Chicago Unbound Values and Consequences
Chicago Unbound Values and Consequences
Chicago Unbound Values and Consequences
Chicago Unbound
Coase-Sandor Working Paper Series in Law and
Coase-Sandor Institute for Law and Economics
Economics
1998
Recommended Citation
Richard A. Posner, "Values and Consequences: An Introduction to Economic Analysis of Law" (Coase-Sandor Institute for Law &
Economics Working Paper No. 53, 1998).
This Working Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Coase-Sandor Institute for Law and Economics at Chicago Unbound. It has been
accepted for inclusion in Coase-Sandor Working Paper Series in Law and Economics by an authorized administrator of Chicago Unbound. For more
information, please contact [email protected].
CHICAGO
JOHN M. OLIN LAW & ECONOMICS WORKING PAPER NO. 53
(2D SERIES)
Richard A. Posner
Richard A. Posner1*
I am going to give a very brief, thumbnail sketch of economic analysis of law, and
then focus on just two uses of the analysis, and in doing so try to give you a bit of its
flavor. The first use is to make law simpler to understand and evaluate; and the second is
to press you to defend your values.
That there is a relation between economics and law has been known for an awfully
long time, at least since Hobbes’s discussion of property in the seventeenth century. But
until very recently, the relation received focused attention only in relation to a handful of
legal fields, mainly antitrust and public utility regulation, that dealt explicitly with
competition and monopoly, which as early as the 1930s were receiving the sustained and
sophisticated attention of leading English and American economists. (Competition and
monopoly had received the attention of economists since Adam Smith; hence the
qualification “sustained and sophisticated.”)
In retrospect, an economic literature dealing with other fields of law, notably Robert
Hale’s work on contract law, which also dates from the 1930s, can be identified. But even
after the Journal of Law and Economics commenced publication—at this law school,
naturally—in 1958, the “law and economics” movement, if discernible at all, would have
been associated primarily with problems of competition and monopoly, although
occasional forays had been made into taxation (Henry Simons) and corporations (Henry
Manne), even patents (Arnold Plant), and if one went back to the eighteenth century there
was Bentham’s largely forgotten utilitarian—essentially, economic—analysis of crime
and punishment. It was not until 1961, when Ronald Coase’s article “The Problem of
Social Cost” was published,2 and at about the same time Guido Calabresi’s first article on
torts,3 that an economic theory of the common law could be glimpsed. When Gary
Becker published his article “Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach,”4 reviving
and refining Bentham, it began to seem that perhaps no field of law could not be placed
under the lens of economics with illuminating results. And within a few years, sure
enough, papers on the economics of contract law, civil and criminal procedure, property,
1* Chief Judge, United States Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit; Senior Lecturer, University of
Chicago Law School. This is the text of a Coase Lecture given at the University of Chicago Law School on
January 6, 1998.
2 3 Journal of Law and Economics 1 (1960 [but actually published in 1961]).
3 Guido Calabresi, “Some Thoughts on Risk Distribution and the Law of Torts,” 70 Yale Law Journal 499
(1961).
4 76 Journal of Political Economy 169 (1968).
5 Remarks of Anthony T. Kronman, The Second Driker Forum for Excellence in the Law, 42 Wayne Law
Review 115, 160 (1995).
University of Chicago Law School, Program in Law and Economics Working Paper 53 2
however. The essence is extremely simple, although the simplicity is deceptive; the
simple can be subtle, can be counterintuitive; its antithesis is “complicated,” not
“difficult.”
Most economic analysis consists of tracing out the consequences of assuming that
people are more or less rational in their social interactions. In the case of the activities
that interest the law, these people may be criminals or prosecutors or parties to accidents
or taxpayers or tax collectors or striking workers—or even law students. Students treat
grades as prices, so that unless the university administration intervenes, unpopular
professors, in order to keep up their enrollments, will sometimes compensate students for
the low perceived value of the course by giving them higher grades, that is, by raising the
price that the professor pays for the student.
I said that the tracing out of consequences is subtle as well as simple, and here is an
example. Have you heard of the spendthrift trust? That is a trust, very common, indeed
standard, in which the trustee is forbidden to pay out any of the money or other property
in the trust to the creditors of the trust’s beneficiaries. The law will enforce such a
restriction, yet it has seemed to many students of the law a fraud on creditors; for the trust
beneficiary, assuming that his whole wealth is in the spendthrift trust, can borrow all he
wants, spend what he borrows, and not be forced to repay the lenders. But if you think
about this for a moment, you’ll be driven to the opposite conclusion—that, provided the
provision preventing creditors from reaching into the trust is not concealed, a spendthrift
trust limits borrowing by the trust beneficiary, because he can’t offer security to the
lender. And the next step in the analysis is to see how increasing the rights of debtors in
bankruptcy, far from causing an avalanche of reckless borrowing, could reduce the
amount of borrowing, and so the incidence of bankruptcy, by causing lenders to make
smaller loans to risky borrowers. So lenders may oppose easy bankruptcy not because
they fear there will be more defaults, but because they fear a reduction in the volume of
loans. To see this, imagine how many, or rather how few, loans there would be if
borrowers had no obligation to repay. Notice also how creditors are as hurt by
excessively stringent as by excessively lenient bankruptcy rules: if creditors had the legal
right, as under ancient Roman law, to carve up a defaulting borrower into as many pieces
as there were creditors, most people would be afraid to borrow. Can you see now why
loan sharks in Chicago break the legs of defaulting borrowers, but do not kill them?
Rationality implies decision making, and people often have to make decisions under
conditions of profound uncertainty; fortunately, economists have devoted a good deal of
attention to decision under uncertainty. A simple but important example of a law-related
decision under uncertainty is the decision as to how much care to take to avoid an
accident. The accident will occur with probability P, and let us assume that if it does
occur it will impose a cost that I’ll call L, for loss; and assume further that eliminating the
possibility of such an accident would impose on the potential injurer a cost, which I’ll
call B (for burden). Then it is easily seen that the cost of avoiding the accident will be
6 United States v. Carroll Towing Co., 159 F.2d 169 (2d Cir. 1947).
7 Richard A. Posner, Economic Analysis of Law (5th ed. 1998).
8 Dr. Miles Medical Co. v. John D. Park & Sons Co., 220 U.S. 373 (1911).
University of Chicago Law School, Program in Law and Economics Working Paper 53 4
make money if they could sell more, they will compete in nonprice dimensions of
competition, such as stocking more inventory or having better-informed salespeople. If
these services are important to the manufacturer’s marketing strategy, he can use resale
price maintenance to evoke them. For by setting the minimum resale price above the
dealer’s barebones cost of sale, dealers will vie to get additional sales by offering
customers more service, until eventually they bid away the profit built into the minimum
resale price, which is just what the manufacturer wants.
A dealers’ cartel would have this effect too; members of the cartel, each of whom
would like to increase his sales at the cartel price because it’s above cost, will try to
attract customers away from other dealers by offering better service. The difference is
that the dealer may be providing more service than the customer wants, in the sense that
the customer might prefer a lower price with less service. If that is what the customer
prefers,9 the supplier, if he is doing the price-fixing, will give it to him; for otherwise the
supplier will lose business and profits to a competitor. But if the customers want a lower
price and less service, competition will force the supplier to give them that, provided the
dealers aren’t allowed to collude.
I now skip to what may seem an unrelated topic. Critics of the deregulation of the
airline industry have pointed out that airline service is in some respects inferior to what it
was in the days when it was a regulated industry. Planes are more crowded, there is less
legroom, and the food is poorer. Gone are the piano bars from American Airlines’ 747s.
This is what economics predicted. The regulated airline industry was a government
enforced cartel. Prices were kept high and as a result the industry was deflected into
nonprice competition. When the airlines had finally competed away all their cartel profits
in the form of service competition, the industry was ripe for deregulation. And when it
was finally deregulated, price fell and with it the level of service, because this was what
the consuming public wanted, as we can infer from the enormous growth in air travel
since deregulation.
So we see, and this is the point of the discussion, that resale price maintenance of
patent medicines and the deregulation of airline transportation raise the same economic
issue, that of the relation between price and nonprice competition, even though one
involves goods and the other services, one is old and one is recent, and one involves the
judicial interpretation of the antitrust laws and the other legislative reform of common
carrier regulation. And this is the sort of thing we encounter all the time in the economic
analysis of law. Practices, institutions, bodies of law that seem wholly disparate from the
standpoint of orthodox legal analysis are seen to involve the identical economic issue.
Whole fields of law are interchangeable when viewed through the lens of economics.
When I was a law student, the law seemed an assemblage of completely unrelated rules,
9 More precisely, the marginal customer, but I will not pursue that refinement. See Posner, note 3 above, at
321.
University of Chicago Law School, Program in Law and Economics Working Paper 53 6
Sandel’s attempt to distinguish the practices reveals an ignorance of basic economic
principles. To begin with, he points out that compared to Dr. Hicks’s “homespun
enterprise, commercial surrogacy, a $40 million industry, is big business.” But Sandel is
comparing one seller in a market to an entire market, and moreover one seller in an
illegal market, where sellers conceal themselves, to an entire legal market. With more
than a million abortions a year, the potential for “baby selling,” if legalized, to eclipse
commercial surrogacy is manifest.
Sandel’s principal ground of distinction between baby selling and surrogate
motherhood is different; it is that commercial surrogacy, unlike what Dr. Hicks did,
encourages what Sandel, using a Marxist term, calls commodification, but which just
means commercialization. “Dr. Hicks’s black market in babies responded to a problem
that arose independent of market considerations. He did not encourage the unwed
mothers whose babies he sold to become pregnant in the first place.” He did not have to.
Demand evokes supply. Women who knew there was a market for their baby if they did
not want to keep it would tend to use less care to avoid becoming pregnant. No doubt
fewer women knew there was a market than would if it were a legal market rather than a
black market. But Sandel does not suggest that Dr. Hicks’s practice is redeemed by
having been illegal!
I do not suggest that on the basis of my economic analysis those of you who are
opposed to surrogate motherhood should give up your opposition. I don’t believe that
economics (or any other body of thought, for that matter) can compel a moral judgment.
But those of you who are opposed to surrogate motherhood may feel pressed by my
analysis to reconsider your opposition. Maybe you agree with Sandel that what Dr. Hicks
did was not immoral even though it was illegal, and maybe you agree with me that
Sandel has committed an economic error in thinking that what Hicks did was different
from what the commercial surrogacy industry is doing and that it makes a difference that
he was just one person and the commercial surrogacy industry consists of a number of
persons.
Here is a different and (though I promised you simplicity) somewhat more complex
example.13 The federal pension law, ERISA, provides that if an employer establishes a
defined-benefits pension plan—he doesn’t have to establish any pension plan, let alone a
defined-benefits plan, but if he does—it has to provide for the vesting of the employee’s
rights under the plan after five years. The purpose is to correct an abuse consisting of
establishing a nonvesting pension plan and then firing an employee on the eve of his
retirement.
The economist asked to evaluate this provision in ERISA would want to consider
first how common this nonvesting scam would be in the absence of the law and whether
forbidding it might have bad effects, in particular on the intended beneficiaries, the
University of Chicago Law School, Program in Law and Economics Working Paper 53 8
check by his concern with preserving a reputation for fair dealing (if he lost that, he
would have to pay new employees higher wages) and by the bargaining power that the
possession of firm-specific human capital confers on a worker. (If he quit in anger or
disgust, or was fired to eliminate his pension benefits, the firm would have to invest in
training a green employee to replace him.) In fact, as I have said, before ERISA
opportunistic discharges of workers covered by a pension plan were rare; and the statute
has had no detectable impact on discharges of covered workers.
But by limiting incomplete vesting, the Act has tended to reduce the control of
employers over their older employees. Such a loss of control would be expected to have
two bad effects on the employees themselves. The first would be to lead employers to
invest less in the employees’ firm-specific human capital, and so the employee’s
productivity and hence wage will be lower. Second, because employers would have a
smaller investment in the employees to protect and the employees would have less
incentive to perform well (not being faced with a substantial loss of pension benefits if
they were fired), employers would be expected to resort more frequently to an explicit or
implicit threat of discharge in order to maintain discipline. And third, anything, legal or
otherwise, that adds to the cost of employing a worker will cause employers to employ
fewer workers or to pay them lower wages or both.
Even if you agree with my economic analysis, you may feel that on balance it is
more important for workers to have secure pension rights or greater autonomy from their
employers. But, once again, you will be forced to ask yourself whether your feeling is
strong enough to offset the consequences brought out by economic analysis, including
adverse consequences on the workers themselves, in the form of lower wages—or even,
ironically, less secure employment.
I’ve given two examples of what might be called the “conservative” bias of
economics. But actually economics is pretty value-neutral, or at least aspires to be value
neutral, and there are many liberal practitioners of economic analysis of law, such as
Guido Calabresi of Yale and now of the Second Circuit and John Donohue of Stanford.
And so I’ll close with an example of how economics can throw some cold water on a
policy that conservatives favor.14 Consider statutes that empower the government to
designate a building’s façade as a landmark; upon designation, the owner cannot alter the
façade. An alternative to designation would be the purchase (possibly backed up by the
threat of condemnation, subject to payment of just compensation) by the government of
an easement in the façade. This is favored by most conservatives. They believe that the
government should not be permitted to get things for nothing and in the process impose
heavy costs on the owners of property. And so they urge that the principle of just
compensation be given maximum play. They would be inclined to argue, these
conservatives, that landmark-preservation statutes lead the government to designate too
14 The discussion that follows is based on id. at 66–67; Daniel A. Farber, “Economic Analysis and Just
Compensation,” 12 International Review of Law and Economics 125, 131–132 (1992).
University of Chicago Law School, Program in Law and Economics Working Paper 53 10
adverse or at least costly, of acts or practices that we might otherwise think clearly good
or clearly bad.
Richard A. Posner
Senior Lecturer
The Law School
The University of Chicago
1111 E. 60th Street
Chicago, IL 60637
University of Chicago Law School, Program in Law and Economics Working Paper 53 12
29. Daniel Shaviro, Budget Deficits and the Intergenerational Distribution of Lifetime
Consumption (January 1995).
30. Douglas G. Baird, The Law and Economics of Contract Damages (February 1995).
31. Daniel Kessler, Thomas Meites, and Geoffrey P. Miller, Explaining Deviations from
the Fifty Percent Rule: A Multimodal Approach to the Selection of Cases for
Litigation (March 1995).
32. Geoffrey P. Miller, Das Kapital: Solvency Regulation of the American Business
Enterprise (April 1995).
33. Richard Craswell, Freedom of Contract (August 1995).
34. J. Mark Ramseyer, Public Choice (November 1995).
35. Kenneth W. Dam, Intellectual Property in an Age of Software and Biotechnology
(November 1995).
36. Cass R. Sunstein, Social Norms and Social Roles (January 1996).
37. J. Mark Ramseyer and Eric B. Rasmusen, Judicial Independence in Civil Law
Regimes: Econometrics from Japan (January 1996).
38. Richard A. Epstein, Transaction Costs and Property Rights: Or Do Good Fences
Make Good Neighbors? (March 1996).
39. Cass R. Sunstein, The Cost-Benefit State (May 1996).
40. William M. Landes and Richard A. Posner, The Economics of Legal Disputes Over
the Ownership of Works of Art and Other Collectibles (July 1996).
41. John R. Lott, Jr. and David B. Mustard, Crime, Deterrence, and Right-to-Carry
Concealed Handguns (August 1996).
42. Cass R. Sunstein, Health-Health Tradeoffs (September 1996).
43. Douglas G. Baird, The Hidden Virtues of Chapter 11: An Overview of the la and
Economics of Financially Distressed Firms (March 1997).
44. Richard A. Posner, Community, Wealth, and Equality (March 1997).
45. William M. Landes, The Art of Law and Economics: An Autobiographical Essay
(March 1997).
46. Cass R. Sunstein, Behavioral Analysis of Law (April 1997).
47. John R. Lott, Jr. and Kermit Daniel, Term Limits and Electoral Competitiveness:
Evidence from California’s State Legislative Races (May 1997).
48. Randal C. Picker, Simple Games in a Complex World: A Generative Approach to
the Adoption of Norms (June 1997).
49. Richard A. Epstein, Contracts Small and Contracts Large: Contract Law through the
Lens of Laissez-Faire (August 1997).
50. Cass R. Sunstein, Daniel Kahneman, and David Schkade, Assessing Punitive
Damages (with Notes on Cognition and Valuation in Law) (December 1997)
51. William M. Landes, Lawrence Lessig, and Michael E. Solimine, Judicial Influence:
A Citation Analysis of Federal Courts of Appeals Judges (January 1998)
52. John R. Lott, Jr., A Simple Explanation for Why Campaign Expenditures are
Increasing: The Government is Getting Bigger (February 1998)
53. Richard A. Posner, Values and Consequences: An Introduction to Economic
Analysis of Law (March 1998)