Leibniz Equivalence. On Leibniz's (Bad) Inuence On The Logical Empiricist Interpretation of General Relativity
Leibniz Equivalence. On Leibniz's (Bad) Inuence On The Logical Empiricist Interpretation of General Relativity
Leibniz Equivalence. On Leibniz's (Bad) Inuence On The Logical Empiricist Interpretation of General Relativity
Abstract
interpretation of General Relativity, the paper attempts to show that this labeling is
in the 19th century debate about geometry, by authors such as Poincaré, Helmholtz
or Hausdor. However, they clearly failed to give a plausible account of General Rel-
new kind. Weyl's analysis of Leibniz's and Einstein's indiscernibility arguments is used
1. Introduction
It has become commonplace in the literature to argue that Einstein's celebrated ar-
from Einstein's review of his general theory of relativity; CPAE 6, Doc. 30; Die Grund-
lage der allgemeinen Relativitätstheorie, 1916), if considered as a response to the also
celebrated hole argument (known from Einstein's private correspondence with Michele
Besso, Paul Ehrenfest, Hendrik Lorentz and others; CPAE 8a, Doc. 173, 178, 180, 183;
see Norton 1984), would amount to a defense of what has been famously labeled Leibniz
In particular the role played by what we now call dieomorphisms (transformations that
preserve only smoothness and the uniqueness of the coordinates) in Einstein's argument
would recall that of translations (which preserve also the distance between any pair
of points) in Leibniz's shift argument against Clarke. In both cases worlds which can
Preprint submitted to Studies in History and Philosophy of Science March 16, 2011
same world. John Earman and John D. Norton drew the parallel in detail in their
seminal contribution (Earman and Norton, 1987) and the protagonists of the huge debate
created by this paper, such as Tim Maudlin (1988), Jeremy Buttereld (1989), John
Stachel (1993), Robert Rynasiewicz (1994), Carl Hoefer (1996) and Simon Saunders
polemical target. From this perspective the hole argument should be considered as a
In this article I will try to show that reference to Leibniz in this context is in many
those of Leibniz. I will try to bring out this point through what I may dare to call an
of the Leibnizian kind, encouraged by the use of such arguments in the 19th century
philosophical debate about geometry. However, they clearly failed to give a plausible
analysis of the reasons for and the origins of this failure should show, in my opinion,
that the comparison between Leibniz's indiscernibility arguments and Einstein's point-
I will proceed as follows: developing an idea of Hermann Weyl's, I will argue that
lation of the whole universe or its mirroring by changing east into west and so on, can
way of mapping the object onto itself while preserving all of its structure. In my opinion
Weyl's suggestion, although surely questionable from a strict philological point of view,
indiscernibility arguments and most of all to understand the role that Leibnizian ar-
guments played in the 19th century debate about geometry. The ma jor protagonists
of that debate, such as Hermann von Helmholtz, Henri Poincaré, but also Felix Haus-
dor (to whom I will mostly refer), in considering automorphisms (or isomorphisms)
that preserve progressively weaker levels of geometrical structure, were able to generalize
Leibniz's thought experiments, showing that two worlds would be indistinguishable even
if they were mapped onto each other by any continuous deformation whatsoever.
Early Logical Empiricists (Moritz Schlick, Hans Reichenbach, Rudolf Carnap) explic-
itly interpreted General Relativity in the light of such Leibnizian kinds of arguments.
of indiscernibility in the sense of Leibniz. I will suggest that the inadequacy of Logical
The lesson that, in my opinion, we can draw from such a reconstruction is that, even
2
see, it was precisely Weyl himself who already clearly recognized this point. In a rst
apparent physical dierences that cannot nd expression in the mathematical apparatus
of the theory, what we may call Einstein's indiscernibility is the consequence of appar-
ent mathematical dierences that cannot nd any correspondence in physical reality. In
Hermann Weyl was perhaps the rst to emphasize the depth of the philosophical
twist (Weyl, 1952, p. 127) that Leibniz gave to the simple geometrical notion of simili-
tude or similarity between two gures: Leibnitz [sic ] declared: two gures are similar
or equivalent if they cannot be distinguished from each other when each is considered by
itself, because they have every imaginable property of ob jective meaning in common, in
spite of being individually dierent (Weyl, 1934/2009, p. 21). Leibniz thus exhibited
the true general meaning of similitude (Weyl, 1939/1997, p. 15). According to Weyl
such a `philosophical' denition of similar gures can be considered as the rst deni-
automorphism carries a gure into one that in Leibniz's words is `indiscernible from it
if each of the two gures is considered by itself ' (Weyl, 1952, p. 18). Automorphisms
are, namely, transformations of space into itself that leave all relevant geometrical struc-
ture intact, so that the result is indistinguishable from the original unless one refers to
something that does not participate in the transformation, which thus serves as a frame
of reference (Rosen, 2008; Kosso, 2000). The ction of a change that involves the entire
universe serves exactly to exclude in principle the possibility of such comparison. Two
formation which preserves some geometrical structure, are to be considered the same
world, since there is in principle nothing outside the universe with respect to which the
transformation can be referred. Thus, after the transformation, one cannot say if the
transformation has taken place or not, and it is impossible to establish whether one is
In the next section I will try to show that Weyl's suggestion can nd supporting
precise account of Leibniz's philosophy of geometry can be made in this context (for a
recent reconstruction see De Risi, 2007; still relevant for my exposition is Schneider, 1988;
see also Freudenthal, 1972; Münzenmayer, 1979; Wallwitz, 1991). The more humble aim
light of his reections about geometry throws a dierent light on the meaning of similar
This will be helpful further on, when we will consider the dierence between Leibniz
2.1. Leibniz's Denition of Similarity and the Nocturnal Doubling Thought Experiment
of gures (see De analysi situs, GM V, pp. 179-80; Leibniz 1976, p. 255). Every gure,
according to the period's mathematical parlance, includes besides quantity also quality or
3
form (GM V, p. 179; Leibniz 1976, p. 254). Similar gures were usually considered those
that have the same form or quality, but possibly dierent magnitude or quantity : for
instance two equilateral triangles or two cubes may have the same form but dierent
size. However, such a denition appeared to Leibniz fully as obscure as the thing
dened (GM V, p. 180; Leibniz 1976, p. 254). Indeed, according to Leibniz, it is not
enough to designate ob jects as similar whose form is the same, unless a general concept
is further given of form (GM V, p. 180; Leibniz, 1976, p. 254). But the concept of form,
gures which cannot be distinguished when observed in isolation from each other (GM
V, p. 180; Leibniz 1976, p. 255). As far as we know, Leibniz provided such a denition for
the rst time in 1677 (Leibniz to Gallois; GM I, p. 180), and he later repeatedly insisted
that the Euclidean denition of similarity was just a particular case of his more general
Things are similar in which when they are considered one by one, nothing by which
they can be dierentiated can be found as two spheres or circles (or two cubes or
perfect squares) A and B . For example if the eye alone without the rest of the body is
imagined now to be inside sphere A now in sphere B it will not be able to distinguish
them but it will be able if it considers both at once, or if it brings with it other organs
of the body, or another standard of measure which it applies now to one now to the
other. Therefore to distinguish similar things, they must either be present together,
or between them a third thing must be present to each successively. [Similia sunt
in quibus per se singulatim consideratis inveniri non potest quo discernantur, ut duo
sphaerae vel circuli vel duo cubi aut duo quadrata perfecta A et B. Ut si solus oculus
sine aliis membris ngantur, nunc esse intra sphaeram A nunc intra sphaeram B, non
poterit eas discernere, sed poterit si ambas simul spectet, vel si secum membra alia
corporis aliamve mensuram introrsum aerat, quam nunc uni nunc alteri applicet.
Itaque ad similia discernenda opus est vel compraesentia eorum inter se, vel tertii cum
singulis successive.] (GM VII, 30; tr. Cox 1978, p. 234)
do not see them together [ita triangulum isosceles facile discernitur a scaleno, etsi non
simul videantur] (GM V, p. 155). But if one wants to determine which is the larger of
two equilateral triangles, one must compare the two triangles [collatione Triangulorum
cum aliis opus habeo] (GM V, p. 155). Then the quality of a gure is what can be
known in a thing separately, while quantity is what can be grasped only when the
gures are actually present together (GM V, p. 180; Leibniz 1976, p. 254).
Leibniz was deeply convinced of the superiority of his own denition of similarity, for it
has not been deduced from the consideration of angles, which represents only one instance
of similarity, but from a deeper principle, that is from the principle of discerning (LH
XXXV, I, 14, bl. 23-24; tr. De Risi 2005, p. 145). Euclid's denition of similarity
based on the congruence of angles is a special case which does not reveal the nature of
similarity in general (GM V, p. 181; Leibniz, 1976, p. 256). Leibniz explicitly claims
that it is possible to deduce the congruence of angles from his perceptual denition of
similarity, allowing congruence to be dened from similarity rather than the other way
4
around.
adopted for instance in the Specimen geometriae luciferae (GM VII, pp. 281-82), to
congruence (De Risi, 2007, p. 141.) However, in my opinion, following Weyl's interpre-
tative suggestion, we should be able to grasp the philosophical intuition behind Leibniz's
the important role of similitude in elementary geometry is related to the fact that trans-
formations which change the size of segments, but preserve both the ratio of lengths and
the size of angles, cannot change any geometric properties of gures. Geometry does
not have at its disposal any conceptual resources to establish the dierence between, say,
a smaller and a bigger circle; every objective statement about the one would hold about
the other, for the size of gures cannot be taken into consideration in geometrical theo-
rems: every theorem, construction, propriety, proportion or relation that can be found
in a circle, could be found also in the other [Omnia theoremata, omnes constructiones,
omnes proprietates, proportiones, respectus, qui in uno circulo notari possunt, poterunt
etiam in alio notari] (GM VII, 276). Thus similar gures (which have the same shape but
possibly dierent sizes) are clearly the same gure for the geometer. Their dierence
son [comparaison intuitive] (Couturat, 1961, p. 412), that is through what Leibniz calls
comperceptio.
Leibniz's celebrated thought experiments serve exactly to show ideal cases, where the
possibility of such comparison is ctionally excluded. If, for instance, God were to dimin-
ish all appearances in and around us in a closed room (in aliquo cubiculo), preserving
would appear the same, and we would not be able to distinguish the state before from
that after transformation, without exiting our closed room and considering the things
that have not been diminished (nisi sphaera rerum proportionaliter imminutarum, cu-
biculo scilicet nostro, egrederemur) (GM V, p. 153s). The dierence would emerge
only through comparison between two situations: one that has been scaled, and one
that has not. Something must remain untransformed as a standard against which the
If God were to change everything conserving the proportion, we would lose all our
measures and it would not be possible to know how much the things have changed,
because it is impossible to determine a certain denition of measure or to conserve
it in the memory. From that I believe I could explain the dierence between size
and species, between quantity and quality. [At si quemadmodum alibi jam dixi Deus
omnia mutaret proportione eadem servata perisset nobis omnis mensura nec possemus
scire quantum res mutatae sint, quoniam mensura nulla certa denitione comprehendi
adeoque nec memoria retineri potest, sed opus est reali ejus conservatione. Ex quibus
omnibus discrimen inter magnitudinem et speciem inter quantitatem et qualitatem
elucere arbitror.] (GM VII, 276)
In the well-known terminology due to Leibniz, the original universe and the transformed
1 An attempt to give an account of the dierent forms (logical, metaphysical, empirical, etc.) that
5
cannot ascertain the change of a length in the course of time, but only the change of
its ratio to real standards of measure which are assumed to be unchanging (GP V,
134; Leibniz 1976, p. 147). Thus if all lengths were diminished or magnied by the
same factor, that is conserving the angles and the proportions among lengths, Euclidean
geometry would provide us with no tools for ascertaining the dierence. Any attempt
to establish through geometrical methods whether we are in the original or the scaled
part of his denition of similarity. Leibniz himself explicitly establishes this connection
for the very rst time when he introduced this denition in his never sent letter to Jean
2
Gallois, to which we have already referred. Leibniz was so impressed by his own denition
of congruence (see Schneider 1988 for list of passages). Two gures are congruent if
they can be distinguished not only through the simultaneous perception of both of them,
but also requiring the perception of a third ob ject: Congruent are those things that can
be distinguished only through the comperception with a third [Congrua sunt quae sola
comperceptione cum tertio discerni possunt] (LA VI.4a 565). Two similar gures that
dier in magnitude can be distinguished even if they are in the same place, for one can
But if two things are not only similar, but also equal, i.e. they are congruent, they
cannot be distinguished even if they are perceived together, if not because of the
place, that is only when something it is assumed outside them and it is observed
that they have a dierent position respect to this third object. [Si vero duae res non
tantum sunt similes sed et aequales, id est si sint congruae, etiam simul perceptas non
discernere possum, nisi loco id est, nisi adhuc aliud assumant extra ipsas et observem
ipsas diversum habere situm ad tertium assumtum.] (GM V, 155)
Thus congruent gures, in Leibniz's scholastic parlance, are dierent solo numero, only
by the reference to something external ( solo erga situ ad externa discernuntur; GM VII,
275), because one is more on the west or more on the east, more on the north or more on
the south, more above or more below, or because some another body is posited outside
them [unum alio orientalius aut occidentalius vel septentrionalius aut meridionalius vel
superius aut inferius esse vel alteri alicui corpori extra ipsa posito esse] (GM VII, 276).
Leibniz did not remain satised with such a denition of congruence (De Risi, 2007,
pp. 143.). However, it is plausible that the very famous arguments that Leibniz used
in his correspondence with Clarke can be considered the exact counterpart of such a
the principle of identity of indiscernibles assumes in Leibniz's work is impossible here and not only for
space constraints; on some of the forms that the principle assumes in Leibniz, see (Cherno, 1981).
2 Having thoroughly inquired, I have found that two things are perfectly similar when they cannot
be discerned other than by com-presence, for example, two unequal circles of the same matter could not
be discerned other than by seeing them together, for in this way we can well see that the one is bigger
than the other . . . In fact, if all the things of the world aecting us were diminished by one and the
same proportion, it is evident that nobody could make out the change. (GM I, p. 180; tr. De Risi
(2007, p. 58)).
6
doubling thought experiment is the counterpart of Leibniz's denition of similarity.
Two congruent gures A and B in the same plane may show many dierences, when
they are considered in their relations to some xed frame of reference. However, these
dierences are not geometrical dierences; every ob jective statement that geometry can
make for one gure will hold for the other. If therefore the reference to the third external
gure is eliminated, we would be left without any geometrical tools to establish if the
in principle no external reference frames can be imposed upon it, so that the very concept
to suppose that the universe could have had at rst another position of time and place,
than that which it actually had . . . is an impossible ction (Leibniz, 1976, p. 667).
The details of Leibniz's static shift argument (following the nomenclature introduced
by Maudlin 1993) have been rehearsed so many times in the literature that I refrain
from doing so again here. The only aspect I would like to pinpoint is that it seems clear
that the goal of Leibniz's thought experiment is to make the simultaneous perception
of the original situation and the changed one in principle impossible - showing that
all. Geometrically we cannot establish if we are living in the original or in the displaced
world.
Similarly, when in the Third Paper, 5, Leibniz so famously argued that if we inter-
change all matter east to west, or left to right, no dierence would emerge, he seems
to imply that the inner geometrical structure of Euclidean space does not allow one to
distinguish a left from a right-handed screw without reference to some third external
asymmetric object. The dierence between left and right is not a geometrical dierence,
as Leibniz seems to admit in this passage: But it is impossible to distinguish left and
right . . . if not for the fact itself or the perception, that the human being experiences
that a motion is more comfortable on one side that on the other [Sed dextrum a sin-
istro discerni non potest . . . nisi facto ipso, seu perceptione, dum ab uno latere motum
A passage of Leibniz's summarizes eectively the simple path that we have followed
through the rather messy conglomerate of his notes, drafts and manuscripts on geom-
etry: the quality can be observed in one thing, the quantity in two . . . the position in
three [qualitas est in uno observabilis, quantitas in duobus . . . positio in tribus] (A IV.1,
the form of a gure from its position and magnitude seems to express the fundamental
dierence between conceptual denition and intuitive exhibition (Weyl, 1927b, p. 73;
tr. Weyl, 2009b, p. 11), the idea that is impossible to describe a position or x a unit
of length in a conceptual way, through geometric methods, and not by means of a
tude are geometrically unascertainable and emerge only through an intuitive comparison.
denitions of congruence and similarity, in as much they serve to ctionally exclude the
However, precisely for this reason, it is easy to see that they do not succeed at all in
supporting the fully relational conception of space usually attributed to Leibniz, that
is to reduce space to the consequence of the relations among bodies , as in the received
7
view of Leibniz's philosophy of space. On the contrary, the arguments arm something
very precise about the structure that space possesses independently from the relations
among bodies. Leibniz's arguments work because it has been settled in advance that
the space, as is said in a recently published manuscript, is not only uniform, i.e. self-
congruent but also self-similar (LH XXXIV, I, p. 14, Bl. 23 retro; tr. De Risi 2005,
p. 140), that it is at or Euclidean. Space, as Leibniz explicitly points out, is not like
a spherical or a cylindrical surface, i.e. one of the surfaces that Leibniz dened as a
uniform locus, self-congruent, but not self-similar; but it is like a plane (LH XXXIV,
I, p. 14, Bl. 23 retro; tr. De Risi 2005, p. 145), which is everywhere internally similar
2.3. A Glimpse into the Relationalism vs. Substantialism debate. Leibniz's Kinematic
Shift Argument
From this point of view it is not clear how Leibniz could credibly have believed that he
argument. Newton's absolute space is obviously endowed precisely with the same Eu-
clidean symmetries of Leibniz's space. Leibniz's arguments seem to confuse the problem
of absolute position with that of absolute motion, that is the problem of the same posi-
tion in dierent times, which was Newton's concern (DiSalle, 2002b). Obviously, Leibniz
A ship may go forward, and yet a man, who is in the ship, may not perceive it (GP
VII p. 403; tr. Leibniz 1976, p. 705). As in the other indiscernibility arguments, also
in this Galilean thought experiment one can perceive the motion of the ship only by
reference to something outside the ship, that does not participate in its motion. Once
again the ction of the motion of the whole universe eliminates in principle the possibility
of such a comparison:
3 since there is nothing outside the universe, the motion of the whole
universe, per denition, cannot be observed, and when there is no change that can be
observed, there is no change at all (GP VII, p. 404; tr. Leibniz, 1976, p. 705).
Thus the static shift argument can be easily transformed into a kinematic shift
argument: To say that God can cause the whole universe to move forward in a right
line, or in any other line, without making otherwise any alteration in it, is another
chimerical supposition. These two states indiscernible from each other would be the
same state, it would be a change without a change (GP VII, p. 373; tr. Leibniz, 1976,
p. 705).
There was a time when the philosophical supremacy of Leibniz's relationalist account
questionable. However, it has more recently become commonplace to argue that such
a generalized indistinguishability between motion and rest, the idea that there are no
3 In this sense Galilei's ship experiment is the prototype of every indiscernibility argument. According
to Galilei, uniform motion exists relatively to things that lack it, but for things that participate equally
in the motion, motion is as if it does not exist (come s'e' non fusse) (Galilei, 1632/2005, I, p. 205;
tr. Galilei 1967, p. 116). The indiscernibility emerges from the exclusion of the external reference to
other bodies lacking that motion. Similarly Leibniz's changes that involve the whole universe mean
agendo, nihil agere (GP VII, p. 396), since the reference to something that has remained unchanged
is in principle impossible. There is therefore a connection between global symmetries, indiscernibility
and the possibility of subdividing the universe into isolated subsystems (see Brading and Brown, 2003,
p. 99-98).
8
exceptions to the general law of equivalence (Letter to Huygens, 12/22 June 1694, A
III.6, p. 131; tr. Leibniz, 1989, p. 308) is obviously incompatible with Galilean relativity.
Galilean relativity is the statement that motion in a right line is indistinguishable from
stasis, and not that also motion in any other line (however zigzagging) is indistinguish-
able from stasis. Leibniz's indiscernibility arguments, if applied in all their generality
to all motions, it is said, are unable to make sense of the privileged status of inertial
motion, the uniform motion in straight line, that one should be able to distinguish from
an accelerating motion. Thus Newton's bucket experiment correctly shows that circu-
Newton's alleged claim (Rynasiewicz, 2000) that this argument would provide evidence
for the existence of absolute space is commonly considered puzzling: Newton's laws of
motion presuppose absolute time, but not absolute space; absolute acceleration, but not
absolute velocity.
It has now become usual (Stein, 1967/1970; DiSalle, 2002a, 2006) to argue that the
Leibniz-Newton debate can be better understood if one assumes that it concerns not the
geometrical structure of space, but that of spacetime. Let me resort once more to Weyl's
account. Not only was Weyl probably the rst to make this point clear, but most of
all his position will reveal itself particularly signicant later on for the purposes of the
present paper. As Weyl famously pointed out, the dynamic inequivalence of dierent
states of motion teaches us that the world bears a structure (Weyl, 1927a, p. 70 ; tr.
Weyl 2009b, p. 101). Since unaccelerated motion is also called inertial motion, one
also refers to such structure as the inertial structure. But in the concept of absolute
space this inertial structure is evidently not sized up correctly; the dividing line does
not lie between rest and motion, but between uniform translation and accelerated mo-
tion. spacetime of classical mechanics has dened structure, since straight lines can be
objectively distinguished from curves, but in the family of all straight lines one can single
out the vertical ones only by a convention based on individual exhibition (Weyl, 1927a,
may call it Galilean spacetime, in which the particles are immersed and against which
inertial and non-inertial motion can be distinguished (a body that is not moving in
line (a body at absolute rest, the ob jective occurrence of two events in the same place).
4
Leibnizian spacetime, on the other hand, bears too little structure : if Leibniz requires
the relativity of all motions, then he could not distinguish straight lines from curved lines
(Weyl 1927b, p. 57; tr. Weyl 2009a, p. 41), without a real inertial structure. Then,
as Weyl points out, the concept of the relative motion of several bodies would have no
more foundation than the concept of absolute motion for a single body (Weyl 1927b, p.
57; tr. Weyl, 2009a, p. 105). In fact, if the automorphisms of spacetime do not preserve
4A much more sophisticated catalog of classical spacetimes is discussed in John Earman's denitive
study World Enough and spacetime (Earman, 1989). Leibnizian spacetime in particular is not completely
amorphous, because Leibniz seems to admit a foliation in hyperplanes of simultaneity. See Roberts 2003
for an overview and a criticism of the received account of Leibnizian spacetime.
9
any structure relational theories of motion would - as we shall see later - be dynamically
(Huggett and Hoefer, 2009) of Leibniz's philosophy of space and time, which, as recent
literature has shown, is far from exhausting Leibniz's much more articulated conception
shall see later, Weyl's suggestion is useful in order to restate once more what Leibniz's
were to move with constant velocity, we would certainly not notice the dierence from
a universe at rest: parallel world lines would be mapped into parallel world lines; the
ane structure of spacetime gives us no means of picking the vertical lines among the
others. All relevant geometrical structure would appear the same, in the universe at
rest and in the uniformly moving one. However, classical mechanics arms that if the
whole universe were rotating, parallel lines would be mapped into curved lines. The
original universe and the transformed situation would not be indistinguishable at all, for
the ane structure gives us the possibility of distinguishing between curved and straight
trajectories in spacetime.
This was of course hard to grasp without having the possibility of considering spacetime
as a single geometrical structure. However, exactly for this reason, we are in a better
position to recognize that it is the geometry, which has been settled in advance, that
remark that motion depends upon being possible to be observed (GP VII, 403; tr.
Leibniz 1976, p. 705) (like Reichenbach's reading, as we shall see) obscures the fact that
it is the inner structure of Galilean spacetime that does not allow the establishment
of the dierence between rest and uniform motion, but does allow that between uniform
motion and acceleration. From today's standpoint, the fact, taken as obvious, that such
reality appears more than surprising. Not only does spacetime geometry make bodies
conspire to move in straight lines at uniform speeds, but it even opposes resistance when
one attempts to deviate bodies from such trajectories: It is probably fair to say that
anyone who is not amazed by this conspiracy has not understood it (Brown, 2005, p.
14).
Weyl's intuition seems to oer a good insight into Leibnizian indiscernibility argu-
ments: in geometry two gures are considered the same gure if one can be carried
5 As is well known, in many passages Leibniz insists that a distinction between true motion and merely
relative motion can be drawn in terms of force or vis viva , that is mv2 . This claim is usually considered
inconsistent or at least circular (measurement of mv 2 depends on the denition a reference of frame);
this nevertheless makes clear that Leibniz's spacetime had probably a richer structure than what is now
called Leibnizian spacetime (Roberts, 2003, p. 553). In Roberts 2003, for instance, it is argued that
Leibniz would have even defended a form of absolutism about motion; for Arthur 1994 on the contrary
Leibniz was a full-blooded relativist. According to (Jauernig, 2008) it should be possible to reconcile
absolutism and relativism about motion by considering the dierent ontological levels, the dynamical
and the phenomenal levels, that characterize Leibniz's thought. See also (Slowik, 2006).
10
into the other by an automorphism (Weyl, 1927a, p. 79; tr. Weyl 2009b, p. 73), i.e. by a
structure preserving mapping of the space onto itself. That is now our interpretation of
Leibniz's denition of similar gures as gures that are indiscernible if each is considered
by itself (Weyl, 1927a, p. 79; tr. Weyl 2009b, p. 73). Thus, which worlds count as indis-
cernible depends on what kind of mathematical structure, we are concerned with. Once
this is known, we should be able to pinpoint what mappings preserve the structure, that
- the scaling of the entire world or, in his dispute with Clarke, the interchange east with
west or displacement of everything three feet east - are not arbitrary since they preserve
some geometrical structure. The original and the copy are indistinguishable precisely
because all the relevant geometrical structure that was found before the transformation
will appear the same in the transformed situation. In other words, indiscernibility arises
because the geometrical structure we are considering does not allow the expression of
This point becomes particularly clear if one considers the story of indiscernibility argu-
ments in the 19th century debate on the foundations of geometry. The rapid development
that geometrical thought experienced from the 1830s opened to the protagonists of this
debate, such as Helmholtz, Poincaré and, as we shall see, Hausdor, the possibility of gen-
two worlds will be indistinguishable not only if they are congruent or similar, but even
if they are mapped onto each other by any continuous deformation whatsoever, only re-
quiring that points that are close together before the transformation is applied also end
up close together. In other words, the 19th century debate seems to be dominated by
the tendency to consider transformations of space into itself that preserve progressively
weaker levels of geometrical structure. Two worlds arising from each other by a trans-
formation which preserves some geometrical structure are to be considered the same
world.
Helmholtz's and Poincaré's arguments have been abundantly discussed in the literature
(see for instance DiSalle 2006). I will therefore try to reconstruct summarily the 19th cen-
tury geometrical debate from a signicant, but less commonly considered, point of view.
The German mathematician Felix Hausdor, in his major philosophical work Das Chaos
in kosmischer Auslese
6 (Mongré 1898, now in Hausdor 2004, with the same pagination),
published in 1895 under the pseudonym of Paul Mongré (Paul to-my-liking), oered a
good overview of all the Leibniz-style indiscernibility arguments that were widespread in
the period's debate about geometry. Hausdor is surely better known for his fundamental
contributions to topology and set theory than for his early forays into philosophy of ge-
ometry, to which scholars' attention has been attracted only recently (Epple 2006, 2007).
overview into the use of indiscernibility arguments in the 19th century philosophical de-
bate about geometry - a debate that, as is well known, profoundly contributed to shaping
the new-born philosophy of science at the turn of the century (Friedman, 1999).
whole universe showing that a consciousness would necessarily remain unaware of them,
as long as all meter sticks used to ascertain any change, also underwent the same de-
formation (Mongré 1898/Hausdor 2004, pp. 84-94). But according to Hausdor, one
would consider two worlds as indistinguishable even if the objects of the universe were ar-
tigkeiten und Singularitäten] (Mongré 1898/Hausdor 2004, pp. 84-94): We would not
dialectic [Von gewissen Transformationen des Raumes würden wir nichts bemerken: das
ist der Refrain meiner transcendentalen Dialektik] (NL FH Kapsel 49; Fasz. 1079; Bl.
26).
This was also the refrain of the whole period's philosophical-geometrical debate, which
was entirely dominated by similar thought experiments, showing in a popular illumi-
nating way [in populär einleuchtender Weise], how a space transformation can elude
our empirical perception [dass eine Raumtransformation sich der empirischen Wahr-
nehmung entzieht] (Mongré 1898/Hausdor 2004, p. 100). Hausdor is aware that the
71; Bl. 33) already oered an example of such an approach, even if Helmholtz was more
keit nicht euklidischer Verhältnisse] (Kapsel 24: Fasz. 71, Bl. 65) than of showing the
undated, Hausdor confesses that he found similar reasoning also by others (Poincaré)
[auch bei Andern (Poincaré)] (NL FH Kapsel 49; Fasz. 1079; Bl. 4), who similarly argued
that our actual space does not dier from any space that one can derive from it by any
However, Hausdor could consider such a type of thought experiment only as a special
cip, Abbildungsprincip; Princip der Ersetzbarkeit] (Kapsel 24: Fasz. 71, Bl. bl4 [7]).
Two spaces that are point-wise coordinated to one another, in such a manner that
their whole physical content participates in this point-correspondence, produce the
same mental image . . . Every space stands for a whole class of spaces, among which
no dierentiation, and thus also no choice, is possible. [Zwei Räume, die einander
punktweise zugeordnet sind, derart dass ihr gesamter physischer Inhalt an dieser Cor-
respondenz der Punkte betheiligt ist, erzeugen dasselbe Bewusstseinsbild. . . . jeder
Raum Repräsentant einer ganzen Klasse von Räumen, zwischen denen keine Unter-
scheidung, auch also keine Entscheidung möglich ist] (Kapsel 24: Fasz. 71, Bl. 65)
This approach is surely commonplace for someone who is familiar with the work of
Hausdor 's attempt to approach the issue using the modern concepts of Cantorian set
theory, then new-born (Cantor, 1874, 1878). This seems surprising at rst sight. Only
a few mathematicians at that time were interested in this eld and probably none at-
lems. However, precisely this rst unusual contact with Cantor's theory showed Hausdor
the potentialities of the Mengenlehre, that he later dened as the groundwork of all
12
mathematics [das Fundament der gesamten Mathematik] Hausdor, 1914/2002, p. 1. In
1904 Hausdor began to work actively in this area, and in 1914, in his celebrated Grund-
züge der Mengenlehre , he developed the theory for which he is now rightly famous, the
theory of topological spaces, Hausdor 's labeling for sets endowed with an additional
structure in which distinct points have disjoint neighborhoods (actually what we now
call Hausdor spaces; see Hausdor, 1914/2002, p. 718f.; Hausdor (1927, 1935/2007,
p. 226f.)).
the tendency to consider space as point sets endowed with a structure. In particular,
Hausdor considers the empirical and the absolute space as two point sets. Between
these two, one can apply what has been newly called a transformation or a mapping of a
space onto the other [was man neuerdings eine Transformation oder Abbildung des einen
Raumes auf den anderen nennt] (Hausdor, 2004, p. 82 ), that is a transformation that
preserves some geometrical structure. That idea that dierence between the empirical
and absolute space would not fall in our consciousness [nicht in unser Bewuÿtsein fallen
würde] (Hausdor, 1903, p. 17) means now that they can be mapped onto one another
space (the real one), but for all its univocal mappings [Also: Geometrie gilt nicht von
Einem bestimmten Raum (dem wirklichen), sondern von all seinen eindeutigen Bildern].
Once again, which worlds count as indistinguishable depends upon which geometrical
structure one wants to preserve. If all the relevant structure is preserved by the mapping
(one-to-one and onto, but Hausdor considered more general cases), then the original and
the deformed world would be regarded as the same and dierence between them would
escape any observation. The sense of the expression the same is here intended as mere
a mapping in the set theoretical sense, it becomes clear that it does not make any sense
to demand any congruence or similarity from such a mapping [von dieser Abbildung
Congruenz oder Ähnlichkeit oder derlei zu verlangen] (Kapsel 49: Fasz. 1077, Bl. 4).
Leipzig University, in order to give an idea of this procedure, Hausdor eectively com-
pares the empirical space exactly to a geographical map of the absolute space: If this
conception is correct, then the original can undergo every transformation whatsoever,
without any change in the mapped copy: exactly as you cannot recognize in a geograph-
ical map, if it was drawn from the original or from another geographical map [Wenn
13
diese Auassung richtig ist, so muÿ man das Urbild einer beliebigen Transformation un-
terwerfen können, ohne daÿ das Abbild sich verändert: gerade so wie man einer Karte
nicht ansehen kann, ob sie nach dem Original oder nach einer anderen Karte gezeichnet
ist] (Hausdor, 1903). Thus in order to know the nature of the absolute space starting
from the empirical one, one has to know which kind of pro jection has been used, that is,
For example, a map of the world shown in Mercator's pro jection accurately depicts only
the equatorial regions of the Earth's surface. As one moves nearer and nearer to the
polar regions, so the features of the map become progressively distorted. This distor-
tion is particularly pronounced for Greenland and Antarctica, which become drawn out
horizontally far in excess of their true proportions. The reason for this is well known,
of course, it being simply due to the fact that the surface of the Earth is spherical,
and it is not possible to represent a curved surface on a at map without distortion.
However, since all measuring instruments would be equally distorted, someone living
in the distorted situation would not notice the dierence. The only way to know the
structure of the absolute space from the empirical one, our geographical map, is to know
the Abbildungsverfahren , the kind of mapping, that has been used to draw the map
(Mercator, Stereographic, etc.). The empirical space is no faithful copy of the absolute
one, but only a mapping according to an arbitrary, indeterminable pro jection principle
[keine getreue Kopie des absoluten, sondern nur sein Abbild nach einem beliebigen, un-
bestimmbaren Pro jektionsverfahren] (RP 17). If we don't know which structure (angles,
areas, geodesics, etc.) has been preserved by the mapping, there is no way to infer the
Helmholtz and Poincaré, but also Hausdor/Mongré, are the authors to whom Moritz
Schlick refers in his celebrated Raum und Zeit in der gegenwärtigen Physik (Schlick,
1922/2006, tr. Schlick, 1978a), which achieved four editions from 1917 to 1922. If
Helmholtz's and Poincaré's inuence on Schlick is well known and well documented in
the literature (Coa, 1991; Pulte, 2006; Ryckman, 2005; Friedman, 1995), the relationship
between Schlick and Hausdor has only recently been brought to the attention of a larger
14
audience (Epple, 2006). For the aims of this paper, it is interesting in particular that,
obliged to add a note to recognize the value of Hausdor 's philosophical reections.
8
This says a lot about Schlick's position regarding the connection between 19th century
In particular, the third chapter of Schlick's booklet is entirely dominated by the re-
production of Leibniz-style thought experiments. Schlick starts by considering the case
in which the imaginary transformed world is geometrically similar to the original one,
then he imagines that the dimensions of all ob jects are lengthened or shortened in one
direction only, and nally he considers the case where the objects in the universe are
1978b, p. 227). Schlick's conclusion is invariably the same: as long as we suppose that
all measuring instruments, including our own bodies share the same deformation, the
In mathematical phraseology we can express this result by saying: two worlds, which
can be transformed into one another by a perfectly arbitrary (but continuous and
one-to-one) point-transformation, are, with respect to their physical reality, identical.
That is: if the universe is deformed in any way, so that the points of all physical
bodies are displaced to new positions, then [. . . ], no measurable, no real change
has happened at all, if the co-ordinates of a physical point in the new position are
any arbitrary functions whatsoever of the co-ordinates of its old position. (Schlick
1922/2006, p. 204; tr. Schlick 1978b, p. 227)
Moving from the consideration of space to that of spacetime, it was easy for Schlick to
use this sort of argument in the context of General Relativity. The connection between
the 19th century debate and the new theory can be found in the, as John Stachel has
in Einstein's 1916 review article Die Grundlage der allgemeinen Relativitätstheorie . Ein-
stein, as is well known, maintained that the physical content of a theory is exhausted
material points of our measuring instruments with other material points (CPAE 6, Doc.,
30, p. 291f.). According to Schlick, this implies that all worlds that agree on such co-
incidences are equivalent, and that a choice among them is the result of an arbitrary
stipulation (an implication that Schlick called the geometrical relativity of space ):
All world pictures which lead to the same laws for these point-coincidences are, from
the point of view of physics, in every way equivalent. We saw earlier that it signies
no observable, physically real, change at all, if we imagine the whole world deformed
in any arbitrary manner, provided that after the deformation the co-ordinates of every
7 The letters are preserved in Noord-Hollands Archief in Haarlem (NL): 102/Haus-2 Letter to Schlick
(23.2.1919, Greifswald); 102/Haus-2 letter to Schlick (17.7.1920, Greifswald).
8 Unfortunately, only after the publication of the second edition of this writing have I learned about
the most astute and fascinating book [Das Chaos in kosmischer Auslese]. The fth chapter of this
monograph gives a very perfect presentation of the considerations that follow in the text above. Not
only Poincare's reections, but also the extensions added above have been anticipated there (Schlick
1922/2006, p. 198, note 1, tr. Schlick 1920, p. 24, note 1).
15
physical point are continuous, single-valued, but otherwise quite arbitrary, functions
of its co-ordinates before the deformation. Now, such a point-transformation actu-
ally leaves all spatial coincidences totally unaected; they are not changed by the
distortion, however much all distances and positions may be altered by them. For, if
two points A and B, which coincide before the deformation (i.e. are innitely near
one another), . . . as a result of the deformation . . . must be at the same point (or
innitely near) A. Consequently, all coincidences remain undisturbed by the deforma-
tion. (Schlick 1922/2006, p. 232; tr. Schlick 1978b, p. 227)
sense the point-coincidence remark has been famously dened as the beginnings of the
(Friedman, 1983, p. 24). It is indeed the case that Einstein's point-coincidence argu-
ment fascinated contemporary philosophers for its vericationist turn of phrase. But the
argument actually oered them much more. It allowed them to exorcise the novelty of
Einstein's newborn theory, by simply inserting it in the context of the by then already fa-
miliar 19th century debate about geometry. Einstein's point-coincidence argument is just
one of those many Leibniz-style philosophical arguments that one can nd in Helmholtz,
Schlick had by that time reached the philosophical stature necessary to transform
such an interpretative proposal into the received view. As is well known, he was a
trained physicist, having taken his doctorate under Max Planck, who notably singled
out Schlick as one of his best students, together with Max von Laue, later awarded the
Nobel Prize. But most importantly, Schlick and Einstein were in correspondence by late
1915; Schlick sent Einstein a copy of his paper on the philosophical signicance of the
theory of relativity (CPAE 8a, Doc. 296; 4 February 1917), which Einstein famously
praised for its unsurpassed clarity and perspicuousness [Übersichtlichkeit] (CPAE 8a,
Doc. 297, p. 389; 6 February 1917; see also Doc. 165; 14 December 1915). When
in 1922 Schlick was appointed to the chair in philosophy held earlier by Ernst Mach
and by Ludwig Boltzmann at the University of Vienna, he was already the recognized
Schlick's inuence on the philosophical debate on geometry and relativity was enor-
mous. The young Rudolf Carnap in his doctoral Dissertation Der Raum (Carnap, 1922)
drew mostly upon from Schlick's interpretation of Einstein's passage on the geometri-
are the only topological invariant, and are therefore unambiguous, whereas anything
else - pro jective, ane or metric structure is the result of a stipulation. Later Car-
nap remained essentially faithful to this approach, even after abandoning the Husser-
lian/Kantian framework in which it had originally been developed. And it was after hav-
ing corresponded with Schlick that Hans Reichenbach (1923/24), for whom Einstein later
created a chair in the philosophy of science in the physics department at Berlin, quickly
the direction of the metric conventionalism for which he later became famous with his
Reichenbach was perhaps the rst among Logical Empiricists to insist on the fact that
16
were nothing but variations of Leibniz's argument in the Leibniz-Clarke correspondence
anity with Leibniz. According to Reichenbach, Leibniz went so far as to recognize the
relationship between causal order and time order (Reichenbach, 1949/1951, p. 300), and
most of all with his principle of the identity of indiscernible, discernible in connection
with the veriability theory of meaning, he laid the foundation of what Reichenbach
calls the theory of equivalent descriptions (see for instance Lehrer 2004; Klein 2001)
where Leibniz's indiscernibility explicitly oods into the period's debate about geometry
than a single description, can correctly describe the geometry of physical space, in as
deformed in such a way that the spatial relations of adjacent bodies remain unchanged:
In this context belongs the assumption that overnight all things enlarge to the same
extent, or that the size of transported objects is uniformly aected by their position.
Helmholtz's parable of the spherical mirror comparing the world outside and inside
the mirror is also of this kind; if our world were to be so distorted as to correspond
to the geometrical relations of the mirror images, we would not notice it, because all
coincidences would be preserved. (Reichenbach 1928/1977, p. 38-, tr. Reichenbach,
1928/1958, p. 27; my emphasis)
denition of rigid bodies or straight lines may yield dierent geometrical descriptions of
Leibniz, the reader may recall, had earlier defended a similar point of view. If there is
in principle no way of deciding between two statements, Leibniz declared, we should
not say they have dierent meaning. If all bodies in the universe doubled in size
overnight, would the world seem strange to us next morning? Leibniz said it would
not. The size of our own bodies would double, so there would be no means by which we
could detect a change. Similarly, if the entire universe moved to one side by a distance
of ten miles, we could not detect it. To assert that such a change had occurred would,
therefore, be meaningless. Poincaré adopted this view of Leibniz's and applied it to
the geometrical structure of space. (Carnap, 1966, p. 148)
This passage clearly shows that the strategy adopted by Logical Empiricists to assimilate
Poincaré or Hausdor applied their arguments to space alone, Einstein simply extended
17
world lines presupposes nothing concerning the metrical relations of space and time, so
metrical properties of spacetime are deemed less fundamental than topological ones.
The ob jective system of coincidences does not depend on an observer, it is therefore
independent of all arbitrariness and an ultimate fact of nature, whereas the metric
be more constant then the metrical ones, so that the transition from the special theory to
the fundamental topological character of space and time remains the same (Reichenbach
1924, p. 115; tr. Reichenbach, 1924/1969, 195; see Ryckman 2007, 2008).
idea (on which Howard 1999 famously insisted) that point-coincidences are taken to be
real because of their observability, and thus they qualify as invariant, seems however to
arise at all from the impossibility of observing certain dierences physically, but from the
impossibility of expressing them geometrically. Just as Euclidean space does not allow
one to establish the dierence between left or right without a coordinative denition,
a bare topological space would not allow one to observe the distinction between
straight and curved lines. From such a conclusion, it is not hard to prognosticate that
relevance, was destined to failure from a theoretic point of view. Probably only the
implementation of a generalized Machian point of view in which the inertial force can
tr. Reichenbach, 1928/1958, p. 214), prevented them from seeing that the interpretation
they were suggesting would have made General Relativity dynamically empty.
argument can be considered the core of the Logical Empiricist interpretation of General
Relativity, at the same time then it is the reason for its substantial inadequacy. As we
have tried to show, Leibniz's indiscernibility arguments express the global symmetries of
space or spacetime: two universes mapped by some kind of deformation would be indis-
tinguishable, if all relevant structure were preserved, since all that the theory considered
geometrically relevant would appear the same in both universes. If the point-coincidence
argument were an indiscernibility argument of this kind, its result would be therefore to
enlarge the spatio-temporal symmetry group of spacetime to the group of all one-one,
bi-continuous point transformations: only the topological features of events are preserved
by this group of transformations, that is, the notion of the coincidence of two events
and the notion of two events being near one another in spacetime.
the symmetry group of an arbitrary general relativistic spacetime is not the widest group
of all smooth coordinate transformations that preserve only point-coincidences, but the
narrowest one consisting of the identity alone. The use of the full group of admissible
transformations in General Relativity does not imply that we are working in the context
18
of a very weak, though xed, geometrical structure, but, rather, that we are working in
the context of a highly structured spacetime, endowed with a perfectly denite, although
variable, metric. In this context indiscernibility arguments in the sense of Leibniz do not
even make any sense. In an inhomogeneous space it really would make a dierence if one
would shift everything into a region of increasing spatial curvature, and the consequences
of doubling would depend on where the doubling were carried out (Nerlich, 1994, p. 152).
When Weyl (1924b), upon whose authority we wish once more to rely, reviewed Re-
ichenbach's Axiomatik der relativistischen Raum- Zeit-Lehre , (Reichenbach 1924, tr. Re-
ichenbach, 1924/1969) he found the book not very satisfactory, too laborious and too
yond mathematical technicalities, what Weyl probably felt to be the most philosophically
eral Relativity with the separation between the factual and conventional components,
those which are xed once and for all, and those which result from the stipulations of
rigid rods and ideal clocks. Weyl's reliance on the use of trajectories of force-free mass
according to Weyl, the main novelty of Einstein's theory of gravitation was that it had
transformed the guiding inertial structure, that counts as standard for no-acceleration,
from a rigid geometric property of the world, xed once for all (Weyl, 1934/2009, p.
134) to a guiding eld (Führungsfeld , as Weyl famously called it) a physical reality
which is dependent on the state of matter (Weyl 1921/1968, p. 141 tr. Weyl 1921/2009,
p. 21): The distinction between guidance [Führung] and eld is preserved, but guidance
has become a eld (as the electromagnetic eld [An dem Dualismus von Führung und
Kraft wird also festgehalten; aber die Führung ist ein physikalisches Zustandsfeld (wie
The philosophical meaning of General Relativity should be sought not in the distinc-
tion between arbitrary and non-arbitrary structures, but in that between dynamical and
non-dynamical ones. The dierence between Galilean spacetime and Special Relativis-
tic spacetime lies in the dierence between their inertial structures. Nevertheless, both
structures are non-dynamical in the sense that they are independent of their contents:
the unique ane connection (compatible with the spacetime metric), it is said, provides a
standard for absolute acceleration and rotation. The radical novelty of General Relativ-
ity does not consist in weakening such a xed background structure, but in transforming
the xed background into a dynamical one. Since all bodies are inuenced by gravity in
precisely the same way (equivalence principle), there are no physical phenomena inde-
pendent of gravitation that might serve to measure the background spacetime geometry;
on the contrary we can measure the acceleration of a particle in a magnetic eld relative
to the inertial tra jectory of a body that is not aected by magnetism. In other terms,
there is no unique decomposition of the ane structure into an inertial structure and the
9 So Weyl summarizes his position: the metrical structure of the world is already fully determined by
its inertial and causal structure, that therefore mensuration need not depend on clocks and rigid bodies
but that light signals and mass points moving under the inuence of inertia alone will suce (Weyl,
2009b, p. 103).
19
4.2. The Point-Coincidence Argument as a Response to the Hole Argument
Even if the distinction between dynamical and non-dynamical structures (or dynamical
and absolute objects, in James Anderson's terms; Anderson 1967) turned out to be not
suciently sharp (Giulini 2007; see Pitts 2006), nevertheless it is now a widely shared
opinion that it better expresses the philosophical spirit of General Relativity than the
the case that the metric that was non-arbitrary in previous theories has become arbitrary,
but that the metric that was non-dynamical has become dynamical - it has become a
As we argued, the Logical Empiricists' failure to grasp this point seems connected
comprehensible. The echo of the widespread use of such arguments in one of the most
exciting philosophical debates of the turn of century was still vivid. Moreover Einstein's
Helmholtzian insistence on the importance of practically rigid rods and clocks (Ein-
stein, 1921, 1925) could be easily seen as the authoritative conrmation that this was
the correct interpretative context (Ryckman, 1996; see also Howard, 2005). Only re-
cent scholarship initiated by John Stachel (Stachel, 2002) discovered the key to a proper
dence from that period . The meaning of what we may call (following Rynasiewicz 1999)
the public point-coincidence argument can be understood only if one knows the private
point-coincidence argument as a response to the infamous hole argument. The details
of both versions of the argument have been rehearsed many times in recent literature,
so it does not seems necessary to repeat here the Hole Story, as Earman and Norton
(I) The public point-coincidence argument, as we said, appeared for the rst time in
Einstein's 1916 review article on General Relativity, and it is used to express the formal
nature: The laws of nature are only propositions about spatio-temporal coincidences;
therefore they nd their natural expression in generally covariant elds equations (CPAE
7, Doc. 4, 38; Prinzipielles zur Relativitätstheorie , 1918). In this context the argument
are all that matters physically, then we ought to be able to use any coordinate system,
since all coordinate systems necessarily agree on such coincidences (Norton, 1995). The
young Wolfgang Pauli (at his third semester), in his celebrated Enzyklöpedie article on
In this form the argument is customarily regarded as physically vacuous, since such
of the laws. The unavoidable reference is to the now familiar argument of the young
20
mathematician Erich Kretchman, who as early as 1917 (Kretschmann, 1917) turned the
relations, then for this very reason all spacetime theories can be given in a generally
(II) The private point-coincidence argument is a response to the hole argument, which
probably rst occurred to Einstein by November 1913 (Stachel, 1980/2002) at the latest.
two dierent solutions of generally covariant eld equations would arise at a single point
within a hole (a region devoid of matter and energy), whereas the sources outside the hole
have not changed. Einstein overcame this diculty when he came to realize that two sets
of eld lines that intersect in the same way, that is that agree on point-coincidences, dene
the same physical situation, since we do not have any means to separate a background
system of rigid grids from the eld lines. Hence, two metric elds whose geodesics
intersect one another in the same way are the same metric eld.
ably nowhere more in evidence than in Einstein's correspondence with Paul Ehrenfest in
late December 1915 and early January 1916 (CPAE 8a, Doc. 173, 26 December 1915, and
Doc. 180, 5 January 1916). Ehrenfest, in a letter that no longer exists, presumably asked
Einstein to consider a situation in which light from a distant star passes through one of
Einstein's holes and then strikes a screen with a pinhole in it that directs the light onto
a photographic plate. The question is whether the same point on the photographic plate
would have received the light after a coordinate transformation. In fact, the coordinate
transformation would change the metric in the hole, determining a dierent geodesic
In his answer (CPAE 8a, Doc. 180), Einstein imagines representing the situation
deforms the tracing paper arbitrarily then one would obtain a solution that is math-
ematically a dierent one from before (CPAE 8a, Doc. 180, p. 238). Deforming the
paper means deforming the coordinate systems, and according to the well-known rules
of tensor calculus, one would obtain a dierent metric eld, and therefore a dierent
geodesic trajectory of light rays. Einstein's worries that this would jeopardize the uni-
vocality of the description of nature disappeared, when he realized that this is only a
mathematical dierence - physically it is exactly the same. (CPAE 8a, Doc. 180, p.
239; my emphasis). In fact the background coordinate system (the orthogonal drawing
paper coordinate system) with respect to which the situation would have appeared de-
formed is only something imaginary [eingebildetes]: What is essential is this: As long
as the drawing paper, i.e., `space,' has no reality, the two gures do not dier at all. It is
only a matter of coincidences, e.g., whether or not the point on the plate is struck by
light. Thus, the dierence between your solutions A and B becomes a mere dierence of
representation, with physical agreement (CPAE 8a, Doc. 180, p. 239; my emphasis; tr.
meaning of both versions of the argument (Ryckman, 1992; Howard, 1999). The public
21
point-coincidence argument is not an indiscernibility argument at all. The private in-
Leibnizian sense. I argued that the reason for such a failure is not so much the conse-
point of view. It is rather the fact that, given the philosophical context in which they
developed their interpretation, they could hardly resist the temptation to interpret the
argument more geometrico , as one of the many Leibniz-style argument that dominated
the 19th century debate on the foundations of geometry. Only recently has the knowledge
dierent background, one that the Logical Empiricists could not, if not partially, have
known (see Einstein's letter to Schlick, CPAE, Doc. 165; 14 December 1915). However,
it is signicant that it was precisely Hermann Weyl had already clearly seen the dierence
same years when the Logical Positivists were publishing their philosophical reections on
relativity.
of plasticine traversed by individual bers, the world lines of material particles (Weyl
1927b, p. 73; tr. Weyl 2009b, p. 105). According to Weyl it is impossible to distinguish
conceptually between the system of lines and the system of curves resulting from them
by a spatial deformation (Weyl 1927b, p. 21; tr. Weyl 2009b, p. 24; my emphasis). In
fact only such relations have an objective signicance as are preserved under arbitrary
deformations of the plasticine. The intersection of two world lines is, for instance, of
this kind (Weyl 1927b, p. 73; tr. Weyl 2009a, p. 129; my emphasis). In this way,
however, the world would be an amorphous continuum without any structure (Weyl
point conguration can be made at this stage, but it would be impossible to distinguish
the straight lines from the curved ones (Weyl, 1932/2009, p. 41; my emphasis). Thus
every guiding structure, every standard for distinguishing inertial motions and deviation
from the inertial motion would have been lost. The consequence of the Leibnizian strategy
a strategy clearly destroys the possibility of dealing with the problem of the relativity
of motion, since no solution of the problem is possible as long as one disregards the
structure of the world (Weyl 1927b, p. 65; tr. Weyl 2009b, p. 105; see Coleman and
Korté 1984).
the hole argument, cannot therefore be confused with an indiscernibility argument in the
sense of Leibniz. The great achievement of General Relativity, as Weyl never tires of
telling, lies in the fact that the inertial structure of the world is not rigid, but exible,
and changes under material inuences (Weyl, 1934/2009, p. 133). The standard for
distinguishing between inertial and non-inertial motion has itself become dynamical, that
is, in Weyl's parlance, a guiding eld: acceleration means deviation from the trajectories
of particles sub ject only to gravitation, tra jectories that, however, depend in turn on the
22
1924, serves to avoid the mistake that Einstein committed in 1914 [den gleichen Fehler,
The reference is clearly to the hole argument that was rst published in January 1914
(CPAE 4, Doc. 26; January 1914) in the Bemerkungen added to the article version of
the Entwurf paper written with Grossman (rst published as separatum CPAE 4, Doc.
13; 1913) and repeated in two papers both dating from early 1914 (CPAE 4, Doc. 25,
In fact Weyl rst observed that if the matter disappears, the guiding eld must be-
werden] (Weyl, 1924a, p. 202; my emphasis). The very same physical state can be real-
under arbitrary coordinate-transformations, then I will get from a solution [of the eld
equations] by means of a transformation, innitely many new ones [wenn die Naturgeset-
einer Lösung durch Transformation unendlich viele neue] (Weyl, 1924a, p. 203). Weyl's
working on the Entwurf theory, Weyl was his colleague at the ETH in Zürich (Weyl came
to Zürich in Fall 1913, whereas Einstein left Zürich for Berlin in Summer 1914).
cut that separates both its edges [Teile ich die Welt durch einen dreidimensionalen
Querschnitt, welcher ihre beiden Säume, voneinander trennt, . . . in zwei Teile]. Weyl's
reformulation of the hole argument is similar to that of David Hilbert in 1917 (Renn and
Stachel, 2007), in using a open space-like hypersurface (a Cauchy surface) that separates
the future from the past, rather than a closed hypersuface as Einstein. Then, Weyl
continues, if I apply only those [coordinate] transformations that leave unchanged the
part `below' [verwende [Ich] nur solche Transformationen, welche die untere Hälfte
unberührt lassen], but change the metric eld in the part above, then all these solutions
[of the eld equations] will describe also in the underpart the same state evolution as of
the original ones [so stimmen alle diese Lösungen gleichwohl in der unteren Welthälfte
mit der ursprünglichen überein] (Weyl, 1924a, p. 203; emphasis mine). According to
Weyl, Einstein's mistake depends on the fact that he initially overlooked that there
was a dierence only if the four-dimensional world were a resting medium [daÿ ein
Unterschied nur bestünde, wenn die vierdimensionale Welt ein stehendes Medium wäre]
(Weyl, 1924a, p. 203). However, as Weyl immediately emphasizes such a resting Medium
... is completely repudiated by the theory of relativity [Ein solches stehendes Medium
wird aber . . . von der Relativitätstheorie durchaus geleugnet] (Weyl, 1924a, p. 203).
Einstein's kind of indiscernibility argument, as Weyl's exposition shows, does not imply
that the inertial structure has been dissolved in a Leibnizian/Machian way, but that it
has been, as Weyl wrote in an essay of 1925, so to speak, freed from space [vom Raume
abgelöst]. It has become an existing eld within the remaining structureless space [sie
1925/1988, p. 4). Dierences that would appear only with respect to such a structureless
space are not real dierences. On the other hand, Weyl shows that the strategy implied
10 So gibt es, doch unendlich viele Möglichkeiten, wie sich dieser Zustand im Weltcontinnum realisieren
kann (Weyl, 1924a, p. 202; my emphasis)
23
in Leibniz's indiscernibility arguments, to which the Logical Empiricists resorted, has
simply, as we may say, freed space from the minimum of structure that can play the role
of inertial guidance. In these two opposite manners of grasping Einstein's famous remark
that spacetime has lost its last vestige of physical reality, one can recognize most easily
It may be worth mentioning, even if only in passing, that Weyl's insistence on the fact
that, in General Relativity, the metric eld has been freed from the manifold (Korté,
2006, pp. 193, 201) should probably be understood in the context of his attempt to dene
hood (Umgebung , Weyl 1913). Such an attempt, initiated by Hilbert (1902) in the
same years, was, as Weyl recognizes, was pursued more systematically [Systematischer]
by Hausdor in his Grundzügen der Mengenlehre (1914) (Weyl 1925/1988, p. 4; the
approach, where the manifold was considered as a number manifold, as the manifold
of all possible values of x, y, z, t. Thus it could be argued, that Einstein was forced to
introduce his indiscernibility argument precisely in order to wash out this additional
is, in my opinion, instructive for the animated debate stirred by Earman and Norton's
fundamental paper (1987). Weyl's version of the hole argument is astonishingly similar
to that of Earman and Norton (much more so than Einstein's original version), and also
addresses the same substantivalist opponents; but at same time Weyl is also careful
argument.
famous argument due to Leibniz himself against Newton's substantival ontology of space
(Janssen, 2005, p. 74). The analogy between Leibniz's and Einstein's arguments could
actually appear prima facie very plausible. Leibniz considered two material universes as
indistinguishable or as the same universe. Einstein, roughly two centuries later, found
thus physically identical. In both cases there are apparently dierent possible worlds
allowed by the theory that actually correspond to the same physical reality. Leibniz
referred to alternative worlds that dier from the actual one only in position, orientation
or magnitude, but agree in the measure of the angles and proportions of lengths. Einstein
could imagine alternative worlds that agree exactly with the actual world outside the
hole, while diering within the hole. In both cases what seems at rst sight a dramatic
dierence reveals itself actually as being no dierence at all, since the dierence is declared
irrelevant.
However, the similarity between the two arguments is only apparent. The dierence
should strike the reader when they simply consider the dierent structures of the two
that aects every physical entity without exception ; if this condition is violated, the two
24
situations could be easily distinguished. But Einstein's argument explicitly violated this
condition, allowing a transformation that leaves everything unchanged with the exception
of a region devoid of matter. Of course both are indiscernibility arguments. They both
aim to ctionally eliminate the reference to a xed standard against which the change
can be measured, so that the apparent change would reveal itself to be no change at
all. However, such a standard is clearly dierent in each case: Leibniz-style arguments
dissipate the illusion of a transformation that would appear only with respect to some
would emerge, only while referring to the rigid geometry of the empty space.
The now usual exposition of physical theories in terms of models, where the models
are intended to represent the physically possible worlds that satisfy the laws of the
theory, can be useful to see this point. I will provide a slightly more formal presentation
in the appendix. Each model comprises a dierential manifold and various geometric
objects on it, such as metric and matter elds. Indiscernibility arguments in the sense of
Leibniz work well in a theory with global symmetries that presupposes that all relevant
geometrical structure of space appears the same in all universes or models governed
by the theory, so that the theory does not have the conceptual resources to distinguish
among them. In General Relativity, on the contrary, there are no non-trivial symmetries,
except identity. Therefore there is no spacetime background that would look the same
across all possible universes or models allowed by the theory, so that any reference to
Thus in theories where spacetime is endowed with global symmetries, it makes perfect
sense to apply Leibniz's indiscernibility arguments. Such arguments after all simply
postulate a trivial identity (Stachel and Iftime, 2005) of all models of the theory: it is, so
to speak, the very same model or better - in Leibniz's terms - models that are dierent solo
numero . On the contrary, Einstein's indiscernibility arguments make sense in theories
without global symmetries, where one has to deal with a plurality of dierent models that
are declared non-trivially equivalent, although they show, to resort to Leibniz's parlance
As we have seen, Leibniz's arguments serve to identify the physically relevant geo-
metrical structure of a theory, so that physical dierences that do not nd expression
with respect to such a structure cannot be considered physically meaningful. In the rst
case we have dierent physical situations expressed by the same mathematical model, in
the second case dierent mathematical models that express the same physical situation
worlds that at rst sight physically dierent turn out to be mathematically identical ;
in the hole argument apparently mathematically dierent worlds reveal themselves as
physically identical.
If one can speak in both cases of indiscernibility, it seems to me that we have to do
with dierent forms of indiscernibility: (1) an indiscernibility that arises because there
is too little structure to express some alleged physical dierences - dierences that might
which apparent mathematical dierences emerge, that are however declared physically
irrelevant, since they express the same physical situation in reality. In the rst case, one
25
might say, indiscernibility is the consequence of underdetermination, since the theory
does not have the tools to express at rst sight real dierences. In the second case, we
dierences that do not have any correspondence in reality. In my opinion simply re-
it is ritually repeated in the literature, would miss the dierence between these two
sorts of indiscernibility arguments: dierent physical situations that are declared math-
ematically indiscernible and dierent mathematical ob jects that are declared physically
indiscernible.
The historical reconstruction I have attempted should have shown that neither the
covariance, nor its private version, a response to the hole argument, can be interpreted
as a response to the hole argument, shows on the contrary that the main feature of
General Relativity is best summarized by John Stachel's celebrated motto: no metric,
no spacetime.
The Logical Empiricists believed that General Relativity was the result of a sort of
Leibniz's equivalence stricto sensu : in the Logical Empiricist interpretation of the point-
coincidence argument dieomorphisms play exactly the same role that translations
space or spacetime. However, such an approach clearly failed to give a plausible account
of General Relativity. Einstein's equivalence (as we may call it) must therefore have
a dierent meaning and dieomorphism must play a completely dierent role, a role
that it is more similar to that which it is usually called gauge freedom, akin to that of
the same physically measurable eld strengths can be expressed by several potentials,
11
similarly in General Relativity an entire equivalence class of dieomorphically-related
11 The freedom to choose among gauge-equivalent potentials is not a physical degree of freedom: it
rather results from the fact that we have many distinct mathematical objects all of which represent the
same physical state of aairs (Maudlin, 2002, p. 2, my emphasis; see also Belot, 1998). Another usual
example of the role of surplus structure in physical theories is to be found in modern particle physics.
→
−
Let a single, free non-relativistic particle be described by the wave function ψ(x) . Multiplying this wave
function by a complex number of unit modulus, a phase factor of the form eιθ , gives a wave function
−
→ →
− →
− →
−
ψ ′ (x) = eιθ ψ(x) : ψ(x) and ψ ′ (x) dier mathematically by an overall global phase. However, they
represent physically the same quantum state: the probability distribution for position and momentum
and the time evolution of probability distribution would be the same. As these well-known examples
show gauge freedom arises because the mathematical formalism introduces dierences that are physically
meaningless. At the contrary, global spacetime symmetries arise because certain empirical dierences
(of position, velocity etc.) are not allowed to appear in the mathematical expression of any physical law
(see also Brading and Brown, 2004).
26
We cannot enter the discussion on the legitimacy of such an analogy between General
Relativity and gauge theory (Weinstein, 1999), on which Norton himself, has insisted
(Norton, 2003). However, the simple possibility of establishing such an analogy, shows
the dierence between Leibniz equivalence and Einstein equivalence. Leibniz equiv-
say, try to convince us that are no dierences at all. It is more a kind of Leibniz identity
The use of spacetime models oers a very simple way to grasp what I think it is
the theoretical core of the historical reconstruction I suggested: the dierence between
Leibniz and Einstein indiscernibility, or between Leibniz and Einstein equivalence. Even
will provide at least a rapid overview. Following the current parlance stemming from
(Hawking and Ellis, 1974, ch. 3; see also Wald) models of a spacetime theory consist
of a manifold, a metric with Lorentz signature, and optionally one or more matter elds
(electromagnetic eld, neutrino eld etc.) that can be regarded as material content of
spacetime. Each of such elds is assumed to satisfy the eld equations. The models of a
From this point of view, one can easily see the dierence between a theory like Special
Relativity (SR) and General Relativity (GR), and the reason why Leibniz indiscernibility
arguments apply only to the former and Einstein indiscernibility argument only to the
of obtaining any solution to the equations of motion. In General Relativity, on the other
hand, the relevant geometrical structure has no a priori prescribed values, but rather
A model of SR has the form ⟨M, ηµν, , F 1, , F 2, ..., F n, ⟩ where M, ηµν , and Fi , represent
the spacetime manifold, the metric eld and the other elds (gravitational, electromag-
ηµν : in all models allowed by the theory ηµν = (−1, 1, 1, 1). Thus there is a xed space-
time structure, the metric structure ηµν, , whose ane structure Γλ µν = 0 represents a
xed standard of non-acceleration. This structure will appear the same in all possible
worlds.
A model of GR is given by a triple M = ⟨M, gµν , Tµν ⟩ where M, gµν , and Tµν
represent the spacetime manifold, the metric eld, and the stress-energy eld respectively.
Such models are taken to represent the physically possible worlds of General Relativity
when they satisfy Einstein's eld equations Gµν = κTµν (where Gµν is the Einstein
tensor describing the curvature of spacetime, and κ the coupling constant, proportional
to Newton's universal constant of gravitation). In contrast to SR, the gµν are then
subjected to the equations of the theory: they have become a eld among others. In
27
GR the symmetry group of ⟨M, gµν ⟩ is the identity group, since there is in general no
transformation that leaves gµν invariant. Hence there will be in general dierent models
′ ′′
of the theory: ⟨M, gµν ⟩, ⟨M, g µν ⟩, ⟨M, gµν ⟩, ... The Christoel symbols Γ µν gure as
λ
the components of the gravitational-inertial eld (so they are in general ̸= 0), whereas the
ρ
Curvature tensor or Riemann-Christoel tensor (Bµστ ) represents the eld gradient, or
λ
tidal eld. The fact that Γ µν is not a tensor is the formal expression of the non-unique
The analogy of the Leibniz shift can be found only in pre-relativistic theories, such
displacements, rotations, or boosts up to the speed of light) that preserves all relevant
geometrical structure (in the case of SR the metric structure uniquely determining the
inertial structure), that is h ∗ ηµν = ηµν (an isometry). If such a structure would not be
preserved, that is if h ∗ ηµν ̸= ηµν , the two universes or models would not be indistin-
guishable. The indistinguishability arises because the transformation produces the very
same model (it is a trivial identity). The original and the transformed situations are
indiscernible simply because they are mathematically exactly the same. The ηµν are the
only quantities pertaining to spacetime structure which can appear in any physical law.
Thus dierences that cannot be encoded in such a spacetime structure are not dierences.
In order to introduce further distinctions, for instance of spatial orientation, one has to
allow further aspects of spacetime structure to appear in physical laws (Wald, 1984, p.
60).
transformation h (dif f (M)) that does not preserve the relevant geometrical structure
(the metric structure determining the geodesics), that is h∗gµν ̸= gµν . An indiscernibility
argument in the sense of Einstein is needed because the theory introduces dierent models
that, however, are declared physically exactly the same : the same gravitational eld
ter, had at their disposal only Leibniz indiscernibility): noticing that the group of trans-
formations of GR, does not preserve the metric gµν , (h ∗ gµν ̸= gµν ), they declared the
metric conventional and identied spacetime with the invariant M held across models.
Dierences that cannot be expressed in M, like in a Hegelian night, are not dierences:
dif f (M) with a global spacetime symmetry. Einstein's indiscernibil-
that is they identify
ity argument moving from h∗gµν ̸= gµν concludes that spacetime is the equivalence class
′
(up to dieomorphism) of all ⟨M, gµν ⟩,⟨M, gµν ⟩, ..., so that dierences with respect to
M are not dierences, they are a mere mathematical redundancy: dif f (M) resembles
more closely an expression of gauge freedom (a whole family of gauge-related solutions
of the eld equations represent the same physical situation) (Wald, 1984, p. 438).
References
12 For sake of comparison I follow here John Stachel in arguing that the hole argument cannot be
taken over to the pregeneral-relativistic case (Stachel, 1993). This opinion is however controversial. I
cannot however address this issue here. My aim is rather to emphasize the opposite issue that Leibniz
arguments work only in pregeneral-relativistic theories.
28
Anderson, J. L., 1967. Principles of Relativity Physics. Acad. Pr., New York [et al.].
Arthur, R., 1994. Space and Relativity in Newton and Leibniz. The British Journal for the Philosophy
of Science 45 (1), pp. 219240.
Bartels, A., 1994. What is Spacetime, if not a Substance? Conclusions from the New Leibnizian Ar-
gument. In: Majer, U., Schmidt, H.-J. (Eds.), Semantical Aspects of Spacetime Theories. BI Wis-
senschaftsverlag (1994), Mannheim, pp. 4151.
Bartels, A., 1996. Modern Essentialism and the Problem of Individuation of Spacetime Points. Erkenntnis
45, 2543.
Belot, G., 1998. Understanding Electromagnetism. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science
49 (4), pp. 531555.
Brading, K., Brown, H. R., 2003. Symmetries and Noether's theorems. In: Symmetries in Physics.
Philosophical Reections. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, U.K.; New York, pp. 87109.
Brading, K., Brown, H. R., 2004. Are Gauge Symmetry Transformations Observable? British Journal
for the Philosophy of Science 55, 645665.
Brown, H. R., 2005. Physical relativity : space-time structure from a dynamical perspective, 1st Edition.
Clarendon, Oxford.
Buttereld, J., 1989. The Hole Truth. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 40 (1), 128.
Cantor, G., 1874. Ueber eine Eigenschaft des Inbegris aller reellen algebraischen Zahlen. Journal für
die reine und angewandte Mathematik (Crelles Journal) 1874 (77), 258262.
Cantor, G., 1878. Ein Beitrag zur Mannigfaltigkeitslehre. In: Zermelo, E. (Ed.), Gesammelte Abhand-
lungen mathematischen und philosophischen Inhalts. No. 119-133. Olms, Hildesheim.
Carnap, R., 1922. Der Raum. Ein Beitrag zur Wissenschaftslehre. Reuther & Reichard, Berlin.
Carnap, R., 1966. Philosophical Foundations of Physics: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science.
Basic Books, inc., New York.
Cherno, F., 1981. Leibniz's Principle of the Identity of Indiscernibles. The Philosophical Quarterly
31 (123), 126138.
Coa, A. J., 1991. The Semantic Tradition from Kant to Carnap: To the Vienna Station. Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge.
Coleman, R. A., Korté, H., 1984. Constraints on the Nature of Inertial Motion Arising from the Uni-
versality of Free Fall and the Conformal Causal Structure of Space-Time. Journal of Mathematical
Physics 25, 35133527.
Couturat, L., 1961. La logique de Leibniz d'après des documents inédits. Olms, Hildesheim.
Cox, C. B., 1978. Leibniz's Philosophy of Space. Diss. - Columbia University, New York.
CPAE: Einstein, A., 1996-. The Collected Papers of Albert Einstein. Princeton University Press, Prince-
ton.
De Risi, V., 2005. Leibniz on Geometry: Two Unpublished Texts with Translation and Commentary.
The Leibniz Review 15, 127132.
De Risi, V., 2007. Geometry and Monadology: Leibniz's analysis situs and Philosophy of Space.
Birkhäuser, Basel; Boston.
DiSalle, R., 2002a. Conventionalism and Modern Physics. A Re-Assessment. Noûs 36 (2), 169200.
DiSalle, R., 2002b. Newton's Philosophical Analysis of Space and Time. In: Cohen, I. B. (Ed.), The
Cambridge Companion to Newton. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 3354.
DiSalle, R., 2006. Understanding Space-Time: The Philosophical Development of Physics from Newton
to Einstein. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK ; New York.
Earman, J., 1989. World Enough and Space-Time: Absolute vs. Relational Theories of Space and Time.
MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.
Earman, J., Norton, J. D., 1987. What Price Substantivalism. The Hole Story. British Journal for the
Philosophy of Science 38, 515525.
Ehler, J., 1988. Hermann Weyl's Contributions to the General Theory of Relativity. In: Deppert, W. H.
(Ed.), Exact sciences and their philosophical foundations: Vorträge des Internationalen Hermann-
Weyl-Kongresses, Kiel 1985 = Exakte Wissenschaften und ihre philosophische Grundlegung. Lang,
Frankfurt am Main [et.al.].
Einstein, A., 1921. Geometrie und Erfahrung. Springer, Berlin.
Einstein, A., 1925. Nichteuklidische Geometrie und Physik. Die neue Rundschau 36, 1620.
Epple, M., 2006. Felix Hausdor 's Considered Empiricism. In: Ferreirós, J., Gray, J. (Eds.), The Archi-
tecture of Modern Mathematics: Essays in History and Philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Epple, M., 2007. An Unusual Career between Cultural and Mathematical Modernism: Felix Hausdor,
1868-1942. In: Charpa, U., Deichmann, U. (Eds.), Jews and Sciences in German Contexts: Case
Studies from the 19th and 20th centuries. Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen, pp. 77100.
29
Freudenthal, H., 1972. Leibniz und die analysis situs. Studia Leibnitiana 4 (2), 6160.
Friedman, M., 1983. Foundations of Space-Time Theories: Relativistic Physics and Philosophy of Science.
Princeton University Press, Princeton.
Friedman, M., 1995. Poincaré's Conventionalism and the Logical Positivists. Foundations of Science 2,
299314, now in [Friedman 1999].
Friedman, M., 1999. Reconsidering Logical Positivism. Cambridge University Press, New York.
Galilei, G., 1632/2005. Discorso intorno a due nuove scienze. In: Brunetti, F. (Ed.), Opere. UTET,
Torino.
Galilei, G., 1967. Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems, Ptolemaic and Copernican. Uni-
versity of California Press, Berkeley.
Giulini, D., 2007. Remarks on the Notions of General Covariance and Background Independence. Lecture
Notes in Physics 721, 105120.
Giulini, D., Straumann, N., 2006. Einstein's Impact on the Physics of the Twentieth Century. Studies
In History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies In History and Philosophy of Modern Physics
37 (1), 115 173, 2005: The Centenary of Einstein's Annus Mirabilis.
GM: Leibniz, G. W., 1850. Leibnizens mathematische Schriften. Schmidt, Halle.
GP: Leibniz, G. W., 1875. Die philosophischen Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. Weidmann,
Berlin.
Hausdor, F., 1903. Das Raumproblem. Annalen der Naturphilosophie 3, 123.
Hausdor, F., 1914/2002. Grundzüge der Mengenlehre. In: Brieskorn, E., Chatterji, S. D., Epple, M.
(Eds.), Gesammelte Werke. "Grundzüge der Mengenlehre". Vol. II. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg etc.
Hausdor, F., 1927, 1935/2007. Mengenlehre. In: Brieskorn, E., Hirzebruch, F., Remmert, R., Purkert,
W., Scholz, E. (Eds.), Gesammelte Werke: Deskriptive Mengenlehre und Topologie. Vol. III. Springer,
Berlin, Heidelberg etc.
Hausdor, F., 2004. Das Chaos in kosmischer Auslese. Ein erkenntnisskritischer Versuch. In: Stegmaier,
W. (Ed.), Gesammelte Werke: Philosophisches Werk. Vol. VII. Springer, Berlin.
Hausdor, F., 2010. Gesammelte Werke: Geometrie, Raum und Zeit. Vol. VI. Springer, Berlin, Heidel-
berg etc.
Hawking, S. W., Ellis, G. F. R., 1974. The large scale structure of space-time. Cambridge monographs
on mathematical physics ; 1. Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge.
Hilbert, D., 1902. Über die Grundlagen der Geometrie. Mathematische Annalen 56, 381422.
Hoefer, C., 1996. The Metaphysics of Space-Time Substantivalism. The Journal of Philosophy 93 (1),
pp. 527.
Howard, D., 1999. Point Coincidences and Pointer Coincidences. Einstein on the Invariant Content of
Space·Time Theories. In: Goenner, H. (Ed.), The Expanding Worlds of General Relativity. Birkhäuser,
Basel, pp. 463500.
Howard, D., 2005. 'No Crude Surfeit': A Critical Appreciation of The Reign of Relativity"., delivered
at 2005 Pacic meeting of the American Philosophical Assocation, manuscript.
Howard, D., Norton, J. D., 1993. Out of the Labyrinth. Einstein, Hertz, and the Gottingen Answer to
the Hole Argument. In: The attraction of gravitation : new studies in the history of general relativity.
Birkhäuser, Basel, pp. 3062.
Huggett, N., Hoefer, C., 2009. Absolute and Relational Theories of Space and Motion. In: Zalta, E. N.
(Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, fall 2009 Edition.
Janssen, M., 2005. Of pots and holes: Einstein's bumpy road to general relativity. Annalen der Physik
14, 5885.
Jauernig, A., 2008. Leibniz on Motion and the Equivalence of Hypotheses. The Leibniz Review 18, 140.
Klein, C., 2001. Conventionalism and Realism in Hans Reichenbach's Philosophy of Geometry. Interna-
tional Studies in the Philosophy of Science 15 (3), 243251.
Korté, H., 2006. Einstein's Hole Argument and Weyl's Field-body Relationalism. In: Demopoulos, W.,
Pitowsky, I. (Eds.), Physical Theory and its Interpretation. Vol. 72 of The Western Ontario Series in
Philosophy of Science. Springer Netherlands, pp. 183212.
Kosso, P., 2000. The Empirical Status of Symmetries in Physics. The British Journal for the Philosophy
of Science 51 (1), 8198.
Kretschmann, E., 1917. Über den physikalischen Sinn der Relativitätspostulate. A. Einsteins neue und
seine ursprüngliche Relativitätstheorie. Annalen der Physik 53, 575614.
Lariviere, B., 1987. Leibnizian Relationalism and the Problem of Inertia. Canadian Journal of Philosophy
17 (2), 437448.
Lehrer, K., 2004. Reichenbach on Convention. Synthese 34/2, 237248.
Leibniz, G. W., 1976. Philosophical Papers and Letters: A Selection, 2nd Edition. Synthese historical
30
library ; 2. Riedel, Dordrecht.
Leibniz, G. W., 1989. Philosophical Essays. Hackett Pub. Co., Indianapolis, IN.
Maudlin, T., 1988. The Essence of Space-Time. SA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philos-
ophy of Science Association 2, 291.
Maudlin, T., 1993. Buckets of Water and Waves of Space. Why Spacetime Is Probably a Substance.
Philosophy of Science 60 (2), 183203.
Maudlin, T., 2002. Thoroughly Muddled McTaggart. Or, How to Abuse Gauge Freedom to Create
Metaphysical Monostrosities. Philosophers' Imprint 2 (4), 119.
Münzenmayer, H. P., 1979. Der Calculus Situs und die Grundlagen der Geometrie bei Leibniz. Studia
Leibnitiana 11, 274300.
Mongré, P., 1898. Das Chaos in kosmischer Auslese. Ein erkenntnisskritischer Versuch. Naumann,
Leipzig, now in Hausdor [2004].
Nerlich, G., 1994. What Spacetime Explains: Metaphysical Essays on Space and Time. Cambridge Univ.
Press, Cambridge [et al.].
NL FH: Hausdor, F., -. Nachlass, the Nachlass is located at the Main Library of
the University of Bonn (D). An online catalogue can be found at http://www.aic.uni-
wuppertal.de/fb7/hausdor/ndbuch.asp. The papers on philosophy of geometry will be published
in Hausdor [2010].
Norton, J. D., 1984. How Einstein found his Field Equations: 1912-1915. Historical Studies in the
Physical Sciences 14, 253316.
Norton, J. D., 1989. Coordinates and Covariance: Einstein's View of Spacetime and the Modern View.
Foundations of Physics 19, 12151263.
Norton, J. D., 1992. The Physical Content of General Covariance. In: Studies in the History of General
Relativity: Einstein Studies. Birkhauser, Boston, pp. 281315.
Norton, J. D., 1995. Did Einstein Stumble? The Debate over General Covariance. Erkenntnis 42 (2),
223245.
Norton, J. D., 1999. Geometries in Collision: Einstein, Klein and Riemann. In: Gray, J. (Ed.), The
Symbolic Universe. Oxford University Press, Oxford; New York, pp. 128144.
Norton, J. D., 2003. General covariance, gauge theories, and the Kretschmann objection. In: Brading,
K., Castellani, E. (Eds.), Symmetries in Physics. Philosophical Reections. Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge, pp. 110123.
Pauli, W., 1921. Relativitätstheorie. In: Enzyklopädie der mathematischen Wissenschaften. Vol. 5. Teub-
ner, pp. 539775.
Pauli, W., 1958. Theory of Relativity. Pergamon Press, London.
Pitts, J. B., 2006. Absolute Objects and Counterexamples: Jones-Geroch dust, Torretti Constant Curva-
ture, Tetrad-Spinor, and Scalar Density. Studies In History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies
In History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 37 (2), 347 371.
Pulte, H., 2006. The Space between Helmholtz and Einstein: Moritz Schlick on Spatial Intuition and the
Foundations of Geometry. In: Hendricks, V. F., Jørgensen, K. F., Lützen, J., Pedersen, S. A. (Eds.),
Interactions Mathematics, Physics and Philosophy, 1860-1930. Springer, Dordrecht.
Reichenbach, H., 1920/1977. Relativitätstheorie und Erkenntnis a priori. In: Kamlah, A., Reichenbach,
M. (Eds.), Gesammelte Werke in 9 Bänden. Vol. 3. Braunschweig; Wiesbaden, Vieweg.
Reichenbach, H., 1924. Axiomatik der relativistischen Raum-Zeit-Lehre. Braunschweig, Vieweg.
Reichenbach, H., 1924/1969. Axiomatization of the Theory of Relativity. University of California Press,
Berkeley,.
Reichenbach, H., 1928/1958. The Philosophy of Space and Time. Dover Publ., New York.
Reichenbach, H., 1928/1977. Die Philosophie der Raum-Zeit-Lehre. In: Kamlah, A., Reichenbach, M.
(Eds.), Gesammelte Werke in 9 Bänden. Vol. 2. Vieweg, Braunschweig; Wiesbaden.
Reichenbach, H., 1949/1951. The Philosophical Signicance of the Theory of Relativity. In: Schilpp,
P. A. (Ed.), Albert Einstein. Philosopher-Scientist. Tudor, New York, pp. 289311.
Renn, J., Stachel, J., 2007. Hilbert's Foundation of Physics: From a Theory of Everything to a Con-
stituent of General Relativity. In: Renn, J., Janssen, M. (Eds.), The Genesis of General Relativity.
Springer Netherlands, pp. 857972.
Roberts, J. T., 2003. Leibniz on Force and Absolute Motion. Philosophy of Science 70 (3), pp. 553573.
Rosen, J., 2008. Symmetry Rules: How Science and Nature Are Founded on Symmetry. Springer, Berlin;
Heidelberg.
Ryckman, T., 1992. (P)oint-(C)oincidence Thinking. The Ironical Attachment of Logical Empiricism to
General Relativity. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 23 (3), 471497.
Ryckman, T., 1995. Weyl, Reichenbach and the Epistemology of Geometry. Studies in History and
31
Philosophy of Science 25 (6), 831870.
Ryckman, T., 1996. Einstein Agonists: Weyl and Reichenbach on Geometrv and the General Theory
of Relativity. In: Giere, R. N. (Ed.), Origins of Logical Empiricism. University of Minnesota Press,
Minneapolis, pp. 165209.
Ryckman, T., 2005. The Reign of Relativity. Philosophy in Physics 1915-1925. Oxford University Press,
Oxford, New York.
Ryckman, T., 2007. Logical Empiricism and Philosophy of Physics. In: Richardson, A. W., Uebel, T.
(Eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Logical Empiricism, 1st Edition. Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge [et al.], pp. XI, 430 S.
Ryckman, T., 2008. Early Philosophical Interpretations of General Relativity. In: Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Fall 2008 Edition. plato.stanford.edu/entries/genrel-early/.
Rynasiewicz, R., 1994. The Lessons of the Hole Argument. The British Journal for the Philosophy of
Science 45 (2), 407436.
Rynasiewicz, R., 1999. Kretschmann's Analysis of Covariance and Relativity Principles. In: Goenner,
H. (Ed.), The Expanding Worlds of General Relativity. Birkhäuser, Basel, pp. 431462.
Rynasiewicz, R., 2000. On the Distinction between Absolute and Relative Motion. Philosophy of Science
67 (1), 7093.
Saunders, S., 2002. Indiscernibles, General Covariance, and other Symmetries. In: Ashtekar, A. V., Renn,
J., Howard, D. (Eds.), Revisiting the Foundations of Relativistic Physics: Festschrift in Honour of
John Stachel. Kluwer, Dordrecht/Boston/London, pp. 151173.
Schlick, M., 1920. Space and Time in Contemporary Physics, an Introduction to the Theory of Relativity
and Gravitation. Oxford University Press, Oxford/New York.
Schlick, M., 1922/2006. Raum und Zeit in der gegenwärtigen Physik. In: Neuber, M., Engler, O. (Eds.),
Gesamtausgabe. Vol. I,2. Springer, New York/Berlin.
Schlick, M., 1978a. Philosophical Papers. Vienna Circle collection ; 11. Reidel, Dordrecht.
Schlick, M., 1978b. Space and Time in Contemporary Physics. In: Mulder, H. L. (Ed.), Philosophical
Papers. Vol. 1 of Vienna Circle collection ; 11. Reidel, Dordrecht.
Schneider, M., 1988. Funktion und Grundlegung der Mathesis Universalis. Studia Leibnitiana Sonderheft
15, 162182, (Leibniz: Questions de Logique).
Slowik, E., 2006. The "dynamics" of Leibnizian relationism: Reference frames and force in Leibniz's
plenum. Studies In History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies In History and Philosophy of
Modern Physics 37 (4), 617 634.
Stachel, J., 1980/2002. Einstein's Search for General Covariance, 1912-1915. In: Einstein from "B" to
"Z". Birkhäuser, Boston, pp. 301337, the paper was rst paper read at the Ninth International
Conference on General Relativity and Gravitation, Jena in 1980.
Stachel, J., 1993. The Meaning of General Covariance: The Hole Story. In: Earman, J. (Ed.), Philo-
sophical problems of the internal and external worlds : essays on the philosophy of Adolf Grünbaum.
Pittsburgh-Konstanz series in the philosophy and history of science ; [1]. Univ. of Pittsburgh Pr.,
Pittsburgh, Pa., festschrift Adolf Grünbaum.
Stachel, J., Iftime, M., 2005. Fibered Manifolds, Geometric Objects, Structured Sets, G-Sets and all
that: The Hole Story from Space Time to Elementary Particles. arxiv.org.
Stachel, J. J., 2002. Einstein from B to Z. Einstein studies ; 9. Birkhäuser, Boston.
Stein, H., 1967/1970. Newtonian Space-Time. In: Palter, R. (Ed.), The Annus mirabilis of Sir Isaac
Newton, 1666-1966. The MIT Press, Cambridge (Ma.)/London, pp. 254284.
Wald, R. M., 1984. General relativity. Univ. of Chicago Pr., Chicago [et al.].
Wallwitz, G. G., 1991. Strukturelle Probleme in Leibniz Analysis Situs. Studia Leibnitiana 23, 111118.
Weinstein, S., 1999. Gravity and Gauge Theory. Philosophy of Science 66, 146155.
Weyl, H., 1913. Die Idee der Riemannschen Fläche, 2nd Edition. Mathematische Vorlesungen an der
Universität Göttingen ; 5. Teubner, Leipzig [et al.].
Weyl, H., 1921/1968. Elektrizität und Gravitation. In: Chandrasekharan, K. (Ed.), Gesammelte Ab-
handlungen. Vol. 2. Springer, Berlin, pp. 141142.
Weyl, H., 1921/2009. Electricity and Gravitation. In: Pesic, P. (Ed.), Mind and Nature: Selected Writings
on Philosophy, Mathematics, and Physics. Princeton Univerity Press, Princeton.
Weyl, H., 1924a. Massenträgheit und Kosmos. Ein Dialog. Naturwissenschaften 12, 11.
Weyl, H., 1924b. Rezension von: H. Reichenbach: Axiomatik der relativistischen Raum- Zeit Lehre.
Deutsche Literaturzeitung. 45, 21222128.
Weyl, H., 1925/1988. Riemanns geometrische Ideen, ihre Auswirkung und ihre Verknüpfung mit der
Gruppentheorie. Springer, New York; Berlin; Heidelberg.
Weyl, H., 1927a. Philosophie der Mathematik und Naturwissenschaft. In: Bäumler, A., Schröter, M.
32
(Eds.), Handbuch der Philosophie. Olde, München/Berlin.
Weyl, H., 1927b. Zeitverhältnisse im Kosmos, Eigenzeit, gelebte Zeit und metaphysische Zeit. In: Pro-
ceedings of the Sixth International Congress of Philosophy. Harvard University, Cambridge, Mas-
sachusetts, United States of America, September 13-17, 1926. Longmans, Green and Co., Cambridge,
Ma., pp. 5458.
Weyl, H., 1932/2009. The Open World. In: Pesic, P. (Ed.), Mind and Nature: Selected Writings on
Philosophy, Mathematics, and Physics. Princeton Univerity Press, Princeton.
Weyl, H., 1934/2009. Mind and Nature. In: Pesic, P. (Ed.), Mind and Nature: Selected Writings on
Philosophy, Mathematics, and Physics. Princeton University Press, Princeton, pp. 83150.
Weyl, H., 1939/1997. The Classical Groups: Their Invariants and Representations. Princeton University
Press, Princeton.
Weyl, H., 1952. Symmetry. Princeton Univ. Pr., Princeton, NJ.
Weyl, H., 2009a. Mind and Nature: Selected Writings on Philosophy, Mathematics, and Physics. Prince-
ton Univerity Press, Princeton.
Weyl, H., 2009b. Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Science. Princeton University Press, Princeton.
33