Legal Positivism - An Analysis
Legal Positivism - An Analysis
Legal Positivism - An Analysis
DigitalCommons@USU
Undergraduate Honors Theses Honors Program
5-1-2011
Recommended Citation
Chambers, Jonathan Brett, "Legal Positivism: An Analysis" (2011). Undergraduate Honors Theses. Paper 79.
http://digitalcommons.usu.edu/honors/79
This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Honors
Program at DigitalCommons@USU. It has been accepted for inclusion in
Undergraduate Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of
DigitalCommons@USU. For more information, please contact
[email protected].
LEGAL POSITIVISM
by
of
DEPARTMENTAL HONORS
in
Philosophy
in the Department of Languages, Philosophy and Speech Communication
Approved:
Spring 2011
introduction
research se minar into the philosoph y oflaw with Dr. Huenemann changed that. Taking Brian
Leiter 's book Naluralizing Juri.lprudence as our gu ide, we dived into the vast question of "what
is the law?" This seemingly simple question has shaped western society in too many ways to
acco unt.
for instance, Legal Realists - one group that believes all rights "are the creations of
governmen t and the legal rules it lays down,,1 - dramatically changed labo r laws in the earl y 20 th
century by changing the long-held belief that property rights were static. If their philosophy
hadn ' t become popular, would co urts have continued to side with factory owners in post-
industrial America? Consequently, if res ulting labor laws such as the Norri s-LaGuardia Act of
1932 hadn ' t been enacted, what wou ld our society look like today?
I began to understand that justice. morality, and the law are intricately tied , and how we
understand an yone of them will affect the others. More, I realized that legal phi losophy is in
constant motion, adapting to vogue ideas. Society, built upon the principle of law, likewise
The following is one perspective of what the law is. Though no theo ry is completely
dominant today. Legal Positi vism as formulated by 1-l.L.A. Hart, has arguably had the greatest
th
impact on legal philosophy since the 20 century.
Organization
This paper will explore Legal Positi vism (hereafter referred to as Positi vism), a theo ry
that argues for the interpretation of law through social rules. Its implications concerning
Austin's Command Theory, accred ited as th e first Positivist theory, will be given, as will
contemporary forms of Positivism. Within contemporary Positivism there exist two opposing
schools, each answering the role of morality within law in its own way. Both versions will be
Following the outline of Positivism, the theory will be contrasted to Kant' s ideal of the
law. Comparisons and differences in the two approaches will receive al1ention, leading to further
understanding of Positivism. Lastly, Pos itivist trends within mainstream Mormonism will be
discussed, of which it is hoped, will shed light on the theory's practical side. The two
concluding sections each include a brief explanation. so as to clarify their organization and for
The latter two essays were originally presented to research conferences at Utah State
University (2010 LPSC Student Research Symposium) and the University of Utah (2010
intermountain West Student Philosophy Conference). For inclusion into this paper, they've been
School. As a Presidentia l Scholar, Lillywhite recipient, and Research Fellow, he had the
opportuni ty to study under vario us professors in the Philosophy department - the highlight of his
undergraduate career. Former research proj ects were presented at the 20 I 0 Intermountain West
Student Philosop hy Conference , University of Utah; 2010 HASS Co ll oq ui Lull, Utah State
University; 2010 Research Day, Utah State University; and 2009 I-lASS Co lloq uium, Utah State
University. Whi le earn ing hi s B.A. in Philosophy and minor in Political Science, he spent the
He will graduate in Sprin g 20 I I, following which he wi ll move to Ann Arbor, Michi gan. There
Principally arising as a confutati on of Natural Law theory, Positi vism is a theory ofla w
that is based on social fa cts and not on moral claims. Positi vism hold s that law is based on social
facts that have been posited, or assertions, from authoritati ve figures (heads of state, judges,
legislators, etc). that qualify as law. These social facts. as will be investi gated later in the
Pedi gree Thesis. are found ed on social establi shment, and not on morality.
While morality and law may share similarities, and are used synonymously at times, they
are se parate fields. "The positi vist thesis does not say that law's merits are unintelligible,
unimportant , or periphera l to the philoso phy of la w. It says that they do not determ ine wbether
An exampl e of the similarity between law and morality in legal systems today is their
joint condemnation of murder. Whil e Natmal Law theory, the legal embod iment of morality,
would denounce murder on moral grounds and incidentally on legal grounds. Positi vism would
condemn murder on legal grounds, with little or no regard for moral justifi cation. furthermore,
while one version ofPositi vism-lnciusionary Positi vism or soft positivism. mi ght argue that a
moral value has become a social fact and thus become legally valid, Exclusionary Positivism or
hard positi vism, would deny tlle influence of morality in the formation o[la w (except tlu'ough
abstract means, further detai led on pages 4-6). These two versions will later be di sc ussed in
greater length.
valid. Exampl es of this include the laws that deprived Jews of property and life. These laws were
I. Morality and law share no necessary connection. Tho ugh law shares certain featu res
with morality, it does not depend upon morality for its justification. This is referred to as the
Separability Thesis.
2. Law is a social invention. Vario us methods are employed in the determination of who
or what quali fies as a social authority. These soc ial facts establish what qualifies as law. This is
The Separability Thesis. one ann of Positi vism. argues for the separation of law and
morality, as separate field s of inquiry. John Austin wrote. "the existence of law is one thing; its
merit and demerit another. Whether it be or be not is one enquiry; whether it be or be not
conformable to an assumed standard , is a different enquiry."" What the law is, independent of
morality. is one thing. What it ought to be, dependent upon morality, is another. No matter how
"just, wise, efficient, or prudent is never sufficient reaso n for thinking that it is actually the law,
and the fact that it is lUljuSt, un wise. inefficient or imprudent is never sufficient reason for
doubting il.,,3
To illustrate the LP view, an excellent point made by Andrew Altman may be useful.
"From the day they took power in Germany in 1933. the Nazis ruthlessly suppressed all political
2
opposition ... The Nazi regime enacted secret laws in order to persecute its enemies, applied laws
retroactively to absolve of criminal responsibility Party members who used direct violence, and
intimidated judges who wo uld not twist and stretch the meaning oftbe laws to favor Nazi
goals ... During the time of Nazi rule, there were private citizens who sought to take advantage of
the brutality and law'lessness of the regime ... they [informed] the authorities of allegedly illegal
acts performed by ri vals or enemies against whom they had a personal grudge. [After the war]
many Germans demanded the punislunent of the informers.,,4 Altman raises this situation and
then questions whether the informers should have been charged for previously legal activity.
The question boils down to whether the Grudge Informers, as tbey became known, had
violated the law. Legal Positivists take the position that they did 1101 violate the law by
informing on their neighbors. Though this position seems unpopular, it is disconce11ing to many
Natural La w theory argues, then the actions of the United States in regulating 311d fostering the
slave trade weren't legal. However, few legal theorists today wo uld go so far as to say they were
5
illegal; morally despicable, yes, but ill egal, 110
By taking the position that Grudge Informers were within the law, Legal Positi vists aren't
necessarily COlllillitted to condoning the Grudge Informers. Rather, the position merely entails
Within Legal Po sitivism, two juxtaposed schools of thought have arisen over this
sep31·ation. One, referred to as Soft Positivism (Inclusionary Positi vism), 31'gues that law 311d
morality do not necessarily sh31'e common ground. A similar yet di fferent claim is made by
J
Hard Positivism (Exclusionary Positivism), that morali ty necessarily is not configured into law.
These two versions of interpreting the Separability thesis have led to different schools of thought
Inclusionary Positivism OP), as put forth by H.L.A. Hart, consists in, " [the1simple
contention that it is in no sense a necessary truth that laws reproduce or satisfy certain demands
of morality, though in fac t they have often done SO.,,6 In other words, in any given la wful
society, it is not necessary that " laws reproduce ... demands of morality," though this has often
been the case. Laws of a legal system may consist in, though not depend upon, morality in
exercise and adjudication. for example, if a law uses morally based lan guage, then that law
doesn ' t derive its basis from morality , only its fLmction - specifi c to that law.
Interestingly, Hart acknowledges that the very existence of a legal system is based upon a
teleologically based moral duty for society to survive. This is referred to as the "minimum
content of Natural Law ." Survival of society, as an extended form of survi val of the ind ividual,
is the only acce ptable necessary corU1ection between morality and law. Hart explains "to raise
this or any other question concerning how men should li ve together, we must assume that their
aim, generally speaking, is to li ve.") Morali ty, centrally concerned with "how men should live
together" CalIDOt make any other necessary claim on law other than the claim that it is man's and
society's obj ecti ve to survive. [n order to achieve "minimwn content", social rules and
obligations are requ ired. These rules and obligations are what constitute a legal system. further
explanation of Hart's rules will be disc ussed in pages 8-1 1 (Pedigree Thesis).
4
To clarify, IP accepts morality as a system outside of law that may be employed in the
interpretation and implementation of laws. As said earli er, la w doesn ' t derive its basis from
Certain doubts as to the consistency of Hartial1 IP are raised when closely examined.
Ci ting David HLune, Hart says "Human nature cannot by any means subsist without the
association of indi viduals: and that association ne ver could have place were no regard paid to the
laws of eq uity and justice."s "Equity and justice," implying moral qualities, are necessary to the
credence be given? Either "it is in no sense a necessal')' truth that laws reproduce or satisfy
certain demand s of morality", or "[society] never could have place witho ut [equity or justice ]" .
While Hart does acknowledge this irregularity by elucidating his concept of the
"minimum content of natural law", he does not totally reconc ile this view with his claim that law
sho uld not "reproduce demands of rn orality." It seems that Hart's purpose in formulating hi s
concept of the "minimum content of Nat ural Law" was to establi sh the definition of law as one
partially al1d nominally defi ned by morality, and thereby independent fro m it in future analysis.
However, tho ugh morality ' s role is initia ll y m in imal, it is nonetheless necessary in the
By analogy, consider the parallel claim "that it is in no sense a necessary truth that laws
reproduce or satisfy certain demands of' mat hematics. Wh ile thi s claim seems tolerable at first
glance, one must keep in mind Hart's other claim that the purpose of law is to ensure the
existence of society. Society is 311 org311ization of two or mo re indi vidual s. Buil t into the notion
of society is a mathematical principle of multiple individuals. Similarly, built into the notion of
law is a moral pri nciple of equity 311d justice. It does not adequately exempt morality fr0111 law
5
by presuming that if morality's initial influence is inherent in defining law, then further moral
Joseph Raz. the principle ad vocate of Exclusionary Positi ViSIll (EP), denies any reli ance
of law upon morality. He argues for an in terpretation of the la w on strictly social grounds,
excluding any moral claims as legally considerabl e. "So urces of law include both the
circumstances of its promulgation and relevant interpretati ve materials, such as court cases
A variety of reasons are given as to why morality and law sho uld remain se parate
endeavors. When evaluating a judge's decision, law wo uld be greatl y sti gmati zed if the general
perception was that the judge's decision was due to personal moral beliefs. T he current common
notion of lalY is one of obj ecti vity and entwinement with morality. If that belief were to change,
Furthermore, a system of law in whi chjudges are tasked with determining the morality
behi nd every law wo uld encum ber the judiciary. One can imagine a system in whichjudges
must weigh each law against another. Figurati vely speaking, the weight given to particular
morals may be more substanti al, depending on whichjudge receives tJle case. The law must be
Another argument fo r EP is that mora lity and law are independent fields. Morality is an
outside value system which can but need not be used in the execution of la w. An exanlination of
the Eighth Amendment will pro ve ti-uitful in th is regard. The Eighth Amendment specifies that
6
"Excessive bail shall not be required, nor excessive fines imposed, nor cruel and unusual
punishments inflicted."lo The language used in the Eighth Amendment, typical of many laws, is
value-laden. In other words, it requires a system outside of the law to determine how those laws
are to be enacted. If the mechanism fo r determining value-laden laws was intra-legal, then a
central tenet of EP would be violated. for thi s reason, the definition of val ue-Iaden laws must be
assessed by an outside means. In this case, morality is th e non-legal system required. The
Online Stanford Encyclopedia offers anoUler in sightful analogy. The analogy is between
mathematics used in the Income Tax and moral ity used in legal systems. The law, in directing a
though the law may direct a moral requirement, morality is not a necessary component of law. I I
EP also ex plains how morality can become diffused into law. By considering moral
claims when det lmining a case. Ulrough the method described before, a judge is creating new
law and setting legal precedent. Because tbe case was dec ided by a legall y-authoritative source--
the judge-- it becomes law. In future situations. when similar cases arise. the law bas been
determined. Thus. moral claims are di sregarded and law can bui ld upon itself, independent from
moral claims. Once ilie judge decides, the la w ceases to be questionable and progress is made.
In this way, the most that morality can affect law is to instruct authorities to employ
One criticism of EP is that its differentiations between morality and law are merely
semantic. If morality is within the law or outside Ule law, it is still necessary for the
interpretation of certain laws. While Jaw's foundation lllay be bereft of morality, it nonetheless
7
systems supposedly similar to morality. such as mathematics, offer few services that law would
cons ider essentia l. One can imagine a system in which algebra or geometry is forgone from law.
While areas of the law would certainly be inhibited. such as taxation and construction law,
society would continue to function to a degree. However, it is much more difficult to imagine a
legal system in which moral input is entirely prohibited . Laws such as the Eighth Amendment
prohibiting "cruel and unusual puni slun ent" would become verbose and cumbersome as the legal
Because of its emphasis on legal precedent and rejection of extra- legal so urces, it
The Pedigree Thesis, a central component of Positi vism, holds that the leg itimacy of law
(legal validity) is founded on social fac ts. The recogn iti on of these social facts is the subj ect of
various Positi vist theories. Perhaps the original Positivist theory - JOIUl Austin 's Command
Jeremy Bentham and Jolm Austin , some of the first Positi vists, artic ulated the idea that a
lega l system is one in which a soverei gn iss ues commands and is obeyed witho ut ap peal to a
higher authority. Always backed UJl by the threat of force/coercion, the sovereign's conmland s
are legally binding in his society. A ustin' s view has been termed the Conunand Theo ry.
Conmland Theory had many di screpancies. and H.L.A. Hillt was a leading critic in
articulating millly of those criticisms. Austin' s theory failed to account for govenullents with no
discernable sovereign. Systems that wo uld be excluded from their theory wo uld include
parl iamentary and legislati vely based governments. In such govenunents where power resides
8
with the population, lawmakers, tho ugh granted certain coercive powers, do not possess ultimate
sovereign authority.
According to Austin, a sovereign has no legal restrictions placed upon him. Neither he nor
another body may place limits on the coercive/legal power of the sovereign. In constit utional
In the United States fo r example, courts accept the restrictive po wers of the Constituti on
as legally binding. The Supremacy Clause of Article VI of the Constitution states that the
"Constitution ... shall be the supreme Law of the Land; and the Judges in every State shall be
bo und thereby."'" A ustin, in answering this dilemma, pro vides a poor answer. Such
Using the colorful analogy of a gUIU11an, Hart cri tici zed A usti n's theory as being over-
simplistic. In Hart' s analogy a gunman command s a teller to give him the money in the banJe
The analogy is meant to ill ustrate the difference between the obli gations of the la w and threats of
an indi vidual. According to Austin 's Conunand Theory, the gumnan's tlu'eat s are equivalent to
the tlu'eats of a sovereign and thus woul d qualify as law. Austin' s theory fai ls to acco unt for this
discrepancy; in lawful societies, not j ust any individual with some power of coerc ion is able to
It sho uld be noted , as P.M.S . Hacker appropriately did, that Hart's theory was to be a
l4
conglomeration of both Austin's Command Theory and Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law While
12 Ke nneth Hi mma. I EP
13 Austin , John, L e~{lIres 017 .Jurisprudence and {he Phdosophy of Positive Law
I~SO as not to dil ute the foc us of this paper, Ke lsen's Pure Theory of Law wilt not be discussed herein. Ho wever,
readers interested in Lega l Posit iv ism will fmd Kelsen's theory strikingly si milar and worth eval uation.
9
Austin reli ed upon a "law-creating organ [i.e.] (the legal sovereign)" 15 to define law, Kelsen's
analysis was based on a " law-creating norm (the basic norm),,16 Hart, partially rej ecting and
accepting both, establi shes hi s theory as one socio logicall y based - norm s or social customs -
fo und in, but not necessarily created by, legal organs - courts.
For these reasons and more, Hart reformul ated Positivism fr0111 the traditional A ustinian
version and argued for an interpretat ion of legal systems as rul e-based. Hartian Positi vism
consists of primary, secondary, and further sub-labeled rules to categori ze the legal system.
I/ou's Th eo n ' 17
Human be haviuur
.-----
Social hahils
-------
Eli quellC .
-----------------
Sm.:i ai ruks
Ohli":JJ.i~'
~~ ------------
chcs~ etc
Mora lily
Sanction
Re cogni tion Adjuu ica ti(1I1
Ch ange
As can be seen in the diagram above, law is derived from social rules, or social facts. In
this way, Hartian Positi vism reli es heavily upon soc ial practices, customs. and traditions to
determine lalV. Primary rules (referred to by Hart as rules of the firs t type) are designed to
regulate the acti ons of ind ividuals (coercion). While primary rules are necessary in the
maintenance of a lawful soc iety, a society must not subsist on them alone. Because law is based
10
on soc ial facts, and social practices change and evo lve, it must refl ect social norms in any given
lawful society. These changes are made through secondary rules. Secondary rul es serve basic
needs of the legal system. They recognize, change. and enac t (adjudication) the law.
(I ) the rule of recognition, which 'spec ifi es some feat ure or features
ind ication that it is a rul e of the gro up to be suppOited by the social pressure
it exerts'; (2) the rul e of change, which enables a soc iety to add, remove,
and mod ify valid rul es; and (3) the rule of adj udication, wh ich provides a
Hart' s view, then, every society with a full -blown legal system necessarily
has a rule of recognition that arti cul ates criteria for lega l validity that
incl ude provisions for making. changing and adj udi cati ng law. Law is, to
use Hart's famous plu'ase, " the uni on of primary and secondary n lles." ls
When "social structures" (society) consist exclusively of primary rules, they are
primitive. Primiti ve structures are "pre-legal" and have "tlu'ee main defects". These defects,
unti l corrected by secondary rul es, perpetuate non-legal status. The first of these "defects" is
IIncer/aimy. Similar to our traditions of etiquene, there is no authoritative so urce to identi fy and
clarify what the customs are . " Hence if doubts arise as to what the rul es are or as to the precise
scope of some given rule, th ere wi ll be no procedure for settling thi s doubt, either by reference to
an authoritati ve text or to an official whose declarations on this po int are a uth oritative." 19 This
II
point is especially important fo r modern law. One need only imagine a society where no
distinguishable standard existed for the determination of its member' s actions. If an action was
The second characteristic of primiti ve societi es is the sialic nature of their rules. "There
will be no mean s, in such a soci ety, of deliberately adapting the rul es to changing circumstances,
either by eliminating old rules or introducing new ones " 7.0 When customs change, as is
inevitable due to human nature. rules and obligations ll1ust reflect those changes. However, in
primitive societies, there is no authoritative means to enact those changes . Similar to the
aforementioned authority probl em, Sialic rules are ingrained and unchan geable except through
The third defect is inefficiency. Unable to unitedly punish violators, primitive societies
lack special agenci es existing to exert "social pressure involving physical effort or. .. use of
forc e"?'I
An effecti ve summary of the Rule of Recogniti on was made by D.J. Galligan " [the Rule
of Recognition] determines which officials have authorit y to make law, the limits oflheir
authority, and, when disputes arise, who may resolve them. The second task ... is to confer on
specific rul es their authority as laws ... As a legal obl iga ti on, it is di stinct from other kinds of
obligation. such as one of a moral or religious nature. it s consequences being that legal rules
constitute reasons for officials to act in a certain way. and for their actions to be regarded as
va l 1'd •,,1.).
12
Brian Leiter, remarking on the Pedigree Thesis n explained the difference between
custom and law by highl ighting the Rule of Recognition. Witho ut the Rule of Recognition he
says, speeding on a highway and eating with one's mouth open wou ld be equivalent. The Rule
of Recognition is crucial in differentiating the two. Furthermore, indi viduals intuiti vely
understand the difference betlVeen a legislature 's regulation ofa highway and an ordinary
citizen's regulation of a highway. Both mi ght seek to enforce their will, but only one has the
authority of law. The Rule of Recognition is the socially obli gating force that identifies and
Hart's Rule of Recogn ition is decidedly social in origin and nature. It arises out of
practice and aIJows the legal system to have ob li gation. Without the R ule of Recognition, Hart' s
system of primary and secondary rules wo uld be insufficient in ·recognizing' what is law.
4
Interestingly, as pointed out by the Internet Encyclo pedi a ofPhi losoph/ , the citi zenry ofa
lawful society need not lUlderstand that the Rule of Recognition is the method by which its
officials identify law. "The reality of the situation is that a great proportion of ordinary citizens -
perhaps a majority - have no general conception of the legal structure or its criteria of
validity.""
All that is needed for the Rule of Recognition to function is that offic ials accept their own
behavior and practices as conforming to the law. In other words. if authori ti es accept that they
are the authoriti es and that their practices/actions must fa ll in line to certain standards, the law,
then by the very nalLlre of the authorities being authorities. citizens will accept their
13
indeterminacy in Positivism
Ronald D workin. fo remost amongst modern crit ics of Positi vism, le vels an interesting
dil emma. With in law, there exist certain cases where the law is silent. This is referred to as
indeterminacy, when the law gives confli cting or no guidance to a particular situation.
Indeterminacy can also arise from situations in whi ch the law directs an outcome contrary to
moral ity or ' sits uneasily in our gut.' Dworkin arg ues thaliP offers no solution to indeterminate
cases. Citing a New York appellate court case, Riggs v Palmer, Dworkin argues that IP cannot
account for the court' s legal decision. An explanation of Riggs v Palmer is needed. In the words
of di ssenting j udge John Gray " [Riggs], a lad of 16 years of age, bei ng aware of the provisions in
hi s grandfather's will, which constituted him the residuary legatee of the testator's estate, ca used
hi s death by poison, in 1882. For this crime he was tried. and was conv icted of murder in the
second degree ... This action was brought by two of the children of the testator for the purpose of
having those pro visions of the will in the respondent 's favor cancel ed and annull ed.,,)6
In this case, the law was quite specific in its direction, namely, that the will was in effect
and the ' lad' shou ld receive his inlleritance. As Dworkin pointed out "the court began its
reasoning with this admissio n: ' it is quite true that statutes regulating the making, proof and
effect of wi ll s. and the devolution of property, if literally constHled, and if their force and effect
can in no way and under no circumstances be controlled or modifi ed, give this property to the
l11urderer. ··,71
·· .
Dworkin 's contention is that lP 's view of the lalV is too narrow and doesn' t properl y
account for holV th e co urt ruled n There being two alternat ives in this case, an analysis wi ll be
14
given of both with the difficulties arising for IP. If the law was executed as prescribed, the will
going into effect and the courts transferring property to Riggs, then broad social consensus
(feeling that the law is unjust) might derail the va lidity of the law because the rule of recognition
would give conflicting guidance. The rule of recognition refl ects what is acceptabl e to those
governed and the view of those in authority. If a law passed by authoritative fig ures is legal in
the authori ties' eyes yet in va lid in those governed. then is the law still va li d? Beca use the law
did not meet the vali dity req uirement for social acceptance (being unj ust). and IP unable to
The other al ternative. the one actually chosen by the court. also presents a problem for II' .
The fact that the court di d consult extra-lega l so urces in its decision points to the nanow concept
of law employed by IP. R ightly argued, a theory of law is insuffic ient if its theories are
Hart answers Dwork in ' s criticism by clarifying his theory of Posit ivism . His theory does
not, as Dworkin says, seek ' ultra-gu iding laws'. (stipulating the fact that indeterminacy is a
necessary component of legality,) but rather it tolerates indeterminacy in the law. Hart only
wonders to what degree indetermin acy is acceptable. "Even if laws co uld be framed that co uld
settle in advance all possible q uestions that cou ld arise about their meaning. to adopt such laws
would often war with other aims whi ch law sho uld cheri sh. A margin of uncertainty should be
tolerated, and indeed welcomed in the case of many legal rules, so that an informed j udicial
decision can be made when the composition of an unforeseen case is known and the issues at
stake in its dec ision can be identified and so rationall y se ttled .,,79
own iniq uity. or to acquire prope lty by his own crime. These maxim s are dictated by public po licy, have their
foundation in un iversa l law administered in all civi lized cou ntries. and have nowhere been superseded by statutes."
- Riggs v Palmer - See http://www.coorer-ulen.com/cases.htm#Riggs%20v.%20Pall1ler
7.9 Hart, Concept of Law pg. 252
15
The "j udicial decision" of which Hart speaks occurs when "existing law fai ls to dictate
any decision as the correct one.,,30 Hart comments that the judge should " act as a conscientious
engaged in unjust ex post facto law making. If ajudge creates law where it is previously si lent,
and then that law is used in a I11at1J1er to sanction an action that was previously wuawful
(wliawful in that the law did not regat'd it). then these quasi legislatively-active judges are
Hart defended hi s tlleory oflegislati ve ly-acti ve judges from Dworkin by referring to the
accusation of the unjustness of"ex post facto law making" as ungrounded. The unfairness of
usual "ex post facto law making" was based on cases in which atl action occurred under the
former clear-guiding law, and was later changed "ex post facto". However, Hart rightly points
out that it "seems quite irrelevant in hard cases since these are cases which the law has left
incompletel y regulated and where there is no known state of clear established la w to justify
expectations.,,3? In other words, with no "expectations" to satisfy, the law cannot be unjust when
Until Hart's 1994 Postscript to Dworkin. Hartian Positivism was thought to exclude
moral conside rations. However, with Hart's recen t reformulation, morality in law may be
interpretation of law, what of one of its central premises: '·[that it is tlle] simple contention that it
is in no sense a necessary truth that laws reproduce or satisfy certain demands of morality,,?33
16
Specifically concerning the outcome of Riggs v Palmer, it seems that the law certainly
acquiesced to the "demands of morality." With Hart' s adaptations, one is left to wonder what IP
Fwther, if Hart 's explanation is true, then how canjudges be expected to rule on an area
previously umegulated? Ifno expectation ex ists for ajudge to vio late, conversely, how can a
judge pass a legitimate ruling based on ... nothing. Something is clearly lacking from l-lrut's
explanation.
A n Oxy moron?
introduction
Immanuel Kant is known as many thin gs: theo logist, rnetaphysicist genius, moral
philosopher ... but what about Legal Positi vist? Jurisp rudential theories have trad iti onally
compared Kant' s legal philo sophy to Natural Law theory. forming a del icate relationship
between the two; howeve r, is this compariso n accurate? Th is section will argue that Kant's
analysis oflaw was fundamentally Legal Positivist in doct rine. First, Krult 'S moral philosophy
will be exp lained. After. Kantian ethi cs wil l be compared ru1d contrasted with Legal Positivism.
Finally, irreconcil able flaws in Krult' S reaso ning will also discussed.
Underlying much of Kant' s writings on the nature of soc iety and law is a Lega l Positi vist
Rights
17
In his famo us Categorical Imperative Kant states "act only according to that maxim
whereby you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law.,,34 Topically this
wo uld seem contrary to the Legal Positivist approach to rights. for a Kantian, in order for all
actions to be moral, they must be hypothetically expandable to all persons. If an action wo uld
violate this principle, it would somehow violate an individ ual' s rights. In contrast, a Legal
Positi vist would employ sociological means to determine whether an action violated some degree
of normalcy in a given society. Yet further inspection reveals Kant's true purpose when put in
"However well disposed and la w-abiding men might be, it still lies a priori in the rationa l
Idea of such a condition ... that before a public la wful condition is established, indi vidual men,
peoples, and states can never be secure against violence from one another, since each has its own
right to do what seems right and good to it. ,,35 In a state of nature, Kant believed that all persons
will ultimately do what they think is best. In this state of nature, persons would use empirical
j udgment, which is inherently subj ective . Morality for Kant was something ac hieved t1u-ough
reaso n. In a state of nature, people would rely upon thei r personal judgment to determine what
"seems right and good" to do . Because those judgments are based on empirical influences, they
are ' COlTUpt' and inadequate for uni versal application. Thu s, in order for morality to be possible,
the state of nature must be left behind and persons must enter into a social compact, submitting
to laws t11at can be universally applied. These laws. though perhaps not perfect ly just, are
36
preferable to an existence in which reason - and t11uS morality - is absent
i8
Necessity of Public Offici als
Kant believed the state was necessary in order for rights and freedo ms to exist. A
rephrasing of Kant's statement, keeping its original intent, cou ld be: ' [each indi vid ual) has [his
or her) own right to do whal seems righl and good to it, [which leaves morality unattainable,
until states come into being.)' jf every individual was to have freedom of wi ll and rights, then
some inte rcessory being wo uld need to inte ract. Otherwise, as Kant hypothesized, freedom of
This intercessory being, taking the form of the slate and the state's executors, i.e. public
servants/officials, would necessarily coerce certain individua ls when those indi viduals violated
the freedom of others. A state wo uld be morall y justified in pursuin g thi s course of act ion if its
environmel1l where publ ic officials are absent, the other a modern society.
I. Treg is gathering apples for the coming wint er. Upon findin g a suffici ent amount of
apples, Treg puts the app les in a pile at the entrance to his cave and enters the cave to sleep.
Geth is walking along when he discovers the food suppl y. Knowing these apples were gathered
for the sustenance of another, Geth nonetheless decides 10 take the appl es regardl ess of the
conseq uences for Treg. Treg awakens awhile later, discovers ul at his stockpile is missing but is
unable to gather anymore apples and starves as a result. Accordin g to Kant, Geth 's actions were
immoral because he treated someone else as a means. His actions couldn' t be duplicated
universally. Finally, and perhaps most wrongly. Geth deprived Treg of the freedom of choice.
19
2. Greg is gathering eno ugh money for the retirement years. Upon depositing a
sufficient amoul1l of money in the bank, Greg retires to Arizona to lVatch reruns of MASH and
Matlock. Beth, an employee of the bank and an identity thi ef, is searching for helpless victims to
take advantage of. Upon discovering Greg's savings account, Beth decides to take the money
regardl ess ofLhe consequences for Greg. A whil e later Greg receives a notice from the bank of
his insufficient fund s. Greg becomes a Wal-Mart greeter to pay for his twilight activities and
simultaneo usly informs the sheriff s department of the theft. Upon investigation, Beth is caught
and forc ed to rellU'n the money to Greg. Though the sheriff s department coerced Beth into
returning Greg's resources, their actions were moral beca use they acted in a way that could be
Interestingly, in Kant' s view, an action can be 1110ral. despite its superficial immorality -
if it preserves the freedom of others. Yet tllis contradi cts Kant 's reply to Swi ss philoso pher
Benjamin Constant. Constant inquired of Kant as to whether it was morally justifiabl e to lie to
protect someone from a murderer. Writing in his On (/ Supposed Righi 10 Tell Liesfi'oll1
Benevolenl Molives, Kant defended the application of his theory and verified that it was morally
wrong to lie to a murderer even when the murderer' s inunoral intent is kno wn.
Kant 's views seem contradictory. On one hand he believes states are morally justifi ed in
their coercive po wers, yet he also believes ind ividual s can never lie. even to protect another.
Perhaps for Kant, inaction by the state in even one in stance is substantially more dangero us to
universal freedom than occasional impairment of indi vidual freedom. for example, imagine that
Beth from the prev ious story had in stead been framed , and the sheriff kno ws her innocence.
After deliberation by the cou rts, she is to be executed in the public square. If the state
20
approached the sheriff inquiring her whereabo uts, would he be morally allowed to lie on her
behalf? If freedom is to exist for anyone, the state must exist. And for the state to continue, its
orders/laws must be obeyed. The sheriffs decision thus precipitates between denying freedom
Although, of course. it wou ld be wrong for the Kantian sheriff to cons ider the possible
consequences of his actions, he wo uld still have difficulty in making a decision ifhe considered
the problem as choosing between lying and obeying the state. Both seem to have a first order
Kant endorses both possibilities thus produci ng confusion. He is both adamant that the
state - tlu'ough the will of the sovereign - was to have fina l say in all coercive decisions, and that
it is never morally permissible to treat another as a means to an ends. This dilenuna is murky
legal views that are large ly cOl1sequentialist. Despite these compl exit ies, Kant shares the view
wi th Legal Positi vists that public officials are a necessary part of the law.
The third element in our focus is the concept of the sovere ign. Jolm Austin . one of the
original fomenters of Lega l Po siti vism. argued that law is nothin g more than the commands of
the sovereign. This sovereign. an ungoverned governor, is the origi nal source of law. Though
his laws create duties for the subjects of a state, he is the only indi vidual upon whom no legal
duty to observe the law exists. The definition of a sovereign can be simplified as : "one who
21
receives habitual obedience from the bulk of the population, but who does not habitually obey
Kant's thoughts on the topic are surprisingly similar to Austin's. "Man's equality as a
subject migbt be formu lated as fo llows. Each member of the conunonwealth has rights of
coercion in relation to all the others excep t in relation to the head of state. for he alone is not a
member of the commonwealth, but its creator or preserver, and he alone is authorized to coerce
others without being subj ect to any coercive law himself. But all who are subject to laws are the
subjects of the state, and are thus subj ect to the right of coercion along with all other members of
the conunonwealth; the only exception is a single person (in either the physical or the moral
sense of the word) the head of state, tlu'o ugh whom alone tlle rightful coercion of all other
members can be exercised. for if he too co uld be coerced, he wo uld not be the head of state, and
Admittedly, modern Legal Positivists are apt to distinguish themselves from Austin 's
problematic theori 9; nevertheless, Kantian and early Legal Positivist views of the command-
must issue commands that are wliversally applicable yet at tlle same time inapplicable to himself.
A seeming contradiction, perhaps Kant was not able to full y elaborate his meaning.
An End to Co nj ectures
While many more factors would need to be considered before Kant was conclusively
labeled a Legal Positivist, Kant's political views do indicate such a legal positivist mentality.
22
Drawing upon the words of the pbilosopher himse lf, "In law a man is guilty when he violates the
rights of others. In ethics he is guilty ifhe only thinks of doing SO. ,,40 Kant, employing a form of
the Separabil ity thesis, saw morality and law as separate entities. Eerily Austinian in nature 41 ,
Kant's jurisprudential views are reservedly Positivist in theory. For these and other reasons,
Introduction
"We believe in being subject to kings. presidents, miers, and magistrates, in obeying,
honoring, and sustaining the la w.,,47. Written by the Mormon propbet Joseph Smith in the year
43
1842, only 12 years after the found ing of the LDS chu rch , the LDS fa ith has departed from
traditional Clu'istian understandings of law by adopting a view compatible with H.L.A. Hart's
legal positivism. This section will demonstrate why the Mormon approach to government and
44
law is agreeable with Legal Positivism , focu sing on Hart's theory. In order to do this,
explana tions of Mormon doctrinal beliefs will be given with emphasis placed on scriptlu'al and
23
historical examples. H.L.A. I-Iart's legal positivist theory will also be briefly introd uced with key
As stated earlier, one of the 13 core articles of faith states that Mormons "believe in being
subject to kings, presidents, rulers, and magistrates, in obeying. honoring, and sustaining the
law." At the center of Mormon belief is the understanding that two categories of laws exist:
hea venly laws and ealthly laws. Not mutuall y exclusive nor completely compatible, heavenl y
laws and earthly laws serve different fWlctions. Whil e heavenly laws pertain to irrevocable
commands given by deity, earthly laws pertain to the institutions and governments presiding over
" We believe that governments were instituted of God fo r the benefit of man; and that he
ho lds men accountable for their acts in relation to them. both in making laws and administering
them, for the good and safety of soc iety ... We believe that all governments necessarily requi re
ci vil officers and magistrates to enforce the laws of the same; and that such as will administer the
law in eq uity and justice shoul d be so ught for and upheld by the voice of the people if a republic,
or tJle will of the sovereign. ,,45 Mormonism. as a Christian-based faith. is interesting in that it
lea ves trad itional dogma by accepting the validity of earthly law despite any moral
quali fications. Its teachings include instructions to obey authorities oftJle law without recourse
to moral value for validity. President Marion G. Romney of the First Presidency (the highest
co uncil of the Church) taught the importance of legal authority to tJle LOS Church. "Civil
24
authority is of di vine origin. It may be more or less adapted to the needs of man; more or less just
and benevolent, but, even at its worst, it is better than anarchy.,,·'6 Past president of the LDS
Church Joseph f. Sm ith echoed the same. citizens of the Church should " be subject to the
Mormon conceptions of law stretch beyond the common belief in the separation of
ch urch and state. While many churches, including Mormonism, promote se paration of reli gion
and govenunental bod ies, the majo rity ascribe to the Natu ral Law Theo ry for an evaluation of
law. A traditional Christ ian view might be "Laws are valid to the degree they conform with
certain moral qual ities." Mormonism , however. grasps the relationship differently. The validity
oflaw, as SUI1Ulled up clearly by Pres ident N. Eldon Ta rll1er. sustains the legal positi vist views
that state authority grants legal va lidity. "There are many who question the constitutionality of
certain acts passed by their respective governments. even though such laws have been
established by the highest co urts in the land as being constitutionaL and they fee l to defy and
di sobey tlle law. Abraham Lincoln once observed: 'B ad laws, if they exist, shou ld be repealed as
soon as possible; sti ll, whi le tlley contin ue in force. they should be religio usly observed. ' This is
the attitude of the Chmch in regard to law observance.,,48 So, though a law may be morall y
49
hideous, it is still legall y vali d
True to the Legal Positivist thesis. President Tanner' s wo rd s are similru' to those of
Hart's. " What these [positivists) were. in tlle main, concerned to promote was clru'ity ruld
honesty in the formulation of the theoretical and moral iss ues rai sed by the ex iste nce of
pru"tic ular laws which were morally iniquitous but were enacted in proper form , cleru' in meaning.
25
and satisfied all the acknowledged criteria of validity of a system . Their view was that, in
thinking about such laws, both the theorist and the unfortunate offic ial or pri vate citizen who was
called on to apply or obey them, co uld only be confused by an invitati on to refuse the title of
' law' or 'valid' to them. They tho ught that... we should say 'Thi s is law; but it is too iniquito us
to he applied or obeyed. '" Further Positi vist comment s solidify the relationship between
Mormon ism and Legal Positivism. "Now, to say that human laws which conflict with the Divine
law are not bind ing. that is to say, are not laws, is to talk stark nonsense. The most pernicious
laws, and therefore those which are 1110st opposed to the will of God , have been and continually
Partl y treated in the previous thesis, Mormonism compares to Pos itivism in its rej ection
of the validity of law being morally based. Three spec ifi c exampl es wi ll assist in understanding
this relationship. The first comes from the bedrock of Mo rmon belief, the Book of Mormon , in
which an example of Legal Po siti vism is to be found. Morianton si. an ancient king of the
Jaredite people. was a wicked king who was pec uliar in that he did "justice unto the people. but
not unto himself. .. [and was] cut off from the presence of the Lord." This di stinction is
important. While King Morianton was immoral, hi s rules and law were vali d in the eyes of the
people. The interpretation of this verse may be, ' Morianton did good works for the people, but
evil fo r himself and in the eyes of God.' This passage contains two significant correlations to
50 John Aus tin, The Province a/Jurisprudence Deferm ined pg. 18/1 - Credit to Brian Z. Tamanaha for bringing up
thi s poi nt Australian Journal of Legal Philosophy. Vol. 32: 2007
51 Ether 10:9- 11 : 9. And it came to pa ss after the space of many years. Morian ton ... did establish himself king over
all the land. 10. And after that he had estab lished him self king he did ease th e bu rden of th e people, by which he
did gain favor in the eyes of the people. and th ey did anoint him to be their king. I I . And he did do j ustice 111710 (he
people, b1l1 no! unto hill/set/because of his many whoredollls; where/ore he \lias CI/f oj}/j·om the presence of the
Lord.
26
Legal Positivism. first, the people didn ' t consider Morianton's actions to be outside the domain
oflega!. Hart explains why. "Those rules of behavior which are valid according to the system's
ultimate criteria of validity must be generally obeyed, and ... its rules of recognition specifying
the criteria of legal validity and its rules of change and adj udication must be effecti vely accepted
as common public standards."5/. This case exemplifies how Positivism is integral in Mormonism
The seco nd significant detail is the implied relationship hetween God and lega l entities,
in this case, a relationship between moral ity and lega l en ti ties. The Book of Mormon remarks
that Morianton was "anoint[ed]" by the people "to be their king," While God , in this instance
personifying morality, disappro ved of Morianton, Morianton was sti ll sovereign and hi s
commands were nonetheless leg itimate. This relat ion ship is insightful of what Mormons believe.
As a piece of Mormon theology King Morianton's cOlUlection to moral ity helps form tlle way in
The second example draws upon Mormonism's founder Joseph Smith. As will be seen,
Smith's example is indicati ve of modern Mo rillon perceptions of law. Elder Jack Goaslind
explains an encounter of Smith while residing in Nauvoo, "As mayor of Nauvoo, Joseph was
called upon to render judgment on Anthony, a black man who had ... been se lling liquor in
vio lation of th e law ... Anthony implored Joseph for leniency, stating that he needed money to
buy the freedom of his child held as a slave in a southern state. Joseph said, 'I am sorry,
Anthony, but the law must be observed, and we will have to impose a fine ... ,53 One might
attribute Smi th's attitude to racial currents of his day; however, Smith' s perception of the
27
validity of law changes in light of his personal aboliti onist sentiments 54 Running for President
in 1844, Smith's platform incl uded a complete ban on slavery by 1850 and freedom for existing
slaves. 55 The issue is further compounded by Smith 's obvious understanding of the moral
implications of taking Anthony's money. Imposing the fine would surely limit Anthony's ability
to fi·ee his son. To minimize the impact of the fine, Smith sold a horse to contribute money for
Smith's seem ingly contrary ind ividual and political actions are derived from his Legal
Positivist understanding of the law. In the words of John A ustin, " the existence of law is one
thing; its merit and demerit another. Whether it be or be not is one enquiry; whether it be or be
not conformable to an ass umed standard, is a different enquiry.,,5 7 Smi th knew the law
prescribed punishment for Anthony: whether such a fi ne was moral or immoral was another
matter.
A third and more modern example of Monno ni sm adapti ng a Legal Positivist vie IV is the
turn of the century fight over pol ygamy. While the two previous examples exhi bited
Mormonism as deferential to lega l authority, the third involves conflict between heavenly law
and earthly law. Openly "avow[ing],,58 plural marri age in 1852, the LDS Church's stance
conunenced a series of legal attacks upon the LDS church. While a history of the struggle
between the LDS church and U.S. government wo ul d be lengthy and beyond the present foc us,
one aspect of the conflict is pertinent. Despite dispute over the morality of mandated
:)~ ~'NIy cogitations, likeDaniel's have fo r a long time troubled me, when I viewed the cond ition of men tlu·oughout
the world, and more especiall y ill this boasted realm, where the Dec laration of Independence 'holds these truths to
be self-evident. that alllTlen are created equa l: that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable ri ghts;
that among these are life, liberty: and the pursu it of happiness:' but at the same time some two or three millions of
people are he ld as slaves for life, because the spirit in them is covered with a darker skin than ours," History of the
Church, Vo1.6. Ch.8, pp. 197- 198
55 History of the Ch urch , Vol. 6:205
" Elder Jack Goaslind. B YU Devotiona l Joseph SlIIith·s Christlike Allrihutes 27 June 1995
JJ Stanford Encyclopedia - Legal Positivism
J8 Gary C. Bryner, Political Teachings
28
monogamous marriage, Mormonism respected the claims of govenunent and its entities as
legall y bindi ng. In 1904 special hearings were held to determine whether Senator-elect Reed
Smoot co uld take his seat. In the ensuing hearings, President of the Church Joseph F. Smi th
(grand-nephew of founder Joseph Smith), was ca lled to tes tify conce rning Mormonism' s
compliance with mo unting lega l pressure to adopt monogamo us marriage . When Senator Hoar
asked whether church revelati on trum ped legal responsibi lity. Smith's answer was that
determination of the matter was fo r "[members to decide) whichever they pleased. ,,59
Interestingly, Smi th did not repudiate the legitimacy of the law. Tradi tional conce pt ions
of religious authority are disposed to assess the law in its conformity to moral values. In other
word s, based on Natural Law theory's perception of law. as passed down tlu'ough western
Clu·istianit y. many churches would see law as illegitimate when it co nfl icted with religious/moral
dogma; Mormonism is distinct in this regard. Departing fro m the main stream, Smith and
Mormoni sm embrace Hart' s Legal Positi vist view that law is valid whether or not it embodies
moral duties.
Criti cs of Legal Positivism have at times misinterpreted the theory to endorse blind and
imm oral obedience of the law. However, proponents of Legal Positivism are apt to point out this
is not the case 60 Mormonism provides a suitable model for recogni zing the validity ofl aw yet
59 Name Unknown. What k/ormol1s Do When Lall's Conflict: New York Ti mes 5 Mar. 190 /1; "Suppose YOll rece ived
a reve lation commanding your peopl e to do something whi ch would confl ict with the law of th e land. Which wou ld
they have to obey?"-Sen. Hoar ·'V.,Ihichever th ey pleased, there is no compul sion ... Wi th me perhaps the reve lat ion
wou ld be uppermost." - Pres. Sm ith
60 "The ir discomfort is sometimes the product of confus ion. Lawyers often use 'positivist' abusively, to condemn a
fo rmal istic doctrine accord ing to which law is always clear and. however poi ntless or wrong. is to be rigorously
app lied by officials a nd obeyed by subjects. It is do ubtful that anyo ne ever held this view; but it is ill any case fa lse,
it has noth ing to do with legal positivism, and it is expressly rejected by aU leading posit ivists." "The pecu liar
29
rejecting it on moral grounds. In the years leading up to the prohibition of polygamous
marriage 61 , Church members frequent ly saw tJle United States Govenunent's law as valid but
immoral and therefore unable to foll ow it. The reflection of an early church member gives
insight into how rank-and-file Mormons perceived the law. Upon learning that federal troops
were being sent to Utah to enfo rce monogamous marriage laws, Richard Ballantyne remarked
tJlat it "was a virtual declaration of war by a state against one of its own political subdi visions. ,,6)
Though tJle govenmlent was conuuitting a foolish act against one of its own "s ubdivi sions," in
Hrut. commenting on the sometimes confrontation between law and morality, said " what
surely is most needed in order to make men clear-sighted in confronting the offic ial abuse of
power, is that they should preserve the sense that the certi fication of something as legally valid is
not conclusive of the majesty or authority which the officia l system may have, its demands must
in the end be subm itted to a moral scrutiny. ,,63 "Moral scru tiny" is indeed fam ili ar to
Mormonism. When posed with the hypothetical si tuation of abandoning hi s children because of
monogamo us laws, Joseph F. Smith (then current president of the Churc h) rep lied to the
heavenly law vs. earthly law conflict that '\mder the discipline that had been maintained for the
last twenty years the peopl e in tJle Mormon Church wou ld obey the laws rather than any
revelati on which might be in conflict. .. but 1 should not Iike to be put into tJle position where j
would be compelled to abandon my chi ldren. j could not do tl1at.,,64 Though certainl110ral
bounds could be crossed. others wo uld not be. In determining which laws would be followed , it
accusation that positivists believe the law is always to be obeyed is wi thollt foundation." - Stanford Encyc loped ia -
Legal Positivism
Gl Smith , Joseph. Doctrine (Ind Covenants Official Declaration pg. 1
62 Conway B. Sonne. Knighl a/the Kingdom page 17 1
63 H.LA . Hart., Concept of Lalli page 210
6-1 Name Unknown, What }\I10r1110115 Do When Laws COJ?f!icl; New York Times 5 Mar. 1904
30
is important to note that Smith explicitly cited moral eva luation in his answer. He didn't
The ways in which Mormonism accepts Lega l Positivism are many and varied. As seen
in the preceding examples, Mormonism has developed its recognition of the validity of law
regardless of moral wlderpimungs. Tlu s connection is unique considering the religious nature of
Mormonism. As time progresses further research will reveal whether Mormonism retain s its
To best understand Legal Positi vism, one must remember how/ why it was born. Natural
Law theory had dominated western j urisprudence for centuries, with the res ult that little
distinction was made between law and morality. The concept that "the existence oflaw is one
thing; its merit and demerit another" 65 was radical at the ti me and has remained the centrally
Both Positivi sm 's theme and its limited role are often overlooked. Unfortunately, the
theory has been misapplied both within and outside j urisprudence. Perhaps the most common
charge is that Lega l Positi vism implies a fund amental submi ssion to ' legal yet morally wicked
6:> Austin 's doctrine, though intellectually bare in comparison 10 Han" s. has remained tJl e mainstay of Legal
Positivism through to today.
31
behavior. ' As Brian Bix points out, this is due to many individual's belief that a legal theory
should answer "important questions of law and practical reasoning. " However, as Bix advises
"this complaint is not so much wrong as a misunderstanding. One should no more expect
theories about the nature of law to guide behavior or answer difficult ethical questions than one
It was under the former cbarge that H.L.A. Hart endeavored to show that Legal
Positi vism was indifferent to Nazi Germany. Some critics argued that Positivism - at the time
gaining influence in Germany - may ha ve contributed to the horrendous acts of the Second
World War. Perpetrators commonly claimed they were ' following orde rs' or 'following the
law; ' in this environment, witho ut a true understanding of Positivism's purpose, the theory
seemed malicious.
blaming the spread of AIDS on a medical theory that anal yzes disease epidemics. far from
Yet, as a fina l thought on the subject, Positi vism 's role has been both practical and
analytical - raising doubts that the theory does not influence "important questions of law," as
remarked by Brian Bix. By Hart's own admission, Legal Positivism was instrumental in
66 Bri an Bix, The Blackwell Guide /0 'he Philosophy of Law and Legal Theol ) ; pg. 32
6i "Much dissati sfaction has for long been fe lt in England with the criminal law relatin g to bOlh prostihItion and
homosexuality, and in 195 /1 th e committee well known as the Wolfenden Commi ttee was appointed to con sider the
state of the law. This committee reported in September 195 7 and recommended certain changes in the la w on both
topics"' H.L. A. Hart, Law, Liberty, and k/orality pg. 13
32
be de-criminalized in England, Due to Hart 's effecti ve reasoni ng, the committee eventually
based its decision on the idea that "[morality is] not the law's business, ,,68
For its advancement of jurisprudence and the demarcating of law and morality, Legal
Positivism will long hold a unique position in legal academia - and rightly so ,
33
Acknowledgement
patience, ideas, and thoughtful criticism have had an incredible impact, and will continue to
influence me positively for many years. 1 would also to thank the phil osophy department - those
professors who always made time to meet with amateur philosophers exploring new and old
ideas.
The Honors department, for setting balanced requirements and helping me grow in
meeting them. Their assistance, as well as many others, have all played into this essay. I am
Altman, Andrew. Arguing A bout Law. 1st. Belmont: Wadswol1h Publishing Company, 1996.97.
Print.
Austin, John, Lectures on Jurisprudence and the Phil osophy of Positive Law; St. Clair Shores,
Ml: Scholarly Press, 1977
Bix, Brian. "Lega l Positivism." The BlaclC>llell Guide to the Philosophy of Let.", and Legal Theory.
'Ed'. Martin P. Goldin and William A. Ed mundson. Malden: Blackwell Publishing, 2005.
Print.
Bryner, Gary C. "Political Teachings " 1st Edi tion. I. New York: Macmi llan, 1992. Print.
"Eighth Amendment. " Law JRank. Law JRank, Unknown. Web. November 2009.
<http://la w.jrank.orgJpages/6368/Eighth-Amendment.html>.
Goaslind , Jack. "Joseph Sm ith's Chri stlike Attributes." BYU Devotoni al Address. BYU. Provo,
Utah. 27 June 1995 . Address.
Guy, Unknown. "Jurisprudence." Doc Stoc. Doc Stoc, 2008. Web. November 2009.
<http://www. docstoc.com!docs/344 1716/J uri sprudence-for-dummies-a-guide-to-fo r-the-
rest-of>.
Hart, H.L. A. Law, Liberty, and Morality. I st. Stanford: Stanford Uni versity Press, 1963. 13.
Print.
Hart, H.L.A. The Concept o/La'''''' 2nd Ed iti on. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994. Print.
Hacker, P.M.S .. "Hart's Philosophy of Law." La]\l, Morality. and Society . 'Ed'. P. M.S. Hacker
and J. Raz. Oxford: Oxford Uni versity Press. 1977. Print
Green, Leslie. "Legal Positivi sm." Stanford Encyclopedia 0/ Philosophy. Stanford Encyc lopedia
of Phil osophy, 03/01 /2003 . Web. November 2009.
<http://plato .stanford. ed u! entri es/legal-positi vism/> .
Leiter, Brian. Naturalizing Jurisprudence . I st Ed ition. Oxford: Oxford Un iversity Press, 2007.
66. Print.
Tanner, N. Eldon. "The Laws Of God ." Ensign . ov. 1975: 82. Print.
Smith, Joseph. Articles ofFaith. Salt Lake City: LDS Ch urch Publi shing, 1842. I. Print.
Smith, Joseph. Doctrine and Covenants 134. Salt Lake City: LDS Church Publishing, 1835 . I .
Print.
Schossberger, Cynthi a. "Raising a Question - Coercion and Tolerance in Kant's Politi cals."
Ethic@. 5.2 (2006): 165-17 1. Print.
Tamanah, Brian Z. "The Contemporary Relevance of Legal Positi vism." Australian Journal of
Legal Philosophy. 32 (2007): Print.
Unknown. "What Mormons Do When Laws Confli ct." New York Times 5 Mar. 1904, Weekend
Ed.Print.
Unknown. " 1957: Homosexuality 'should not be a crime'" BBC On This Day. BBC, 2005. Web.
3 Jan 20 11.
<http://news. bbc. co. u klo nth isdayIh il dates/stori esl septem ber/4/news id_ 3007000/3007686.
stm>.