Economic Prosperity and Cultural Peril: The Promise of Globalization
Economic Prosperity and Cultural Peril: The Promise of Globalization
Economic Prosperity and Cultural Peril: The Promise of Globalization
Globalization is the most important fact of our time. We are experiencing a revolution not
merely of the political order, but a revolution in the transnational order, a revolution in the way
we live and do business, the way we conceive of ourselves and of mankind, a revolution, to
quote Burke, "in manners, morals, and sentiments." This revolution promises a reduction in
poverty and strife—and seems already to have delivered on that promise substantially—while
also bringing new instabilities and economic difficulties. The most important consequences of
boundaries may reduce conflict but also threatens community. And a breakdown in community
threatens character, fraternity, virtue—the ends for which we live, to which economic goods can
only provide the means. In this essay I want to briefly reflect on the economic promise and
cultural peril brought by globalization, and to consider how we ought to make the best of it.
Principles of Economics
The history of economic thought is in large part the history of the defense of free trade.
Adam Smith's Wealth of Nations attempted to destroy the mercantilist mythology which
privileged state control over free commercial exchange. To use the terminology of modern
economics, Smith realized that the wealth of nations was not a zero sum game—one country's
gain was not another country's loss. In the same way that a buyer and seller both benefit when
willingly trading, two nations both benefit through the aggregation thereof. Nations that wealth,
Smith demonstrated, should spend less time plundering and more producing and trading to make
polemicist against protectionism. Throughout his career he was motivated by his opposition to
England's Corn Laws. The principles of comparative advantage, which he illuminated, revealed
precisely how all nations benefit from free trade. If our country's resources or the talent of our
population allow us to produce one good relatively better than another, then both the world's
total product and our own income can be increased when we produce those for which we have
relative advantage, and trade for those in which we have a relative disadvantage. This allocation
of production allows the greatest prosperity and is the natural result of economic pressures in
free markets. Government controls to protect industries in which nations have a disadvantage
only hurt that country by allocating capital to less efficient uses, decreasing the world's total
supply. They also hurt the nation's total income and decrease the exports which could be used to
Modern economics is, of course, more complicated than this, and many scholars have
claimed that there are circumstances in which globalization and trade hurt the weaker party. And
although trade usually helps everyone in the long run, the transition, in which once prosperous
industries die and take jobs with them, is always painful. An argument can be made for efforts to
mitigate the pains of these transitions. Additionally, economists have not yet achieved a
complete consensus that free trade is always good for developing countries. Even so, nearly all
would admit that, though there could be some exceptions, trade usually benefits all parties.
Despite this, the media are constantly concerned by economic globalization. They make
us more aware of the pains of economic change than of the benefits. When a manufacturing plant
closes and moves across the border, it is covered on the news and we see it; when protectionism
stops jobs from ever being created, we don't see it—the costs of protectionism are invisible.
Cheaper, better-made cars, and the creation of new jobs dispersed throughout the country don't
make headlines as attractive as stories of manufacturing jobs in one place being lost to China.
Consequently, more attention is drawn to the bads of globalization than the goods, and
politicians feel pressured to protect dying industries. But these efforts always fail. If economic
forces cause a nation to lose its comparative advantage in an industry, political interference can't
maintain it very long. And jobs are destroyed every time taxes and tariffs are raised for
protection. Protectionism usually only delays painful job losses while slowing the economy's
economic benefits. It has contributed to American prosperity and dragged billions out of poverty,
bringing extended political freedom with it. The process is imperfect, to be sure, but it is the best
hope for the world's impoverished. And the alternative—government interference—often adds to
The Us
The great humorist P.G. Wodehouse relies on a hilarious trope in creating the lovable but
ridiculous dandy, Bertie Wooster. Whenever Bertie attempts to summon moral courage for some
vainglorious endeavor, he speaks with pride of the heroic qualities of "we Woosters." It is a
source of humor for the readers who know that the only Woosters who figure strongly in
Wodehouse's stories—Bertie and Aunt Agatha—are far from courageous martyrs. Though he
uses it for humorous effect, Wodehouse clearly observes what a wide variety of moral
philosophers and cultural critics have noticed: moral statements are very often phrased,
understood, and felt as "us"-statements. Members of families speak with pride about the Shaffer
way or the Smith way. Religious groups often phrase their moral imperatives as we-statements.
And citizens speak fondly of the American way and American values. Wodehouse makes
humorous use of this universal tendency. But the question arises, if our moral sensibilities flow
largely from our sense of solidarity with a group, then what shall happen in a world without
community identity?
motivated by a frustration with the nihilism and contentious disagreement found at the end of
reasoning from pure abstraction and individualistic calculation. This neo-Aristotelianism seeks
an account of morality better grounded in the shared interests and values of a community.
In contrast to Aristotle, Plato had hoped to discover the Good by ascending intellectually
to the pure forms—a perfect, mathematical reality, separate from experience. The history of
philosophy shows how hard it is, for even Plato's most devoted acolytes, to grasp these forms.
Frustrated with inability to get beyond experience and culture to the unmediated Platonic form or
reconstruct morality around individual, material interests. Others abandoned foundational moral
philosophy, advocating pragmatism. And yet even this has also proved unsatisfactory, ending in
nihilism.
The best hope for moral philosophy, many believe, is the neo-Aristotelian project
abstraction and the mundane materialism of individualistic calculus, by drawing on Aristotle and
his communitarianism. We should begin our moral enquiry, Aristotle and MacIntyre would
argue, by looking to the community around us. Morality is to be located in the shared values and
common interests of a community, rationality in their shared traditions and conversations. A
morality that is abstracted from human life, existing in Platonic forms, is either impossible to
at all.
The insights and promise of neo-Aristotelian philosophy on the one hand provide hope
for a belief in, and justification of, the good life. But it also brings a frightening implication for a
globalized era. If morality and rationality are inextricable from a community, then a world
without community becomes a world with in which rational morality is impossible. If the good
life cannot be abstracted from the shared interests and concerns of a community or the shared
The U.S.
We can perhaps address the philosophical question from a cultural perspective. Is
America a community today? Is there such a thing as an American people? It becomes ever hard
to answer in the affirmative. The fact that we are able to speak of a culture war indicates a
broken America. Increasingly there are different sides within our own country, and we become
strangers and aliens to our fellow citizens within our common borders. The rancor of our politics,
the nastiness of late-night talk shows, and the varieties of political humor that concern
themselves with demographic stereotypes, all seem to show that in an increasingly globalized
world Americans are ceasing to consider Americanism as a primary constituent of their identity,
and now identify more strongly along ideological and other demographic grounds. We are no
longer bound together by common interests and sentiments as on a ship of state. Without a
character, distinct values, and a distinct destiny, what are the consequences for our political
order? American liberty has in large part been sustained by the American's conception of
herself—as dedicated to freedom, valuing the individual, independent and rugged. Without a
belief in an American people, the values that have extended from this community may fade as
well.
Comedians today like to use ‘un-American’ as a term of ironic abuse. Whenever we wish
to demean a politician or thinker for being inexcusably backward, we adopt an ironic tone, feign
a southern accent, and express their position as, ‘that's un-American.’ But there was a time when
it was possible to use the word ‘un-American’ earnestly. Then, fascism, communism, and all
forms of totalitarianism were sincerely rejected as un-American. And we should be thankful. For
it was precisely this assertive sense of an ‘us’—jealous after our freedoms, committed to our
preserve it for the rest of the world. Long before the fall of the Berlin wall economically and
politically discredited communism, it was rejected in America as contrary to the distinct values
American people. Lincoln spoke of our fathers bringing forth a new nation, a metaphor in which
a whole nation is conceived of as a family. And he resolves that our distinctive project and
destiny as a people, "government of the people, by the people, for the people," and the American
dream of liberty and equality, "shall not perish from the earth." We as a people, for Lincoln, are
linked from birth to destiny. It is a sentiment which seems to be fading among Americans today.
What is to be done?
To join the reaction against globalization would be a dangerous move. Many anti-
globalization efforts are based on shoddy economics, and accomplish little to protect character
and community, while doing much to harm the march of prosperity for those most in need. What
efforts we take to protect community from any corrosive effects of globalization must not be of
best civic institutions. Irving Babbitt articulated a great defense of the puritans in Democracy
imposing strict, authoritarian rules on others. But historically, as Babbitt demonstrates, this is
unlike America's puritan founders. They were, to the contrary, extremely jealous of political
liberty, and were truly puritanical only in their attempts at self-restraint and self-discipline.
Babbitt goes so far as to suggest that the central political question for all time is whether restraint
individual should exercise self-restraint—as for America's puritans. For Babbitt, ironically
enough, true liberalism and true Puritanism depend on each other, for the best protection against
In The Quest for Community, Robert Nisbet develops this idea with one important
difference: Nisbet considers the central conflict to be between community and state, rather than
individual and state. For him, history's particular intellectual villain is Rousseau, who hoped to
'liberate' men from the strictures of the church, the guild, the town and the community with a
underpinnings are flawed, too. Rousseau was correct to observe that communities direct and
restrain the individual as much as the state. But he was wrong, I think, to conclude that man must
be liberated from these communities. Not all checks on individual autonomy are bad per se.
But why did Rousseau think they were? We all associate Rousseau with the phrase ‘noble
savage.’ Men were, Rousseau presumed, naturally good, noble human beings. It was only the
coercion of the church, of the university, of the guild, and of the community at large, that made
us bad. To make us good again, Rousseau's logic goes, a strong state that will liberate us from
Rousseau is not alone in this. One can find points of agreement between him and Plato
and Marx and even Marcuse. But totalitarianism lurks as the consequence of this premise. And
because it employs a Rousseau's justification of liberating the individual from the binds of
community and religion. For Nisbet, this shows the dangers of exalting individualism as the
highest ideal—hostility toward community and institutions can, in fact, lead to a loss of liberty.
In contrast to the tradition of Rousseau there is the story of creation in the Judeo-
Christian tradition. Here it is said that man is fallen and corrupt from birth, not by the evils of
community. Fallen man's wayward desires must be mitigated and corrected by institutions,
forces and even Grace, all forces external to the individual himself.
And Aristotle, though not within the Judeo-Christian tradition, looked to his community,
classical Athens, not as a corrupting or oppressive influence, but one in which to become a
virtuous person through friendship, through interaction with others, and even through the
judgment and shame sometimes imposed by the community. Aristotle opposed Plato, Rousseau
and Marx in recognizing that human flourishing is located in a virtuous community, not in an
I propose a fusion of the Aristotelian and Judeo-Christian traditions against the Platonic
and Rousseauin ideals. This conception acknowledges man's profound imperfection, but looks to
his betterment in self-restraint and community, not in the State. Traditional goods, of
community, character, and virtue, should be preserved through the institutions of family,
globalization, our individual and collective efforts to preserve them are of ever-increasing
import.
both of moral philosophy and of community. In the famous closing lines of After Virtue, he
writes:
A crucial turning point in that earlier history [before the dark ages] occurred when men
and women of good will turned aside from the task of shoring up the Roman Imperium
and ceased to identify the continuation of civility and moral community with the
maintenance of the Imperium...What they set themselves to achieve instead- often not
recognizing fully what they were doing- was the construction of new forms of
community within which the moral life could be sustained so that both morality and
civility might survive the coming ages of barbarism and darkness. If my account of our
moral condition is correct, we ought also to conclude that for some time now we too have
reached that turning point. What matters at this stage is the construction of local forms of
community within which civility and the intellectual and moral life can be sustained
through the new dark ages which are already upon us. And if the tradition of the virtues
was able to survive the horrors of the last dark ages, we are not entirely without grounds
for hope. This time however, the barbarians are not waiting beyond the frontiers; they
have already been governing us for quite some time. And it is our lack of consciousness
of this that constitutes part of our predicament. We are waiting not for a Godot, but for
another-doubtless very different- St. Benedict.
This reconstruction of "local forms of community within which the moral life [can] be sustained"
is no doubt an ambitious task. But in some ways globalization could help provide the means for
these communities.
capitalism. He saw in the surplus value created by free markets the potential for a total
could meet all our needs with minimal work, and devote the rest of our time to the enjoyment of
the libido. We could, in short, do away with the discontents of civilization and create a Marxist,
post-Freudian utopia.
I won't go into full detail about my objections to Marcuse's work, but to point out that,
even if his ideals were feasible, it's not clear they'd be satisfying. And his vogue has largely
passed with the student revolution. But Marcuse, in his own way, draws attention to the potential
brought by a new era of global prosperity. As we become ever wealthier, we are ever less tied to
the land. Contrary to Marxist fears that industrialization would lead to ceaseless labor, economic
data show that industrial advance has everywhere decreased the share of time we devote to labor.
With this new freedom from back-breaking work comes a new potential for time and energy
devoted to the good life. The liberation we should look to from late capitalist prosperity is not,
with Marcuse, libidinal liberation, but liberation from the quotidian and mundane, liberation
The prosperity brought by global capitalism should be considered precisely the condition
necessary for a rebirth of the life of the mind. Philosophy itself began among those, like Socrates
and Plato, affluent enough to afford the leisure of looking up to the Eternal instead of down at
the harvest. Aristotle found his students and his community among Athens' leisured. In the
renaissance the liberal arts were born among those liberated from onerous duties and able to
pursue the arts of free men—the ars liberales. And even on campuses today there is among many
the concern that only the affluent can afford to dabble in literature and philosophy, whereas the
less fortunate must pursue practical education to pay off loans. Global capitalism, by making
free, prosperous, and even potentially leisured men of so many of us, at once makes possible
global decadence, but also makes possible a greater concern for the good, for the great
Perhaps our greatest hope for the community in which moral goods can flourish is the
university. Today, traditions of liberal learning are threatened by a nihilism which seeks to
reduce truth to politics, a materialism which equates education with utility, and a popular culture
which disdains truth, beauty and goodness. Under these three pressures, the liberal arts are
suffering. But if the university can once again help students fall in love with humane learning,
they can become precisely the communities MacIntyre hoped for. I suggest that in an era of
globalization we cling to what virtuous communities we can find. The faithful should cherish
faith more than ever. Citizens of small towns should recognize their importance to each other and
commit themselves to building solidarity. And we should all, with particular energy rededicate
ourselves to a robust university in which liberal education—education being far more truly
liberating than libidinal release, as Plato realized—and the good life can flourish.
Conclusion
The forces of globalization are irresistible. They should not be fought, only used to the
greatest advantage. Economically, globalization brings great prosperity, but also some
transitional difficulties. Our goal must be to manifest the advantages as much as we can, and
and unity may flourish threatens the good life. State intervention to preserve communities is
impractical at best and dangerous at worst. Our goal must be to preserve mediating institutions
that we value. Those with religion should cherish it in a time of globalization. The university
must recognize its role as more important than ever. And every individual should recognize that,
now that our communities are no longer determined for us by location, class, religion, or the
circumstances of birth, the impetus is upon us to actively seek out and sustain communities, even
communities of our own choosing. It is impossible to tell what these new communities will look
like, whether like Benedictine sanctuaries or more like online fora. But if we are to survive what
MacIntyre called the "new dark ages," we need to find something to hold on to in which our best