Charter Conflicts What Is Parliaments Role PDF
Charter Conflicts What Is Parliaments Role PDF
Charter Conflicts What Is Parliaments Role PDF
net/publication/31271537
CITATIONS READS
2 50
1 author:
Mark Tushnet
Harvard University
199 PUBLICATIONS 1,529 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:
All content following this page was uploaded by Mark Tushnet on 09 April 2016.
5
As a textual matter, “demonstrably justified” certainly does invite conversations about justifica-
tions for limitations on rights. As Hiebert points out, § 1 of the Charter invites Parliament to
respond to a judicial determination that a particular statute violates the Charter by coming up
with additional factual material “demonstrating” that the limitation is justified.
6
Canada’s Supreme Court is a general high court, not a specialized constitutional court. Its nine
members are appointed by the Prime Minister, with three required to come from the province of
Québec.
7
See JANET HIEBERT, CHARTER CONFLICTS: WHAT IS A PARLIAMENT’S ROLE? 218 (McGill-Queen’s University
Press 2002).
8
See HIEBERT, supra note 7, at 8.
9
See id. at 50. (discussing Hiebert’s preference for the metaphor of conversation rather than the
more common one of dialogue, because she believes that the term conversation connotes a more
fluid and less structured interaction than does the term dialogue. See also Peter W. Hogg & Allison
A. Bushell, The Charter Dialogue Between the Courts and Legislatures (Or Perhaps the Charter of Rights
Isn’t Such a Bad Thing After All), 35 OSGOODE HALL L.J. 75 (1997). I would note, as well, that the cel-
ebrated Hogg–Bushell analysis of what they call the dialogue between court and Parliament seems
to me to show a rather high level of monologue (or the kind of Socratic dialogue Plato gives us,
with one side saying everything important and the other nodding in agreement).
736 BOOK REVIEWS
10
See HIEBERT supra note 7, at 53.
11
Hiebert notes that this model is promoted by the “notwithstanding” clause and the general
limitations clause. That seems right as to the limitations clause, but the terms of § 33 of the
Charter seem to me more problematic. Its words appear to require Parliament to acknowledge that
its legislation does violate Charter rights but wishes it to go into effect anyway.
12
See HIEBERT supra note 7, at 220.
13
See id. at 55.
14
See id. at 70–71.
15
See id. at 95.
BOOK REVIEWS 737
16
See id. at 7–8 (noting that getting accurate and detailed information is difficult).
17
See id. at 8.
18
See id. at Ch. 7.
19
See id. at 119.
20
Obviously, the degree to which such a political culture permeates the political branches will vary
from nation to nation (and, within any nation, from time to time). Hiebert’s analysis weighs
against strong versions of cynicism, and perhaps might shift the burden on to the cynics to show
that, in the political cultures they are dealing with, cynicism is justified.
21
See HIEBERT supra note 7, at 12.
738 BOOK REVIEWS
But, Hiebert argues, the Canadian political culture in the executive bureau-
cracy has taken risk assessment too far. A narrow concern is that, where
constitutional doctrine is unsettled, risk assessment may become risk aversion
as policy makers view the Charter “through the lens of Justice lawyers.”22
rather than through a better set of more policy-oriented lenses. More broadly,
risk assessment embeds the courts’ perspective on the Charter deep in the
bureaucracy rather than operating as a limit on what statutes should be
pushed forward. Hiebert observes that the conversation she envisions will be
most productive if Parliament understands that its role is to articulate its own
understanding of the rights the Charter protects. After all, the Charter—as do
nearly all constitutions with regard to the most important human
rights—identifies the rights it protects on a rather high level of abstraction.
Scholars of constitutional law have devoted a great deal of attention to the
problems courts face in specifying what those rights actually are in particular
contexts. Hiebert notes, modestly but importantly, that the same problem of
specification arises at the legislative level. And, she suggests, judicial consider-
ation of the specification question would be improved if it were informed by the
legislature’s independent analysis of that question.
Hiebert makes the argument in her case studies that Parliament has a
mistaken understanding of its role in this context. The legislature’s response to
a judicial decision invalidating a comprehensive program of regulating
tobacco advertising, Hiebert says, “demonstrates how judicial review of rights
claims can undermine political will to exercise independent judgment about
how best to pursue a course of action deemed to be in the public interest, even
when the rights claim is far removed from the philosophical purposes of
protecting rights from state actions.”23 Parliament responded to the Court’s
action by adjusting its legislation to fit precisely within the contours the Court
had identified, even though doing so substantially impaired the accomplish-
ment of the goals Parliament initially thought important. It may be worth not-
ing, as well, that the problem of regulating tobacco advertising was difficult
politically in the first place; even a slight disruption of the equilibrium struck
in the enacted legislation could produce a deadlock in response.24
Hiebert’s discussion of Canada’s gay rights cases comes down on the courts’
side, influencing her overall assessment of the “dynamic role the Charter
performs in changing the assumptions and expectations of the polity.”25 The
Charter, she continues, “is influencing assumptions about the judiciary’s role
22
See id. at 142.
23
See id. at 73.
24
A more cynical view is that Parliament may have enacted the regulations knowing that they
were likely to be invalidated, counting on scoring points with the public for trying to do something,
and on not losing points with the tobacco industry for actually doing something.
25
See HIEBERT supra note 7, at 201.
BOOK REVIEWS 739
26
See id.
27
See id. at 219.
28
For the United States, my sense is that the executive branch has a reasonably good system, oper-
ated by the Office of Legal Counsel in the Department of Justice, and that neither house of
Congress has anything approaching that system in scope or quality.
740 BOOK REVIEWS
29
One possibility is that such evaluation is better in parliamentary systems when the government
relaxes party discipline and allows a free vote. If that is correct, the inquiry is pushed back to the
next level, where one would seek to identify the conditions under which governments allow free
votes.
30
Again, time may be less important for the executive ministries in parliamentary systems,
because they have a great deal of control over when legislation is introduced, giving them the time
beforehand in which to do the constitutional evaluation.
31
Recent scholarship on the creation and maintenance of constitutional courts has focused on
whether there is a dominant political party or coalition, or, instead, a party system in which par-
tisan control of the legislature is believed by all to be likely to change periodically. See generally TOM
GINSBURG, JUDICIAL REVIEW IN NEW DEMOCRACIES: CONSTITUTIONAL CASES IN ASIAN COURTS (Cambridge
University Press 2003): RAN HIRSCHL, TOWARDS JURISTOCRACY: THE ORIGINS AND CONSEQUENCES OF THE
NEW CONSTITUTIONALISM (Harvard University Press 2004); Matthew C. Stephenson, “When the Devil
BOOK REVIEWS 741
Turns . . .”: The Political Foundations of Independent Judicial Review, 32 J. LEGAL STUD. 59 (2003).
Perhaps some similar mechanism might be at work conducing legislatures to adopt the appropri-
ate long-term perspective required for independent legislative constitutional evaluation.