Working Capital TOOLS

Download as docx, pdf, or txt
Download as docx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 11

Chapter

Duty Ethics

What is Duty Ethics?

Duty Ethics is a duty-based ethics that place special emphasis on the


relationship between duty and the morality of human action. Duty-based Ethics
based morality on specific and foundational principles of obligation. Duty Ethics is
known as Deontological Ethics. It is sometimes called “Non-Consequentialist”.

DEONTOLOGICAL ETHICS

Deontological Ethics is derived from the Greek word deon which means
“duty” and logos as “science”. In Contemporary moral philosophy, it refers as one
of those kinds of normative theories regarding which choices are morally
required, forbidden, or permitted.

In other words, Deontological Ethics falls within the domain of moral


theories that guide and assess our choices of what we ought to do (deontic
theories), in contrast to those that guide and assess what kind of person we are
and should be (virtue theories).

In deontological ethics an action is considered morally good because of


some characteristic of the action itself, not because the product of the action is
good. It holds that at least some acts are morally obligatory regardless of their
consequences for human welfare.
NON-CONSEQUETIALIST

“Some kinds of action are wrong or right in themselves,


regardless of the consequences.”

Non-Consequentialist is those whose principles are obligatory, irrespective


of the consequences that might follow from a certain action.

For Example:

 Do the right thing.


 Do it because it's the right thing to do.
 Don't do wrong things.
 Avoid them because they are wrong.

Under this form of ethics you can't justify an action by showing that
it produced good consequences, which is why it's sometimes called 'Non-
Consequentialist'.

Duty-based ethics teaches that some acts are right or wrong because of the
sorts of things they are, and people have a duty to act accordingly, regardless of
the good or bad consequences that may be produced.

DEONTOLOGIST vs. CONSEQUENTILIST

Deontologists live in a universe of moral rules, such as:

It is wrong to kill innocent people

It is wrong to steal

It is wrong to tell lies

It is right to keep promises


Deontologist is who follows Duty-based ethics should do the right thing,
even if that produces more harm (or less good) than doing the wrong thing.

While, Consequentialist determines right actions from good ends.

If we compare Deontologists with Consequentialists we can see that


Consequentialists begin by considering what things are good, and identify 'right'
actions as the ones that produce the maximum of those good things.

Deontologists appear to do it the other way around; they first consider


what actions are 'right' and proceed from there.

History of Deontological

The first great philosopher to define deontological principles was Immanuel


Kant, the 18th-century German founder of critical philosophy. Kant held that
nothing is good without qualification except a good will, and a good will is one
that wills to act in accord with the moral law and out of respect for that law
rather than out of natural inclinations.

He saw the moral law as a categorical imperative, an unconditional


command, and believed that its content could be established by
human reason alone. Thus, the supreme categorical imperative is: “Act only on
that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it should become a
universal law.”

Kant considered that formulation of the categorical imperative to be


equivalent to: “So act that you treat humanity in your own person and in the
person of everyone else always at the same time as an end and never merely as
means.” The connection between those two formulations, however, has never
been entirely clear.
In any event, Kant’s critics questioned his view that all duties can be
derived from a purely formal principle and argued that, in his preoccupation with
rational consistency, he neglected the concrete content of moral obligation.

That objection was faced in the 20th century by the British philosopher Sir
David Ross, who held that numerous “prima facie duties,” rather than a single
formal principle for deriving them, are themselves immediately self-evident.

Ross distinguished those prima facie duties (such as promise keeping,


reparation, gratitude, and justice) from actual duties, for “any possible act has
many sides to it which are relevant to its rightness or wrongness”; and those
facets have to be weighed before “forming a judgment on the totality of its
nature” as an actual obligation in the given circumstances.

Ross’s attempt to argue that intuition is a source of moral knowledge was,


however, heavily criticized, and by the end of the 20th century, Kantian ways of
thinking, especially the prohibition on using a person as a means rather than an
end were again providing the basis for the deontological views that were most
widely discussed among philosophers.

At a popular level, the international emphasis on protecting human rights


and thus on the duty not to violate them can also be seen as a triumph for
deontological ethics.
 Kantian duty-based ethics

Immanuel Kant was arguably one of the greatest philosophers of all


time.

Kant thought that it was possible to develop a consistent moral


system by using reason.

If people were to think about this seriously and in a philosophically


rigorous manner, Kant taught, they would realise that there were some
moral laws that all rational beings had to obey simply because they were
rational beings, and this would apply to any rational beings in any
universe that might ever exist.

Kant taught (rather optimistically) that every rational human being


could work this out for themselves and so did not need to depend on God
or their community or anything else to discover what was right and what
was wrong. Nor did they need to look at the consequences of an act, or
who was doing the action.

Although he expressed himself in a philosophical and quite difficult


way, Kant believed that he was putting forward something that would help
people deal with the moral dilemmas of everyday life, and provide all of us
with a useful guide to acting rightly.
 What is Good?
Although Kantian ethics are usually spoken of in terms of duty and
doing the right thing, Kant himself thought that what was good was an
essential part of ethics.

Kant asked if there was anything that everybody could rationally


agree was always good. The only thing that he thought satisfied this test
was a good will:

“It is impossible to conceive anything in the world, or even out of it,


which can be taken as good without limitation, save only a good will”.

All Kant means is that a good will alone must be good in whatever
context it may be found.

Other things that we might think of as good are not always good, as
it's possible to imagine a context in which they might seem to be morally
undesirable.

Kant then pondered what this meant for human conduct. He


concluded that only an action done for 'a good will' was a right action,
regardless of the consequences.

But what sort of action would this be? Kant taught that an action
could only count as the action of a good will if it satisfied the test of the
Categorical Imperative.

 Kant's Categorical Imperative

The Categorical Imperative

Kant's version of duty-based ethics was based on something that he


called 'the categorical imperative' which he intended to be the basis of all
other rules. Categorical imperative is a rule that is true in all
circumstances.
The categorical imperative comes in two versions which each
emphasize different aspects of the categorical imperative. Kant is clear that
each of these versions is merely a different way of expressing the same
rule; they are not different rules.

Kant is saying that people should always be treated as valuable - as


an end in themselves and should not just be used in order to achieve
something else. They should not be tricked, manipulated or bullied into
doing things.

This resonates strongly with disapproving comments such as "he's


just using her", and it underpins the idea that "the end can never justify the
means".

Here are three examples of treating people as means and not ends:

 treating a person as if they were an inanimate object


 coercing a person to get what you want
 deceiving a person to get what you want

Kant doesn't want to say that people can't be used at all; it may be
fine to use a person as long as they are also being treated as an end in
themselves.

The importance of duty

“Do the right thing for the right reason, because


it is the right thing to do.”

Kant thought that the only good reason for doing the right thing was
because of duty - if you had some other reason (perhaps you didn't commit
murder because you were too scared, not because it was your duty not to)
then that you would not have acted in a morally good way.

But having another reason as well as duty doesn't stop an action


from being right, so long as duty was the ‘operational reason’ for our
action.
If we do something because we know it's our duty, and if duty is the
key element in our decision to act, then we have acted rightly, even if we
wanted to do the act or were too scared not to do it, or whatever.

 Rossian duty-based ethics

Rossian duty-based ethics

Kantian ethics seems pretty uncompromising and not really suited to


the untidiness of many moral choices that people have to make.

The 20th Century philosopher, William David Ross suggested that it


would be helpful to look at two kinds of duty:

 Prima facie duties


 Actual duties
 Prima facie duties

Prima Facie duties are self-evident and obvious duties. Prima facie is
a Latin expression meaning 'on first appearances' or 'by first instance'. It
can be known to be correct if a person thinks about them and understands
them

 Actual duties

Actual duties are the duty people are left with after they have
weighed up all the conflicting prima facie duties that apply in a particular
case. The ground of the actual rightness of the act is that, of all acts
possible in the circumstances, it is that whose prima facie rightness in the
respects in which it is prima facie right most outweighs its prima facie
wrongness in any respects in which it is prima facie wrong.

Ross listed seven prima facie duties:


 Fidelity
 Reparation
 Gratitude
 Justice
 Beneficence
 Self-improvement
 Non-maleficence (avoiding actions that do harm)

Calling these 'duties' may be a bit misleading, as they are not so


much duties as "features that give us genuine (not merely apparent) moral
reason to do certain actions".

Ross later described prima facie duties as "responsibilities to


ourselves and to others" and he went on to say that "what we should do
(our duty proper [our actual duty]) is determined by the balance of these
responsibilities."

Problems with the Rossian approach

Ross's idea still leaves some problems:

 How can we tell which prima facie duties are involved in a particular case?

 How can we compare and rank them in order to arrive at a balance which
will guide us as to our actual duty?

Ross thought that people could solve those problems by relying on


their intuitions.
Test your memory. Identify if the statement is either under Kant’s duty-based
ethics or Ross duty-based ethics.

1. “Do the right thing for the right reason, because it is the right thing
to do.”
2. 'on first appearances’
3. "responsibilities to ourselves and to others"
4. Non-maleficence
5. 'the categorical imperative'
6. 'a good will'
7. 'by first instance'
8. Reparation
9. Actual Duties
10. “So act that you treat humanity in your own person and in the
person of everyone else always at the same time as an end and
never merely as means.”

Test your memory. Fill in the blanks with the correct answer.

Moral law as a , an unconditional command, and


believed that its content could be established by alone. Thus, the
supreme is: “ only on that through which you can
at the same time will that it should become a .”

If we compare with we can see that


Consequentialists begin by considering what things are , and identify
'right' actions as the ones that produce the of those good things.
Test your ability. Answer the question briefly.

1. What did Kant mean by “Some kinds of action are wrong or right in
themselves, regardless of the consequences.” Explain.

You might also like