A Reflective Note For Dialectical Thinkers: Cadell Last, Vrije Universiteit Brussel
A Reflective Note For Dialectical Thinkers: Cadell Last, Vrije Universiteit Brussel
A Reflective Note For Dialectical Thinkers: Cadell Last, Vrije Universiteit Brussel
ISSN 1751-8229
What went wrong with Žižek? We have with us two fundamental works of
philosophy, Less Than Nothing (2012) and Absolute Recoil (2014), with no simple
guide to how they can help us to resolve the major paradoxes and antagonisms which
we encounter today in epistemological fields as diverse as sexuality, politics, science,
religion and so forth. This work aims to play a role in resolving this problem by
making transparent as possible the main drive of Žižek’s philosophical program.
Towards this end let us reflect on the central aim of Žižek’s last masterwork, Absolute
Recoil (2014, p. 18-19):
“The present work endeavors to elevate the speculative notion of absolute recoil into a
universal ontological principle. Its axiom is that dialectical materialism is the only
true philosophical inheritor of what Hegel designates as the speculative attitude of
thought towards objectivity. [...] The consequences of this axiom are systematically
deployed in three steps: 1) the move from Kant’s transcendentalism to Hegel’s
dialectics, that is, from transcendental “correlationism” [...] to the thought of the
Absolute; 2) dialectics proper: absolute reflection, coincidence of the opposites; 3) the
Hegelian move beyond Hegel to the materialism of “less than nothing”.”
This work ‘repeats’ Žižek’s gesture as pure repetition with no desire to idealize the
end product, it is simply left open to be destroyed and repeated again. We ground this
work as a thought on the Absolute itself, as a reflection that attempts an intensive
mediation of the coincidence of the opposites. Thus ‘A Reflective Note for
Dialectical Thinkers’ offers the reader an attempt to understand dialectical thinking in
a subjectively authentic, pragmatic and historically grounded form which aims at a
speculative objectivity. Dialectical thinking is a useful tool with a concrete form (a
spiritual bone) which reveals an elementary structure to the historical workings of
symbolic reason that is at once metaphysically profound and practical. I also want to
inscribe myself into this work so that you can see the way in which I subjectively
engage with dialectical thinking, and to potentially help you to reflect on the way you
already deploy the dialectic, or the way in which you may start to deploy the dialectic.
2
The dialectic is something that can be situated between (as a coincidence of) two
dominant modes of thought today: deconstructive thought and metalinguistic thought.
Deconstructive thought would deny the existence of the Absolute, whereas
metalinguistic thought would claim that its conceptual schema (alone) clearly and
coherently represents (speaks) the Absolute. Dialectical thinking is something other
than both of these forms. Dialectical thinking gives us something of a glimpse of the
Absolute eternity of rational discourse as it speaks in and for itself. In other words,
dialectical thinking historicizes eternity (the Absolute). This glimpse was perhaps
best articulated on the very last pages of Žižek’s Less Than Nothing (2012, p. 1010):
“The voice of reason or of the drive is often silent, slow, but it persists forever.”
I would thus like to situate dialectical thinking as the eternal voice of reason itself
between the opposites of deconstructive modes of thought and metalinguistic forms of
thought. In deconstructive modes of thought what is emphasized is historical
relativity. What is emphasized is the historical relativistic nature of our constructions,
that any construction we conceive, any construction which we engage with the world,
is something contingent, something that could have been otherwise. In that sense
there is no such thing as an Absolute ‘eternal truth’ claim, there is no such thing as a
truth as we would think of it in the religious perspective as a transhistorical eternal
truth subsisting independent of human action and reason. From the deconstructive
perspective, any claim whatsoever is just a particular contingent relative truth
expressed by a historical sociocultural individual.
3
What does the dialectical middle ground look like between deconstruction and
metalanguage?
From my perspective I would say that dialectical thought situates itself in the mode of
an eternal present constituted by the totality of logos (inclusive of its movement, its
unconscious and its impossibility). What persists across time in language (or as time),
in the rational order of the logos, is that through our partiality, through our limitation,
we can come to reason, and through engaging with reason, by the subject engaging
with its partial limitation, it can transcend the partial limitation. Technically, you
could be anywhere and anytime, and as long as you are open and attentive to reason,
then our dialogue can transcend any space or time that separates us, or that would
create a distance.
In this way the dialectical reversal of the problems of deconstructive thinking and
metalinguistic thinking is precisely not to deconstruct language as irreducibly
historically relative, and neither is it to (prematurely, perhaps) jump into the mystical
beyond of a universal language. Instead, the dialectical reversal counter-intuitively
sees the potential in what most intuitively see as a limitation, of the way in which the
necessary self-limitation of reason directly unites the particular finite entity (the
creature) with the universal infinite immortal absolute (the creator). When this link is
lost, then all is lost. When we unite creature and creator we have perhaps the most
important ‘coincidence of the opposites’, where two things seemingly different (a
duality), are revealed as one thing (a singularity). The reason of the drive, logos,
allows me to (magically) go beyond my partial engagement with language, to express
an infinite judgement, and an immortal truth, despite the fact that I am a finite mortal
creature. Through the insistence of my reason I can be united with something that
persists. In Plato and Hegel this insistence is already very strong. One can see in
Parmenides and Phenomenology of Spirit that philosophy in its most authentic form is
something that allows one to touch ‘something’ (or less than nothing) in language that
is not merely historically relative, and at the same time it is not a type of objective
global view of the whole situation. We are, coincidentally, at the same time,
irreducibly partial and limited.
4
This is why the Hegelian formula for the Absolute is C=T (Concept = Time) (Kojève
1980, p. 111). The Hegelian formula for the Absolute does not recognize the
concept’s temporality as its failure to reach eternity (deconstructive thinking), and nor
does it recognize the concept’s temporality as immanent to a conceptual eternity
(metalinguistic thinking). The concept (“that is, the integration of all concepts, the
complete system of concepts, the “idea of ideas,” or the Idea” (ibid))) and time
(temporal reality) are one and the same thing, the deployment of eternity in
temporality (Hegel 1998, p. 38, 558):
“Time is the Concept itself, which is there. [...] In what concerns Time, it is the
Concept itself which exists empirically.”
Here, repeating Žižek, we can clearly unite the Hegelian idealist tradition with the
Freudo-Lacanian psychoanalytic tradition by way of identifying the homology
between the concept, the signifying structure of language and the subject’s temporal
position vis-a-vis this Absolute metastructure (Last 2018a). To define it as clearly as
possible, the Freudo-Lacanian psychoanalytic tradition is a tradition that proclaims
psychoanalysis as the “science of language inhabited by the subject” (Lacan 1993, p.
243).
5
conscious ego (on the register of the imaginary, the specular image), are brought to
confront the most real as an anti-identity, or non-identity (a black hole).
On the metalinguistic hand, Lacan often deployed the idea that ‘there is no
metalanguage’ (Lacan 2005a, p. 816) or ‘there is no Other of the Other’ (Lacan
1999a, p. 80-1). This means that there is no way to get an objective universal
language or absolute conceptualization, there is no way in which you can eliminate
the contingency and eliminate the partiality of your engagement with language. There
is no way you can develop a conceptual schema that is transhistorical (either scientific
or religious), because we are historical creaturely creators, we are living beings. This
is a sort of inability internal to the relationship between language and the Absolute. I
think that this conversation is important to situate in contemporary discourse
specifically between the emergence of language and the (potential) emergence of
transhumans (Last 2017). What I mean by this is that the emergence of language
(emergence of logos) represents a qualitative transition to a different type of
experience, and a different type of realm. And when we hear about transhuman
visions (as is quite common in our present discourse), whether about future mind-to-
mind communication via brain machine interface, or via interaction with artificial
intelligences, we get the image of another qualitative transition in mind, specifically
related to language.
Thus, with the formula C=T I attempt to situate dialectical thinking as a bridge
(potentially) between the emergence of language (the conceptual fall into time, or the
concept’s time: past-future) and some transhuman future (that we do not understand).
This transhuman future is a mystery pure and simple. Whatever the nature of this
transhuman future it could be that dialectical thinking is the structure of our thought
in its most rational form and thus our best attempt to understand how to mediate the
human realm in its transition state: not an asymptotic approach to the singularity
(Kurzweil 2005), but rather a mediation of a singularity (or field of singularities) that
are always already here right now. To elaborate on Žižek’s aforementioned insistence
(2012, p. 1010):
6
unconscious forces. The problem here, of course, lies with the very distinction
between reason and the unconscious: on the one hand, the Freudian unconscious is
“rational”, discursive, having nothing to do with the reservoir of dark primitive
instincts; on the other hand, reason is for Freud always close to “rationalization”, to
finding (false) reasons for a cause whose true nature is disavowed. The intersection
between reason and drive is best signaled by the fact that Freud uses the same
formulation for both: the voice of reason or of the drive is often silent, slow, but it
persists forever. This intersection is our only hope.”
In this context we may meta-reflect on our own historical engagement. Humans all
gather together to share in language. In this engagement, what we appear to want is
to infuse our language with our ownmost rational spirit (inclusive of its unconscious
dimension), irrespective of its partiality and limitation (inclusive of our partiality and
limitation), as opposed to being a ventriloquist dummy of the symbolic order. Thus
we are still very much in the mode of trying to represent our partial truth in language,
to give voice to our limitation. We will cry out in pain until that is realized. In the
Hegelian sense this truth is not the Absolute eternity of an immovable fixed ideality,
but rather the oppositional coincidence of the Absolute non-identity of eternity
(nothing, chaos) in a temporal becoming (something, order), where self-relativization
or limitation and partiality brings one absolutely closer to the universal, not farther
away (Fig 1).
Thus, instead of seeing language only in its negative historically relative limitation, or
as something to be overcome via asymptotic approach to a metalanguage, the
dialectician aims to see what we can accomplish universally in language, through a
radical partial and contextual engagement with reason.
7
2. Metaontology (or: map as territory)
For a dialectical program we do not need a metalanguage but we may find useful the
introduction of a metaontology. A metaontology is related to the axiom of the
Absolute as substance and subject (Žižek 2012, chp. 6). I would situate metaontology
as something different then a grand unified theory of everything (as is common in, for
example, big history (Last 2017, 2018a)). If you are scientifically minded or aware of
the scientific literature, the idea of a grand unified theory is persistent, and many great
thinkers and philosophers have tried to come up with a grand unified theory of
everything, a theory that would explain everything in existence or being.
There are perhaps two prominent examples today that would claim to be striving for a
grand unified theory of everything. One example would be quantum gravity in
physics, which represents the idea that one day we will have a complete theory of the
macroscopic and the microscopic, general relativity and quantum mechanics (Smolin
2001). This is the idea that we will be able to explain the birth and death of matter,
and everything in between, inclusive of reductionist explanations for life and mind.
Another contender for a grand unified theory might be self-organization theory in
evolutionary paradigms (Kauffman 1995). In self-organization theory there is the
idea that we can explain all emergent order in the universe based on local interaction
principles of spontaneous organization (Heylighen 2014, p. 14). In this view the
universe is totally relational, and everything we see in the world is a consequence of
evolutionary processes following or tending towards a logic of increasing fitness
which is naturally selected. Both forms of knowledge explicitly posit conceptual
schemas which would guarantee their Absolute universality, transcending the
postmodern insistence on historical relativity of the concept.
The difference between these types of grand unified theories and a metaontology is
that a metaontology is interested in the position of the subject inhabiting language and
the nature of the subject inhabiting language. Metaontology inscribes the paradoxical
move (essential for dialectical thinking) of epistemology as ontology (C=T). In this
view we see our knowledge as a part of the Absolute and our deepest thought as
Absolute’s own reflection. The reflective metaontological question for people who
develop grand unified theories is along the lines of action principles for their own
being in the world, for the consequences of their own knowledge constructs in the
8
world. When you (dear reader) develop a grand unified theory, how is that serving
you in the world? And what are the consequences of these abstractions in the world?
Metaontology also recognizes that there is a field of knowledge that is itself divided
between multiplicity of subjectivities, each of whom have their own grand unified
theory (which may or may not be contradictory and inconsistent with each other).
This dialectical consideration basically complicates things immensely because it is
hard to wrap your own mind (your own identity) around this level of complexity and
nuance. It actually requires that you are prepared and able to dissolve your identity.
9
In this way, with metaontology, we have to inscribe the observer within the system in
a very radical way. To put this attempt into the formula of the ‘Absolute’ as
‘substance but also as subject’, we do not only have to understand the abstractions of
general relativity, but we also have to understand the way in which a temporal figure
of consciousness, Albert Einstein, appears in history and constitutes the whole of
being with abstractions. This is why the Lacanian algorithm for the signifying chain
follows an asymmetrical logic over and above the signified: S|s. The map has its own
territory and points towards a horizon internal to and yet outside of itself, to be
immanently constituted by its own dynamical motion.
Now to build on this, let us analyze my own personal map, in order to grasp a
properly reflective dialectical work. I will cite the following quartet of thinkers from
each philosophical epoch: Plato-Hegel-Lacan-Žižek.
2.1.1 Plato
This can be philosophically grounded in the well-known fact that Plato’s Academy
had outside of its door “Let no one ignorant of geometry enter” (expressing the
importance of mathematics). However, we must also consider that a well-known
contemporary Platonic philosopher, Peter Sloterdijk, started his Spheres Trilogy
(2011, 2014, 2016) with a modification of this ancient axiom, claiming that by
“shutting out the ageometric rabble” Plato started a cult of “an intelligence coming
10
from the world of the dead” (2011, p. 9). In contrast to Plato, Sloterdijk would have
outside of his academy the axiom of “let no one enter who is unwilling to praise
transference and to refute loneliness” (ibid, p. 13). Thus, here we may think that the
two of the greatest living Platonist philosophers, Alain Badiou and Peter Sloterdijk,
embody this higher order contradiction between the importance of mathematics and
love. Here a question for a Žižekian philosophy, also very much open to a revisioning
of a post-Deleuzian Plato (2012, p. 31-32), is something along the double lines of: can
the worlds of the rabble experience (hold) the truth Event of mathematics?, can the
worlds of the mathematicians experience (hold) the truth Event of love? Do the
coincidence of the living lovers and the dead geometricians meet their singular real in
what Žižek articulates in his concepts of the living dead? (2014, p. 235).
Another reason why I am interested in Plato is because he is in some sense the arch-
enemy of postmodernity, which emphasizes thinking in terms of multiplicity of
multiplicities (over the One). To capture the essence of multiplicity thought consider
a well known principle from Gilles Deleuze’s A Thousand Plateaus (1988, p. 8):
“Principle of multiplicity: is only when the multiple is effectively treated as
substantive, that it ceases to have any relation to the one.” What is clear in this quote
is that Deleuze philosophy is trying to get at a total disconnection from the One (as
opposed to a positivized or a negativized One). There is nothing of a One in Deleuze,
just a multiplicity of multiplicities (inspired by the mathematical work of Gauss,
Riemann, Klein). Deleuze attempted to express this concept with the idea of a
suprasensible virtual plane of immanence, a centrifugal force spiralling out in a
multiplicity of directions indefinitely. This is a direct metaphysical attack on Plato
and the Western tradition. The Western tradition has tended to see a suprasensible
singularity as a type of centripetal force spiralling inwards towards a common
(extimate) core, a singularity that can (perhaps) be mathematical and emotional, a
singular coincidence of two fundamental opposites.
Thus it may not be a surprise that in postmodernity proper (among the rabble) we
have a situation where anti-religious sophistry predominates over Truth (mathematical
and sexual), and religious fundamentalism in its most distorted grotesque form
appears as its obscene opposite. In other words, postmodernity can be seen as the
absence of the sublime or the sacred (what Plato would call the presence of a ‘horror
11
vacui’). Of course, Platonic philosophy proper, in its advanced dialectical mediation,
can be seen as the most sophisticated attempt to avoid the sophistry of relativistic
opinion, while at the same time avoiding the dogmatism of an unknowable Absolute
closed to discursive modification (Žižek 2012, p. 77-78). There is really a good
philosophical challenge here for reason, thinking again this relation (or non-relation)
between Plato and Deleuze. In a precise dialectical move we should not be afraid to
assert that even Deleuze, the arch-enemy of the dialectic, may have his own most
historical oppositional determination. By doing this is it may be possible to inscribe
multiplicity directly into the One, through the historicity of oppositional
determination.
2.1.2 Hegel
Second, the reason I play with Hegel is for the way in which he attempted to
understand the historical movement of the One or the Absolute. If Plato is criticized
for his insistence on the fixed ideality, Hegel injects movement as fundamental. In
other words, the One or the Absolute can no longer be conceptualized as a fixed
transhistorical entity, and also can no longer be thought of as existing independently
of subjectivity. This is reflective of Hegel’s time. Hegel was writing at a time of
enormous transition, enormous rupture and enormous break with the old world. And
that is captured in his philosophy which can dialecticize transitions, ruptures and
breaks, where everything appears to get flipped upside down. Hegel very much saw
the way the Absolute was subjectively mediated, the way in which the problem of
love and the problem of the Absolute were central to the historical drama and could
be understood through radical dialectical mediation of this engagement (Žižek 2012,
p. 9).
In this way Hegel tried to think the One not as a totalizing sphere but as a One
structured by pure division. Hegel thus approaches the problem of love as Absolute
Oneness and the reality of a subjectivity seemingly divided from this Absolute
Oneness in the mode of a subject-object division opening onto a multiplicity of
phenomena (Last 2018b). The genius of Hegel’s phenomenology is that he
conceptualizes Absolute love as this cut or division itself and not as the sphere which
we supposedly fall from and return to. In other words, what subjectivity tends to
12
think of as a spherical unity is in fact the obfuscation of a hole or absence at the very
core of being, where the subject appears as a cut or a division. To quote Hegelian
philosopher Mladen Dolar on this minimal level of Hegel (2011, Part 1):
“What cannot be divided any further is the division itself. [...] The substance [atoms]
is permitted by the void, but [the ancients] did not have any inkling that this would
have any relation to the place of the subject. This is Hegel at his minimum, the place
of the subject, in the adage of substance and subject, is the cut, introduced as the
moving principle into being.”
From this perspective there is something about the One that requires a gap or a hole,
and this is where Hegel situates his dialectic which we may think of as the narrative
path (and where critics of Žižek claim he (re)introduces the ‘wobbly’ (contradictory,
impossible) subject). It is a transition from a geometry of thinking a global perfect
sphere (an apriori totalizing unity, or Oneness), and being able to think a local
division or cut where a story about being itself appears, narrativizing a totalizing
unified Oneness. Here is the crucial passage from Less Than Nothing regarding the
importance of understanding the narrativization of being vis-a-vis the Absolute (Žižek
2012, p. 15-16):
“The narrative is not merely the subject coping with its division from Being, it is
simultaneously the story Being is telling itself about itself. The loss supplemented by
the narrative is inscribed into Being itself, which means [...] the narrative already does
the job of intellectual intuition, of uniting us with Being. [...] It is the narrative path
[not intuition] which directly renders the life of Being itself.”
In this way we can approach the movement of ‘atoms and the void’ (something and
nothing) as opposed to a static-fixed representation of atoms and the void.
Throughout the tradition of idealism, culminating with Hegel, the idea that the
movement of atoms (something) was dependent on void (nothing) as opposed to some
13
transcendent other worldly something. This is clearly expressed in Hegel (2013, p.
15):
“[T]he void [is] recognized as the source of movement. This implies a completely
different relation between atoms and the void than the mere one-beside-the-other and
mutual indifference of the two. [...] The view that the cause of movement lies in the
void contains that deeper thought that the cause of becoming pertains to the negative.”
In other words it is clear here that the source the basic mechanics of the Hegelian
dialectic, the historical becoming, can be found in the relation between something and
nothing. This is a topic that Dolar further identifies as closely linked historically with
the concept of clinamen qua becoming (2013). This notion of clinamen represents a
type of formal curvature or twist in being itself that has a rich history in philosophy,
from Lucretius and Cicero, and even appears in Deleuze’s meditation on fundamental
movement of becoming (2013, p. 18):
“Clinamen or declination has nothing to do with the slanting movement which would
come to modify by accident a vertical fall. It is present since always: it is not a
secondary movement nor a secondary determination of movement which would occur
at a certain moment at a particular place. Clinamen is the originary determination of
the direction of movement of an atom.”
14
distortions must be inscribed as the truth itself, their narrative path, their becoming, is
the Absolute One.
2.1.3 Lacan
Third, the reason why I would play with Lacan is because of the way in which he
attempted to unearth the meaning of the Freudian unconscious as a form of
knowledge that is constitutively unconscious (meaning: a knowledge (form) which
does not know itself). The definition of the unconscious as a knowledge which does
not know itself is sufficiently precise to avoid the type of obscurantism which is often
levelled at Lacan as a thinker. What we gain here is a certain level of self-recognition
in the sense that we do not know ourselves. The unconscious means we are not as
self-transparent to ourselves as we would like to think: our drives, our motives, the
distance between our thoughts and our actions (Lacan 2005b, p. 526):
““[T]he core of our being” - it is not so much that Freud commands us to target this,
as many others before him have done with the futile adage “Know thyself”, as that he
asks us to reconsider the pathways that lead to it. Or, rather, the “this” which he
proposes we attain is not a this which can be the object of knowledge, as he teaches
us, I bear witness as much and more in my whims, aberrations, phobias, and fetishes,
than in my more or less civilized personage.”
Thus Lacan identifies the crucial psychical historicization of the gap or absence of
unconscious knowledge which is missed by all of the intellectually fashionable
secular humanisms which tell us all to self-realize and self-actualize. What these
ideologies obfuscate is the way in which the core of our being is never transparent,
and even terrifyingly abyssal (‘there is no big Other’). In other words, even for the
self-consciousness who wants to ‘self-actualize’, the problem is precisely that there is
no ‘global standard’ (perfectly clear spherical One) that one could use to measure this
self-actualization.
In this move we also gain an emphasis on the importance of the distinction between
the unconscious as understood through psychoanalysis, and the subconscious of
neuronal processes, which are endlessly discussed in the contemporary ‘brain
sciences’. What Lacan emphasized in the unconscious is not subconscious neuronal
processes that influence or determine our self-conscious brain activity. Instead, what
Lacan is emphasizing with the unconscious is precisely a type of knowledge which
cannot be known, and thus not something that can be approached asymptotically with
15
advances in science and technology. In other words, the unconscious is not
something that we will one day know through future advances in our knowledge. It
has a constitutive element of itself the fact that it is not knowable in principle (like the
conditions of singularities in the abstractions of general relativity, or like the location
of the subatomic particle before its collapse (measurement)).
Thus we can only approach the unconscious through the positivization of a negativity,
to see the way in which an unknown knowledge functions and structures human
historicity. All of this may be why Lacan found it so useful to engage with Hegel’s
dialectic of knowledge. Hegel’s dialectic is about the movement of the Absolute
knowable in its processual narrativization, and the straw-man of Hegel is that we are
on this asymptotic approach to total or complete knowledge as if the subject will
finally consume all of substance with its narrative performativity (Žižek 2012, p. 399-
400). But when Hegel is read through Lacan, and when Lacan is read through Hegel,
it is easy to realize that this is not necessarily the nature of the Absolute that is
revealed in their reflection. What we learn with Hegel and Lacan is that we must be
much more humble with our self-conscious knowledge, we must be much more
humble with the story (stories) we tell ourselves because internal to the story is an
unconscious real which escapes its mechanics.
In this way the unconscious is actually the true knowledge or order at the ‘core of our
being’ which precedes and orients our narrative. This, once again, helps us to avoid
a metalinguistic set of perfect concepts for self-consciousness, and also historical
relativism and deconstruction. The unconscious as a form of non-conceptual, non-
contradictory, non-identifiable real of knowledge that does not know itself and is
operative even if you think you have analyzed your own epistemology, your own
abstractions (Lacan 1998, p. 20-23):
16
well not be determined. In this gap, something happens. [...] [A]nd what does [Freud]
find in the hole, in the split, in the gap so characteristic of cause? Something of the
order of the non-realized. [...] At first, the unconscious is manifested to us as
something that holds itself in suspense in the area, I would say, of the unborn. [...] It
is not without effect that, [...] one directs one’s attention at subjects, touching them at
what Freud calls the navel - the navel of the dreams, he writes, to designate their
ultimate unknown centre[.] [...] Now [...] I am in a position to introduce into the
domain of cause the law of the signifier, in the locus in which this gap is produced.”
In some way, then, the unconscious of the symbolic order, the multiplicity of
narratives, is an invariant principle and the most real locus for the constitution of
subjectivity. In other words, the unconscious is there, present in its absence, in all
symbolic universes, as both the primordial abyssal cause and the indivisible
remainder (where the continuous open mouth of a spurious infinity meets or fails to
meet its own tail), the object-cause of desire, of any symbolic-discursive operation.
In relation to the symbolic chain the objet petit a is thus an indivisible remainder of
the subject’s desire which emerges at the core of the subject’s own division (own
repetition automatism in the symbolic chain). In this way objet petit a should not be
thought of as a substantial object, but can be thought of as a formal curvature in a
state space (and nothing but the virtuality of this curvature) (Žižek 2014, p. 248-249):
“[T]he objet a: an entity that has no substantial consistency, which is in itself “nothing
but confusion”, and which acquires a definite shape only when looked upon from a
17
standpoint distorted by the subject’s desires and fears - as such, as a mere “shadow of
what is not”. As such, the objet a is the strange object which is nothing but the
inscription of the subject itself into the field of objects, in the guise of a stain which
acquires form only when part of this field is anamorphically distorted by the subject’s
desire.”
Consequently, the objet petit a is a consequence of the symbolic but not on the level
of the symbolic. The objet petit a is rather something that corrodes symbolism from
within, like reason’s ownmost otherness. In this very important sense, what thinking
this unconscious real allows us to confront in analysis is, ultimately, the immanence
of sexuality. Almost without question it is the dimension of sexuality, with its
psychical libidinal energies and drives, which proves to be the worthy opposite of
reason, reason’s ownmost otherness. For anyone who has ever loved, for anyone who
has ever desired the unity of the most fundamental opposites, one will understand the
importance of the conceptual of the objet petit a and its role in the real of symbolic
functioning. What should be focused on, precisely, if one is to bring this concept to a
new level of understanding, however, is not the spectral unity that is at work in
sexuality, but rather the a priori contradiction or antagonism that precedes its
emergence (Zupancic 2017, p. 3):
“The pages that follow [in What Is Sex?] grew out of a double conviction: first, that in
psychoanalysis sex is above all a concept that formulates a persisting contradiction of
reality. And, second, that this contradiction cannot be circumscribed to reduced to a
secondary level (as a contradiction between already well-established entities/beings),
but is - as a contradiction - involved in the very structuring of these entities, in their
very being. In this precise sense, sex is of ontological relevance: not as an ultimate
reality, but as an inherent twist, or stumbling block, of reality.”
This notion of ‘sex’ as an inherent twist or stumbling block of reality is thus not
something that we can reduce to either the biological realm of animal instincts, nor
something that we can dismiss as a historically contingent social construction, but
rather, as a primordial and constitutive feature, the unconscious of the symbolic order.
This makes sexuality not only something that we should think of as on the level of
the symbolic (Zupancic 2017, p. 1):
“The point is that the satisfaction in talking is itself “sexual”. And this is precisely
what forces us to open the question to the very nature and status of sexuality in a
radical way.”
But also something that we should think of as a deeply intellectual, perhaps the most
intellectual, activity (ibid, p. 2-3):
“The satisfaction in talking (or any kind of intellectual activity) is “sexual” is not
simply about abasement of intellectual activities, it is at least as much about elevating
sexuality to a surprisingly intellectual activity…”
18
Perhaps it is time to talk more time to focus on what the rabble are always (not)
talking about, the negativity which underlies their positivized symbolic motion.
2.1.4 Žižek
Now to move to Žižek. Žižek’s philosophy in Less Than Nothing and Absolute Recoil
tie all of these figures together in a type of Hegelian-Lacanianism (inclusive of a
return to Platonic One that can think movement and the unconscious). What Žižek
adds to this tradition is trying to understand the status of repetition qua impossibility,
of a repetition freed from its impossible idealization, which paradoxically, sustains a
true or real ‘materialist’ idealism. In this sense, for Žižek, all talk of the One
structuring the symbolic order in history is the movement of the unconscious as the
voice and vision of the Absolute’s impossible fulfillment (2012, p. 651):
“What ultimately distinguishes humans from animals is not some positive feature
(speech, tool-making, reflexive thinking, etc.), but the rise of a new point of
impossibility designated by Freud and Lacan as das Ding, the impossible-real
ultimate reference point of desire. The often noted experimental difference between
humans and apes acquires here all its significance: when an ape is presented with an
object out of reach, it will abandon if after a few attempts to grasp it and move on to a
more modest object [...], while a human will persist in its effort, remaining transfixed
on the impossible object.”
How do we deal with this dimension of desire? For Žižek we do not reach this
impossible object in some futural dimension as the ideal light at the end of the tunnel,
but rather via the pure repetition which is the nature of the non-psychical drive
beyond psychic desire. Thus almost all of Žižek’s philosophy revolves around
understanding this transition between desire and drive (2014, p. 150-1):
“[I]n Freudian terms [the] drive [...] [is] a joyous repetitive movement in which gain
and loss are inextricably intertwined and which enjoys its own repetition. [...] In
other words, what pushes the drive is not the persisting attachment to the lost object,
but the repeated enacting of the loss as such - the object of the drive is not a lost
object, but loss itself as an object. [...] The [...] drive which emerges at the concluding
moment of the dialectical process [is this] shift from the idealizing progress of
sublation to pure repetition[.]”
In this way Žižek brings things full circle, without closing the circle, leaving it open
for the pure repetition which is the nature of the non-psychical drive beyond psychic
desire. In other words we attempt to think the inscription of impossible negativity of
the Absolute in its positive dimension, the singular eternal drive at the heart of the
19
temporal desires structuring binary opposition. In the mode of desire, subjectivity
experiences the real of being internally thwarted, twisted as a fundamental negativity,
as what is preventing it from uniting with the Absolute; in the mode of the drive,
nothing and everything change, as subjectivity experiences this same real of being
internally thwarted, twisted in its positivity, as what unites it with the Absolute.
In this way we can conceptualize the dialectical unity/oneness that structures Western
history (maths/science, politics, art, love) as a paradoxical impossible virtual entity
internal to the repetitive emergence of the symbolic order which can be neither
deconstructed nor captured and controlled by a metalanguage. There is something of
a conceptual breakthrough in this type of thinking because there is a tendency in
contemporary knowledge to see everything as relational (as opposed to Absolute). In
both Lacan and Žižek being is relational but what is interesting about the human
universe (structured by the symbolic order) is that it is defined precisely as the
emergence of the non-relation or the Absolute. This non-relation can be most
intensely approached in sexuality and politics where processes of ideal sublation
always obfuscate pure repetition. In coming to realize this Lacan proposed the two
step dialectical motion where one first realizes that ‘there is no sexual relation’ (ideal
sublation) (1999b, p. 144-5):
and then one secondarily realizes that ‘there is a non-relation’ (pure repetition) (ibid):
20
“I have also defined the sexual relationship as that which “doesn’t stop not being
written”.”
This is a much more radical ontology, an Absolute recoil, because it forces upon us
the negativity at the core of relationality (impossibility of sublated love with the
other) and invites us to explore a paradoxical ontology where we are not just thinking
in terms of relations between things present, but also the unspoken, the real absence at
the heart of things present. When one understands this absence one may be able to
approach a reconciliation between the body and love (Žižek 2014 p. 172-3):
“Love is not an illusory One of imaginary fusion covering up the underlying deadlock
of the sexual relationship; authentic love is rather the ultimate case of a weird “one”
in which this very non-relationship is embodied[.]”
The notion of the non-relation is pragmatic and useful, and theoretically very
interesting because this is where Žižek situates his understanding of the problem of
something and nothing, and perhaps most importantly, his engagement with the
concept of less than nothing. Whenever we engage with ‘das nichts’ in the mode of
ideal sublimation we always delay the creation of something truly new in favour of
protecting ourselves from the primordial void with a fantasmatic imaginary screen
with a presupposed established order of things (Žižek 2012, p. 691-2):
“[T]he image/screen/veil itself creates the illusion that there is something behind it -
as one says in everyday language, with the veil, there is always “something left to the
imagination.” One should take this ontological function at its strongest and most
literal: by hiding nothing, the veil creates the space for something to be imagined[.]”
21
Thus pure repetition embodying impossibility (non-relation) is how Žižek deploys the
dialectical machinery to approach creation ex nihilo, creation of something out of
nothing. The way he goes about it is innovative on the level of historical dialectics.
In order to understand we have to situate this conversation properly in its historical
dimensions.
Žižek situates the historical dialectic in a radical way on this level of inquiry. Instead
of asking the standard modernist scientific question: “Why is there something rather
than nothing?” (a question emphasized throughout modern science , since Leibniz), he
rather emphasizes: “Why is there nothing rather than something?” (2012, p. 38-39).
This is a question which inverts any coherent attempt at a logical positivism which
would presuppose a background. How do things (something) emerge from the virtual
void? This virtual void, which Žižek refers to as den in honor of the classical
materialist category proposed by Democritus, is not nothing but teeming with entities
which are somehow both more than something and less than nothing (Žižek 2012, p.
495-6) (Fig 2):
22
“Den is [...] more than Something but less than Nothing. The relationship between
these three basic ontological terms - Nothing, Something, den - thus takes the form of
a paradoxical circle, like Escher’s famous drawing of the interconnected waterfalls
forming a circular perpetuum mobile: Something is more than Nothing, den is more
than Something (the objet a is in excess with regard to the consistency of Something,
the surplus-element which sticks out), and Nothing is more than den (which is “less
than nothing”).”
Furthermore, Žižek’s engagement with the question ‘Why is there nothing rather than
something?’ can be expressed both on the physical reductionist level (questions of
general relativity and quantum mechanics) and the human or spiritual emergentist
level (questions of secularism and religion). Why is there this absence on both sides?
Why is there this void on the physical side where nature seems to be incomplete,
indeterminate, unknowing of its own self. This quantum void may seem eerily similar
to the unconscious as a form of knowledge that does not know itself. Is the discovery
of quantum mechanics the discovery of nature’s unconscious? And on the human-
spiritual side, why are we these conscious beings who strive for immortality and
eternity (in both religious and scientific modes)? It is as if we are pathologized or
colonized by some excess which can never die, which will forever overdetermine the
course of human affairs. At the same time, we all die, we all face the void of our own
existential dissolution, leaving our desires permanently incomplete, indeterminate, a
form of unknowing. This is what Žižek is getting at, and trying to think this
23
coincidence simultaneously: the fact that both nature and humanity is incomplete,
unable to determine and know its own-most identity, the core of being.
24
shoulders of those who came before us. Instead, with the notion of retroactivity we
think in terms of its opposite: future-present-past, where the future directed motion of
a subject (as its own cause) can transform the past.
Consequently, what happens when we flip temporality in the symbolic order is that
the future all of a sudden gains the ability to change (what we think of as) the past.
What this means is that the past is not a fixed substantial actuality but rather a virtual
construction in the present. In this way the future present of a work can retroactively
change that historical work. Thus, instead of totally destroying the works that feel to
us outdated, we can see the old in the light of the new, where a new thinker, by first
working through the old, allows us to see the old in a totally new way. This is what I
claim can be done with thinkers like Lacan, Hegel and Plato. When we think of
understanding the repetitive embodiment of impossibility qua potential, how does this
change the way we think about the historical dimensions of the unconscious,
movement and unity or oneness? How can these dimensions of historical thought be
re-thought in the light of new presuppositions? We can rethink the One: we can go
back to Plato with a dynamical repetition of the impossible, with the unconscious of
thought, and with incessant movement. We use the new to shed light on the old, to
bring it back to life in a new way.
25
The inscription of a repeated impossibility in the symbolic universe around which our
minds circulate changes the way we conceive the network dramatically. The reason
why this may be a better representation is that I think it allows us to think the way we
struggle to relate to each other on a fundamental level, where our identities circulate a
real antagonism for recognition which precedes any symbolic presuppositions
supporting our becoming. In this way we can see that there is a non-relation as
Absolute at the core of discursivity that structures our discourses. You can see this in
a discursive mediation (duel-duet), for example, between Slavoj Žižek and Graham
Harman (2017). Žižek would emphasize psychoanalytic philosophy structured by the
objet petit a (2012) and Harman would emphasize object-oriented philosophy of
thinking a new approach to reaching the ‘things-in-themselves’ (2018). There is just
an inability to relate, there is no way to mediate the two. Harman accuses Žižek of
sneaking transcendental subjectivity back into philosophical discourse; Žižek accuses
Harman of avoiding the way in which objectivity is always already mediated by the
subject. They simply circulate this impossibility, and we have to think the network
inclusive of this irreducible antagonism. It is not just a multiplicity of multiplicities
(Žižek and Harman as two indifferent atoms side by side), there is this negativity at
the core of the multiplicity of figures of consciousness.
The antagonism extends back into time, allowing us to perceive an archaeology of the
real. From this perspective can we do an archaeology of knowledge without the
historical relativism? Can we think an archaeology of knowledge that situates itself in
relation to (not a transhistorical substantial truth, or a ‘Perennial Philosophy’ (Huxley
1945)), but a transhistorical impossibility expressed as a historically idealized
repetition that inscribes contingency into its negativized core? Knowledge is still
contingent to the obstacles, to the real of a time, but there is still something of the
becoming of the Absolute here, something which overdetermines our discourse,
something which prevents us from all agreeing, from getting on the same page, so to
speak. In Hegelese there is something which prevents the integration of the Concept
(“that is, the integration of all concepts, the complete system of concepts, the “idea of
ideas,” or the Idea” (Kojève 1980, p. 111)). My point of reflecting on these non-
relations is to potentially help you, if you are following along, to play and represent
the nature of this symbolic order.
26
We can even go back to the ancient world to get at the texture of the becoming of the
symbolic order throughout history. Some of the questions that come to my mind are:
what are the questions that the human mind comes to find of great importance? Why
does the human mind come to find these questions of high importance? How do we
view these questions today? How was the Oneness conceived in Plato’s time or
within alternative conceptual networks? You could technically take any thinker from
any historical layer of mind and construct your own structural metaontology. In the
same way I am trying to build one from the perspective of Plato, Hegel, Lacan and
Žižek, one could easily do this with another layer of thought. The question would be
where does this field of thought take you? Can you think something that has never
been thought before by playing with a particular curvature of historical mind?
In order to better capture the geometry of these spaces we may need to play with a
different metaphor. In network representations we are inspired by metaphors of
rhizomatic thinking, multiplicity thinking, and so forth (which is the philosophical
ground of network ontologies) (Deleuze & Guattari 1988). But one might also find it
useful to use the metaphor of curved spacetime in Einstein, because in Einstein’s
curved spacetime, and in the Riemannian manifold, things are still all relational.
However, what is interesting about Einstein’s spacetime is that there are unified
unconscious impossibilities: singularities. Material repetitions, the unconsciousness
and the movement circle these impossible unities. This may (also) be useful for
conceiving the history of the symbolic order. Each map as territory is the becoming
of all of these webs of thought across time, and the way in which their repetitions
curve and warp the space around their point of impossibility. We are all becoming as
a part of this manifold of the symbolic order. In this way we can think repeated
relations of being plus impossibility informing possible repeatable relations.
This impossibility is not transhistorical in the fact that it does not change. The
impossibility changes but invariant impossibility as such informs possible relations.
The possible relations are informed by its internal points of impossibility (Zupančič
2017, p. 24):
“The non-relation [points of impossibility] gives, dictates the conditions of, what ties
us, which is to say that it is not a simple, indifferent absence, but an absence that
27
curves and determines the structure with which it appears. The non-relation is not the
opposite of the relationship, it is the inherent (il)logic (a fundamental “antagonism”)
of the relationships that are possible and existing.”
With this view we can at the same time think the symbolic in terms of effectivity.
Again, instead of map as not territory, map as territory (a positivized negativity). So
instead of thinking about the way in which Newton’s map does not get at the real of
the in-itself of nature, we can think of the way in which Newton’s map transforms
humans into space travelling astronauts. That is a symbolically mediated
transformation: humans went to the moon as an ontological fact on the field of
Newtonian epistemology. Indeed Newtonian epistemology is a good example of the
way in which the impossible itself changes, informing new possible relations. Before
the rise of Newtonian epistemology the idea of human beings actually travelling to the
moon was in a primordial realm of fantasmatic proto-science fiction (e.g. Johannes
Kepler’s Somnium (1634)). After the rise of Newtonian epistemology the idea of
human beings travelling to the moon became an actual possibility, an embodied
impossibility enacted through strict repetitive adherence to the scriptures of natural
philosophy. That is a question for the relation of epistemology to the world. But
what about the self?
In terms of a question for the self what are the consequences of inscribing
epistemology into ontology vis-a-vis the attempt of the self to objectivize itself (to
reach the core of one’s being)? When we try to think the curvature which attempts to
circle back on itself in a twisted structure, we get at the possibility that metaontology
is always about an Absolute reflection, an attempt to understand ourselves in the
deepest sense. We may find that this symbolic texture is realized by a future-directed
motion which calls back to the origin. Is the discovery of the self a return to this
origin? A return to a primordial impossible unity or singularity which births all
things? Or is the discovery of the self nothing but the process of this motion? In
other words, is the self in terms of a ‘self-consciousness’ nothing but a finite-mortal
curved asymptotic approach to (or circumambulation around) singularity
(consciousness as clinamenesque), whereas the singularity in-itself is the of
dimension of unconsciousness as a form of knowledge that cannot know itself? In
quantum mechanics this would be the dimension of the infinite virtual void, and in
general relativity this would be the dimension of infinite singularities.
28
3. Dialectical foundations
“[T]ime is the sublation (negation of the negation) of space, [thus] we can also say
that teleiosis is the inscription of time into space in the sense of space-time, of time as
another (fourth) dimension of space: teleiosis supplements the three dimensions
which determine the spatial position of an object with the virtual and temporal
dimension of its spatial movement. A purely spatial definition which immobilizes its
object produces a non-actual abstraction, not a full reality; the unfinished
(ontologically incomplete) character of reality which compels us to include the
virtuality of teleiosis in the definition of an object is thus not its limitation, but a
positive condition of its actual existence.”
Plato’s starting point with historical knowledge is that our phenomenal and discursive
reality, in its irreducible temporality, falls into oppositional determination. We fall
into contradictory appearances as a feature of the concept (Kant’s ‘antinomies of
reason’) which structures conflict and misunderstanding (as opposed to the eternal
harmonious One of perfect understanding) (Žižek 2012, p. 958-9). For Plato, thus,
the humans of the Cave are the humans who fail to see the way in which we are
singularly entangled as One. The oppositional determination that stimulates and
motivates Plato from the beginning is the oppositional determination between
religious zealotry (1) and nihilistic sophistry (0). Religious zealotry has this idea of
the eternal One that exists independently of us, for all time: God, basically, as the
ultimate reason and cause. The nihilistic sophist, on the other hand, has the idea that
there is no meaning in the universe, that we are just here for no reason. We are in the
realm of doxa. There is no invariant truth that you can utilize to organize your world.
29
Whereas the religious subject believes in an invariant truth: the truth of God. This is
the problem that Plato wanted to approach with the dialectic in a more sophisticated
way.
But it must be emphasized that the dialectic is a general tool beyond that particular
duality. As is common knowledge there are dualities everywhere: light and dark,
order and chaos, masculine and feminine, life and death, peace and war, health and
sickness, temporality and eternity, movement and stillness, something and nothing,
and so on. The dialectic is what helps us to realize the entanglement of the paradoxes
of these dualities, allowing us to approach them in discourse in a way that sheds light
on their singular coincidence. The general mechanism by which dialectics
approaches this is the thesis, antithesis and the synthesis. Thus dialectics represent a
type of triadic logic (A + B = C). In this logic the important dimension is that in the
geometry of the triangle, the third term, the synthesis, is never a complete closure, it is
rather that the synthesis leads to new oppositional determination. It sets forth a new
motion of coincidental structure. The One cannot hold itself in time as a perfect
unity, it is only actual as a division.
We could give a quick example of dialectical thought with Plato’s original query.
The thesis, antithesis and synthesis might be:
The not-One is the singular coincidence of the presence and absence, 1 and 0,
something and nothing. The not-One is what allows for subjectivities, irreducible
Ones (atoms). In this way you can see the way in which a thesis-antithesis (A-B) can
be brought to a new reconciliation (C). However, what is crucial is that this
reconciliation does not end the process of reason, but presents to us a new field with
new questions: how are we to make sense of science and religion in light of the not-
One?
In this perspective the why of dialectics (why bother?) is basically to avoid freezing
your reason as an eternal truth. Frozen knowledge is not real knowledge, it is not
knowledge connected to the real of life and mind, it is not knowledge which embodies
30
the non-relationship, and enacts the partial-limitation. In many discourses, religious
metaphysical and scientific naturalistic discourses, for example, subjects tend to
frame their language as if it is frozen in time, as if it is ahistorical. They try to frame
their discourse as if their knowledge reflects an eternal truth or is an eternal truth.
What dialectics forces us to confront is the movement of reason and the paradoxical
becoming of eternal truth. There is no system of thought that can close itself off and
complete itself. The only closure is the recognition that the truth is our very path of
becoming, that we are the temporal nihilation of the truth (or the truth is temporal
nihilation).
As philosophers interested in the dialectic we are able to approach the truth with a
type of rigour and at the same time a type of novelty injected into our discourse.
What is being studied is the discursivity of historical forms or figures of
consciousness. For me it is so invigorating to do this because you can take a field of
thought and you can see above or below the oppositional determination that structures
the characters of this field. For example, it may be useful, especially today, to take
the literature and discourse in quantum gravity, and pay attention to the forms of
consciousness that are becoming in this field. In this attempt we can study the way
two figures in this field will approach the same problem differently, or see the way in
which two figures are producing each other. If there can be a synthesis between them,
there very historical characters, the opposition of their historical characters, would
simply dissolve.
But what I want to emphasize here is the fact that the genius of Plato and Hegel is that
the very structure of their discourse is higher order. This is what separates them from
the other historical figures of consciousness. If one actually reads Plato and Hegel
one will quickly find that the dialectic is built into its very metastructure. In other
words, their work is represented in a triadic form making it exceptionally difficult to
interpret accurately but at the same time allowing for higher reflection of the
Absolute. The machinery of their ideational deployment is mediated by something
like a thesis, antithesis and synthesis. On a pragmatic level, when you become
sophisticated with your understanding of the dialectic, this can be infused in your own
work in a very meaningful way, in a very creative way.
31
The first example is Plato. In Plato’s metaontological triad, as many people know,
you have the physical world, you have the mental world, and you have the
transcendental truth of God, the Absolute. This is the structure of the Cave Allegory.
The physical world is the cave world, the illusory multiplicity of phenomena that the
mind is perceiving. However, what is truth, what is good, and what is beautiful, is the
One, is God, and that reality is suprasensible, beyond normal perception. In other
words, one cannot perceive God through our normal sensations (our sight, our smell,
our taste, our hearing, our touch). God is the ‘mind’s eye’, the suprasensible. Many
different spiritual traditions talk about this suprasensible realm of Ideas, but in
dialectical materialism proper, we focus on mediating the emergence of truth, as
understood in terms of the purely formal surface of an event (Fig 3).
Thus, you can see why thinkers like Badiou and Žižek would separate democratic
materialism from dialectical materialism. In democratic materialism there are just
bodies and languages, but in dialectical materialism there are bodies, languages and
truth (Žižek 2012, p. 42). The total situation is not just a pure multiplicity of
multiplicities, it is not just anything goes, it is not just that anything is correct. There
is an ‘up’, there is a direction, there is a way forward, there is an orientation. This is
in relation to the suprasensible truth of reality. The dialectic is trying to understand
the truth of this reality. In relation to the Platonic One, even if the Platonic One has a
32
difficult time understanding movement or the unconscious or impossibility (as we are
trying to inscribe now), we do have this idea of the truth in Plato as a Oneness that
orients us. In Plato’s Parmenides he states that:
“Human nature was originally One and we were originally whole, and the desire and
pursuit of the whole is called Love.”
This is what Badiou and Žižek and dialectical materialists do not want to give up, this
driving force or force of the drive, is conceived of as the unity of love. We see the
One in the way we find our true life’s organization, the way it structures the way we
want to relate and the way we want to become, and the way we want to express our
spirit.
The axiom of Plato is thus ‘monism’: ‘there is only One’. Everything is all and only
One, somehow. But as already stated above, what Plato cannot approach is the
movement of this One. I am tempted to give some speculations on how Plato’s
triangle is connected in movement. We could easily situate Plato’s ontology into
modern cosmology (as Roger Penrose does in The Road to Reality (2004, p. 20)). In
this ‘Platonic cosmology’ the big bang is the birth the physical, as God giving birth to
the physical; and then the physical gives rise to the mental, through processes of
evolutionary transformations (self-organization, natural selection, and so forth), and
then the mental returns to God around the cognitive mediation of Oneness (unity), as
thought reflecting on its deepest emergent essence. Here even Christian ontology is
helpful, since Christianity is essentially built on/from a Platonic ontology (Kojève
1980, p. 106). In Christianity, God falls into the physical world as a finite mortal
individual to demonstrate his Love of humanity, and then the field of finite mortal
individuals returns to God through a repetitively enacted collective belief in immortal
Love (embodying the impossible). It is still possible to hold this ontology with logic.
But even if you do not buy those speculations the importance of going back to Plato
in the structure of a metaontology (instead of starting with someone like Buddha), is
that Plato emphasizes there is a truth in the appearances. For Plato this truth must be
dialectically mediated, it must be understood by better understanding the structure of
our maps of meaning (Peterson 1999).
33
Now what happens when we move from Plato to Hegel and Lacan is really a
complexification and a sophistication of the Platonic ontology, but it is the same
structure. There is still the triad, but the nature of the triad is different. With Hegel’s
triad you have nature-logic-spirit, and with Lacan you have imaginary-symbolic-real.
You can see here that there is a structural overlap between nature-imaginary; logic-
symbolic; spirit-real. This overlap is not precise, not totally equivalent, there are
important differences, but they are comparable structures, there is some rough
homology.
34
operation we try to realize something real (we try to test the real) in a transformation
process. What is left over after this process, the gap between the imaginary desire and
the symbolic operation, is the real, which is conceived of as a constitutive absence of
obstacle which internally structures the symbolic. The relationship between these
three terms captures the way in which can read Lacan or one can read Hegel, or one
can read Žižek (Fig 4).
When thinking this triad we are trying to mediate the dialectical unity of the
opposites. We can formalize this with the very general formula A=B. The important
point to understand is that A and B co-constitute each other. The movement between
A and B is that if you took away A, B would disappear; if you took away B, A would
disappear. They depend on each other, they only exist in relation to each other, or
more precisely, they only exist in the impossibility of their relation to each other.
That is the core of oppositional determination. The dialectic operates in some sense
not from the position of A or B, but C. What is C? C is a fuzzy indeterminate space
of superpositions. In other words, C is not a higher positivity but rather a
reconciliation between A and B which can be identified by the dissolution of A and B
as contradictory semblances. The mistake of historical self-consciousness is thinking
A is true or B is true; instead of realizing that A true in the way you are relating to B,
and B is true in the way you are relating to A. But neither A or B is true in a
dialectical sense, since both will dissolve in the temporal mediation of the dialectic.
To demonstrate this dialectical truth in a historically real way, we could analyze the
becoming of the religious and secular subject. We can do this by pragmatically
operationalizing Johann Fichte’s I=I. Here the first “I” stands for identity, and the
second “I” stands for impossible image. With religious subjectivity we can say that A
35
(representing religious identity) at first could not equal itself in the form of its own
impossible imaginary (A=not-A). Of course for religious subjectivity you would say
the notional ideal would be something like Jesus Christ or Buddha, the perfect
subject. And A=not-A means that the religious subject cannot equal Jesus Christ or
Buddha. In other words, there is an irreducible asymmetry between the actual identity
and the virtual potentiality therein. Because of this impossibility A spontaneously
transforms into B via the practical deployment of reason.
What this means is that the religious subject becomes the secular subject. With the
secular subject, in its most extreme manifestation, we get the formation of another
impossible imaginary. In its most extreme manifestation this impossibility might be
something like someone attempting to become the subject of World Communism or
the subject of Global Utopia. In other words, the secular subject’s impossibility may
be something like the subject attempting to enact the ultimate notion of a world peace
and harmony. In our culture we are approaching the impossibility of this identity, we
are approaching the impossibility of the naivety of the secular subject, the idea that
the secular subject can participate in a transformation of our world into a secular
utopia. In that sense B has to spontaneously transform itself into C via the practical
deployment of reason. However, at the moment, it is unclear what C is, exactly. We
are in this indeterminate fuzzy space, and the identity of C has not yet emerged. This
could be why A (religious subjectivity) and B (secular subjectivity) still find
themselves in an identitarian conflict, perhaps most obviously and extremely
expressed in the cultural battle between Islamic fundamentalism and Western
secularism.
On the level of the collective we have the same pattern because the subject and the
collective of subjectivities mirror each other. The collective is simply the emergent
work product of all and every subjectivity. Thus, to repeat the logic from above, the
religious subject makes the Church, and the Church’s ideal is the Kingdom of
Heaven. Of course, in this construction, A does not equal A. In this way, by forming
the Church you do not form the Kingdom of Heaven, and this is a real that corrodes
the Church from within. From this you might get the State, which systematically
subordinates the power of the Church, so A turns into B. But the problem is that the
ideal of the State becomes secular utopia, which is still very much alive. However,
36
we are reaching a limitation of this ideal and maybe the State is now corroding from
within because of this impossibility. In the same way that we do not know the C of
the subject, we do not know the C of the next collective stage. We do not know what
is to come in the subject and its collective organization. Perhaps it is related to the
individuated embodiment of an impossible repetition beyond sublation (beyond or
without futural image). But, in either case, this is a practical demonstration of the
dialectic because it allows us to understand the structure of history, and brings us to
this little piece of the real that we cannot (yet) think (Fig 5).
Now that we have worked through the foundations of the dialectic we can give some
concrete examples that are of pragmatic application in the structure of knowledge
today. These examples are just meant to be thought provoking. I want to present the
field as I see the field and I just want it to be stimulating for future subjectivity to
work through the dialectical contradictions of A=B, to take these oppositional
determinations and play with them in a way that we can see a new C, a new singular
coincidence. Maybe new thought will emerge from this engagement. The most
important thing to note when thinking about this field is that, according to the
37
Hegelian dialectic, A and B are not equal or balanced opposites. In Hegelian
dialectics the opposites are asymmetrical, with one opposite (B, antithesis)
representing a lack in the other opposite (A, thesis). Consequently, when one wants
to synthesize a given field, it is important to remember that the path to C is most
likely to be found by identifying why a lack emerges with respect to the ‘higher’ term
necessitating the enaction of a ‘lower’ term (Žižek 2012, p. 303):
“The opposition of poles [...] conceals the fact that one of the poles already is the
unity of the two [...] [thus] the goal is not to (re)establish the symmetry and balance of
the two opposing poles, but to recognize in one pole the symptom of the failure of the
other (and not vice versa).”
38
everywhere and can describe everything, like a universal acid (Dennett 1995, p. 63).
However, there is still something that persists in the notion of religious eternity, at
least on the level of phenomenal and discursive historicity internal to itself. The point
is that there is no evolutionary argument or logical process which eradicates the
phenomenal-discursive real of authentic religious engagement. There must be an
enormous lack internal to the evolutionary worldview. To be specific, religious
eternity appears to strongly contrast with the evolutionary worldview because it is a
real that never changes, it is a real identity that persists as a perfect unified love
independent of time.
A (evolution) = B (eternity)
The structure of the oppositional determination between the sciences and the
humanities has perhaps had the strongest impact on intellectual or academic life in
modern times (Snow 1959). In the sciences we are told to focus on external
observation, formulating tests that can be universally repeated, situating ourselves in
relation to a knowable nature that represents a collective objectivity that we can all
predictively verify. We are trained to think literally and materially about the world
and our relation to the world. The world becomes something that can be captured in a
formula or embodied in an algorithm. In contrast, in the humanities we have a much
stronger emphasis on the experience of subjectivity, that what is experienced as
reality is most fundamentally a story or a narrative which is laden with metaphorical
knowledge and entangled with ethics, values and morals. For the humanities reality is
more open to emergent interpretation and conjecture, where there can be a
multiplicity of views that are all somehow valid and real.
A (sciences) = B (humanities)
The next tension we may focus on is one that is paradoxically emergent to philosophy
itself where an oppositional determination appears between analytical and continental
traditions. The differences between these forms of philosophy can be found in the
idea that analytic philosophy emphasizes an argumentative structure of logical rigour,
conceptual clarity, general laws and so forth. For the analytic tradition we thus focus
on formulating a symbolic knowledge that can be demonstrated to all linguistic
subjectivity in a way that leads to a cumulative and measurable increase in our
understanding. In contrast continental philosophy emphasizes a universality internal
39
to our phenomenal world but it is an experience that is not necessarily purely logical
or rational, but rather an illogic internal to logic. For continental philosophy we are
interested in experiences even if they cannot be shared between subjectivities via
language, and even if they are unrepeatable experiences that evade any formula or
algorithm. These experiences undeniably shape subjectivity and require their own
special attention. We may also say that in the analytic tradition there is more focus on
correlationalism and actuality, whereas in the continental tradition there is more an
emphasis on speculative imaginaries and potentiality. The main difference between
these two communities may involve communication where the analytic camps want to
emphasize information that can be universally communicated; whereas the continental
camps want to emphasize information that is universally experienced even if it is not
communicable.
A (analytical) = B (continental)
A (communism) = B (fascism)
40
The political division may mirror a deeper unresolved psychical oppositional
determination between individuation and collectivism. On the level of individuation
we would emphasize the becoming of the psychological unit, the irreducible
individuality of a psyche, emphasizing its potential to become different, its potential
to become other. Here the mystery of the self and its development is taken as the
central mystery of the whole. Moreover, it is impossible to know what the
consequences and farthest limits of mass individuation (or transindividuation) would
really be on the scale of deep time. By definition the farthest limits of the
individuated self would represent the capacity for total difference and otherness which
eliminates even our notions of self, leaving only pure individuation (Hallward 2006,
p. 82). On the other side you have the level of collectivization with the notion that
what is of the highest value and importance is thinking the good and the development
of society as a whole. Here instead of thinking about the individuation of psychical
units we try to think social becoming as a whole, networks of subjects, the
entanglement of subjects, identities and experiences that transcend the individual.
This view challenges us to think in way that does not ‘atomize’ the individual, but
rather thinks in a way that we are all linked together in a field (Wendt 2015, p. 173).
A (individuation) = B (collectivist)
The political and psychic issues are made all the more difficult by the sexual
oppositional determination between the masculine and feminine. The main issue with
the seuxal level is even being able to study it in the first place in a way that is properly
interdisciplinary. From the biological perspective everything is framed in terms of
evolutionary paradigms emphasizing adaptive reasons for sexual difference, and from
the social perspective everything is framed in terms of constructivist paradigms
emphasizing the potential for radical freedom from sexual difference. To make
matters more complicated, in terms of transcendental archetypes, both the biological
evolutionary and social constructivist arguments fail to recognize the eternal image of
man and woman reflected in historical sexual action which constrains the possible
good, true and beautiful. Thus we may say that the biological evolutionary paradigms
may have to recognize the free performative dimension of sexuality, the social
constructivist paradigms may have to recognize the natural historicity of sexuality,
and both paradigms may have to recognize the reasons why sexuality appears to be so
41
tightly intertwined with spiritual and religious foundations. In this quest
psychoanalysis may be of the highest utility (Zupančič 2017).
A (masculine) = B (feminine)
The foundational antagonism of scientific modernity may in fact be the relation and
mystery of matter and mind or the physical and the spiritual. The physicalist or
materialist view of the universe is founded in the origin of philosophical materialism
with Democritus and properly formalized by thinkers like Newton, Leibniz and
Descartes. In the physicalist view the universe is reduced to fundamental subatomic
particles which are governed by eternal physical laws. From this perspective we can
understand the nature of reality by understanding the way in which elementary
physical interactions are constituted at the lowest scales of being. Although this view
structures modern particle physics it also presents irreducible contradictions with
emergence and complexity (Carroll 2017). On the other hand, the mental or spiritual
view of the universe has represented the other side of philosophy in many ancient
forms of idealism. From this perspective we must understand the universe holistically
which necessitates recognizing that everything ‘falls into consciousness’. In this view
what governs the universe is not physical laws but the freedom of spiritual becoming
which always already frames what physicalists claim about materiality.
A (matter) = B (mind)
42
sense of the coincidence of these two determinations? How are we to make sense of
the relentless quest for eternity and immortality? (Cave 2012)
A (life) = B (death)
Finally: something versus nothing. This is the final oppositional determination I will
present in this overview of 21st century knowledge. On the one hand we have
something which we can think as the minimal existence of anything at all. Something
could be framed as being itself. Something is always the object or other of thought
which is why philosophy in some sense forms with the couple thought-being, and
why the first gesture of philosophy is the constitution of an idea of the ‘Absolute
Being’ (Dolar 2013, p. 11-12). Throughout the history of thought humans have
understood something in terms of substance, things, objects, relations or just a
presence. On the other side you have nothing. Nothing is usually referred to as a
void, vacuum, absence, or death. Throughout the history of philosophy, religion and
science nothing and its relation to human beings has received various interpretations.
In the contemporary field the idea that nothing requires a more sophisticated
inclusion in the structure of our positive knowledge has been seriously entertained
(Deacon 2011).
A (something) = B (nothing)
Now towards the end of this reflective note we must approach some final principles
that can help to deploy dialectical thinking concretely. I would encourage you to
think for yourself on these oppositional determinations that structure our field of
knowledge. In our present condition we desperately need a return to serious
fundamental metaphysical thought from first principles. The contemporary
metaphysical field appears to be fracturing. On the one hand we have ‘scientific
ontologies’ of quantum cosmology and the brain sciences (operating as a type of
metalinguistic evolutionary thought), which really aim to eliminate philosophy
proper. On the other hand we have a type of relativistic or constructivist ontologies
structuring most of social, political, cultural and gender studies. In some sense both
fields aim to eliminate any reference to a real Absolute. However, in the real of
history, both fields are exhausting their potential and may represent a disconnection
43
from the reflective real depths of human life: individual, familial, communal or
otherwise.
The void in academia appears to be filled by many Western thinkers tending towards
an Eastern metaphysics which grounds ‘non-dualism’. On some level this may be
happening because of the failure of Plato. The Platonic and monistic view can be
captured by the axiom of ‘there is only One’, whereas non-dualism represents as its
opposite of ‘One undivided without a second’. The difference is subtle but important.
What non-dualism means, ultimately, is that the world of appearances (of duality) are
a fake, an illusion, and that the truth is the underlying pre-subjective unified reality.
Consequently, the truth in this view is the ‘un-division’, the truth has nothing to do
with the division of the subject, and the appearances. In this way there is no space for
dialectical thought proper. In dialectical thinking the dualistic appearances have a
meaning related to the division between A and B (and the emergence super or anti-
space of C). In this structure parts are struggling for the meaning of the whole, our
partial engagement changes the whole because the whole manifests through the parts.
In the Eastern view there are struggling parts but the whole is at rest. Thus, in
Eastern metaphysics there is no C term where a radical engagement with the
appearances makes meaningful historical sense. One should simply recognize the
historical illusion and return to the pre-subjective unified reality (before the
introduction of a division).
There is a real challenge for Plato here. ‘There is only One’ has become
unbelieveable because it does not help us make sense of temporality. Maybe it has
become impossible for the modern ‘scientific’ mind to conceive or experience the
One. However, in the metaontological tradition deployed in this work, stemming
from Plato and then following Hegel, Lacan and Zizek, we have the introduction of
movement, unconsciousness and impossibility into the One itself, which retroactively
transforms Plato’s own philosophy. What this retroactive transformation opens up is
a revision of monism to ‘non-monism’ (or an invitation to think the not-One). The
axiom I would deploy here is ‘more than One, less than two’ (A=B). This axiom
means that there is a fundamental division and otherness, and we should take it
seriously as a meaningful historical engagement. Here we focus on the divided
subjectivity, emphasizing that there is something in the symbolic chain, something
44
about language, about logos, that continues to move even after it has been
deconstructed back to the (we assume) unified pre-symbolic substance. Even after
you have gone into your self-relating spiritual world, there is something about
oppositional determination that is essential for understanding the truth of being, and
the truth of history (C=T). As you can see it is the impossibility of the two to become
One (there there is more than One, and less than two). This is the impossibility at the
core of the two trying to become One.
Works Cited
Carroll, S. 2017. The Big Picture: On the origins of life, meaning and the universe
itself.
Penguin.
Cave, S. 2012. Immortality: The quest to live forever and how it drives civilization.
Crown.
Deacon, T. 2011. Incomplete Nature: How mind emerged from matter. W.W.
Norton &
45
Company.
Dennett, D. 1995. Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life.
Simon &
Schuster.
Dolar, M. 2011. One Divides Into Two: Dialectics, Negativity & Clinamen.
https://legacy.ici-berlin.org/videos/one-divides-into-two/part/1/ Accessed:
August 17,
2018.
Dolar, M. 2013. The Atom and the Void - from Democritus to Lacan. Filozofski
vestnik, 34(2):
11-26.
Hallward, P. 2006. Out of this World: Deleuze and the Philosophy of Creation.
London: Verso.
Kauffman, S. 1995. At Home in the Universe: The search for the laws of self-
organization and
complexity. Oxford University Press.
46
Lacan, J. 1993. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan: The Psychoses (Vol. Book III).
W.W. Norton &
Company.
Lacan, J. 1998. The Freudian Unconscious and Ours. In: The Seminar of Jacques
Lacan. Book
XI: The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis. Edited by Jacques-
Alain Miller,
Translated by Alan Sheridan. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.
Lacan, J. 1999a. A love letter (une lettre d’âmour). In: The Seminar of Jacques
Lacan. Book
XX: On Feminine Sexuality, The Limits of Love and Knowledge, 1972-1973.
Edited by
Jacques-Alain Miller, Translated with notes by Bruce Fink. New York: W.W.
Norton &
Company.
Lacan, J. 1999b. The rat in the maze. In: The Seminar of Jacques Lacan. Book XX:
On
Feminine Sexuality, The Limits of Love and Knowledge, 1972-1973. Edited
by
Jacques-Alain Miller, Translated with notes by Bruce Fink. New York: W.W.
Norton &
Company.
Lacan, J. 2005. The Instance of the Letter in the Unconscious: or Reason Since
Freud. In:
Écrits: The First Complete Edition in English. Translated by Bruce Fink.
New York:
Norton. p. 526.
Lacan, J. 2005. The Subversion of the Subject and the Dialectic of Desire in the
Freudian
Unconscious. In: Écrits: The First Complete Edition in English. Translated
by Bruce
Fink. New York: Norton.
Last, C. 2017. Big Historical Foundations for Deep Future Speculations: Cosmic
Evolution,
Atechnogenesis, and Technocultural Civilization. Foundations of Science.
22(1):
39-124. DOI: 10.1007/s10699-015-9434-y
47
Last, C. 2018b. Physical Emergence of Subject-Object Division: and a dialectical
approach to
reconciliation. Meoh Working Paper.
https://www.docdroid.net/YgELO8I/physical-emergence-of-subject-object-
division-v1.pdf
Penrose, R. 2004. The Road to Reality: A Complete Guide to the Laws of the
Universe. Alfred
A. Knopf.
Sloterdijk. P. 2016. Foams: Spheres Volume III: Plural Spherology. MIT Press.
Wendt, A. 2015. Quantum Mind and Social Science. Cambridge University Press.
Žižek, S. 2012. Less Than Nothing: Hegel and the Shadow of Dialectical
Materialism. Verso.
48