Principles of Neurotheology PDF

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 5
At a glance
Powered by AI
The passage discusses a review of Andrew Newberg's book 'Principles of Neurotheology', which aims to establish the theoretical foundations of neurotheology, the interdisciplinary field linking neuroscience and religion.

Neurotheology aims to integrate religious and scientific perspectives to tackle questions about consciousness, reality and the existence of God using brain imaging studies of religious experiences. However, the true engine is seen as brain science.

The reviewer criticizes Newberg for not addressing criticisms of the brain-centered view of mind and failing to engage with predecessors. Newberg also does not sufficiently examine whether supernatural entities can be empirically investigated.

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/265446346

Principles of Neurotheology

Article · January 2010


DOI: 10.1080/15665399.2011.10820062

CITATIONS READS

44 2,635

2 authors:

Andrew Newberg Nathaniel Barrett


Thomas Jefferson University Universidad de Navarra
260 PUBLICATIONS   6,726 CITATIONS    36 PUBLICATIONS   113 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

net research View project

Severity Rating Scale in AD View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Nathaniel Barrett on 21 August 2015.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


Ars Disputandi
Volume 11 (2011)
ISSN: 1566-5399

Nathaniel F. Barrett Principles of Neurotheology


INSTITUTE FOR THE
BIOCULTURAL STUDY OF
RELIGION,
By Andrew B. Newberg
UNITED STATES
Surrey: Ashgate, 2010. 286 pp., hb. £ 55.00, pb. £ 16.99; ISBN: 978-1-4094-
0810-9/ 978-0-7546-6994-4.

If you have read anything about brain-imaging studies of religious


experience in the last ten years, it is likely that you have come across the name of
Andrew Newberg. A leading expert in neuroradiology, he has conducted some of
the highest-profile studies of the neurobiological correlates of experiences
induced by meditation and prayer. Moreover, since co-authoring The Mystical
Mind (1999) with Eugene d’Aquili, Newberg has established himself in the public
eye with numerous mainstream media appearances and several provocatively
titled books aimed at a general audience (e.g. How God Changes Your Brain,
2009). With Principles of Neurotheology (2010), Newberg seems to be turning
toward a different audience: his academic peers in the sciences and humanities.
His stated purpose is to clarify the premises, goals, and methods of a massive
interdisciplinary project that he calls ‘neurotheology’; his unstated purpose, I
suspect, is to entice more scholars to join him in this unusual venture.
Newberg’s vision for neurotheology is extraordinarily ambitious. Though his
initial definition of neurotheology is deceptively simple—‘the field of study
linking the neurosciences with religion and theology’ (p. 45)—as this linkage is
further articulated, it becomes clear that Newberg seeks to do more than foster
interdisciplinary dialogue. His goal is the integration of religious and scientific
perspectives in pursuit of an overarching ‘megatheology’ rooted in ‘two universal
elements—religion and the human brain’ (pp. 65-66). However, though he
repeatedly calls for an equal and mutually respectful partnership between
religious and scientific perspectives, by the end of the book it is clear that the real
engine of neurotheology is brain science. Newberg hopes that brain science,
when coupled with a rich phenomenology of religious experience, will allow us
finally to tackle perennial questions about the nature of consciousness, the
nature of reality, and the existence of God. The religions of the world may have
already granted us experiential access to ultimate reality—Newberg is always
careful to leave this possibility open—but he believes that brain science will play
a pivotal role in developing a systematic understanding of religious experience,
and hopes that this understanding will improve the human condition and guide
us toward a ‘new enlightenment’ (p. 267).

Nathaniel F. Barrett, June 30, 2011. If you would like to cite this article, please do so as follows:
Nathaniel F. Barrett, ‘Review of Principles of Neurotheology,’ Ars Disputandi [http://www.ArsDisputandi.org] 11 (2011), 133-
136
Nathaniel F. Barrett, Review of Principles of Neurotheology

Newberg builds his case for neurotheology through the exposition of fifty-
four principles. Although he aspires to a set of ‘necessary’ principles that together
constitute the ‘ideological foundations’ of neurotheology (pp. 1, 267), in the
course of his argument he tends to offer the principles as suggestions or
guidelines rather than necessary axioms. The principles range from
commonsensical tenets of open inquiry (e.g. Principle III, p. 46) to some rather
tendentious claims about the neural constraints of religious belief and experience
(Principle XI, p. 64) and the ‘fundamental uncertainty’ of all beliefs about reality
(Principle XXIX, p. 214). More than anything, it seems that Newberg’s use of
principles is a rhetorical strategy designed for maximum clarity and
straightforwardness, and in this respect he succeeds admirably: one could get the
gist of his book by reading just the principles printed in bold.
However, while the principles are clear and straightforward, they are not
adequately justified. In particular, Newberg does not sufficiently examine, let
alone justify, the epistemological premises that make brain science so important
for the synthesis of religion and science. And yet Newberg’s proposal that brain
functions are a crucial tool for the interpretation of religious beliefs—what he
calls ‘neurotheological hermeneutic’ (see Principle XVII, p. 84; Chapter 5:
‘Towards a Neurotheological Hermeneutic,’ pp. 87-114)—is the most distinctive
feature of his methodological approach. Indeed, I would argue that Newberg’s
picture of how the brain determines our experience of reality is not just the
lynchpin of his planned synthesis of religious and scientific perspectives; it is the
fundamental premise of ‘neurotheology.’
The importance of Newberg’s brain-centered epistemology comes into full
view in the tenth and final chapter, ‘Epistemological Issues in Neurotheology’
(pp. 249-265), where he proposes that brain science, coupled with the
phenomenology of ‘primary epistemic states,’ might provide leverage on
questions about the ultimate nature of reality. Ironically, this leverage is gained
by placing us in an epistemological predicament of seemingly hopeless isolation.
Newberg argues that we ‘are trapped with our brain peering out into the world
and reconstructing it the best we can’ (p. 252). From this position, our only
indication of what is real is what feels real to us. By combining phenomenology
with neurobiology, however, Newberg believes that we might be able to find our
way out of our brains (pp. 262-265).
In my estimation, Newberg’s uncritical conflation of brain activity with
cognition is the book’s major flaw. No one can doubt that the brain is the most
important organ of human cognition, but that does not necessarily mean that we
are trapped within the brain. In Newberg’s vision of neurotheology, the brain is
so important that it crowds out all other objects of scientific investigation. This
narrow scientific focus is reinforced on the religious side by a preoccupation with
the phenomenology of religious experience. In his discussions of the relevant
data for building a scientific understanding of religion, Newberg focuses almost
exclusively on ‘subjective’ accounts of spiritual experience (p. 2) and makes no
mention of physical, cultural, and social environments. My guess is that this
narrow focus is justified by the assumption that all environmental factors must
be ‘filtered’ by the brain (pp. 87-88), so that a full understanding of human

Ars Disputandi [http://www.ArsDisputandi.org] 11 (2011) 134


Nathaniel F. Barrett, Review of Principles of Neurotheology

experience, religious and otherwise, must await a thorough investigation of these


neural ‘filters’ (p. 64). At the heart of Newberg’s vision of neurotheology, then, is
the unexamined notion that we are trapped within the worlds created for us by
our brains, so that brain science is crucial to any attempt to understand what
reality is really like ‘out there.’ This results in a highly truncated view of what is
relevant to the scientific study of religion.
It should be noted that many of Newberg’s presuppositions about the brain
and cognition are commonplace in cognitive science, where the standard
epistemological stance seems to be a kind of ‘evolutionary Kantianism,’ i.e. a
formalist and representationalist view bolstered by evolutionary biology and
given specious clarity by the computational metaphor of the brain as an
information processor. This view is so widely held that it may seem unfair to take
Newberg to task for being insufficiently critical about its premises. But as a self-
conscious attempt to establish the theoretical and methodological groundwork of
a new field of research, Principles of Neurotheology is precisely the sort of work
that should take pains to examine its premises. Newberg not only fails to address
the many criticisms of brain-centered, representationalist epistemology, he
shows no sign of even being aware that they exist. This is an egregious oversight
given the prominence of ‘extended,’ ‘embodied,’ and ‘situated,’ theories of mind
in recent years.1
Another major flaw of the book is that it does not engage important
predecessors and peers. Newberg only briefly acknowledges other proponents of
what he calls ‘neurotheology’ (p. 12) and does not examine the history of the
term’s usage. Although he does provide a helpful review of relevant scientific
research (pp. 170-178), for the most part Newberg settles for extensive citations
rather than detailed engagement with others’ views. If Newberg truly believes
that neurotheology is essentially a collaborative endeavor, that conviction needs
to be reflected in the way that he writes about the subject.
Newberg also fails to address important objections to neurotheology.
Lurking in the background of Newberg’s project is the question of whether
‘immaterial’ or ‘supernatural’ entities can really be the objects of empirical
inquiry. Of course this question cannot be pursued without more precise
definitions. Despite his claim that ‘religious beliefs virtually always begin with a
supernatural foundation’ (p. 51), Newberg does not define the supernatural, and
never faces up to the questions begged by his insistence that neurotheology
remain open to supernatural explanations. As far as I can tell, Newberg is not
shielding a specific theological agenda; rather he is trying to remain true to his
principles of open inquiry. But an open mind still must be clear about what it
means for any entity to be susceptible to empirical investigation: these key
principles of inquiry are missing from Newberg’s book. When Newberg ventures
to speculate about what empirical evidence of an immaterial cause would look
like, he provides what amounts to an inference from the absence of evidence: no
detectable material cause, therefore… (see pp. 182-183). I suggest that those who

1
For instance, see Alva Noë, Out of Our Heads: Why You Are Not Your Brain, and Other Lessons from
the Biology of Consciousness (New York: Hill and Wang 2009).

Ars Disputandi [http://www.ArsDisputandi.org] 11 (2011) 135


Nathaniel F. Barrett, Review of Principles of Neurotheology

wish to emulate Newberg’s bold empirical stance revisit the early history of
psychical research, when a group of exceptionally open-minded scientists (such
as William James) embarked on a futile search for empirical evidence of the soul.
Such criticisms aside, Newberg’s intellectual courage and passion for
interdisciplinary research are extraordinary, and I have no doubt he will continue
to make significant contributions to the scientific understanding of religion. He is
an ideal scientific collaborator for humanistic scholars of religion, the flaws of his
proposed ‘ideological foundations’ notwithstanding. Which brings me to my last
point: does interdisciplinary research really need necessary principles or
foundations in order to be successful?

Ars Disputandi [http://www.ArsDisputandi.org] 11 (2011) 136

View publication stats

You might also like