pp. 107-34; and my (2011)
Searching for Utopia: The History of an Idea, Thames and Hudson.
2
If the Garden of Eden is the key model for the original Western, Judaeo-Christian
utopian tradition, expulsion from it would possibly imply that subsequent human
life is itself “dystopian”.
UTOPIA’S SHADOW
KRISHAN KUMAR
Four. All three were responses, direct or indirect, to the utopias of science
and socialism that were best expressed in the many utopias written by
H.G. Wells in these years, from A Modern Utopia to The Shape of Things
to Come.
It is an interesting question to ask, Which of these dystopias most
appeal today? Which seem to have been the most prescient, in the sense of
most being in tune with contemporary realities? Zamyatin’s We is the most
stylish, from a literary point of view: spare and piercing, making effective
uses of some of the devices of literary modernism. He certainly anticipates
much of the analysis of totalitarianism that we find in Nineteen Eighty-
Four and even – in the sexual arrangements, for instance – some of the
elements of Brave New World. But Zamyatin’s terse and elliptical way of
presenting his material makes it difficult to assess it in political and
sociological terms. What we get is an evocation of mood, a sense of power
and terror which is extraordinarily effective but which leaves as it were the
“machinery” of the society largely unexplored. Hence it is difficult to say
how far the state of the world today matches up to the society of We.
Certainly we might agree that terror and power remain persistent realities
in the world; in that sense Zamyatin may be said to have given us a
timeless glimpse of an enduring feature of modernity. But it remains
largely in the metaphorical mode; its lack of detail makes comparisons
with the more concrete features of today’s world difficult.
Orwell’s Nineteen Eighty-Four abounds in detail; that has always been
one of its great strengths and one of the sources of its continuing appeal.
Everyone remembers the clock that strikes thirteen; the absence of the
small luxuries of life, such as toiletries; the rituals of tea-making in the
room above the antique shop in the proles’ quarter where Winston and
Julia have their romantic trysts. Nineteen-Eighty Four, Orwell seems to
want to remind us again and again, is a novel, not a political tract. It has
many echoes of some of his earlier novels, such as Coming Up for Air.
This is one reason why it is wrong to abbreviate the title of the novel to
1984, as if it is a date. As a date, 1984 is irrelevant to the novel; it simply
reverses the last two digits of the actual date – 1948 – when Orwell wrote
the novel. To concentrate on the date is to treat the work as prophecy, and
this is something that Orwell was at pains to deny. His book was, he said,
a warning, not a prophecy. It was meant say: something like this could
happen, and it might if we don’t do something to stop it. To dismiss
Orwell’s vision because, by 1984 or thereabouts, what he said might
happen did not happen (or did it?) is to miss the point of Orwell’s analysis
of what he regarded as some powerful tendencies in modern society: some