269-Article Text-264-1-10-20170103 PDF

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 8

LEGAL DRAFTING

Dou01.AS STOLTZ

The technical writing engaged in by members of the legal profession


falls into two classes, referred to for convenience as legal writing and legal
drafting. Legal writing embraces all kinds of expository writing including that
encountered in correspondence, legal opinions and text books on legal
subjects, as well as reports of decided cases in which judges set forth their
reasons for decision. Legal drafting is the composition of legal instruments
such as contracts, deeds, wills and legislation.

In their roles as advocates, lawyers often use language as a tool of


persuasion-whether their words are meant to be beard in oral argument or
to be read-and this factor introduces a subjectivity and a rhetorical element
not found in non-legal writing. This distinction aside, legal writing shares the
characteristics of other varieties of technical writing, including a specialized
terminology and a preoccupation with precision and clarity. The function of
legal writing, as distinct from drafting, is descriptive. It is writing about law
and legal matters, much as medical writing is writing about medicine.

The subject matter of law, however, itself takes the form of writing.
Legal rules and legal transactions are created, recorded and communicated
through the agency of language. Written laws and written documents are
to the barrister or solicitor what drugs and clinical instruments are to the
physician or surgeon. The function of written legal instruments is different
from that of other technical writing. It is to create and to give effect to legal
obligations, probtbitions, rights and immunities. Rather than describe
something, they prescnbe or proscribe something.

The way legal provisions are expressed, whether in a contract between


two individuals or in a statute that applies to everybody, can have serious
consequences. Small differences in wording or grammatical arrangement can
produce large changes in meaning and therefore in the impact on people
collectively and individually. Once a contract is signed or a statute is
enacted, its terms become definitive and binding. It is then too late to say,
'That's not what I meani." The drafting process involves finding out what
is meant, and matching that to what is said.
2

The drafting of legislation presents special challenges because of the


large number of persons potentially affected and the difficulty of visualizing
all the possible or likely permutations and combinations of circumstances,
events and transactions to be provided for. The quest for fairness, treating
like cases alike and different cases differently, adds to the importance of
avoiding gaps in the law or, conversely, of inadvertently overextending the
law's reach. When difficulties of interpretation arise, they cannot be resolved
by calling up the Minister who sponsored the Bill, the civil servants who
formulated the policy or the drafters who produced a legislative text. A final
resolution requires resort to the courts with all the costs that that entails for
litigants and for society.

We speak of a well-drafted or well-drawn enactment or document, as


opposed to well-written one. The word "draft" or "draught," used as a verb,
noun or adjective, is a variant of the verb "to draw''. Though we still speak
of draft horses (able to draw loads) or draught beer (drawn from a tap),
"drafting" is now more or less synonymous, outside the legal context, with
mechanical drawing of the kind encountered in engineering and architecture.
Legal texts can be viewed as blueprints for political, social and economic
structures of various descriptions, both large and small. The substantive
content of a statute or contract is determined by the policymaker or client,
just as that of a physical structure is devised by an engineer. The draftsman
( draftsperson, drafter) in both cases then proceeds to translate the concept
into a visible and permanent form making use of established drafting
conventions and vocabulary.

Legal texts, like engineering blueprints, serve utilitarian goals and so


lack embellishment and ornamentation for their own sakes. That does not
mean that esthetic considerations are irrelevant in legal drafting. Qualities
such as simplicity, economy, symmetry and completeness not only produce
a pleasing effect, but further the attainment of the project's objectives by
helping the user to grasp its organization and content. On the other hand,
stylistic features appropriate to non-technical writing that produce vagueness,
ambiguity or doubles entendres are even more dangerous here than in other
kinds of technical writing. Unfortunately for the drafter, language is
inherently ambiguous. Sparing use must be made of adjectives and adverbs
which, being relative in nature, are necessarily vague unless defined in the
document. (What is a "large" object or a "dangerous" substance?) In the
choice of nouns and verbs, preference is given to those which come closest
to pure cognitive meaning as opposed to terms with pejorative, sympathetic
or euphemistic overtones ("intoxicated" versus "drunk" or "inebriated").
3

Relationships among logical categories are the determining


consideration in forming the grammatical structure of sentences and in
grouping and positioning the various provisions within a document. Drafting
and reading are both assisted by giving concrete form to conceptual
organization. The use of a hierarchy of headinp is complemented, at the
sentence level, by the parallel indentation and enumeration of grammatically
equivalent clauses and phrases. h with a blueprint for a piece of
machinery, the relation of the parts to each other ought to be plainly vistble.
They ought to dovetail at appropriate points with other elements of the legal
system. When put into operation, the whole apparatus should function
harmoniously with a minimum of effort and pain.

The end products of legal drafting may be categorized in a number


of ways. A basic distinction is that between rules and commands. Some
examples will illustrate:

A contract for the sale of land shall be in writing. (Statute)

The party of the first part will keep the premises in good repair.
(Contract)

I devise and bequeath all my property to my wife. (Will)

This Court sentences the accused to imprisonment for fifty years.


(Court order)

The first two examples are rules. They arc expressed to govern the conduct
of persons. A rule may be of general application, in the sense that persons
to whom it applies are unidentified. The persons governed by such a rule
are those who, by force of circumstance or by conscious choice, are brought
within its scope. Such rules include most (but not all} of the provisions
found in statutes, regulations and other descriptions of enacted law. On the
other hand, the rules contained in contracts, leases and licences have
application only to the named parties who have submitted themselves to the
terms of such documents.

The second pair of examples are commands. The author of a


command purports to perform some act rather than to govern somebody's
conduct. In the terminology of linguistics, a command is a performative
utterance, a statement that accomplishes something concurrently with the
conveying of information. The thing accomplished is not a physical act, the
tools being mere words, but a conceptual one. Property changes bands by
the execution of a will; the right to sue is relinquished in a settlement
4

contained in a court order; a declaration of bankruptcy realigns the rights of


creditors. Commands operate at a particular instant in time and represent
some discontinuity in the legal status quo. In their most familiar guises their
effect is limited to specific, identified parties. Examples arc found in judicial
orders, property conveyances, wills, declarations, affidavits and notices.

The distinction between rules and commands has consequences for


grammar and composition. However, in practical effect they arc really
different manifestations of a single phenomenon. A rule is an expression of
some ongoing obligation, right or other legal condition while a command
expresses and brings about a change in such a condition. Consider the
following examples.

(1) A licensee may sell cigarettes to minors.

(2A) Smokers World, Inc. is hereby authorized to sell cigarettes to


minors.

(2B) The Commission hereby authorizes Smokers World, Inc. to sell


cigarettes to minors.

Example (1) is in rule form, while examples (2A) and (2B) are in
command form, but the effect is the same. The command form draws
attention to the act of authorizing and, when in the active voice, to the
author of the command. This is appropriate where the parties affected have
direct contact with the author, as in the case of a particular dispute before
a court or other decision-making body. It is less appropriate where the
provision is made by a legislative body addressing the community at large,
in terms that arc unlimited as to time and arc capable of applying to more
than one set of facts. In the statute book, it is sufficient for the fact of
enactment and the identity of the author to be expressed at the beginning
of each Act:

"Her Majesty, by and with the advice and consent of the Senate and
House of Commons of Canada, enacts as follows:"

The substantive provisions that follow then go on to deal in rule form with
the rights and obligations of Her Majesty's subjects, while Parliament recedes
from immediate view.

Just as every rule is given life by some originating command, the


converse also holds true. Every command effects a legal change of
continuing effect either by modifying a regime of rules or, more often, by
s
affecting their applicability. When a court issues a decree of divorce, the
rules of law that govern the relationship of spouses cease to apply to the
parties affected. A conveyance of property attaches to the new owner all the
legal rights and obligations that go with ownership, expressed in the general
law as a series of rules. In both examples, the legal regime governing
individual conduct has been altered.

What are the grammatical distinctions between rules and commands?


Commands operate at a single moment in time. Hence they generally
employ the present tense. In the active voice, the subject is the author of
the command.

We order the appellant to pay costs of the appeal.

I now pronounce you man and wife.

The Council hereby adopts the bylaw.

The undersigned agree to the following terms.

The first person can be used where the command is given orally or where
the context makes clear the identity of its author. It may be unnecessmy to
draw attention to the author, in which case the passive voice can be used.
In legislation, where there is an exacting clause such as that quoted above
and most provisions are in rule form, commands invariably are in the passive.

The accused is convicted and sentenced to 30 days.

March 29th is hereby declared to be Dominion Day.

Section 178 of the said Act is amended by deleting the word


"security".

The National Regulatory Authority is hereby established.

Rules, unlike commands, operate continuously over a time span subsequent


to their enactment. From the perspective of the rulemaker, a future modal
form of the verb would seem called for. However, from the perspective of
those who must observe or apply the rule in given circumstances at a given
time, the present tense would seem appropriate. The verb forms that have
come to predominate result from the unique function of rules themselves.
6
The functions of legal rules are four in number: (1) compelling, (2)
forbidding, (3) enabling, (4) relieving. The legal sentences that express
these norms typically employ the auxiliary verbs "shall", "shall not", "may'' and
"need not" or their equivalents. In fact, every sentence found in a piece of
legislation or other set of rules employs one of those auxiliaries or is
equivalent to one or more sentences that do.

In a so-called state of nature, where people were free of any external


restraints on their conduct, there would be nothing compelled and nothing
forbidden. The appearance of rules begins with the imposition, by some
authority, of requirements to do certain things and to forbear from doing
certain others.

Parents shall care for their children.

People shall not kill each other.

Given the existence of such "injunctive" rules, occasions may arise when it is
necessary to make exceptions from them.

Parents need not care for their adult children.

A person may kill another in self-defence.

In the absence of some "shall" or "shall not", a "need not" or "may'' would be
superfluous. From this perspective the auxiliary "shall" is seen as the basic
morpheme or linguistic element encountered in the drafting of rules in
English. This is a natural extension of its earlier use in other contexts.

English and other languages in the Germanic family employ a number


of modal auxiliary verbs to express various subjective states of mind. Most
of them have application in referring to the future. We are not always in a
position to make a pure prediction and to say what "will" happen at some
future time. More often what we want to express is a conjecture (what
"may'' or "could" happen), an opinion (what "should" occur or "ought" to be
done), a prediction subject to a condition (what ''would" happen if... ), a
suggestion (what "can" or "might" be done), and so on. The auxiliary "shall"
(like its German counterpart "sollen") long ago took its place as the means
of expressing the imposition of an obligation by someone in authority. The
power relationship could be that of parent to child, husband to wife, master
to servant, officer to subordinate, clergy to faithful or deity to mortal.
7

You/he/they shall go at once.

You shall do what you are told

Smith shall deliver the order.

She shall not set foot in this house again.

Thou shalt not kill.

Every such pronouncement could be punctuated for effect by "I say so",
implying that the will of the speaker is all the justification necessary to insist
on compliance. Implicit in each statement is the ultimate availability of some
means of enforcement. It is not a major leap from such an injunction,
delivered orally and in person, to one put into writing and adopted by some
formal procedure. The injunctive effect is simply generalized. It will apply
over and over for as long as it remains in effect.

No person shall kill.

Every parent shall support his children.

A policeman shall not use excessive force.

The non-legal use of "shall" now has an antique ring to it, perhaps
because it smacks of Victorian authoritarianism in an era when the legitimacy
of conventional authority is under permanent attack. Today the imperative
mood is about as far as most authority figures care or dare to go.

I would like you/him/them to go at once.

Do what you are told (please).

Have Smith deliver the message.

She is not to set foot here again.

Formal Rules are in a class by themselves, however. Because they are


anonymous and impersonal, politeness and tact are not an issue. Moreover,
the legitimacy of rules continues to enjoy relative acceptance. Whether in
a legal enactment or a club constitution, rules are usually made by persons
who can make some plausible claim to the right to "rule". The formalities
of adoption, especially if they allow for debate and criticism, add to the
8

legitimacy of the result. (The identification of the maker and the act of
adoption in an "enacting clause" thus has more than symbolic importance.)

Though "shall" may sound stilted or high-handed in everyday discourse,


it remains a useful means of signalling the binding effect of injunctive rules.
Moreover, it succeeds in conveying a sense of ordination or ''laying-down"
that is absent in, for instance, 'Thou must not kill."

Every father must support his children.

Every father is required to support his children.

Every father is obliged to support his children.

Every father has to support his children.

Each of these examples, if accompanied by appropriate sanctions, could


constitute a binding and effective rule. However, each is also capable of
merely describing the effect of a rule imposed elsewhere. Every father
"must" or "is required to", for instance, because the Family Law Act says he
"shall". We would never employ "shall" merely to report an obligation, except
by quoting the rule in which it appears. Each of the alternatives, moreover,
is capable of expressing an exhortation short of a binding injunction. (Some
even more equivocal formulations are "is supposed to", "had better", "ought
to" and "should".) "Shall" alone necessarily expresses both the imposition of
the obligation and its binding nature. Its virtual disappearance from general
usage, if anything, enhances its recognition value as a distinctive feature of
legal and legislative language.

Douglas Stoltz is Legislative Counse~ Department of Justice, Ottawa.

You might also like