Jurisprudence Project On: Dr. Kaumudhi Challa

Download as doc, pdf, or txt
Download as doc, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 36

JURISPRUDENCE PROJECT ON

SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORY AND ITS RELEVANCE IN MORDERN TIMES


AN ANALYSIS

SUBMITTED TO:

Dr. Kaumudhi Challa

Faculty of Jurisprudence

SUBMITTED BY:

Devvrat Vaishnav

V Semester,
Sec-A, Roll No-058.
B.A. LLB (HONS.)

HIDAYATULLAH NATIONAL LAW UNIVERISTY


RAIPUR
Date of Submission- 21-08-2017

I
Declaration
I, Devvrat Vaishnav, have undergone research of the project work titled “Social Contract
Theory And Its Relevance In The Modern Times an Analysis”, as a student of
Jurisprudence hereby declare that-this Research Project has been prepared by the student for
academic purpose only, and is the outcome of the investigation done by me and also prepared
by myself under the supervision of Dr. Kaumudhi Challa, Hidayatullah National Law
University, Raipur. The views expressed in the report are personal to the student and do not
reflect the views of any authority or any other person, and do not bind the statute in any
manner.

I also declare that this Research Paper or any part, thereof has not been or is not being
submitted elsewhere for the award of any degree or Diploma. This report is the intellectual
property of the on the part of student research work, and the same or any part thereof may not
be used in any manner whatsoever in writing.

Devvrat Vaishnav
Roll. No. 58
Section A

II
Certificate
This is to certify that Mr.Devvrat Vaishnav, Roll Number-58, student of Semester- V of
B.A.LL.B.(Hons.), Hidayatullah National Law University, New Raipur (Chhattisgarh) has
undergone research of the project work titled “Social Contract Theory And Its Relevance
In The Modern Times an Analysis”, in partial fulfillment of the subject Jurisprudence. His
performance in research work is up to the level.

Place: New Raipur ………………………… ……………………………

Date: 21.08.2017 Dr. Kaumudhi Challa.

(Faculty- Jurisprudence)

Hidayatullah National Law University, New Raipur, Chhattisgarh

III
Acknowledgements
I feel highly elated to work on the project “Social Contract Theory And Its Relevance In
The Modern Times an Analysis”. The practical realization of the project has obligated the
assistance of many persons. Firstly I express my deepest gratitude towards Dr. Kaumudhi
Challa, Faculty of Jurisprudence, to provide me with the opportunity to work on this project.
Her able guidanceship and supervision in terms of his lectures were of extreme help in
understanding and carrying out the nuances of this project.

I would also like to thank The University and the Vice Chancellor for providing extensive
database resources in the library and for the internet facilities provided by the University.

Some typography or printing errors might have crept in, which are deeply regretted. I would
be grateful to receive comments and suggestions to further improve this project.

Devvrat Vaishnav

Roll No. 58

Section A

IV
Table of Cases
Contents
DECLARATION.......................................................................................................................................................... II

CERTIFICATE............................................................................................................................
INTRODUCTION...........................................................................................................................1
RESEARCH METHODOLOGY....................................................................................................... 3
PROBLEM................................................................................................................................3
RATIONALE.............................................................................................................................3
OBJECTIVES............................................................................................................................3
HYPOTHESIS............................................................................................................................3
NATURE OF STUDY.................................................................................................................3
SOURCES OF DATA.................................................................................................................3
REVIEW OF LITERATURE....................................................................................................... 4
CHAPTERISATION....................................................................................................................4
CONTRIBUTION OF RESEARCH...............................................................................................5
REALIST SCHOOL.......................................................................................................................6
BASIC FEATURES OF REALIST SCHOOL.................................................................................6
SCANDINAVIAN REALIST.............................................................................................................7
PHILOSOPHICAL BACKGROUND..............................................................................................7
AXEL HAGERSTORM (1868-1939)..........................................................................................9
KARL OLIVECRONA (1897-1980).........................................................................................10
ALF ROSS (1899-1979).........................................................................................................13
CONTRIBUTION OF REALIST SCHOOL TO JURISPRUDENCE.................................................14
SCANDINAVIAN REALISM IN THE INDIAN CONTEXT................................................................ 16
CRITICISM AGAINST SCANDINAVIAN REALISM........................................................................19
CONCLUSION............................................................................................................................ 20
REFERENCES.............................................................................................................................21
Introduction

According to Addison (2011), the social Contract of Thomas Hobbes referred to the ideology
of establishment of moral rules that govern relations among people. It just points on the need
to have social order. As the term social comes from society, so “contract “means an
agreement. People have to treat others with respect and follow some basic human rules
agreed upon (Browne, n.d). Browne (n.d), still suggests that Hobbes thought that without this
contract, society would be nasty, dangerous, unbounded, criminal, and disgusting. As
highlighted earlier, the social contract was still developed by several philosophers like Jean
Jacques Rousseau who took another step by affirming that in the society, no one was above
rules. This prevented society from enacting bad rules against themselves and the government.
The theory also attacked comprehensive systems of political philosophy, and it still does so
up to date. In all, the social contract theory articulates that morality consist a set of rules,
governing how people accept to treat one another, for their mutual benefit, on the condition
that others follow those same rules, and practice them. In this document, the relevance of the
social contract of Thomas Hobbes and John Locke to the modern world will be explained in
a summarized manner.

Social contract theory, nearly as old as philosophy itself, is the view that persons'
moral and/or political obligations are dependent upon a contract or agreement
among them to form the society in which they live. Socrates uses something quite like
a social contract argument to explain to Crito why he must remain in prison and
accept the death penalty. However, social contract theory is rightly associated with
modern moral and political theory and is given its first full exposition and defense by
Thomas Hobbes. After Hobbes, John Locke and Jean-Jacques Rousseau are the best
known proponents of this enormously influential theory, which has been one of the
most dominant theories within moral and political theory throughout the history of
the modern West. In the twentieth century, moral and political theory regained
philosophical momentum as a result of John Rawls’ Kantian version of social
contract theory, and was followed by new analyses of the subject by David Gauthier
and others. More recently, philosophers from different perspectives have offered new
criticisms of social contract theory. In particular, feminists and race-conscious
philosophers have argued that social contract theory is at least an incomplete picture
of our moral and political lives, and may in fact camouflage some of the ways in
which the contract is itself parasitical upon the subjugations of classes of persons.
2
Research Methodology
Problem
This project gives an insight to the social contract theory by viewing the theories given by
different philosophers such as john locke ,jean jacques rosseau & thomas hobbes .

Rationale
This project studies social contract theory in details by comparing the views of different
philosophers and it thoroughly contributes to the development of related field of study .this
project also shows light on why social contract theory is important in modern times and its
values .

Objectives
1. To study about Social Contract Theory

2. To study about Philosophers of social contract theory

3. To study the importance of social contract theory in modern times

Hypothesis
There exi.

Nature of Study
This project is based upon doctrinal method of research. This project has been done after a
after a thorough research based upon intrinsic and extrinsic aspects of the project.

Sources of Data
The sources of data in this research project are primarily analytical and based on secondary
source of data. The following secondary sources of data have been used in the project-

1. Articles.

3
2. Books

3. Journals

4. Websites

Review of Literature
1. Anthony Carty, Scandinavian Realism and Phenomenological Approaches to
Statehood and General Custom in International Law

Scandinavian realism, in the argument presented here, has effectively swept away this whole
formalistic apparatus as illusory. The next stage of the argument has been to look at
international society through the eyes of international relations scholars, particularly of a
cultural, socio-psychological inclination, to see where there would be a place for
phenomenological intentionality

2. Jes Bjarup, The Philosophy of Scandinavian Legal Realism

It present Hägerström's philosophical theory and argue that he is committed to the


metaphysical view that the world in time and space consists of causal regularities between
things and events devoid of any values that is related to his epistemological view that what
there is can be known by experience. This approach is followed by his pupils, the Swedish
lawyers A. V. Lundstedt and Karl Olivecrona, whereas Ross appeals to logical positivism.
The naturalistic approach should be taken seriously since it leaves no room for the
normativity of the law and for legal knowledge in terms of reasons for belief and action.

3. Saeesh Naik, The Concept Of Scandinavian Realism

Scandanavian realism is speculative in approach to legal problems, and it does not devote
much attention to psychological behaviour of Judges as the American realist do. It has
empirical approach to law and life alike American Realism and give more weight to the
social effects of law with emphasis on judicial decisions.

Chapterisation
Chapter 1 of the project work deals with the social contract theory and their basic features
of philosophy. Chapter 2 deals with the work of philosophers and different theories of
social contract such as Socrates ,Thomas Hobbes and john locke and their contribution to
the above mentionedsocial contract theory . Chapter 3 deals with the impotance of social
contract theory in modern times . chapter 4 deals with the common criticism of social
contract theory.

4
Chapter 4 deals with the criticism against the Scandinavian school of thought.

Contribution of Research
As a student of law this project work will further help in understanding the thought process of
different jurist while studying about social contract theory as well as understanding
relationship between human and society .

5
WHAT IS SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORY

Social contract theory, nearly as old as philosophy itself, is the view that persons' moral and/or
political obligations are dependent upon a contract or agreement among them to form the society in
which they live. Socrates uses something quite like a social contract argument to explain to Crito why
he must remain in prison and accept the death penalty. However, social contract theory is rightly
associated with modern moral and political theory and is given its first full exposition and defense by
Thomas Hobbes. After Hobbes, John Locke and Jean-Jacques Rousseau are the best known
proponents of this enormously influential theory, which has been one of the most dominant theories
within moral and political theory throughout the history of the modern West. In the twentieth
century, moral and political theory regained philosophical momentum as a result of John Rawls’
Kantian version of social contract theory, and was followed by new analyses of the subject by David
Gauthier and others. More recently, philosophers from different perspectives have offered new
criticisms of social contract theory. In particular, feminists and race-conscious philosophers have
argued that social contract theory is at least an incomplete picture of our moral and political lives, and
may in fact camouflage some of the ways in which the contract is itself parasitical upon the
subjugations of classes of persons.
Generally, social contract theorists advance the view that the state or, more precisely, civil society is the
product of a contract, a covenant, an agreement, or a compact. Its earliest recognizably modern form dates
back to Thomas Hobbes and continues through John Locke, Baruch Spinoza, Samuel Pufendorf, Jean-Jacques
Rousseau (and others) to Immanuel Kant; whilst John Rawls stands out among its contemporary proponents,
not only for resurrecting it from the disrepute into which it fell after Kant but, perhaps more importantly, for
incorporating into it some key elements for its adaptation to the contemporary requirements of the state and
citizenship. Contracarianism and Contractualism are often generally used as synonymous terms for social
contract theories, the central idea of which is that ‘the legitimacy of the state and/or the principles of sound
justice derive their legitimacy from a societal agreement or social contract.’ However, the two terms are also
sometimes distinguished respectively as the Hobbesian model, and the Kantian interpretations of the
justificatory problem, which is a central issue in the modern conceptualizations of the theory.
But, as noted by Frederick Rauscher: These categories are imprecise, and there is often as much difference
within these two approaches as between them; yet, nevertheless, the distinction is useful in isolating some key
disputes in contemporary social contract theory. Among those “contractarians” who—very roughly—can be
called followers of Hobbes, the crucial justificatory task is, as David Gauthier puts it, to resolve the
“foundational crisis” of morality.5 To explicate the idea of the Social Contract Theory, Rauscher suggests five
variables into which contractual approaches may be analysed, namely: (1) the nature of the contractual act; (2)
the parties to the act; (3) what the parties are agreeing to; (4) the reasoning that leads to the agreement; (5)
what the agreement is supposed to show. Tints of the Social Contract Theory, however, exist in the natural law
theories, for example in the medieval Aristotelianism of Thomas Aquinas and in the modernized natural law
theories of Johannes Althusius and Hugo Grotius. The element of contract in Aquinas’ theory derives from his
views on the basis of moral obligation, which according to him is located in man’s nature. Samuel E. Stumpf
paraphrases Aquinas thus: The basis of moral obligation … is found, first of all, in the very nature of man. Built
into man’s nature are various inclinations, such as the preservation of his life, the propagation of his species,
and, because he is rational, the inclination toward the search for truth. The basic moral truth is simply to ‘’do
good and avoid evil’’. As a rational being, then, man is under a basic moral obligation to protect his life and
health… Secondly, the natural inclination to propagate the species forms the basis for the union of man and
wife… And thirdly, because man seeks for truth, he can do this best by living in peace in society with his fellow
men who are also engaged in the quest. To ensure an ordered society, human laws are fashioned for the
direction of the community’s behavior.
Civil society and human laws thus become logically imperative for man’s pursuit of full self-realization. For
Aquinas, human laws are statutes of government and they derive from the general precepts of natural law,
which he conceives of as ‘nothing else than the rational creature’s participation of the eternal law’.7 The
eternal law, he posits, is Divine Reason

6
Socrates' Argument
In the early Platonic dialogue, Crito, Socrates makes a compelling argument as to why
he must stay in prison and accept the death penalty, rather than escape and go into
exile in another Greek city. He personifies the Laws of Athens, and, speaking in their
voice, explains that he has acquired an overwhelming obligation to obey the Laws
because they have made his entire way of life, and even the fact of his very existence,
possible. They made it possible for his mother and father to marry, and therefore to
have legitimate children, including himself. Having been born, the city of Athens,
through its laws, then required that his father care for and educate him. Socrates' life
and the way in which that life has flourished in Athens are each dependent upon the
Laws. Importantly, however, this relationship between citizens and the Laws of the
city are not coerced. Citizens, once they have grown up, and have seen how the city
conducts itself, can choose whether to leave, taking their property with them, or stay.
Staying implies an agreement to abide by the Laws and accept the punishments that
they mete out. And, having made an agreement that is itself just, Socrates asserts
that he must keep to this agreement that he has made and obey the Laws, in this
case, by staying and accepting the death penalty. Importantly, the contract described
by Socrates is an implicit one: it is implied by his choice to stay in Athens, even
though he is free to leave.
In Plato's most well-known dialogue, Republic, social contract theory is represented
again, although this time less favorably. In Book II, Glaucon offers a candidate for an
answer to the question "what is justice?" by representing a social contract
explanation for the nature of justice. What men would most want is to be able to
commit injustices against others without the fear of reprisal, and what they most
want to avoid is being treated unjustly by others without being able to do injustice in
return. Justice then, he says, is the conventional result of the laws and covenants that
men make in order to avoid these extremes. Being unable to commit injustice with
impunity (as those who wear the ring of Gyges would), and fearing becoming victims
themselves, men decide that it is in their interests to submit themselves to the
convention of justice. Socrates rejects this view, and most of the rest of the dialogue
centers on showing that justice is worth having for its own sake, and that the just
man is the happy man. So, from Socrates’ point of view, justice has a value that
greatly exceeds the prudential value that Glaucon assigns to it.
These views, in the Crito and the Republic, might seem at first glance inconsistent: in
the former dialogue Socrates uses a social contract type of argument to show why it is
just for him to remain in prison, whereas in the latter he rejects social contract as the
source of justice. These two views are, however, reconcilable. From Socrates' point of
view, a just man is one who will, among other things, recognize his obligation to the
state by obeying its laws. The state is the morally and politically most fundamental
entity, and as such deserves our highest allegiance and deepest respect. Just men
know this and act accordingly. Justice, however, is more than simply obeying laws in
exchange for others obeying them as well. Justice is the state of a well-regulated soul,
and so the just man will also necessarily be the happy man. So, justice is more than
the simple reciprocal obedience to law, as Glaucon suggests, but it does nonetheless
include obedience to the state and the laws that sustain it. So in the end, although
Plato is perhaps the first philosopher to offer a representation of the argument at the
heart of social contract theory, Socrates ultimately rejects the idea that social
contract is the original source of justice.
Thomas Hobbes
Thomas Hobbes, 1588-1679, lived during the most crucial period of early modern England's history:
the English Civil War, waged from 1642-1648. To describe this conflict in the most general of terms, it
was a clash between the King and his supporters, the Monarchists, who preferred the traditional
authority of a monarch, and the Parliamentarians, most notably led by Oliver Cromwell, who
demanded more power for the quasi-democratic institution of Parliament. Hobbes represents a
compromise between these two factions. On the one hand he rejects the theory of the Divine Right of
Kings, which is most eloquently expressed by Robert Filmer in his Patriarcha or the Natural Power
of Kings, (although it would be left to John Locke to refute Filmer directly). Filmer’s view held that a
king’s authority was invested in him (or, presumably, her) by God, that such authority was absolute,
and therefore that the basis of political obligation lay in our obligation to obey God absolutely.
According to this view, then, political obligation is subsumed under religious obligation. On the other
hand, Hobbes also rejects the early democratic view, taken up by the Parliamentarians, that power
ought to be shared between Parliament and the King. In rejecting both these views, Hobbes occupies
the ground of one is who both radical and conservative. He argues, radically for his times, that
political authority and obligation are based on the individual self-interests of members of society who
are understood to be equal to one another, with no single individual invested with any essential
authority to rule over the rest, while at the same time maintaining the conservative position that the
monarch, which he called the Sovereign, must be ceded absolute authority if society is to survive.
Hobbes' political theory is best understood if taken in two parts: his theory of human
motivation, Psychological Egoism, and his theory of the social contract, founded on
the hypothetical State of Nature. Hobbes has, first and foremost, a particular theory
of human nature, which gives rise to a particular view of morality and politics, as
developed in his philosophical masterpiece, Leviathan, published in 1651. The
Scientific Revolution, with its important new discoveries that the universe could be
both described and predicted in accordance with universal laws of nature, greatly
influenced Hobbes. He sought to provide a theory of human nature that would
parallel the discoveries being made in the sciences of the inanimate universe. His
psychological theory is therefore informed by mechanism, the general view that
everything in the universe is produced by nothing other than matter in motion.
According to Hobbes, this extends to human behavior. Human macro-behavior can
be aptly described as the effect of certain kinds of micro-behavior, even though some
of this latter behavior is invisible to us. So, such behaviors as walking, talking, and
the like are themselves produced by other actions inside of us. And these other
actions are themselves caused by the interaction of our bodies with other bodies,
human or otherwise, which create in us certain chains of causes and effects, and
which eventually give rise to the human behavior that we can plainly observe. We,
including all of our actions and choices, are then, according to this view, as
explainable in terms of universal laws of nature as are the motions of heavenly
bodies. The gradual disintegration of memory, for example, can be explained by
inertia. As we are presented with ever more sensory information, the residue of
earlier impressions ‘slows down' over time. From Hobbes’ point of view, we are
essentially very complicated organic machines, responding to the stimuli of the world
mechanistically and in accordance with universal laws of human nature.
In Hobbes' view, this mechanistic quality of human psychology implies the subjective
nature of normative claims. ‘Love’ and ‘hate’, for instance, are just words we use to
describe the things we are drawn to and repelled by, respectively. So, too, the terms
‘good’ and ‘bad’ have no meaning other than to describe our appetites and aversions.
Moral terms do not, therefore, describe some objective state of affairs, but are rather
reflections of individual tastes and preferences.
In addition to Subjectivism, Hobbes also infers from his mechanistic theory of
human nature that humans are necessarily and exclusively self-interested. All men
pursue only what they perceive to be in their own individually considered best
interests - they respond mechanistically by being drawn to that which they desire and
repelled by that to which they are averse. This is a universal claim: it is meant to
cover all human actions under all circumstances – in society or out of it, with regard
to strangers and friends alike, with regard to small ends and the most generalized of
human desires, such as the desire for power and status. Everything we do is
motivated solely by the desire to better our own situations, and satisfy as many of our
own, individually considered desires as possible. We are infinitely appetitive and only
genuinely concerned with our own selves. According to Hobbes, even the reason that
adults care for small children can be explicated in terms of the adults' own self-
interest (he claims that in saving an infant by caring for it, we become the recipient of
a strong sense of obligation in one who has been helped to survive rather than
allowed to die).

In addition to being exclusively self-interested, Hobbes also argues that human


beings are reasonable. They have in them the rational capacity to pursue their desires
as efficiently and maximally as possible. Their reason does not, given the subjective
nature of value, evaluate their given ends, rather it merely acts as "Scouts, and Spies,
to range abroad, and find the way to the things Desired" (139). Rationality is purely
instrumental. It can add and subtract, and compare sums one to another, and
thereby endows us with the capacity to formulate the best means to whatever ends
we might happen to have.

From these premises of human nature, Hobbes goes on to construct a provocative


and compelling argument for why we ought to be willing to submit ourselves to
political authority. He does this by imagining persons in a situation prior to the
establishment of society, the State of Nature.

According to Hobbes, the justification for political obligation is this: given that men
are naturally self-interested, yet they are rational, they will choose to submit to the
authority of a Sovereign in order to be able to live in a civil society, which is
conducive to their own interests. Hobbes argues for this by imagining men in their
natural state, or in other words, the State of Nature. In the State of Nature, which is
purely hypothetical according to Hobbes, men are naturally and exclusively self-
interested, they are more or less equal to one another, (even the strongest man can
be killed in his sleep), there are limited resources, and yet there is no power able to
force men to cooperate. Given these conditions in the State of Nature, Hobbes
concludes that the State of Nature would be unbearably brutal. In the State of
Nature, every person is always in fear of losing his life to another. They have no
capacity to ensure the long-term satisfaction of their needs or desires. No long-term
or complex cooperation is possible because the State of Nature can be aptly described
as a state of utter distrust. Given Hobbes' reasonable assumption that most people
want first and foremost to avoid their own deaths, he concludes that the State of
Nature is the worst possible situation in which men can find themselves. It is the
state of perpetual and unavoidable war.

The situation is not, however, hopeless. Because men are reasonable, they can see
their way out of such a state by recognizing the laws of nature, which show them the
means by which to escape the State of Nature and create a civil society. The first and
most important law of nature commands that each man be willing to pursue peace
when others are willing to do the same, all the while retaining the right to continue to
pursue war when others do not pursue peace. Being reasonable, and recognizing the
rationality of this basic precept of reason, men can be expected to construct a Social
Contract that will afford them a life other than that available to them in the State of
Nature. This contract is constituted by two distinguishable contracts. First, they must
agree to establish society by collectively and reciprocally renouncing the rights they
had against one another in the State of Nature. Second, they must imbue some one
person or assembly of persons with the authority and power to enforce the initial
contract. In other words, to ensure their escape from the State of Nature, they must
both agree to live together under common laws, and create an enforcement
mechanism for the social contract and the laws that constitute it. Since the sovereign is
invested with the authority and power to mete out punishments for breaches of the
contract which are worse than not being able to act as one pleases, men have good,
albeit self-interested, reason to adjust themselves to the artifice of morality in
general, and justice in particular. Society becomes possible because, whereas in the
State of Nature there was no power able to "overawe them all", now there is an
artificially and conventionally superior and more powerful person who can force men
to cooperate. While living under the authority of a Sovereign can be harsh (Hobbes
argues that because men's passions can be expected to overwhelm their reason, the
Sovereign must have absolute authority in order for the contract to be successful) it is
at least better than living in the State of Nature. And, no matter how much we may
object to how poorly a Sovereign manages the affairs of the state and regulates our
own lives, we are never justified in resisting his power because it is the only thing
which stands between us and what we most want to avoid, the State of Nature.
According to this argument, morality, politics, society, and everything that comes
along with it, all of which Hobbes calls ‘commodious living' are purely conventional.
Prior to the establishment of the basic social contract, according to which men agree
to live together and the contract to embody a Sovereign with absolute authority,
nothing is immoral or unjust - anything goes. After these contracts are established,
however, then society becomes possible, and people can be expected to keep their
promises, cooperate with one another, and so on. The Social Contract is the most
fundamental source of all that is good and that which we depend upon to live well.
Our choice is either to abide by the terms of the contract, or return to the State of
Nature, which Hobbes argues no reasonable person could possibly prefer.

Given his rather severe view of human nature, Hobbes nonetheless manages to create
an argument that makes civil society, along with all its advantages, possible. Within
the context of the political events of his England, he also managed to argue for a
continuation of the traditional form of authority that his society had long since
enjoyed, while nonetheless placing it on what he saw as a far more acceptable
foundation.
8

Jean-Jacques Rousseau
Jean-Jacques Rousseau, 1712-1778, lived and wrote during what was arguably the
headiest period in the intellectual history of modern France--the Enlightenment. He
was one of the bright lights of that intellectual movement, contributing articles to
the Encyclopdie of Diderot, and participating in the salons in Paris, where the great
intellectual questions of his day were pursued.
Rousseau has two distinct social contract theories. The first is found in his
essay, Discourse on the Origin and Foundations of Inequality Among Men, commonly
referred to as the Second Discourse, and is an account of the moral and political
evolution of human beings over time, from a State of Nature to modern society. As
such it contains his naturalized account of the social contract, which he sees as very
problematic. The second is his normative, or idealized theory of the social contract,
and is meant to provide the means by which to alleviate the problems that modern
society has created for us, as laid out in the Second Discourse.
Rousseau wrote his Second Discourse in response to an essay contest sponsored by the
Academy of Dijon. (Rousseau had previously won the same essay contest with an
earlier essay, commonly referred to as the First Discourse.) In it he describes the
historical process by which man began in a State of Nature and over time
‘progressed' into civil society. According to Rousseau, the State of Nature was a
peaceful and quixotic time. People lived solitary, uncomplicated lives. Their few
needs were easily satisfied by nature. Because of the abundance of nature and the
small size of the population, competition was non-existent, and persons rarely even
saw one another, much less had reason for conflict or fear. Moreover, these simple,
morally pure persons were naturally endowed with the capacity for pity, and
therefore were not inclined to bring harm to one another.
As time passed, however, humanity faced certain changes. As the overall population
increased, the means by which people could satisfy their needs had to change. People
slowly began to live together in small families, and then in small communities.
Divisions of labor were introduced, both within and between families, and
discoveries and inventions made life easier, giving rise to leisure time. Such leisure
time inevitably led people to make comparisons between themselves and others,
resulting in public values, leading to shame and envy, pride and contempt. Most
importantly however, according to Rousseau, was the invention of private property,
which constituted the pivotal moment in humanity's evolution out of a simple, pure
state into one characterized by greed, competition, vanity, inequality, and vice. For
Rousseau the invention of property constitutes humanity’s ‘fall from grace’ out of the
State of Nature.

Having introduced private property, initial conditions of inequality became more


pronounced. Some have property and others are forced to work for them, and the
development of social classes begins. Eventually, those who have property notice that
it would be in their interests to create a government that would protect private
property from those who do not have it but can see that they might be able to acquire
it by force. So, government gets established, through a contract, which purports to
guarantee equality and protection for all, even though its true purpose is to fossilize
the very inequalities that private property has produced. In other words, the
contract, which claims to be in the interests of everyone equally, is really in the
interests of the few who have become stronger and richer as a result of the
developments of private property. This is the naturalized social contract, which
Rousseau views as responsible for the conflict and competition from which modern
society suffers.

The normative social contract, argued for by Rousseau in The Social Contract (1762),
is meant to respond to this sorry state of affairs and to remedy the social and moral
ills that have been produced by the development of society. The distinction between
history and justification, between the factual situation of mankind and how it ought
to live together, is of the utmost importance to Rousseau. While we ought not to
ignore history, nor ignore the causes of the problems we face, we must resolve those
problems through our capacity to choose how we ought to live. Might never makes
right, despite how often it pretends that it can.
The Social Contract begins with the most oft-quoted line from Rousseau: "Man was
born free, and he is everywhere in chains" (49). This claim is the conceptual bridge
between the descriptive work of the Second Discourse, and the prescriptive work that
is to come. Humans are essentially free, and were free in the State of Nature, but the
‘progress' of civilization has substituted subservience to others for that freedom,
through dependence, economic and social inequalities, and the extent to which we
judge ourselves through comparisons with others. Since a return to the State of
Nature is neither feasible nor desirable, the purpose of politics is to restore freedom
to us, thereby reconciling who we truly and essentially are with how we live together.
So, this is the fundamental philosophical problem that The Social Contract seeks to
address: how can we be free and live together? Or, put another way, how can we live
together without succumbing to the force and coercion of others? We can do so,
Rousseau maintains, by submitting our individual, particular wills to the collective or
general will, created through agreement with other free and equal persons. Like
Hobbes and Locke before him, and in contrast to the ancient philosophers, all men
are made by nature to be equals, therefore no one has a natural right to govern
others, and therefore the only justified authority is the authority that is generated out
of agreements or covenants.
The most basic covenant, the social pact, is the agreement to come together and form
a people, a collectivity, which by definition is more than and different from a mere
aggregation of individual interests and wills. This act, where individual persons
become a people is "the real foundation of society" (59). Through the collective
renunciation of the individual rights and freedom that one has in the State of Nature,
and the transfer of these rights to the collective body, a new ‘person', as it were, is
formed. The sovereign is thus formed when free and equal persons come together
and agree to create themselves anew as a single body, directed to the good of all
considered together. So, just as individual wills are directed towards individual
interests, the general will, once formed, is directed towards the common good,
understood and agreed to collectively. Included in this version of the social contract
is the idea of reciprocated duties: the sovereign is committed to the good of the
individuals who constitute it, and each individual is likewise committed to the good
of the whole. Given this, individuals cannot be given liberty to decide whether it is in
their own interests to fulfill their duties to the Sovereign, while at the same time
being allowed to reap the benefits of citizenship. They must be made to conform
themselves to the general will, they must be “forced to be free” (64).

For Rousseau, this implies an extremely strong and direct form of democracy. One
cannot transfer one's will to another, to do with as he or she sees fit, as one does in
representative democracies. Rather, the general will depends on the coming together
periodically of the entire democratic body, each and every citizen, to decide
collectively, and with at least near unanimity, how to live together, i.e., what laws to
enact. As it is constituted only by individual wills, these private, individual wills must
assemble themselves regularly if the general will is to continue. One implication of
this is that the strong form of democracy which is consistent with the general will is
also only possible in relatively small states. The people must be able to identify with
one another, and at least know who each other are. They cannot live in a large area,
too spread out to come together regularly, and they cannot live in such different
geographic circumstances as to be unable to be united under common laws. (Could
the present-day U.S. satisfy Rousseau’s conception of democracy? It could not. )
Although the conditions for true democracy are stringent, they are also the only
means by which we can, according to Rousseau, save ourselves, and regain the
freedom to which we are naturally entitled.

Rousseau's social contract theories together form a single, consistent view of our
moral and political situation. We are endowed with freedom and equality by nature,
but our nature has been corrupted by our contingent social history. We can overcome
this corruption, however, by invoking our free will to reconstitute ourselves
politically, along strongly democratic principles, which is good for us, both
individually and collectively.

JOHN LOCKE

Liberalism as a political ideology began with John Locke. No political thinker had influenced
political theorizing on two different countries in two different continents as Locke did He was
the guiding and spiritual father of the 18th century enlightenment period, particularly for
philosopher like Rousseau and Voltaire. He was acknowledged as the founder of modern
empiricism with Hume, J.S. Mill, Russel etc as its exponents. A profound and extensive study
of John Locke has been one of the most remarkable achievements of recent philosophical
scholarship. Perhaps no other political thinker has received greater attention at the hands of
historians of thought with the last fifty years. Locke was interpreted as a collectivist because
of his insistence that the community would be ruled by the will of the majority. He was seen
as a champion of individuality. He was depicted as an enemy of patriartism, preparing the
grounds for women’s equal rights.

John Locke’s life coincided with one of the most significant epochs of British history that
saw the transformation of absolute monarchy into parliamentary democracy. It was a period
of the historic Glorious Resolution of 1688 with Locke was closely associated with the Lord
Ashley, Locke’s friend and patron who was charged with conspiracy to exclude Charles II
from acceding to the throne.

According to John Locke, men in the state of nature entered into a contract due to some
inconveniences such as absence of common law making, law-enforcing and law interpreting
agency capable of protecting natural rights. Therefore, the problem is to form a civil society
by common consent of all men and transfer their right of punishing the violators of Natural
Law to an independent and impartial authority. Lockes’ contract was a contract of each with
all, a surrender by the individual of his personal right to fulfill the commands of the laws of
Nature in return for the guarantee that his rights as nature ordains them - life, liberty and
property - would be preserved. Locke in his ‘Two Treatises on Government’ wrote the nature
of the contract thus: Each individual contracts with each to unite into and constitute a
community. The end for which this contract is made is the protection and preservation of
property, in the broad sense of the word- that is, life, liberty and estate-against the dangers
both from within and without the community” According to Lockean contract, each
individual agrees to give up not all his natural rights but that one of interpreting and
executing the law of nature and redressing their own grievances. But this right is given not to
any person or group of persons but the community as a whole, that too on the under standing
that the natural rights of the individual to life, liberty and property will be guaranteed by the
community. The Lockean contract was, thus, not general as with Hobbes but limited and
specific in character. Locke wrote in book II thus: “ Men being as has been said by nature all
free, equal and independent, no one can be put out of this estate and subjected to the political
power of another without his own consent, which is done by agreeing with other men, to join
and invite into a community for their comfortable safe and peaceable living, one amongst
another, in a secure enjoyment of their properties, and a greater security against any that are
not of it. This any number of men may do, because it enquires not the freedom of the rest
they are left, as they were, in the liberty of the state of nature: when any number of men have
so consented to make one community or government, they are thereby presently incorporated
and make one body politic, wherein the majority have a right to act and conclude the rest”.
As such Lockean social contract was a contract with the community as a whole resulted in the
establishment of that common political superior- the state- which was supposed to enforce the
law of Nature. After they have set up a political or civil society , the next step is to appoint a
government to declare and execute the natural law. Locke calls this process as the supreme
authority established by the commonwealth or civil society. In other words, there are two
aspects in Lockean contract- one by which the civil society is established and the other which
creates the government. While the first is the product of a contract, the second is only a
fiduciary power to act for certain ends and there remains still in the people a supreme power
to remove or alter the legislative, when they find the legislative act contrary to the trust
reposed in them. The relationship between society and the government is expressed by the
idea of trust because it obviates making the government a party to the contract and giving it
an independent status and authority. According to Locke, the newly created government has
three functions - legislative, executive and federative. The legislative is the supreme power to
which all other powers, particularly executive must be subordinate . The executive power is
subordinate to the legislative and is responsible to it. The federative power is concerned with
foreign affairs. Though the legislative power is supreme it is not arbitrary. It exists for
common good which is the preservation of freedom and protection of property. Further, the
legislative cannot rule by arbitrary decrees, but only by duly promulgated and established
laws.
9

THE RELEVANCE OF SOCIAL CONTRACT TO THE MODERNWORLD


They are as explained below;

Natural Liberty guarantee / laws of the state of nature

The social contract theory has led to natural liberty guarantee, which has availed the ownership of human rights.
Originally, this conception was derived from a myth that individuals lived in a natural condition characterized
with the state of nature. In the state of nature, people were completely free and natural of all religious and social
rights. There would be no control, no government, and no courts of law. However, the thesis foundation of the
theory argues that, these natural characteristics of the state of nature of rational individuals are the basis for
creating a free rational government, according to their liberty. The law or state of nature also refers to the idea
that human beings must strive for peace, which is best achieved through an agreement known as the
social contract
, bringing liberty, and not through violence.

Reflecting this to the modern world, rationalists have been guaranteed natural liberty; the liberty to worship,
judge, elect, fight for their rights, and participate in decision making

Freedom in the modern world

The social contract theory of Thomas Hobbes centered on morality among people. This meant that people had to
exercise their freedom as well as those in power to offer it to them (Addison, 2011). On the other hand, John
Locke’s theory in the social contract focused on the notion that only a small amount of freedom had to be given
to people. However, the social contracts theory has offered freedom to people in the modern world, and it is
serving its rational interests thus, it is relevant.

Promotion of Rational Interests

According to Addison (2011), the social contract theory of Thomas Hobbes advocated for rational interests of
publics. It upheld the fact that rational individuals form a government. On top of this, the government was given
the responsibility to protect the property and lives of rationalists, which is being practiced by almost every
government on a global basis. However, the social contract challenges rational individuals to over throw the
government in case if it violates people’s rights. This has promoted rational interests, and justifies why what
seems to be bad governments are over thrown today

Equality

According to the social contract theory, the government can be responsible for assuring an equal opportunity to
own and accumulate private property. This meant or means that individuals in the modern world are perfectly
equal in the state of nature as they compete for the resources available. As people view the world they live in as
“no one is better than the other”, the social contract theory has been relevant towards promoting equality. In the
modern world, the problem of equality can be seen through three major characteristics of human need
summarized below;
a.Equality of human need – All individuals have almost the same needs including food, clothing, and shelter.
Can everyone access these equally?
b.Scarcity of resources – Individuals fight for scarce resources within their environment. Thus, it is difficult for
everyone to possess the same.
c.The equality of human power – All people fight to have what to control, or what to have authority over, and
whom they can lead. Can there be equality?
Truly, the above characteristics would put human nature in tragedy, without the ideas of Thomas Hobbes in the
social contract. There would be absence of social order. But Hobbes’ emphasis on equality has led to
contentment in the modern world. People are able to be satisfied with the little they have by equating it to what
is great through the contract.
10

Promotion of Justice and Relations


Another relevance of the social contract theory of Thomas Hobbes to the modern world is the promotion of
Justice, and relations among individuals, and states. Neidleman (2012), argues that there are two major
dimensions of the social contract theory. The first one is referred to as the “empirical dimension”, which
explains the historical structures of the origin of the state. To me, this means that geographical features may
form a state. The second dimension is the “normative dimension”. It accounts for the principles of justice that
make a state legitimate or real. This reveals the fact that a state is made up of people, and not trees, land, or
buildings, though they contribute to what it is. These two dimensions are very important in making us
understand
the principles of justice, which binds citizens of different nations in their relations with one another.
They also argue a call to unveil
why different national state governments, interact to form relations and sign treaties.
It is all done pointing at the thoughts of early fore fathers of the theory, most especially Hobbes and John Locke.

Rise of sovereignty

As we have seen that the social contract theory is built on the belief that people are equal, and morality grants it
so, it is important that this very element contributes to the rise of sovereignty among states and individuals.
Thus, it should not be seen as irrelevant. From a religious, as well as a historical perspective, sovereign powers
come from God (Neidleman, 2012). God created Adam and gave him authority. When Adam died, his eldest
son took over authority, and this took place generation after generation as the chosen Israelites descendants
ruled nation after nation in the Bible. God chose King David, and it is through his linage that Jesus came. Power
is passed from sovereign individuals to others not to the weak. Political sovereignty can be linked to this!
Relating to the works of Thomas Hobbes, his ideas assumed that patriarchal leadership authority moved from
the power of fathers to their Children, justifying why sovereign powers rise, and seen worthy for them (Filmer,
1991). This is because the theory grants equality and thus, whoever feels sovereign has to practice it.

Individual interest
From an ideological view, the current views of Thomas Hobbes’ social contract ideas assume that individualism
is the basis of seeking power, an evil approach (Matt, 2011). But people need to seek it, in order to survive. On
the other hand, John Locke supposed that people make right choices basing on their individual level. To place
this on deeper perspective, there is need to look at the United States system consisting of a central sovereign – a
president with a supporting congress to serve as a protector from outside forces (Szelenyi, 2012). He is
responsible to make individual decisions for Americans that are not meant to be decided by Americans
themselves. This brings back the idea of morality. People have to be moral by adhering to the president’s
decisions. It also points out another focus of the social contract that “the government should not entitle full
rights to its citizens”
11
12
13
14
11 .

15
16
17
Criticism Of The Social Contract Theory
It is unhistorical
One of the main defects of the social contract theory is that it is historically false. It
claims to be a historical explanation of the origin of the State, but it has no
foundation in history. In the whole range of human history we do not find men
living in a State of nature without social relationships, nor do we find any evidence
of a social contract which created the society and the State. In short, there is no
historical evidence of a social contract in human past It is historically impossible to
believe that men living in the State of nature, and knowing nothing about political
institutions and organisations, should suddenly and deliberately agree to set up a
State. What history teaches us is that “the State is a growth and not a manufacture.
It is sociologically unscientific
The sociological explanation of this theory is also unscientific and false. It asserts
that men lived an isolated and independent life in the State of nature, and that they
voluntarily contracted to establish the society and State, in. which also the
individual remained as a free and independent unit. But social history has clearly
demonstrated that in primitive society the family or tribe was the social unit and
not the individual. He had no rights and no freedom.

His position in the society was determined by his birth. His birth was his social
status. It is only centuries after, i.e., in modem society, that the individual has
become the social unit and enjoys freedom and rights granted by the State. While
history shows that the evolution of society and civilisation has been from status to
contract, from birth position to free choice, the Contract Theory reverses this
historical process by asserting that it was from contract to status. “The individual”,
writes Sir Henry Maine “has been steadily substituted for the family as the unit of
which civil laws take account… The movement has been from one of status to one
of contract”

The transition is impossible: 


The basic assumption of the contract theory is wrong. A sudden transition from a
lawless and, as Hobbes says, even non-moral and warlike condition of the State of
nature cannot change into the law-abiding and peaceful community in the State is
not possible. Such a sudden change in habits, character and conduct of the people
is impossible in human life and society. It requires a long period of training,
education, social control and development to bring about this transition. The
psychological basis of the contract theory is also unsound.
It is self-contradictory:
The contract theory is based on self-contradictory reasoning. It declares that men in
the State of nature came together to enter into a social contract and establish the
State. But this fact of coming together shows that they had common consciousness
before they met each other, and that the “State” had already arisen among them
before they entered into a contract. Moreover, the contract itself implies that there
must be a common authority to enforce it.

It means, therefore, that the origin of the State does not lie in the contract but in the
common will of the men of the natural State to enter into a contract Furthermore,
the contract is a legal term; it presupposes a system of laws to enforce it. But the
advocates of the social contract declare that there were no laws before the contract
In short, the theory is self- contradictory and illogical, because the original
contractors must have already known common authority, a body of laws and
common political consciousness before they assembled to enter into a contract But
if they were so advanced in social and political life, they did not require any
contract whatsoever to establish the society and State, which were, indeed, already
there.

19
Conclusion
In conclusion, it is very difficult to understand if the social
contract theory can justify all the moral obligations in our
modern societies. There is one demerit we have to think
about as we center on morality and the state of nature
which says that I have my rights and you have yours.
Treat me right, I treat you right. I am free to practice
liberty, equality, and so forth. There is need for being
skeptical a little bit. The fact that you can’t steal your
neighbor’s property doesn’t stop him or her from stealing
yours. However, it is true that the social contract allows us
to live in harmony with others. Therefore it important to
recognize its relevancies to the modern world discussed in
this piece of work.
.
20
References
Books
1. Dr. Paranjpe N.V.; Studies in jurisprudence and legal theory; Sixth edition;
Central law agency
2. Freeman M.D.A; Lloyd’s Introduction to jurisprudence; seventh edition
3. Black’s law dictionary
Articles
1. Muaawiz Abu Bakar, Scandinavian_Realist_v_American_Realist
2. H. L. A. Hart 1959,. Scandinavian Realism, The Cambridge Law Journal
3. Eric Millard, Alf Ross and Realist Conceptions of Legislation
4. Torben Spaak, Karl Olivecrona's Legal Philosophy: A Critical Appraisal
5. Marie Sandström , Law – Fact, Fiction or In Between? Axel Hägerström’s Quest
for Legal Realism

Websites
1. www.newindialaw.blogspot.in
2. www.www.grkarelawlibrary.yolasite.com
3. www.www.diva-portal.org
4. www.encyclo.findlaw.com

21

You might also like