Nichols, Physics Envy
Nichols, Physics Envy
Nichols, Physics Envy
RECONCEPTUALIZING SOCIAL
RESEARCH
David P. Nichols
What are appropriate goals and methods for research in the so-
cial sciences? The fact that this question does not have obvious an-
swers for many social scientists is borne out by the existence of two
edited volumes produced as the result of conferences at the Univer-
sity of Chicago, in 1979 (Kruskal, 1982) and 1983 (Fiske & Shweder,
1986). The range of opinions expressed in these volumes is demonstra-
tive of the deep divisions that exist in the social science community
over basic issues.
DAVID P. NICHOLS
thesis is that the idealized model of physics not only is not a good
model for the social sciences, but that it is not even a good model for
physics.
Harding's work points to the fact that some of the same kind of
questioning of basic principles and assimiptions that is taking place
in the social sciences is also occurring in the natural sciences. Much
of the controversy was prompted by the publication in 1962 of
Thomas Kuhn's The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. This bomb-
shell from an historian of science was the external complement to the
events in modem physics previously discussed. Kuhn's challenge to
conventional views of scientific progress was profound enough to be
entertained most seriously by some of the world's most prominent
philosophers and historians of science. A 1965 London symposium on
Kuhn's ideas produced a volume (Lakatos & Musgrave, 1970) that
matches the later social science volumes in the variety of expressed
perspectives.
It is safe to say that the positivist conception of scientific progress
still reigns among the majority of physical scientists. While also a
major force among social scientists, belief in the search for a physics
of social phenomena is no longer near universal. As Cronbach (1986,
pp. 84-85) explains,
DAVID P. NICHOLS
assuming the rules of logic; the game has been rigged from the start.
The onus of responsibility for establishing basic assumptions has
been placed on the relativist, and he or she will surely fail under
these rules. However, should we reverse the responsibility by refus-
ing to assume the rules of logic, the position of the objectivist will fare
no better.
This is so because no system of thought is capable offiiUyjustify-
ing its own assumptions. As Lakatos (1970) puts it, "All scientific
research programmes may be characterized by their 'hard core'. The
negative heuristic of the programme forbids us to direct the modus
tollens at this 'hard core"' (p. 133). This hard core "is 'irrefiitable by
the methodological decision of its protagonists" (p. 135). For logic, a
part of the hard core is the existence of Absolute Truth. Pirsig (1974)
illustrates the resulting fundamental problem with the example of
the Socratic method: "Once it's stated that 'the dialectic comes before
anj^thing else,' this statement itself becomes a dialectical entity, sub-
ject to dialectical question" (p. 353).
The assumption that formal logical principles are the basis of all
scientific thought is so deeply ingrained in modem western culture
that the way out of this dilemma may be unclear to many scientists.
As Shweder (1986) says, "the mythic idealization in our culture of the
physical or natural sciences may have led us to draw an all-too-sharp
contrast between what is hard and what is soft, between what is ob-
jective and what is subjective" (p. 175). In other words, it may not be
the case that one either accepts the existence of Absolute Truth or
else winds up accepting the idea that all views have equal claims to
validity and one therefore cannot with justification argue against any
perspective.
This point is by no means a new one. Bernstein (1976, 1983),
Hubner (1983), Laudan (1984), Pirsig (1974), Rorty (1979), Shweder
(1986), and Toulmin (1972) all explicitly make this claim. What is
important to understand is that the problems involved in the adher-
ence to this dichotomy stem from the fact that the objectivist and
relativist positions are actually both sides of the same coin—an abso-
lutist interpretation of nature that has troubled us for centuries. As
Bernstein (1983) puts it, "Relativism ultimately makes sense (and
gains its plausibility) as the dialectical antithesis to ohjectivism. If we
see through objectivism, if we expose what is wrong with this way of
thinking, then we are at the same time questioning the very intel-
ligibility of relativism" (p. 167).
56
The way out of the dilemma begins with the realization that "in-
ductive and deductive logic cannot account for every example of sys-
tematic, constrained thinking, and there are many examples of im-
personal constraints that are not logical rules—not the least of which
are the rules of language" (Shweder, 1986, p. 179). In Toulmin's
(1972) words, we must "abandon . . . the philosophers' traditional as-
sumption that rationality is a sub-species of logicality" (p. 486). If we
"reject the commitment to logical systematicity which makes absolut-
ism and relativism appear the only altematives available" (p. 84) we
will find that "it is still possible to steer a middle way between the
absolutist and relativist extremes" (p. 497).
Shweder's (1986, pp. 177-178) discussion of this third way is
worth quoting at length:
One basic implication of this view for social research is that "There is
a soft side to all hard data, or perhaps the crucial point is that with-
out the soft side there is no hard side" (p. 174).
For those engaged in research centered on issues of rationality,
the implications are perhaps even more profound: "other conceptions
that rest on a neat and clean contrast between what's objective and
57
DAVID P. NICHOLS
EXPERIMENTAL METHODOLOGY AS
A SET OF HEURISTICS
An excellent example of the potential of this attitude is provided
by Wimsatt (1986) in his study of heuristic strategies. Though much
of his paper centers on biological topics, there is much here to be
59
DAVID P. NICHOLS
DAVID P. NICHOLS
methods are thus thought to be the next best thing. If we can't control
all the important factors directly, we can at least control those of in-
terest directly and control for others statistically, or so the reasoning
goes. In other cases we look to "natural experiments," where changes
in purported causes of interest happen without our intervention, and
again attempt to control for nuisance factors through statistical con-
trols. But just how valid is this reliance on statistical control? In a
monograph that should be required reading for all students of social
processes, Lieberson (1985, p. 19) demonstrates that this approach is
fi-aught with peril.
DAVID P. NICHOLS
studies will confirm it. Unfortunately, this is not necessarily the case.
According to Lieberson, replication won't always tell us what's real
and what's chance or artifact because unmeasured selective forces
will often differ across contexts and replications and thus produce dif-
ferent results. "Further tests, follow-up studies, newer statistical pro-
cedures, exchanges in the journals, bigger samples, more controls,
and the like, may or may not support the original conclusion, but it
does not really matter if they are all based on the same underlying
false premise" (p. 39).
Even the latest and greatest of the super statistical methods such
as structural equation modeling are not up to the task in the presence
of unmeasured selective processes. The current rage for such models
belies the fact that the concept of path models has been around for
more than 70 years (see Wright, 1921) without solving the basic prob-
lems associated with drawing causal inferences from associations or
correlations. Firm causal inference comes from theory and design, not
from statistics. As Cronbach (1982) says, "These advances should in-
crease the yield from field data, but I cannot share the optimism that
superadjustments will warrant causal conclusions. Curve fitting can-
not lift us into orbit unless fueled by substantive insight" (p. 67).
OTHER DANGERS IN
QUASI-EXPERIMENTAL RESEARCH:
CONTAMINATION, ASYMMETRY AND
LEVELS OF ANALYSIS
At the risk of some redundancy, I think it is important to sum-
marize further points made by Lieberson (1985). He lists four other
problems that haunt quasi-experimental research. These by no means
exhaust the threats to validity of quasi-experimental research (see
Cook & Campbell, 1979), but considered in conjunction with the selec-
tivity issue they provide a powerful argument for the need to recon-
ceptualize traditional quantitative social scientific research meth-
odology.
The first hazard, contamination, occurs when the presence of or
change in an independent variable has effects where it is not present
or does not change. Examples would be the impact of tax laws or
professional licensure requirements in some jurisdictions on the be-
havior of governing bodies or professionals in other places. Effects of
the measures on behavior within the original jurisdictions would not
64
The fourth issue, that of the role of variation in causal and statis-
tical analysis, is so important and so widely misunderstood as to war-
rant extensive attention. As anyone who has had an introductory
course in statistics knows, statistical methods cannot be applied
where variation does not exist. The almost universal requirement in
empirical social research to apply statistical methods if one wishes to
have work seriously considered has important implications for our
selection of research problems and our conceptualization of causal
processes. As Lieberson says, "one must ask whether problems are
sometimes posed in a certain way more because they meet statistical
criteria and needs than because they are the most appropriate re-
search question in terms of either substantive or theoretical issues"
(p. 89).
He goes on to point out that issues of variability should be sec-
ondary to more basic issues of underlying causal forces.
65
DAVID P. NICHOLS
DAVID P. NICHOLS
DAVID P. NICHOLS
REFERENCES
Bayer, R. A. (1981). Homosexuality and'American psychiatry: The politics of diagnosis.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Bernstein, R. J. (1976). The restructuring of social and political theory. Philadelphia:
University of Pennsylvania Press.
Bernstein, R. J. (1983). Beyond objectivism and relativism: Science, hermeneutics, and
praxis. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
Bock, R. D. (1975). Multivariate statistical methods in behavioral research New York-
McGraw-Hill.
Camphell, D. T., & Fiske, D. W. (1959). Convergent and discriminant validation hy the
multitrait-multimethod matrix. Psychological Bulletin, 56, 81-105.
Capra, F. (1975). The tao of physics. Toronto: Bantam Books.
Capra, F. (1982). The turning point. Toronto: Bantam Books.
Cook, T. D., & Camphell, D. T. (1979). Quasi-experimentation: Design & analysis issues
for field settings. Boston: Houghton Mifilin Company.
Cronhach, L. J. (1982). Prudent aspirations for social inquiry. In W. H. Kruskal (Ed.),
The social sciences: Their nature and uses (pp. 61-81). Chicago: University of Chi-
cago Press.
Cronhach, L. J. (1986). Social inquiry hy and for earthlings. In D. W. Fiske & R. A.
Shweder (Eds.), Metatheory in social science: Pluralisms and subjectivities (pp.
83-107). Chicago: Universi^ of Chicago Press.
D'Andrade, R. (1986). Three scientific world views and the covering law model. In
D. W. Fiske & R. A. Shweder (Eds.), Metatheory in social science: Pluralisms and
subjectivities (pp. 19-41). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Fausto-Sterling, A. (1985). Myths of gender. New York: Basic Books.
71
DAVID P. NICHOLS
Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univer-
sity Press.
Ryan, W. (1971). Blaming the victim. New York: Vintage Books.
Salmon, W. C. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Schiff, M., & Lewontin, R. (1986). Education and class: The irrelevance oflQ genetic
studies. New York: Oxford University Press.
Schwartz, B. (1986). The battle for human nature: Science, morality and modern life.
New York: W. W. Norton.
Schwarz, J. E. (1988). America's hidden success (rev. ed.). New York: W. W. Norton.
Shweder, R. A. (1986). Divergent rationalities. In D. W. Fiske & R. A. Shweder (Eds.),
Metatheory in social science: Pluralisms and subjectivities (pp. 163-196). Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Toulmin, S. (1972). Human understanding: The collective use and evolution of concepts.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Tuana, N. (Ed.). (1989). Feminism and science. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Wimsatt, W. C. (1986). Heuristics and the study of human hehavior. In D. W. Fiske &
R. A. Shweder (Eds.), Metatheory in social science: Pluralisms and subjectivities
(pp. 293-314). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Wright, S. (1921). Correlation and causation. Journal of Agricultural Research, 20,
557-585.