Ethics of Confucius
Ethics of Confucius
Ethics of Confucius
It was whilst he was teaching in his school that Confucius started to write. Two collections of
poetry were the Book of Odes (Shijing or Shi king) and the Book of Documents (Shujing or Shu
king). The Spring and Autumn Annals (Lin Jing or Lin King), which told the history of Lu, and
the Book of Changes ( Yi Jing or Yi king) was a collection of treatises on divination.
Unfortunately for posterity, none of these works outlined Confucius’ philosophy. Confucianism,
therefore, had to be created from second-hand accounts and the most reliable documentation of
the ideas of Confucius is considered to be the Analects although even here there is no absolute
evidence that the sayings and short stories were actually said by him and often the lack of
context and clarity leave many of his teachings open to individual interpretation. The other three
major sources of Confucian thought are Mencius, Great Learning and Mean. With Analects,
these works constitute the Four Books of Confucianism otherwise referred to as the Confucian
Classics. Through these texts, Confucianism became the official state religion of China from the
second century BCE.
Confucianism
Chinese philosophy, and particularly Confucianism, has always been concerned with practical
questions of morality and ethics. How should man live in order to master his environment,
provide suitable government and achieve moral harmony? Central to Confucianism is that the
moral harmony of the individual is directly related to cosmic harmony; what one does, affects the
other. For example, poor political decisions can lead to natural disasters such as floods. An
example of the direct correlation between the physical and the moral is evidenced in the saying,
‘Heaven does not have two suns and the people do not have two kings’. A consequence of this
idea is that, just as there is only one cosmic environment, there is only one true way to live and
only one correct political system.
If society fails it is because sacred texts and teachings have been misinterpreted; the texts
themselves contain the Way but we must search for and find it.
Another important facet of Confucius’ ideas was that teachers, and especially rulers, must lead
by example. They must be benevolent in order to win the affections and respect of the populace
and not do so by force, which is futile. They should also be models of frugality and high moral
upstanding. For this reason, Chinese education has often favoured the cultivation of moral
sensibilities rather than specific intellectual skills.
Further, under Confucian influence, Chinese politics principally focussed on the intimacy of
relationships rather than institutions.
Confucius' teachings and his conversations and exchanges with his disciples are recorded in
the Lunyu or Analects, a collection that probably achieved something like its present form around
the second century BCE. While Confucius believes that people live their lives within parameters
firmly established by Heaven—which, often, for him means both a purposeful Supreme Being as
well as ‘nature’ and its fixed cycles and patterns—he argues that men are responsible for their
actions and especially for their treatment of others. We can do little or nothing to alter our fated
span of existence but we determine what we accomplish and what we are remembered for.
Confucius represented his teachings as lessons transmitted from antiquity. He claimed that he
was “a transmitter and not a maker” and that all he did reflected his “reliance on and love for the
ancients” (Lunyu 7.1). Confucius pointed especially to the precedents established during the
height of the royal Zhou (roughly the first half of the first millennium BCE). Such justifications
for one's ideas may have already been conventional in Confucius' day. Certainly his claim that
there were antique precedents for his ideology had a tremendous influence on subsequent
thinkers many of whom imitated these gestures. But we should not regard the contents of
the Analects as consisting of old ideas. Much of what Confucius taught appears to have been
original to him and to have represented a radical departure from the ideas and practices of his
day.
Confucius also claimed that he enjoyed a special and privileged relationship with Heaven and
that, by the age of fifty, he had come to understand what Heaven had mandated for him and for
mankind. (Lunyu 2.4). Confucius was also careful to instruct his followers that they should never
neglect the offerings due Heaven. (Lunyu 3.13) Some scholars have seen a contradiction between
Confucius' reverence for Heaven and what they believe to be his skepticism with regard to the
existence of ‘the spirits.’
But the Analects passages that reveal Confucius' attitudes toward spiritual forces (Lunyu 3.12,
6.20, and 11.11) do not suggest that he was skeptical. Rather they show that Confucius revered
and respected the spirits, thought that they should be worshipped with utmost sincerity, and
taught that serving the spirits was a far more difficult and complicated matter than serving mere
mortals.
Confucius' social philosophy largely revolves around the concept of ren, “compassion” or
“loving others.” Cultivating or practicing such concern for others involved deprecating oneself.
This meant being sure to avoid artful speech or an ingratiating manner that would create a false
impression and lead to self-aggrandizement. (Lunyu 1.3) Those who have cultivated ren are, on
the contrary, “simple in manner and slow of speech” (Lunyu 13.27). For Confucius, such concern
for others is demonstrated through the practice of forms of the Golden Rule: “What you do not
wish for yourself, do not do to others;” “Since you yourself desire standing then help others
achieve it, since you yourself desire success then help others attain it” (Lunyu 12.2, 6.30). He
regards devotion to parents and older siblings as the most basic form of promoting the interests
of others before one's own. Central to all ethical teachings found in the Analects of Confucius is
the notion that the social arena in which the tools for creating and maintaining harmonious
relations are fashioned and employed is the extended family. Among the various ways in which
social divisions could have been drawn, the most important were the vertical lines that bound
multigenerational lineages.
And the most fundamental lessons to be learned by individuals within a lineage were what role
their generational position had imposed on them and what obligations toward those senior or
junior to them were associated with those roles. In the world of the Analects, the dynamics of
social exchange and obligation primarily involved movement up and down along familial roles
that were defined in terms of how they related to others within the same lineage. It was also
necessary that one play roles within other social constructs—neighborhood, community, political
bureaucracy, guild, school of thought—that brought one into contact with a larger network of
acquaintances and created ethical issues that went beyond those that impacted one's family. But
the extended family was at the center of these other hierarchies and could be regarded as a
microcosm of their workings. One who behaved morally in all possible parallel structures
extending outward from the family probably approximated Confucius's conception of ren.
It is useful to contrast this conception of ren and the social arena in which it worked with the
idea of jian ai or “impartial love” advocated by the Mohists who as early as the fifth century
BCE posed the greatest intellectual challenge to Confucius' thought. The Mohists shared with
Confucius and his followers the goal of bringing about effective governance and a stable society,
but they constructed their ethical system, not on the basis of social roles, but rather on the self or,
to be more precise, the physical self that has cravings, needs, and ambitions. For the Mohists, the
individual's love for his physical self is the basis on which all moral systems had to be built. The
Confucian emphasis on social role rather than on the self seems to involve, in comparison to the
Mohist position, an exaggerated emphasis on social status and position and an excessive form of
self-centeredness. While the Mohist love of self is also of course a form of self-interest, what
distinguishes it from the Confucian position is that the Mohists regard self-love as a necessary
means to an end, not the end in itself, which the Confucian pride of position and place appears to
be. The Mohist program called for a process by which self-love was replaced by, or transformed
into, impartial love—the unselfish and altruistic concern for others that would, in their
reckoning, lead to an improved world untroubled by wars between states, conflict in
communities, and strife within families.
To adopt impartial love would be to ignore the barriers that privilege the self, one's family, and
one's state and that separate them from other individuals, families, and states. In this argument,
self-love is a fact that informs the cultivation of concern for those within one's own silo; it is also
the basis for interacting laterally with those to whom one is not related, a large cohort that is not
adequately taken into account in the Confucian scheme of ethical obligation.
Confucius taught that the practice of altruism he thought necessary for social cohesion could be
mastered only by those who have learned self-discipline. Learning self-restraint involves
studying and mastering li, the ritual forms and rules of propriety through which one expresses
respect for superiors and enacts his role in society in such a way that he himself is worthy of
respect and admiration. A concern for propriety should inform everything that one says and does:
Look at nothing in defiance of ritual, listen to nothing in defiance of ritual, speak of nothing in
defiance or ritual, never stir hand or foot in defiance of ritual. (Lunyu 12.1)
Subjecting oneself to ritual does not, however, mean suppressing one's desires but instead
learning how to reconcile one's own desires with the needs of one's family and community.
Confucius and many of his followers teach that it is by experiencing desires that we learn the
value of social strictures that make an ordered society possible (See Lunyu 2.4.). And at least for
Confucius' follower Zi Xia, renowned in the later tradition for his knowledge of the Book of
Songs, one's natural desires for sex and other physical pleasures were a foundation for cultivating
a passion for worthiness and other lofty ideals (Lunyu 1.7).[21]
Confucius' emphasis on ritual does not mean that he was a punctilious ceremonialist who thought
that the rites of worship and of social exchange had to be practiced correctly at all costs.
Confucius taught, on the contrary, that if one did not possess a keen sense of the well-being and
interests of others his ceremonial manners signified nothing. (Lunyu 3.3) Equally important was
Confucius' insistence that the rites not be regarded as mere forms, but that they be practiced with
complete devotion and sincerity. “He [i.e., Confucius] sacrificed to the dead as if they were
present. He sacrificed to the spirits as if the spirits were present. The Master said, ‘I consider my
not being present at the sacrifice as though there were no sacrifice’” (Lunyu 3.12).
Ref. Stanford Encyclopedia Of Philosophy
It does not matter how slowly you go so long as you do not stop.
Where so ever you go, go with all your heart.
Life is really simple, but men insist on making it complicated.
Choose a job you love, and you will never have to work a day in your life.
Only the wisest and stupidest of men never change.
Everything has its beauty, but not everyone sees it.
Never do to others what you would not like them to do to you.
Our greatest glory is not in never falling, but in rising every time we fall.
Death and life have their determined appointments; riches and honors depend upon heaven.
I hear and I forget. I see and I remember. I do and I understand.