Descriptive vs. Hermenuetic Phenonmenology
Descriptive vs. Hermenuetic Phenonmenology
Descriptive vs. Hermenuetic Phenonmenology
Phenomenology is essentially the study of lived experience or the life world (van
Manen, 1997). Its emphasis is on the world as lived by a person, not the world or
reality as something separate from the person (Valle et al., 1989). This inquiry asks
“What is this experience like?” as it attempts to unfold meanings as they are lived in
everyday existence. Polkinghorne (1983) identified this focus as trying to understand
or comprehend meanings of human experience as it is lived. The ‘life world’ is
understood as what we experience pre-reflectively, without resorting to categorization
or conceptualization, and quite often includes what is taken for granted or those
things that are common sense (Husserl, 1970). The study of these phenomena
intends to return and re-examine these taken for granted experiences and perhaps
uncover new and/or forgotten meanings.
The attraction of the phenomenological method was, for Husserl (1970), in its
promise as a new science of being. Through this methodology, disclosure of a realm
of being which presented itself with absolute certainty, arising from experience,
seemed possible. Husserl saw this method as a way of reaching true meaning
through penetrating deeper and deeper into reality. Phenomenology, in this sense,
was seen as a movement away from the Cartesian dualism of reality being
something ‘out there’ or completely separate from the individual (Jones, 1975; Koch,
1995).
The main focus for Husserl was the study of phenomena as they appeared through
consciousness. He purported that minds and objects both occur within experience,
thus eliminating mind-body dualism. Valle et al. (1989) reported that Husserl viewed
consciousness as a co-constituted dialogue between a person and the world.
Moreover, he saw access to the structures of consciousness not as a matter of
induction or generalization, but as a result of direct grasping of a phenomena. This
grasping was seen as an intentional process, actively guided by human intention, not
mechanistic causation (Polkinghorne, 1989). Koch (1995)identified that Husserl
viewed intentionality and essences as key to our understanding of this
phenomenology. Husserl saw intentionality as a process where the mind is directed
toward objects of study. Conscious awareness was the starting point in building one's
knowledge of reality. By intentionally directing one's focus, Husserl proposed one
could develop a description of particular realities. This process is one of coming face
to face with the ultimate structures of consciousness. These structures were
described as essences that made the object identifiable as a particular type of object
or experience, unique from others (Edie, 1987).
How does one go about the process of bracketing? Klein and Westcott
(1994) described this as a three-fold process including exemplary intuition,
imaginative variation, and synthesis. In exemplary intuition, the researcher chooses a
phenomena and holds it in his/her imagination. He/she then moves to develop
examples of similar experiences through imaginative variation. Finally, integration of
these variations is achieved through synthesis of the essences of
interest. Polkinghorne (1983) described a two-fold process from Husserl's work. A
method of free variation leads the researcher to a description of the invariant or
essential structures of the phenomena, without which it would not exist. The use of
intentional analysis then focuses on the concrete experience itself and describes how
the particular experience is constructed. Osborne (1994) described bracketing as
identifying one's presuppositions about the nature of the phenomena and then
attempting to set them aside to see the phenomena as it really is. Husserl's goal in
doing this was to actually see things ‘as they are’ through intuitive seeing. He sought
to show the purely immanent character of conscious experience by means of careful
description.
Martin Heidegger (1889–1976) was born in Germany and, like Husserl, began his
career in a field other than philosophy. While Husserl's start was in science,
Heidegger found his in theology. Jones (1975) reported that the philosophy that
Heidegger first committed himself to was Husserlian, yet he was never a formal
student of Husserl. While both men taught at Freiberg, Heidegger worked with
Husserl, who trained him in the processes of phenomenological intentionality and
reduction. Evidently, Heidegger became so proficient in this endeavor that Husserl
thought he had found the heir he had been seeking, and he ensured Heidegger
succession to his professorship. Once established in Husserl's chair, however,
Heidegger disassociated himself from Husserl and his work.
Like phenomenology, hermeneutic phenomenology is concerned with the life world or
human experience as it is lived. The focus is toward illuminating details and
seemingly trivial aspects within experience that may be taken for granted in our lives,
with a goal of creating meaning and achieving a sense of understanding (Wilson &
Hutchinson, 1991). The way this exploration of lived experience proceeds is where
Husserl and Heidegger disagreed. While Husserl focused on understanding beings
or phenomena, Heidegger focused on ‘Dasein‘, that is translated as ‘the mode of
being human’ or ‘the situated meaning of a human in the world’. Husserl was
interested in acts of attending, perceiving, recalling, and thinking about the world and
human beings were understood primarily as knowers. Heidegger, in contrast, viewed
humans as being primarily concerned creatures with an emphasis on their fate in an
alien world (Annells, 1996; Jones, 1975).
Consciousness is not separate from the world, in Heidegger's (1927/1962) view, but
is a formation of historically lived experience. He believed that understanding is a
basic form of human existence in that understanding is not a way we know the world,
but rather the way we are (Polkinghorne, 1983). Koch (1995)outlined Heidegger's
emphasis on the historicality of understanding as one's background or situatedness
in the world. Historicality, a person's history or background, includes what a culture
gives a person from birth and is handed down, presenting ways of understanding the
world. Through this understanding, one determines what is ‘real’, yet Heidegger also
believed that one's background cannot be made completely explicit. Munhall
(1989) described Heidegger as having a view of people and the world as indissolubly
related in cultural, in social and in historical contexts.
Gadamer believed that understanding and interpretation are bound together and
interpretation is always an evolving process, thus a definitive interpretation is likely
never possible (Annells, 1996). While Gadamer (1960/1998) was not opposed to use
of methods to increase our level of understanding and to overcome limited
perspectives, he was emphatic in his stand that methods are not totally objective,
separate or value free from the user. He viewed bracketing not only as impossible,
but attempts to do so manifestly absurd (Annells). Koch (1996) described Gadamer's
position as one of supporting prejudice as the condition of knowledge that determines
what we find intelligible in any situation. These understandings are based on our
historicality of being and all understanding will involve some prejudice. He did not
support the notion that a knower can leave his/her immediate situation in the present
merely by adopting an attitude. His view acknowledged the unquestionable presence
of historicality of understanding and he worked to extend the perspective that these
positions play a positive role in the search for meaning (Gadamer, 1976).
Lincoln and Guba (1985) described questions of ontology (what is the form and
nature of reality and what can be known about it); epistemology (what is the nature of
the relationship between the knower and what can be known); and methodology
(how can the inquirer go about finding out whatever they believe can be known) as
essential in critiquing and conducting research. Extensive literature exists comparing
Cartesian or positivist to constructivist or interpretivist traditions of research (Denzin
& Lincoln, 2000; Gergen, 1985; Kvale, 1996; Packer & Addison, 1989; Pokinghorne,
1983). A brief review of these two traditions and their positions on these issues will
help frame the discussion that will follow about differences between phenomenology
and hermeneutic phenomenology.
On the other hand, the interpretivist framework of inquiry supports the ontological
perspective of the belief in the existence of not just one reality, but of multiple
realities that are constructed and can be altered by the knower. Reality is not
something ‘out there‘, but rather something that is local and specifically constructed.
Realities are not more or less true, rather they are simply more or less informed
(Denzin & Lincoln, 2000). Polkinghorne (1983) described this paradigm as an attitude
about knowledge, not a school of thought. Knowledge is seen as the best
understandings we have been able to produce thus far, not a statement of what is
ultimately real. Epistemologically, this framework sees a relationship between the
knower and the known. The notion of value-free research has been challenged as
questionable and it is believed that attempts to attain such a stance have resulted in
the loss of certain kinds of knowledge about human experience, such as meaning
making (Cotterill & Letherby, 1993; Jagger, 1989). Polkinghorne viewed research as
a human activity in which the researcher as knower is central. Denzin and Lincoln
viewed the investigator and the investigated as interactively linked in the creation of
findings, with the investigator as a passionate participant. Methodologically, the
interpretivist perspective may evolve, for example, in a process of interpretation and
interaction between the investigator and research participants. The primary aims are
understanding and the reconstruction of experience and knowledge. Issues of
reliability and validity or the quality of this type of research have been addressed
through the examination of rigor, trustworthiness, credibility, and authenticity (Beck,
1993; Denzin & Lincoln; Hall & Stevens, 1991).
Similarites and differences exist within the realms of ontology and epistemology for
phenomenology and hermeneutic phenomenology. While Husserl focused more on
the epistemological question of the relationship between the knower and the object of
study, Heidegger moved to the ontological question of the nature of reality and
‘Being’ in the world. As stated earlier, both Husserl and Heidegger took exception to
the Cartesian split between mind and body (Jones, 1975). Husserl believed that while
such a sharp distinction does not exist, individuals were capable of a direct grasping
of consciousness, the essences of whose structures could be seen in intentionality
and bracketing (Polkinghorne, 1983). Heidegger, on the other hand, further erased
any distinction between the individual and experience, interpreting them as co-
constituting each other and unable to exist without the other. From this perspective,
he saw bracketing as impossible, as one cannot stand outside the pre-
understandings and historicality of one's experience (Heidegger, 1927/1962).
While Husserl is not seen as falling exactly within the positivist frameworks of
ontology and epistemology, his early educational focus in the scientific paradigm is
seen as a continuing influence in his conceptualizations of philosophy. His
conceptualizations of consciousness and the relationship of the knower to it have
been described as Cartesian in flavor and focus (Allen, 1995; Koch, 1995). Gadamer
(1960/1998) critiques Husserl:
Heidegger, on the other hand, is critiqued for perhaps going too far in the other
direction. Jones (1975)credited Heidegger's move toward questions of ontology, but
questioned, as Heidegger also reportedly did, whether this path quickly ended. The
extension of Being and Time (Heidegger, 1927/1962) was eventually abandoned and
Heidegger's later writing became more obtuse and less technical in nature. Scruton
(1995)identified much of Heidegger's work to be incomprehensible and questions
how much of it was about his personal spiritual journey rather than philosophy. He
also questioned if Heidegger did not also fall prey, as did Husserl, to a quest for
universal truths, specifically looking at the human condition and the world.
Methodological issues
Shifting our focus away from Husserl and Heidegger, in particular, and moving
toward a broader review of phenomenology and hermeneutic phenomenology,
important distinctions are apparent in methodology. Phenomenological research is
descriptive and focuses on the structure of experience, the organizing principles that
give form and meaning to the life world. It seeks to elucidate the essences of these
structures as they appear in consciousness - to make the invisible visible (Kvale,
1996; Osborne, 1994; Polkinghorne, 1983). Hermeneutic research is interpretive and
concentrated on historical meanings of experience and their developmental and
cumulative effects on individual and social levels. This interpretive process includes
explicit statements of the historical movements or philosophies that are guiding
interpretation as well as the presuppositions that motivate the individuals who make
the interpretations (Barclay, 1992; Polkinghorne). While Allen (1995) argued that a
clear distinction between phenomenology and hermeneutic phenomenology does not
exist, he describes phenomenology as foundationalist, as it seeks a correct answer
or valid interpretation of texts not dependent on the biographical, social or historical
position of the interpreter. Hermeneutic phenomenology, in contrast, is described as
non-foundationalist, as it focuses on meaning that arises from the interpretive
interaction between historically produced texts and the reader.
In light of the descriptions given of these two traditions and their philosophical bases,
what impact does this have on their use as research methodologies? Polkinghorne
(1983) supported the use of the term methodology rather than method to describe
the use of phenomenological and hermeneutic phenomenological traditions. A
methodology is not a correct method to follow, but a creative approach to
understanding, using whatever approaches are responsive to particular questions
and subject matter. Madison (1988) supported the notion that method focuses the
researcher on exact knowledge and procedure whereas methodology uses good
judgement and responsible principles rather than rules to guide the research
process. This use of methodology requires the ability to be reflective, insightful,
sensitive to language, and constantly open to experience (van Manen, 1997).
Whenever phenomenology or hermeneutic phenomenology is pursued in the
research endeavor, however, Osborne (1994) was emphatic that the methodology
used needs to follow from and reflect the philosophy chosen as it carries on
throughout the project.
It is within the embodied relationship that the text or data will be generated and
interpreted in these types of research.
Participants are generally asked to describe in detail their experience of the topic
being investigated. The specific question asked is generally very open in nature, with
follow up discussion being led not so much by the researcher, but by the participant.
Openness is critical and the exchange may be entirely open, with few direct
questions asked (Koch, 1996). The reason for this is to encourage the interview
process to stay as close to the lived experience as possible. Geertz (1973) described
this process as getting at what participants really experienced, from the inside out,
not simulations of what they thought they experienced. Kvale (1996) cautioned,
however, that it is important to look for not only what is ‘said’, but what is said
‘between the lines’. Hence, verbatims do not necessarily capture all of what is ‘really
said’ in interviews. As well, van Manen (1997) supported the importance of paying
attention to silence, the absence of speaking, the silence of the unspeakable and the
silence of being or life itself, as it is herein that one may find the taken for granted or
the self-evident.
The result of this process includes the self-interpreted constructions of the researcher
and each participant, thus reflecting many constructions or multiple realities. Allen
(1995) stressed the importance of reading and writing as core to the production of
meaning in hermeneutic strategy. There cannot be a finite set of procedures to
structure the interpretive process, because interpretation arises from pre-
understandings and a dialectical movement between the parts and the whole of the
texts of those involved. What was called for is an obligation to understand the context
under which the text or dialogue was being produced and to bring forth
interpretations of meaning. These interpretations arose through a fusion of the text
and its context, as well, as the participants, the researcher, and their contexts.
Key aspects of the process are the use of imagination, the hermeneutic circle and
attention to language and writing processes. Smith (1991) described hermeneutic
imagination as asking for what is at work in particular ways of speaking or acting to
help facilitate an ever-deepening appreciation of the world or lived experience. This
requires an attentiveness to ways in which language is used, an awareness of life as
an interpretive experience, and an interest in human meaning and how we make
sense of our lives. To see something in a new imaginative way is to see it other than
it has been seen before and to integrate it into a new semantic context (Madison,
1988).
This interpretive process continues until a moment in time where one has reached
sensible meanings of the experience, free from inner contradictions (Kvale, 1996).
However, Caputo (1987) cautiously noted that coming to a place of understanding
and meaning is tentative and always changing in the hermeneutic endeavor. It is
therefore necessary to account for one's position and trace one's movement
throughout the research process using a hermeneutic circle.
Finally, reliability and validity can be discussed in these traditions as issues of rigor.
In phenomenological research, bracketing, which is incorporated into intentional
focusing on the experience, is one factor that is central to the rigor of the study. For a
hermeneutic phenomenological project, the multiple stages of interpretation that
allow patterns to emerge, the discussion of how interpretations arise from the data,
and the interpretive process itself are seen as critical (Koch, 1995).
Conclusion
Reference