Cap 4 - Distributive Principles of Criminal Law
Cap 4 - Distributive Principles of Criminal Law
Cap 4 - Distributive Principles of Criminal Law
Deterrence as a Distributive
Principle
125 Much of this chapter is taken from Paul H. Robinson & John M. Darley, The Role of
Deterrence in the Formulation of Criminal Law Rules: At Its Worst When Doing Its
Best, 91 Georgetown Law Journal 949 (2003).
126 Glanville Williams, Criminal Law: The General Part §191 at 601 (2nd ed., 1961);
Wayne R. LaFave & Austin W. Scott, Jr., Substantive Criminal Law §2.1 n.88 (1986).
127 Warren v. U.S. Parole Commission, 659 F.2d 183, 188 (D.C. Cir. 1981).
128 Model Penal Code §1.02 comment 14 (1985) states: “Subsidiary themes are to subject
those who are disposed to commit crimes to public control [and] to prevent the con-
demnation of conduct that is without fault.”
76 distributive principles of criminal law
129 For specific authorities, see Role of Deterrence, supra note 125, at 957–958.
130 Model Penal Code §5.01 comment 359–360 (1985) (emphasis added).
Deterrence as a Distributive Principle 77
131 Model Penal Code §5.02 comment 366 (1985); Model Penal Code §5.03 comment 458
(1985).
132 421 U.S. 658 (1975).
133 It could be argued that Park was blameworthy for his failure to take sufficient remedial
steps after being informed of the violation—he ordered a cleanup but gave this order
to the same people who had allowed the problem to occur. But, while one might argue
that the government could have shown Park’s negligence—it is unclear whether they
could have—the point is that the Park opinion allows statutes that do not require such
a showing and, thus, allow criminal liability even if it is clear that no such showing
can be made, the defendant acted entirely reasonably. See Norm Abrams, Criminal
Liability of Corporate Officers for Strict Liability Offenses—A Comment on Dotter-
weich and Park, 28 U.C.L.A. L. Rev. 463, 476–477 (1981).
78 distributive principles of criminal law
134 Richard A. Wasserstrom, Strict Liability in the Criminal Law, 12 Stan. L. Rev. 731, 736
(1960) (emphasis added). He also notes that the deterrent effect may be in deterring
people from engaging in the strict Liability activity at all if they were concerned that
they might not be able to avoid the prohibited harm. “[T]he presence of strict liability
offenses might have the added effect of keeping a relatively large class of persons from
engaging in certain kinds of activity.” Id. at 737.
135 14 Q.B.D. 273 (1884). For more details on the case, see Paul H. Robinson, Criminal
Law Case Studies 14 (2nd ed. 2002); Brian Simpson, Cannibalism and the Common
Law: The Story of the Tragic Last Voyage of the Mignonette and the Strange Leading
Proceeding to Which it Gave Rise (1984).
136 14 Q.B.D. at 288 (emphasis added). The Crown afterwards commuted the defendant’s
sentence to six months’ imprisonment. Id.
Deterrence as a Distributive Principle 79
137 4 Wn. App. 908, 484 P.2d 1167 (Wash. App. 1971).
138 Id. at 913. Similarly, in Edgmon v. State, 702 P.2d 643, 645 (Alaska App. 1985), the
court holds that the “peculiarities of a given individual—his or her intelligence,
experience, and physical capabilities—are irrelevant in determining criminal negli-
gence . . . since the standard is one of a reasonably prudent person.”
139 Commonwealth v. Pierce, 138 Mass. 165, 176 (1884). See also Richard Singer, The
Resurgence of Mens Rea: II—Honest But Unreasonable Mistake of Fact In Self
Defense, 28 B.C.L. Rev. 459, 489 (1987).
80 distributive principles of criminal law
c. Grading Judgments141
140 For specific authorities, see Role of Deterrence, supra note 125, at 961–963.
141 For specific authorities, see Role of Deterrence, supra note 125, at 964.
142 Oliver W. Holmes, The Common Law 49 (1881) (emphasis added).
143 “[The] rational function of the felony-murder rule is to furnish added deterrent to the
perpetration of felonies which, by their nature or by the attendant circumstances,
create a foreseeable risk of death.” State v. Goodseal, 220 Kan. 487, 492, 553 P.2d 279,
285 (1976).
Deterrence as a Distributive Principle 81
d. Sentencing Decisions
148 Deterrence arguments have been used in support of a separate offense of robbery
(rather than relying upon offenses of theft and assault); in support of grading a vehic-
ular killing while intoxicated as manslaughter even without a showing of negligence
or causation; in opposition to application of the felony-murder rule to killings by
nonfelons during the felony; in support of the premeditation aggravation for first
degree murder; in rejecting a mere grade reduction for renunciation (preferring a
complete defense); in support of grading inchoate liability less than that for the sub-
stantive offense, and, where it is graded the same as the substantive offense in support
of making an exception to this rule for first degree felonies; in support of grading theft
of livestock more than other thefts of equal or greater value because the former are
particularly easy to commit and difficult to detect; in support of a lower grade for
intercourse upon invalid consent (by mistake or trick) than by force; in support of
grading theft by amount stolen; in support of reduced grading for “joyriding” (in
comparison to theft); in support of grading credit card fraud of even a trivial amount
as at least a misdemeanor; in support of grading incest no higher than a class three
felony, even if extreme moral indignation of the community would call for a higher
grade; in support of a grading reduction for a kidnapper who “voluntarily releases the
victim alive and in a safe place prior to trial”; and in support of relatively low grading
of perjury. For specific authorities, see Role of Deterrence, supra note 125, at 965–967.
149 For a more detailed account of the McCarty case, see Telephone Interview by C. Todd
Inniss, Eve Brensike, & Colette Routel with Frank Rago, Public Defender, Markham
Public Defender’s Office (Feb. 1999) (notes on file with authors); Sarah Karp, Mother
Copes with Cop’s Death; Markham Officer Struck by Harvey Police Car, Daily
Southtown, Sept. 22, 1997; Karen Mellen, Reckless Abandon; Families Want Driver
Charged with Murder, Chicago Tribune, Oct. 7, 1998; T. Shawn Taylor, Cops Arrest
Teen Linked to Officer’s Fatal Chase; Police Want Subject Held Accountable, Chicago
Tribune, Sept. 23, 1997; T. Shawn Taylor, Markham Cop’s Death Becomes Murder
Case; Bond Hearing Set in Fatal Police Chase, Chicago Tribune, Sept. 24, 1997; Paul H.
Robinson, Criminal Law Case Studies 1–5 (2nd ed. 2002).
Deterrence as a Distributive Principle 83
was convicted for the death of the officer under the Illinois felony-murder
rule, which punishes as first-degree murder any causing of death in the
course of a felony.150 As has already been noted, the felony-murder rule
itself has strong deterrent backing. The sentencing judge in McCarty also
thought to advance deterrence through the exercise of his sentencing dis-
cretion. Though he could have mitigated the harshness of the rule, instead
he imposed a sentence of forty years in prison, explaining that he needed
to “send a message” and that “a sentence does need to be imposed that
would deter others from committing such a crime, a high speed chase
with the police.”151 Such a deterrence rationale is common in the formu-
lation of a wide range of sentencing rules and policies.152
150 Illinois continues to read the felony-murder rule broadly where it applies, although
the rule’s application has been limited to “forcible” felonies. Ill. Comp. Stat. §5/9-
1(a)(3); see, e.g., People v. Lowery, 687 N.E.2d 973 (Ill. 1997) (upholding felony-
murder conviction for robber where victim shot at fleeing robber with gun robber
had dropped, killing bystander).
151 People v. McCarty, Circuit Court of Cook County, No. 97 CR 27339, Sentencing
Transcript 00392:11–13 (Sept. 15, 1998).
152 This includes, for example, arguments in support of the death penalty, in opposition
to the death penalty, in support of automatic imposition of the death penalty on life-
imprisonment prisoners who kill, in support of jail time for drunk driving, in support
of a statutory maximum for fines of double the pecuniary gain, in support of applying
a mandatory penalty enhancement for a subsequent offense to a second offense on a
simultaneous conviction, in support of higher fines for corporate offenders, in sup-
port of a judicially imposed minimum term of imprisonment, in support of fines for
offenses of pecuniary gain, and in guidelines for the exercise of judicial discretion in
setting the length of a prison sentence and the amount of a fine. For specific authori-
ties, see Role of Deterrence, supra note 125, at 968.
84 distributive principles of criminal law
153 Dan M. Kahan, The Secret Ambition of Deterrence, 113 Harv. L. Rev. 413, 414
(1999).
154 For specific authorities, see Role of Deterrence, supra note 125, at 971–972.
Deterrence as a Distributive Principle 85
155 LaFave & Scott, supra note 116, at §7.1, 520–521 (emphasis in original), quoting
Abraham Goldstein, The Insanity Defense 13 (1967).
156 Further, there is a deterrence argument for imposing greater liability in all cases of
excuse in which either internal or external forces press an actor toward a violation. As
Stephen notes in arguing against a duress defense, for example, “it is at the moment
when temptation to crime is strongest that the law should speak most clearly and
emphatically to the contrary.” James Fitzjames Stephen, 2 A History of Criminal Law
in England 107 (Lenox Hill Publishing, 1973) (1883).
86 distributive principles of criminal law
157 C. J. Chivers, New Leaders Send a Signal By Hanging Bandit’s Body, N.Y. Times, Dec 3,
2001, at B4, col. 6.
88 distributive principles of criminal law
158 See Paul H. Robinson & John M. Darley, Does Criminal Law Deter?, supra note 17, at
173, Table 1, col. (d).
90 distributive principles of criminal law
159 See, e.g., Mark Osler, Indirect Harms and Proportionality: The Upside-down World of
Federal Sentencing, 74 Miss. L.J. 1, 1–2 (2004) (“Under [Federal Sentencing] Guidelines,
a woman who holds just six grams of crack for her own use is assigned a higher offense
level (twenty-six) than someone who commits criminal sexual abuse of a minor
(offense level twenty-four), a man who commits negligent homicide by recklessly
shaking a baby to death (offense level eighteen), a woman caught stealing six million
dollars of public money (offense level twenty-four), or the executive who orders
employees to dump a truckload of toxic waste knowing that people may die as a result
(twenty-four). The crack possessor, in fact, receives the same offense level as that appli-
cable to those who finance terrorist organizations (offense level twenty-six). That’s
right—possessing crack is treated the same as funding al-Qaeda.” (footnotes omitted)
160 Neil Kumar Katyal, Deterrence’s Difficulty, 95 Mich. L. Rev. 2385 (1997).
161 See Oren Bar-Gill & Alon Harel, Crime Rates and Expected Sanctions: The Economics
of Deterrence Revisited, 30 J. Legal Stud. 485, 485–486 (2001).
162 Id.
Deterrence as a Distributive Principle 91
Thus, one might set rules based on present conditions but then, as
soon as one’s rules begin to have effect, it would cause those conditions to
change—and thereby change the calculations that justified the rules! In
other words, not only does reliable deterrence analysis require informa-
tion that is not now available and an understanding of the interrelation
among the relevant factors that we do not now have, but it also requires a
constant updating of the analysis because the relevant factors themselves
are constantly in motion. These are not the circumstances under which it
one can have much confidence in setting criminal law doctrine according
to attempts at deterrence analysis.
163 See Paul H. Robinson & Michael T. Cahill, Law Without Justice: How and Why
Criminal Law Deliberately Sacrifices Justice 16 (Oxford 2003).
Deterrence as a Distributive Principle 93
what the rule should be than by the actual content of the law.164 Other
studies have come to a similar conclusion.165
As this makes painfully clear, just making the desert-deviation rule
known to those whose behavior it is designed to control becomes a spe-
cial task for those who seek to manipulate behavior by deterrence-driven
changes in the laws. Because people assume the law is as they think it
should be, according to their perceptions of shared intuitions of justice, it
is in the deviation cases that criminal law has its greatest difficulty in
conveying its rule, for it is in the deviation cases where the legal system
must affirmatively change the community’s existing contrary assumption
about what the law provides. Yet it is rare that the law makes the needed
special effort to bring the law’s nonintuitive rule into the community
consciousness.
Further, it is the deviation-from-desert cases in which the system’s
deterrence-based rules are least likely to be honored during criminal jus-
tice adjudication. This is so because those who take the various discre-
tionary roles within the criminal justice system are likely to have the same
intuitions about justice as the other members of the community and are
likely to commonly allow those intuitions to influence their decisions.
Thus, the exercise of discretion by police, prosecutors, judges, and juries,
including the operation of jury nullification, will commonly subvert the
deviation rule, thus confounding the deterrence program and confusing
the deterrent message. Juries may refuse to convict a person, even if the
legal rules would seem to call for it, if the jurors believe it would be unjust
to do so.166 Prosecutors may similarly exercise discretion in subversion of
rules that produce what they see as an unjust result. Judges, by exercising
164 Darley, Carlsmith & Robinson, The Ex Ante Function of the Criminal Law, supra note
18, at 701.
165 In another study, in a survey of New Jersey citizens, it was found that they perceived
that the morally appropriate penalty for attempts at crimes was an increasing prison
sentence the nearer the perpetrator came to committing the crime. But even an
attempt that came in “dangerous proximity” to the completed crime was penalized
less that the completed crime. And when asked about the laws of the state in which
they lived, they reported that those laws essentially matched their moral intuitions.
But they were badly wrong. New Jersey is a Model Penal Code state that grades an
attempt at a crime that goes past a substantial step toward its completion as heavily as
it grades the completion of the crime. John Darley, Catherine Sanderson & Peter
LaMantia, Community Standards for Defining Attempt: Inconsistencies With the
Model Penal Code, 39 American Behavioral Scientist 405 (1996).
166 Irwin A. Horowitz, The Effect of Jury Nullification Instructions on Verdicts and Jury
Functioning in Criminal Trials, 9 Law and Human Behavior 25 (1985).
94 distributive principles of criminal law
167 John Clark, The Social Psychology of Jury Nullification, 24 Law and Psychology
Review 39 (2000).
168 Erick L. Hill & Jeffrey E. Pfeifer, Nullification Instructions and Juror Guilt Ratings: An
Examination of Modern Racism, 16 Contemporary Social Psychology 6 (1992).
Deterrence as a Distributive Principle 95
169 See, e.g., Irwin A. Horowitz, Jury Nullification: The Impact of Judicial Instructions,
Arguments, and Challenges on Jury Decision Making, 12 Law & Hum. Behav. 439
(1988) (finding that juries that are informed of the possibility of nullification are
more likely to acquit a sympathetic defendant); Michael Kades, Exercising Discretion:
A Case Study of Prosecutorial Discretion in the Wisconsin Department of Justice, 25
Am. J. Crim. L. 115 (1997); Robert A. Weninger, Factors Affecting the Prosecution of
Rape: A Case Study of Travis County, Texas, 64 Va. L. Rev. 357 (1978); Donna M.
Bishop & Charles E. Frazier, Transfer of Juveniles to Criminal Court: A Case Study
and Analysis of Prosecutorial Waiver, 5 Notre Dame J.L. Ethics & Pub. Pol’y 281
(1991).
96 distributive principles of criminal law