Canovan - Populism For Political Theorists
Canovan - Populism For Political Theorists
Canovan - Populism For Political Theorists
9(3), 241–252
Few political theorists believe that populism deserves their attention. Echoing
earlier fears of ‘the many-headed monster’,1 recent students of politics have
indeed tended to treat populist movements as pathological symptoms of some
social disease.2 The aim of this paper is to suggest some reasons why main-
stream political theorists might nevertheless find it worth their while to take an
interest in populism.
It may help to start with an analogy. Fifteen years ago, mainstream political
theorists were not in the habit of paying any attention to nationalism. If they
noticed it at all, they assumed that nationalist politics did not raise any
interesting theoretical questions. However, when the collapse of communism
prompted reflection by putting nationalism on the political agenda the issues it
raised turned out after all to be intellectually interesting, generating a large and
sophisticated theoretical literature. Now that populism in its turn is rising up the
political agenda, is there scope for a similar development? Populism has a bad
name among intellectuals, but there are some inducements for political theorists
to overcome their distaste and take a serious interest in it. I shall argue that at
least four aspects of the topic offer scope for theoretical investigation, though
this paper can offer only a preliminary survey of the territory.
In summary, the four are as follows:
ISSN 1356-9317 print; ISSN 1469-9613 online/04/030241-12 © 2004 Taylor & Francis Ltd
DOI: 10.1080/1356931042000263500
MARGARET CANOVAN
IV. Issues raised by the meanings and ambiguities of populism’s core concept,
‘the People’.
I. Methodological issues
What is ‘populism’? Do the various political phenomena labelled in this way add
up to a distinctive general something? What sort of thing are we talking about,
with what kinds of features?
The ‘populism’ that is most likely to be in the news today is the so-called
‘New Populism’ of the past decade or so: a collection of movements, broadly on
the right of the political spectrum, that have emerged in many established liberal
democracies, challenging existing parties and mainstream policies.3 As political
phenomena go, ‘New Populism’ may seem relatively easy to identify and
characterise (although, as we shall see later, it raises interesting issues about the
relationship between populist and democratic appeals to ‘the people’). Typically
confrontational in style, these movements claim to represent the rightful source
of legitimate power—the people, whose interests and wishes have been ignored
by self-interested politicians and politically correct intellectuals. These chal-
lengers do not in general call themselves ‘populists’, and despite some links they
have not so far seen themselves as branches of an international ideological
movement, but although there are many differences between their policy pre-
scriptions, they do share a distinctive style and message. Cases generally
recognised as falling into this category, despite many differences, include Ross
Perot’s 1992 Presidential campaign in the USA, Pauline Hanson’s One Nation
Party in Australia, and Preston Manning’s Reform Party in Canada. Of the many
European cases, the most long-lasting is Jean Marie Le Pen’s Front National in
France; other particularly conspicuous examples include Jörg Haider’s Freedom
Party in Austria; Umberto Bossi’s Northern League in Italy, and the brief
eruption in the Netherlands of the movement led by Pim Fortuyn. Fortuyn’s
assassination just before the Dutch general election in 2002 dramatically illus-
trated one of the typical features of these New Populist movements, their
overwhelming dependence on personal leadership rather than institutional party
structures.
Claiming to speak for the forgotten mass of ordinary people, New Populists
take on the colour of their surroundings.4 The positions they campaign for and
the values they express depend on local concerns and the kind of political
establishment they are challenging. Invariably critical of professional politicians
and the media, they claim to say aloud what the people think, especially if it has
been deemed by the elite to be unmentionable. New Populists often call for
issues of popular concern to be decided by referendum, by-passing professional
politicians and leaving decisions to the people. By way of emphasising their
closeness to the grassroots and their distance from the political establishment,
they also tend to use colourful and undiplomatic language. They are most
comfortable in opposition, though some have had enough electoral success to
find themselves sharing power. The strength of the populist challenge to
242
POPULISM FOR POLITICAL THEORISTS?
243
MARGARET CANOVAN
244
POPULISM FOR POLITICAL THEORISTS?
245
MARGARET CANOVAN
progressive liberation. They are all universalistic, promising that in the long run
everyone is going to be liberated and made better off; but because they are
progressive, someone or other has to be in the vanguard, showing the way to the
rest.
This vanguardist way of thinking is so familiar that we rarely notice it: not
only is it built into liberalism, socialism and feminism, it is present even in
modern conservatism, as in the ‘trickle-down’ theory of economic growth. And
yet belief in progress is very hard to reconcile with equal respect for all human
beings. It has the inescapable effect of giving a privileged status to the advanced,
thereby devaluing the opinions, beliefs and way of life of the mass of mankind.
This is true even of the most egalitarian forms of liberalism and socialism; there
is always a vanguard further up the escalator of progress, whereas most people
are to be simply the recipients of liberation, education, welfare, Westernisation
and so on. The version of liberal imperialism favoured by our present leaders is
a striking example, but even the anti-growth, anti-globalisation agitators are not
exempt.
We are so used to thinking in these terms that it is quite hard to imagine
questioning them, and yet we need only recall the history of the twentieth
century to see that it is not absurd to have doubts about vanguardism. We could
all draw up a list of projects that seemed obviously ‘progressive’ at the time, and
that were imposed by vanguards on the population. There was Soviet collectivi-
sation, for instance—recall Sidney and Beatrice Webb coming back from Russia
in the 1930s and saying, ‘We have seen the future, and it works’. Eugenics was
supported by all ‘progressive’ opinion in the 1920s and 1930s; nuclear power
was the wave of the future and the answer to all our energy problems; rehousing
people in tower blocks seemed a good idea at the time. So it might be worth
considering alternative ways of thinking, including a populist mind-set.
An anti-vanguardist populism can be conceived in a number of different ways.
One of them might provide a rationale for direct democracy, in Ian Budge’s
sense of continual electronic referendums,18 but there are other directions in
which one might go. There is for example the version of anti-vanguardist
populism explored in the 1990s in the American journal Telos, which denounces
top–down rule by a supposedly enlightened ‘New Class’ of intellectuals and
bureaucrats, and proposes devolution of power to local communities, whether or
not they choose to run themselves in ways that are politically correct.19
A more far-reaching version was suggested in the early twentieth century by
G. K. Chesterton.20 The intriguing thing about it is that in attacking belief in
progress and vanguardism it also questions the assumption that the latest
generation are the most ‘advanced’ and that we can ignore older arrangements
and convictions. It casts doubt therefore on the sovereignty of those people who
are in power now, even if they happen to have majority support at present. For
Chesterton, a decent respect for the opinions of mankind means that we cannot
write off previous experience, as modernists habitually do: we have to pay
serious attention to tradition. ‘Tradition’ may sound like the slogan of Burkean
246
POPULISM FOR POLITICAL THEORISTS?
The implication of this populist way of thinking is that instead of assuming that
the latest way of doing things must be the best, long-standing popular customs
and traditions need to be taken seriously.
The occupational hazard of intellectuals who do pay attention to populist ideas
is that they are inclined to make fools of themselves idealising ‘the People’, like
the Russian Narodniks in the 1870s who ‘went to the people’, expecting to find
ideal community and revolutionary fervour. Despite this danger, the nexus of
populism with scepticism about progress and vanguardism may be worth
thinking about. For one thing, it has affinities with the issues that arise in trying
to spread liberal democracy to non-Western countries, especially those with
deep-rooted popular religion, above all Islam. Perhaps we need to consider what
it would actually mean to pay decent respect to the opinions of mankind.
What the outcome of such reflections might be is hard to say; for the present,
I simply raise the issue and leave it hanging in the air as I go on to a fourth and
last aspect of populism that should interest political theorists: populism’s central
concept, ‘the people’.
247
MARGARET CANOVAN
sovereign; peoples as nations, and the ‘common people’ as opposed to the ruling
elite. Uniquely, however (as far as I know) ‘people’ in English also means
human beings as such, individuals in general. Although this use of the term is
grammatically distinct, its meaning seeps into and colours the other uses, and
that introduces two extra elements of political ambiguity. It makes the sovereign
people look like a collection of individuals as well as a collective body, and it
implies that ‘people’ and their rights are universal, crossing the boundaries that
confine particular ‘peoples’.
That extra dimension of Anglophone ambiguity is connected with a second
feature that comes to light once one maps the meanings of ‘people’. Those
ambiguities turn out to be the key to important and neglected issues for
democratic politics in particular. For the various political struggles that have
stretched and shaped ‘people’ to accommodate different political identities have
also made it the repository of a series of unresolved political problems that are
half-articulated and half-concealed by the term’s contradictions. The central
problem (to which all the others are connected) has to do with the collective
authorisation by the sovereign people from which governments derive their
legitimacy.
This is a notion that is boringly familiar but at the same time problematic in
all sorts of ways. For convenience’s sake one can divide up the problems it poses
into two pairs of issues, the first two concerned with boundary issues and the
others with issues of authority.24
248
POPULISM FOR POLITICAL THEORISTS?
249
MARGARET CANOVAN
250
POPULISM FOR POLITICAL THEORISTS?
251
MARGARET CANOVAN
252