Um Hero Spa-Es Reva Web
Um Hero Spa-Es Reva Web
Um Hero Spa-Es Reva Web
Adi Efal
Bloomsbury Academic
An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc
Bloomsbury Academic
An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc
www.bloomsbury.com
BLOOMSBURY and the Diana logo are trademarks of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc
Adi Efal has asserted her right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be
identified as Author of this work.
Parts of Chapter 1 appeared in Rens Bod, Jaap Maat and Thijs Weststeijn (eds), The Making
of the Humanities Volume II: From Early Modern to Modern Disciplines (Amsterdam:
Amsterdam University Press, 2012), 263–99.
A preliminary version of Chapter 4 was published in Dana Arieli Horowitz and Moshe
Elhanati (eds), Protocols of the History and Theory Department of the Bezalel Academy 14
(October 2009).
Parts of Chapter 5 appeared as ‘Gravity of a Figure’, in Mick Finch and Christopher Smith
(eds), Journal of Visual Arts Practice 12:1 (March 2013), 39–50.
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any
form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or
any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the
publishers.
Acknowledgements ix
Notes 143
Bibliography 185
Index 203
viii
Acknowledgements
In order to understand Erwin Panofsky’s approach to art history this book will
elaborate on some notable affinities between a certain methodical orientation
in the history of art and what could be regarded as a philological rationality.
The ultimate goal is to establish some guidelines for a philological art history,
a formulation that will be reached only towards the conclusion. At the heart of
the book’s thesis stands the concept of figuration. Since whole chapters will be
dedicated to analysing the figure, we shall not linger upon it in this introductory
chapter. But to begin the inquiry, a preliminary and admittedly gross redefinition
of philological rationality will be necessary, one that accentuates the plastic
aspects of philological investigation. The crossover between art history and
philology is a bilateral one: on the one hand, we must ask in what manner are
pictorial aspects and material monuments imbued with philological rationality;
on the other hand, we must examine the ways in which philological issues have
been approached in art historical investigations, even if in a disavowed manner.
Re-reconsidering philology as a viable route to knowledge is a recent
tendency in the humanities.2 Paul de Man, for one, identified a connection
between the return to a certain kind of philology and the willingness to
theorize3 and, indeed, the present work endorses the possibility of establishing
a relation between a philological approach and the central place given to theory
in the historical sciences. Yet it is not evident that philology and theory are,
in fact, concomitant practices. There are many examples of reconsiderations
of philological methods and principles turning rather to an anti-theoretical
methodology.
As this book patrols the frontiers between philology and the history of art,
it may be a good occasion here, at the beginning, to try to pose in as concise
2 Figural Philology
neither an object nor an ‘idea’ inherent in the object, but rather a poietic action,
an action of the production of a work by man. Because it constructs series of
produced things according to subject matter, philology is inherently inter-
ested in genres. Let us recall that for Aristotle (384–322 bce) a genre appears
‘When there is a continuous generation of things of the same type.’45 Philology
is likewise interested in accounting for the continuous generation of forms.
Pictures, transmitting their prototypes more or less efficiently, must hence have
an important role to play in philological inquiries. In philology, therefore, the
γένος precede the εἶδος, and the philological prototype is not an idea but an act
of production of a work. In the morphological, hylomorphic series, form and
meaning are inseparable. Philology, as the activity synthesizing those series, is
not only a science but also an art, a technique.46 As an art, it rehearses the repeti-
tions of statements, imperatives, inscriptions, articulations and imprinting, and
by so doing it produces figures. Its ‘artificial’ character also includes an essential
element of working with misunderstandings and errors: of copies, interpret
ations, inscriptions, applications, extensions, etc.
All these kinds of errors occur in the midst of restorative rehearsal operations.
The significance of rehearsal was already apparent in the Viconian determi-
nation that humans are capable of knowing things that other humans have
made; later, in the nineteenth century, this capacity for rehearsal was formulated
in Boeckh’s principle of ‘Erkenntnis des Erkannten’,47 or the knowing of the
(already) known. This version of the philological dictum collapses certum and
factum into each another: the made is the known, and therefore knowing and not
making (as in Vico’s case) stands at the heart of this version of the philological
method. Indeed, Boeckh’s epistemic understanding of philology points in the
direction of affiliating philology with memory, memory being the knowledge
of the already known.48 In the twentieth century, this principle of rehearsal
was transformed once more in Spitzer’s formulation: ‘to read is to have read,
to understand is equivalent to having understood’.49 Here it is the habitus of
reading that carries the weight of the obligation towards the reality of the past.
Synthesizing the above three versions of the ‘philological rehearsal’ together,
modern philology, understood thus, is a method responsible for the rehearsal
of poietic memory. It would lead us to also consider memory as a human deed,
as a factum. This is why, on numerous occasions in the chapters that follow,
Henri Bergson’s articulations of the relation between memory, duration and
creation will serve as a guiding orientation. Can we read Panofsky and Warburg
with Bergson in mind? Can we read one tradition of discussion with another
tradition in mind? This is part of the task to be undertaken in the present work.
Philological rationality and the constitution of the history of art 11
These three lines of resistance between philology and the dominant orienta-
tions of the humanities in the nineteenth century delineate three borderlines
of philological rationality: (a) temporal experience, (b) interpretation, and
(c) conditions of experience.61 The following inquiry will present Panofsky’s
iconology as engaging along all three borderlines.
The argument to be developed in the following chapters goes two ways: it
is not only that philology includes an essential pictorial-formal element, but
also that art history, in its development as a discipline, has been imbued with a
philological impulse. Philological tendencies can be found in the works of many
Philological rationality and the constitution of the history of art 13
of the founders of the history of art, such as Aloïs Riegl (1858–1905; who will
be discussed in Chapter 2), Julius von Schlosser (1866–1938),62 Aby Warburg
(discussed in Chapter 6), Edgar Wind (1900–1971)63 and, in a more nuanced
fashion, in Henri Focillon (1881–1943)64 and Ernst Gombrich (1909–2001).65
But, as this book proposes, philological traits appear most explicitly in the work
of Panofsky.66 A good opening example of Panofsky’s engagement with philo-
logical rationality can be found in his essay ‘Et in Arcadia Ego: Poussin and the
Elegiac Tradition’ of 1955 (an earlier, different version appeared in 1936).67 This
essay stemmed from an explicitly philological question: how should one read
the inscription in Poussin’s painting carrying the same title?68 Panofsky presents
Poussin neither as a classicist nor as a philosopher-artist, but as an agent of what
he termed the ‘elegiac’ tradition. Poussin, he argues, is responsible for a ‘change
in interpretation’, leading to a ‘mistranslation’, which worked ‘at the expense
of grammar but in the interest of truth’.69 After presenting the philological
problem, Panofsky proceeds to an exploration of texts, commentaries and visual
images (all having the same status as facta), pointing to the various possible
ways to read the inscription in question. Likewise in Panofsky’s other works,
pictorial history itself is inserted into a series of readings, translations and most
importantly mistranslations of formulae. In this essay, Panofsky neither explored
the historical situation in which Poussin’s inscription was made, nor set out to
excavate a universal set of categories that could be used for a Kantian-critical
analysis of the painting (as he would have done in some of his earlier essays).
Rather, he revealed a linkage of transmissions, transfigurations and readings
of a formula, an original ‘type’. The connection between Poussin’s painting
and its own past is the figure that Panofsky drew in this essay. The latter thus
merits being described as paradigmatic, as its iconographic riddle points to the
question of the relation of the western tradition to its primordial past: a past that
is represented by Arcadia, a kind of a hypothetical topos of a primary, eternal
archaic state of living, in which death nevertheless existed.70 Poussin’s picture
is itself presented by Panofsky as a philological reflection on the status of the
archaic origins of the European tradition.
It is on the platform presented thus far that this book will seek to understand
Panofsky’s ‘iconology’; it is an art history, as he himself declared, deeply rooted
in the soil of the humanist tradition.71 The accentuated philological character
of Panofsky’s later works will be touched upon in the later chapters. In his
American period, Panofsky corresponded with Auerbach, Spitzer and Curtius.72
Was his accentuated philologism a consequence of his exile? A remnant of a
shattered European ‘tradition’ resurfacing in the United States of America? That
14 Figural Philology
may well have been the case, but it is not our objective here to explore this facet
of Panofsky’s biography. What is sought after, rather, is a coherent reading of
Panofsky’s project. Many have tried to ponder the meaning of his later icono-
logical phase.73 The thesis to be developed here will present Panofsky’s iconology
as both pertaining to and practising philological rationality. Indeed, this may
also account for the passage of his work from its neo-Kantian beginnings to
a more humanistic, work- and problem-oriented phase. The special character
of Panofsky’s philological awareness is rooted in a hylomorphic dynamics of
form and matter. In fact, as early as the 1920s Panofsky was using hylomorphic
terminology that presented the plastic artwork as composed ‘ontologically’ from
a duality of ‘plenitude’ (Fülle) and ‘form’ (Form).74 On the historiographical level,
the Panofskyan hylomorphist atom mediates between the attention given to
nuances, versions and dialects, and the serial generalization of forming generic
series.75 Panofsky’s art history, as we will endeavour to show, can facilitate the
search for a re-integration of philology into art historical method, as well as the
placing of art history within the general framework of the humanities.
2
The first chapter raised the possibility of thinking of the history of art as a
philological practice. The critical reader may suspect from the outset that in
proposing such a goal, the searched for method will eventually lose the plastic,
‘formalist’ reality of art history. It is possible to conjecture that Panofsky would
have himself subscribed to such an attitude, since in several places in his letters
he recounts that from early on he considered himself as participating in the
Warburgian school, whose efforts, according to Panofsky, were directed at
inaugurating an anti-formalist, that is an anti-Wölfflinian, history of art.1 In
order to support the conviction that, although not a formalist, Panofsky was
nevertheless continuously occupied with establishing a morphological art
historical method, the present chapter endeavours to establish a bond between
Panofsky’s and Riegl’s art histories. The aim is not to go so far as considering
Panofsky a formalist, but rather to show that, like Riegl’s, his method was
heavily bound up with morphological terms. Indeed, in one letter from 1965,
Panofsky explicitly attested to a morphologist creed.2 Riegl and Panofsky are
commonly thought of as representing two competing ways of conceiving of
art history as a discipline: Panfosky as the founder of the textually oriented
iconological tradition; Riegl as one of the founders of the formalist discourse
in the history of art. Hence, if we can establish a stable link between these two
art historical pillars, we may thereby open up a path for forming an alliance
between iconology and explicitly ‘plastic’ formalisms, such as, for example, that
of Henri Focillon.3
David Summers has noted that Panofsky’s art history is marked by a Rieglian
quality4 and Panofsky himself identified the ‘three lights of the Vienna school’
– Riegl, Dvořák and Schlosser – as the most important influences on his work,
after Vöge and Goldschmidt, his direct teachers, but before Warburg and his
school.5 Riegl’s presence is evident in Panofsky’s 1924 book on German Gothic
sculpture, in which Panofsky uses the notion of the ‘Kunstwollen’ several times,
16 Figural Philology
Panofsky’s Riegl
Panofsky’s 1920 essay on the Kunstwollen was written several years after his
criticism of Wölfflin’s notion of style. The ‘Kunstwollen essay’ has merited
the attention of numerous scholars, among them Michael Podro, Michael
Ann Holly, Margaret Iversen, Allister Neher and Frederic Schwartz.8 All have
noted the anti-psychologist, neo-Kantian approach that the young Panofsky
implicitly adopts in this reading. Neher criticizes Holly’s and Iversen’s readings,9
claiming that Panofsky’s reading of Riegl’s Kunstwollen hails the establishment
of a transcendental (i.e. synthetic a priori) science of art, rather than of an
Archimedean points: Monuments as duration reservoirs 17
Die Kunst ist nicht, wie eine den Widerspruch gegen die Imitationstheorie
überspannente Ansicht heute vielfach glauben machen will, eine subjektive
Gefühlsäußerung oder Daseinsbetätigung bestimmter Individuen, sondern die
auf gültige Ergebnisse abzielende und objektivierende Auseinandersetzung einer
formenden Kraft mit einem zu bewältigenden Stoff.13
to articulate the correct method of inquiry into this ‘formulating force’, which
can be used as the atom of the work of art. This hylomorphism accompanies
Panofsky’s development, from his earlier systematic Platonic neo-Kantianism
to the dynamic synthesis of the iconological period. Hylomorphist rationality
can also be found operating in Riegl’s various writings, where the forming
capacity of the plastic arts is enabled and generated by contact with an ever-
changing, dynamic nature. The Rieglian Kunstwollen, as Panofsky’s ‘formulating
force’, represents the meeting point between the human formative power and
material reality.15
A few presentations of Riegl’s work have already noted the latter’s philological
character.16 Yet the philological character of Riegl’s art history is different from
the hermeneutic oriented philological tradition, the closer sibling of the icono-
logical method. It rather originates in the critical, positivist school of philology,
originating in Germany in the method of Jakob Grimm and Karl Lachmann,
and developed, for example, in the diplomatics of Theodor von Sickel (1826–
1908) in Vienna. Riegl’s academic education was undertaken at the Institute
for Austrian Historical Research, led by von Sickel, whose basic task was to
teach and practise diplomatics, i.e. the preparation of critical editions of textual
sources, mostly juridical in nature.17 Von Sickel developed a process of working
with documents which, based on the distinction between external and internal
(inner structure and grammar) ‘markings’ (Merkmale), reveals patterns and
precedents that are handed down from generation to generation by subsequent
versions of a certain text.18 The critical editing of texts – trying to establish an
original text (Urtext) that is deduced (Lachmann insisted on this term) by the use
of analogies between several versions of the text – was the basic occupation of
the positivist philologists of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.19 Though
considered as a primary reality, the Urtext is not materialized by a specific
manuscript version, but is rather a grammatical reconstruction. This kind of
inquiry, a mixture of diplomatics and palaeography (the integrative empirical
research of original texts, including their material characters), was the basic
method absorbed by Riegl in his historical training. The establishing of ‘original’
texts, distinct from lines of transmissions and transmutations, manifested the
basic demand of this school of philology. The deciphering of grammar was
part and parcel of this branch, and was less dominant in the culturally oriented
Archimedean points: Monuments as duration reservoirs 19
philology suggested by Boeckh and Usener, and also later by Auerbach and to
some extent Spitzer (whose formation was in the positivist school of philology).
On that basis, Riegl’s use of the notion of Historische Grammatik – the
‘historical grammar of the visual arts’, to cite the title of the two lecture
series he gave at the University of Vienna in 1897 and in 1899 – becomes
understandable.20 Historical grammatics was a linguistics school that was just
beginning to develop at the time, and Riegl’s lectures offer a rare example of
the application of its method to a discussion of the plastic arts. As a discipline
bordering on philology, history and linguistics, it pursued a comparative study of
the structure of words, word groups and sentences in their historical mutations
and various rhythms of development. It differentiated between the historical
dynamics of linguistic change and the basic linguistic entities that remain
constant throughout linguistic transformations, or that change very slowly.21
Warburg’s and Panofsky’s iconologies – tracking durational transmutations of
plastic structures and motifs over historical periods, but still presupposing basic
constant units – are not so far removed from this type of inquiry. In the above-
mentioned lectures, Riegl explored the morphological foundations of artistic
production while describing their periodical development.
This pioneering enterprise had its followers. In Panofsky’s time, a similar
experiment in forming an essential conjunction between words and things, a
sort of a historical grammar, could be found in the work of a group of Austrian
and German philologists named ‘Wörter und Sachen’. The group established a
journal with the same title, to which the young Leo Spitzer (arriving in Marburg
from Vienna) contributed articles, as did one of the important figures in the
second Vienna school, Jacob Strzygowsky.22 The motto of the journal, taken
from Jakob Grimm, hailed a historical science of language pending between
words and things.23 For this group, there existed a continuity between produced
things and words, a continuity to be followed by the description of series of
repeating morphological units in different monuments, instruments and lingual
expressions. Julius von Schlosser, a Viennese art historian who was slightly
older than Panofsky, was also busy integrating philology into the history of art,
notably in his book Die Kunstliteratur (1924). In its opening pages, Schlosser
declared that it was ‘occupied with philological tasks, and the division of the art
historical sources is also determined by guidelines furnished by this wonder-
fully refined discipline, classical philology’.24 As mentioned above, Panofsky
considered Schlosser to be one of the main influences on his work. In a later
lecture published in 1935, entitled ‘Style History and Language History of the
Visual Arts’,25 Schlosser noted the close relation between Riegl’s art history and
20 Figural Philology
The next point, which is decisive for any philological rethinking of the
history of art, regards the problem of historicism.
A purely historical study, whether it proceeds from the history of form or the
history of content, never explains the work of art as a phenomenon except in
terms of other phenomena. Historical study does not draw on a higher source
of perception: to explain the artistic production of a particular artist within the
framework of his time (or in light of his individual artistic character), it traces
a particular representation iconographically, or a particular formal complex
according to a history of types, or even tries to determine if such a complex
is derived from any particular influence at all. This means that each real
phenomenon to be investigated is referred to all the others within the whole
complex; their absolute locus and significance is not determined by a fixed
Archimedean point outside their essential nature. Even the longest ‘develop-
mental series’ represents only lines which must have their starting and finishing
points within such a purely historical nexus.31
Hence, already upon turning his attention to Riegl’s work, Panofsky acknow
ledged that the question with which they were both occupied was one regarding
the relation between art history and history. Should art history, in the full
and strict sense, be considered as a historical science? The basic problem of
historical explanation, Panofsky specified, is that historicism does not actually
give us permission to posit some fixed point of reference that could be used
as a measure against which to clarify the work. Instead, Panofsky suggested,
the very reality of artistic objects posits a measure or a criterion that is not
entirely embedded in historical ebbs and flows. Accordingly, what characterizes
a historical investigation as such is its inherently contextual nature, built out of
frames of reference; this is a practice that lies at the basis of any iconological
inquiry. But what is lacking in a strictly historical explanation, according to
Panofsky, is an Archimedean point that might supply the possibility of studying
22 Figural Philology
The third section of Panofsky’s essay on the Kunstwollen engages a clear and
distinct philological vocabulary, paralleling art historical work to the work of a
critical philology. This is also how Panofsky understands Riegl’s Kunstwollen: art
historical method should be a process of correction and deciphering, working
Archimedean points: Monuments as duration reservoirs 23
In exact keeping with this, the work of art whose immanent meaning is to be
perceived must also be understood, first of all, in the concrete and formal sense
of its phenomenal appearance which contains this meaning, and, as was said
earlier, this understanding [Verständnis] can be hindered […] the proper under-
standing of a work of art [Kunstdenkmal] can be interfered with by the same trio
of errors or delusions: by errors about the original nature [Beschafenheit] of the
object (if objective changes [sachliche Veränderungen] have come about in it);
through errors about the original effect of the work (if there has been a general
change in the view of art [Kunstanschauung]); and finally, through errors about
the present nature of the object (if by chance it was misunderstood as to its
24 Figural Philology
positive data). Just as the linguistic text can be lost by faulty reproduction or
by subsequent correction of its original content, so the work of art, because of
some unperceived later changes (rebuilding, painting over, or the inadequate
later completion of an unfinished work), can forfeit its objective appearance.
Just as a particular word can have changed its meaning because of a change
in linguistic usage and thus have changed the whole tenor of the linguistic
proposition, so, too, within the total artistic organism any detail at all can be
interpreted in the present completely differently from what it was in the past
and so have a completely erroneous formal effect upon us. (We can think, for
example, of a plastic work which was originally connected in a particular place
with a particular building but which is today conceived as a separate work.)
And finally, just as the understanding of the text can be made impossible by
a slip in reading or a slip of memory, so, too, the understanding of an artistic
phenomenon can be placed in question or disturbed by a material error about
its measurement, its colour, its material significance, or its intention.
The question then arises: what is it that enables us to determine the proper
perception of the monument? First, writes Panofsky, there are documents:
And now we are at the point where the effort to establish the perception of the
immanent meaning needs the help of ‘documents’ […] The documents may
correct these objective and subjective delusions, whether they are documentary
records, art-critical evaluations, theoretical statements about art, or, finally,
pictorial reproductions. The document’s corrective function, as can be seen,
is threefold. The document is first and foremost corrective if it makes possible
the reconstruction of the lost state of a work of art by documentary proof or
pictorial transmission. Second, it corrects exegetically when it proves that a
change of meaning in the formal components has altered the effect which a work
of art has upon us today (whether this correction is expressed in some critical
or theoretical form or, even, by a representation which reproduces the object
in the sense of a particular artistic impression). Finally, it operates correctively
when it moves us to change a false view of the positive data which determine the
appearance of a work of art as such, by means of indications which can again be
in the form either of written remarks or of pictorial reproduction.
A clearer proof of Panofsky’s philological orientation in his early years can hardly
be found. In particular, what becomes clear towards the end of this paragraph
is the importance of error. Errors are the essential reality in the transmission
of texts: philological reality is in its essence a reality of deformation, of myopic
readings and depictions of original works. Without this deflective dynamics, there
would be no need for philological practice at all; and it is by following mistakes
and deformations in the representation of artworks that the philological trail is
formed. Pierre Cerquiglini has suggested that philology is ‘a bourgeois thought
of the family, paternalist and hygienic, which cherishes descent, chases adultery
and detests contamination’. Philology is interested in branches, sources, families,
roots and traditions, but also in the multiple errors and variants shaping these.39
For both Riegl and Panofsky, the researcher must also establish, as comple-
mentary to this serial unfolding, some synthetic a priori set of categories, always
subject to reinspection and rehabilitation. The ‘re-creative synthesis’40 – as Giulio
Carlo Argan referred to the basic iconological gesture, the re-reproduction of the
Urtext – must be aided by these grammatical schemes.
The German–Austrian group Wörter und Sachen was especially interested in
families and homologies of words, in etymologies and their plastic aspect and
in binding words and things together. The vocation of this group was morpho-
logical, connecting the positivist and realist Vienna to the neo-Kantian centres of
Germany. One of its leading members was Meyer-Lübke, who was Leo Spitzer’s
teacher in Vienna. Of his classes, described as ‘historical grammar’, Spitzer wrote:
In Spitzer’s view, historical grammar thus lacked the essence of historicity, which
he related to a cultural spirit. Riegl, coiner of the term ‘historical grammar of the
visual arts’, articulated the consequences of this positivist philological tendency
(not always coinciding with historical impulses) in the domain of the history of
artworks.
26 Figural Philology
Riegl’s Alterswert
The critical correction and reconstruction that is the duty of the art historian,
though not always working in the service of history, received yet another articu
lation in Riegl’s 1903 essay. Here Riegl was occupied with the problem of the
various practices modern culture had been developing regarding things from
the past, or in his terms, monuments (Denkmale).42 In this essay, Riegl deployed
a typology of the various values that modern culture attaches to monuments
(within which category Riegl includes any produced thing). Working with the
notion of value (Wert), familiar from contemporary discourses of history and
economy, Riegl attempted to distinguish exactly what one means when one
uses the term ‘value’ in regard to works of art, but also what can be determined
as the content and meaning of works of art by using this coinage. As will be
seen in Chapter 7, ‘symbolical value’ occupied a central place in Panofsky’s
iconological table, and served for him as the content to be distilled from the
inspected work of art. Value, then, is inseparable from iconology, as well as
from philology.
The various types of value that Riegl enumerates include the following:
historical-value, age-value, memory-value, art-historical value, artistic-value,
newness-value and use-value. On the platform of this historical ‘value-grammar’,
modern culture, according to Riegl, develops its various practices in relation to
monuments. Of all the types of value, it is the concept of age-value that is most
original, suggestive and relevant to the present discussion. As far as I know, the
concept of ‘age-value’, unlike any of the other values, cannot be found as such
in any major text produced around Riegl’s time.43 Age-value, simply put, is the
value of old things, of things having a past, coming to us from the past, as aged-
things. It is a durational value, registering that which the work has been carrying
and gathering around itself through different eras, uses and cultures, with the
deformations and mutations that such a duration includes.
Importantly, Riegl differentiates between age-value and historical-value.44
Whereas historical-value traces a linear trail of development, age-value exclu-
sively follows and stands for everything contracted by a work throughout the
ages: decay, ruin, changes in colour, disintegration, but also additions, changes
of location, etc. While insisting on the effectiveness of age-value, Riegl was
reminding his readers that neither artistic nor historical values are exclusively
at work in the processes by which monuments are received. Indeed, this is the
very same argument that Panofsky elucidated in regard to Riegl’s notion of the
Archimedean points: Monuments as duration reservoirs 27
Kunstwollen: neither history nor aesthetics are sufficient to read the artwork.
Riegl’s 1903 essay seems to form a full circle with Sickel’s formulation of the
‘markings’, the formulae to be found in a series of versions of a certain text.
Age-value is the index of such a series of markings or registrations, changes and
variations over time, and it is this value that philology works through, opens up,
deploys and overcomes, but also protects and preserves.
At the time of Riegl’s essay, value-discourse stood for a whole complex
of competing intentions and metaphysical constructions, mostly centred
around German-speaking intellectual milieus. It was into the midst of this
discourse that Riegl weaved his typology of values. The concept of value was
also integrated into the neo-Kantian discourse of history. Riegl’s notion of
age-value meets this constellation head-on. Age-value is a value that disturbs
the historical wish to construct narratives. It testifies to the duration of a thing
throughout history, ages and cultures, without necessarily evolving, becoming
better or worse, even when decayed by the forces of time and nature. In the
framework of age-value, readings and representations of works act like forces
of nature, changing, forming and transmitting a produced thing, and the
place of the work in world history, or in the history of styles, is of secondary
importance. The work is not considered primarily on the basis of universal or
localized canons of beauty; rather, age-value registers the material acquisition
of marks or changes on the surface of the work. Age-value, wrote Riegl, ‘appre-
ciates the past for its own sake’45 (‘dem Alterswerte, der die Vergangenheit
allein als solche schätzt’).46 The relevance of age-value to museum culture
and practice is evident.47 And the parallel with Panofsky’s interpretation of
the Rieglian Kunstwollen is by now, I hope, rather clear: since the method
of the Kunstwollen tries to correct the reading of a certain monument, it
is with the fabrics of historical-values, age-values and memory-values that
the art historian should work. These are always the marks that time and
culture imprints on a monument, marks in which one can read backwards
the durational sequence carried by it, in order to excavate an approximate
historical reality of the monument in question.
Eine Methode, wie Riegl sie inauguriert hat, tritt – richtig verstanden – der rein
historischen, auf die Erkenntnis und Analyse wertvoller Einzelphänomene und ihrer
Zusammenhänge gerichteten Kunstgeschichtsschreibung ebensowenig zu nahe,
wie etwa die Erkenntnistheorie der Philosophiegeschichte: die ‘Notwendigkeit’, die
auch sie in einem bestimmten historischen Prozesse feststellt, besteht ja – vorausge-
setzt, daß der Begriff des Kunstwollens methodologisch berichtigt ist – nicht darin,
daß zwischen mehreren zeitlich aufeinander folgenden Einzelerscheinungen ein
kausales Abhängkeitsverhältnis konstatiert würde, sondern darin, daß innerhalb
ihrer, als in einem künstlerischen Gesamtphänomen, ein einheitlicher Sinn
erschlossen wird.52
The present chapter sets out to distinguish between formalization and figuration,
a distinction that can be conceived as a foundation for theorizing the pictorial
domain of production. This foundation can be construed by way of integrating
the element of the figure into the understanding of what is usually referred
to as the ‘formalist tradition’, that is to say, methodological discussions of art
furnishing a unitary set of a priori characteristics of plastic and visual elements
– that same tradition, it will be recalled, of which Alois Riegl is considered one
of the founders and to which Panofsky’s work is usually taken to be opposed.
Intuitively one realizes that a figure is not identical with a form. In the first
place, a figure does not belong to the strict order of abstraction or general
ization, adhering rather to a concrete specific physical reality whose outlines
are portrayed in the process of the delineation of the figure. The specificity of
the figure makes it capable of relating to decipherable and identifiable themes,
genres and types, and thereby capable of drawing together plastic things and
literal topics, just as formalization, at least in its radical version, tends to take
one away from concrete themes towards abstract structures. The distinction
between forms and figures is a modal one;2 that is, both forms and figures pertain
to the pictorial domain. In this domain, nevertheless, forms and figures answer
to two distinct functions: just as forms belong to the transcendental-structural
34 Figural Philology
foundation of an artwork (a level which for Panofsky relates to the level of art
theory3), figures result from the observation of specific realities in movement
– that is to say, they exist as historical realities. Riegl referred to this moving
reality, causing and forming the artwork, as ‘transitory nature’ (die vergängliche
Natur4), marking the foundation of the formation of the plastic arts. Forms,
on the other hand, belong to what Riegl called the ‘historical grammar of the
visual arts’, discussed in the previous chapter. Within the domain of pictorial
reality, forms and figures intermingle and each needs the other in order to
function as pictorial entities. In order for a form to be deduced, one must begin
with the figural data; on the other hand, figures effectuate mutations in the
formal schemes. If the form is traditionally associated with an inner idea,5 with
the structure of the work of art or its inner scheme (as will be shown in the
following chapters), then the figure pertains to the outlines of things, furnishing
their contours.
In so far as the formalist tradition, exemplified in the writings of Heinrich
Woelfflin or Clement Greenberg, has been concerned with structural differenti-
ations between various media on the basis of their respective dimensionalities,6
discussions and analyses concerning the figure are usually occupied with the
interstice between two- and three-dimensionality. The figure, therefore, binds
the various plastic dimensions rather than separates them from each other.
Figuration works as bridging between media, enabling passages between them.
The ‘matter’ from which the figure is furnished is the pictorial domain at large,
within which figures effectuate selections,7 distinctions and separations. In
what follows, we will focus on describing what happens when the figure unites
and distinguishes between the surface and the depth of the picture. And the
suggestion here is that this distinction is fundamental for the production of
figures.
In the history of the theory of art, one encounters a continuous discussion
of plastic works of art as effecting a perceptual movement between a flat-
surface sensuality (based on the sense of touch) and a sensuality capable of
spatial representation (based on the sense of sight). This binary thematics
appeared already in the eighteenth century, for example in Johann Gottfried
von Herder’s Plastik,8 and it continued to serve as a central theme in
nineteenth-century theory of art, for instance in Adolf von Hildebrand’s differ-
entiation between Nahbild and Fernbild, in his Das Problem der Form in der
bildenden Kunt of 1893,9 a differentiation that was adopted and developed by
Riegl in both ‘Naturwerk und Kunstwerk II’10 and Spätromische Kunstindustrie
(1901).11
Forms and figures: Two fundamental modes of pictorial production 35
The distinction between the haptic and the optic distinguishes two levels
within plastic perception: a basic, primary level generally associated with haptic
perception, and a secondary, ‘developed’ level associated with optical perception.
In some cases, such as in Herder’s Plastik, haptic perception is considered the
more truthful of the two, on the grounds of its primary, ‘simple’ character. In
all of the mentioned sources, sculpture is considered as related to the sense of
touch, just as painting is related to the sense of sight. On this basis, painting is
treated as illusionist to its very core, while sculpture is considered as adhering
to material reality.12 Indeed, it was the illusionistic ‘threat’ that Greenbergian
formalism disclaimed: instead of incorporating an illusionistic subject matter,
Greenberg wished painting to concentrate and incorporate its own sovereign
two-dimensional elements. Nevertheless the approach here will be to suggest
the following, cohering with earlier versions of formalism such as those of Riegl
or Focillon:13 the possibility of the formation of a two-dimensional surface
presupposes the conditions of foundation, matter and borderline, all three
originating in the extended reality of three-dimensional bodies. Thus form,
foundation, matter and borderline compose the figural dynamics. Riegl, in his
Historical Grammar of the Visual Arts, insisted that ‘All things in nature possess
form [geformt]; that is, they extend themselves in the three dimensions of
height, width, and depth.’14 One can follow Riegl and suggest that the dynamics
of the possession of form – to have a form, to lose a form, to engage in a form,
to change form, etc. – belong to the figural mode.
Therefore, the duality here is designated as figural, the one taking place
between surface and depth is to be conceived from within the framework of
formalist discourse. Figural dynamics, so conceived, relate to the thematics of
the possession of forms: things having forms, bodies having forms, histories
having forms, but also thoughts having form. And figuration, it is here suggested,
should be located at the point of passage between the two modes of appre-
hension: surface-perception and depth-perception. Approaching the question
of the basic concepts of the history of art, Panofsky also based his analysis of the
entire structure of the pictorial arts on the movement between ‘values of depth’
(Tiefenwerte) and ‘values of surface’ (Flächenwerte), a movement that he called
the ‘contrast of figural values’ (Gegensatz der Figurationswerte).15 And, likewise,
in Panofsky’s description, surface and depth are intrinsically intermingled
within the pictorial domain, on the figural level of analysis.
Within a tradition of writing regarding the ‘grammar’ of the plastic arts,
figural dynamics conform to the understanding of the pictorial field as a domain
extending between the various dimensions of point, line, surface, space and
36 Figural Philology
change. This should be differentiated from the more ‘purist’ formalist approaches
that developed ‘separatist’ methods, distinguishing between artistic media and
their basic characteristics, like those of Gotthold Ephraim Lessing, Wölfflin,
Greenberg16 or Adrian Stokes.17 Separatist formalism can be of help in our
endeavour to articulate what happens in the figural passage, when a perceptual
movement is formed from a certain surface to a certain depth by the gesture of
drawing a separating line. And it can also assist in defining the plastic elements
that compose situations of figuration. However, the less ‘separatist’ formalist
authors, who addressed a continuous, encompassing, multi-dimensional plastic
domain, traversing two- and three-dimensional realities – such as Riegl,
Focillon, Pierre Francastel, Kurt Badt,18 Rosalind Krauss and, indeed, iconolo-
gists like Warburg, Panofsky or Edgar Wind – are closer in attitude to the one
adopted here.
mundane work. The following section will look at the fundamental movement
of the plastic figural situation, that between a figure and its carrying surface.
When examining the place of the concept of the figure in the history and theory
of art, one confronts a rather scattered and fragmented corpus of evidence.
Rosalind Krauss, in her Optical Unconscious, gives an informative theoretical
account of the figure, locating it in a structuralist (‘Kline group’) scheme
in which the figure is posed vis-à-vis the ground. The dialectical dynamics
between ground and figure, Krauss argues, stand at the basis of modern, specifi-
cally avant-garde, pictorial production. Here are central passages from Krauss’s
description of how she arrived at this constellation of figure and ground:
I start with a square. In its upper right corner I write figure and in its upper
left I write ground. This […] is the universe of visual perception, the one
that is mapped by a distinction between figure and ground so basic that it is
unimaginable […] without the possibility of this distinction.
[…] Figure versus ground, and not-figure versus not-ground. But also, figure
versus not-figure and ground versus not-ground […] All around the square we
find the same thing stated over and over […] The opposition without which
no vision at all: vision occurring precisely in the dimension of difference, of
separation, of bounded objects emerging as apart from, in contrast to, the
ambiance of ground within which they appear […] The not-figure/not ground
of the ‘neutral axis’ is that peculiar conversion of empirical vision’s figure/ground
distinction that can be seen to have generated one modernist icon after another:
the grid, the monochrome, the all-over painting, the color-field, the mise-en-
abyme of classical collage […] The ground is not behind; the ground is what it,
vision, is […] Perception marks this figure that the eye singles out by labeling
it ‘pure exteriority’: set off from the field on which it appears, it is even more
surely set off from me, the beholder […] figure versus ground; ground versus
not-ground; not-ground versus not-figure; not-figure versus figure […] figure
in this case being the ‘same’ as not-ground […] The frame-within-a-frame is a
way of entering the figure into the pictorial field and simultaneously negating it,
since it is inside the space only as an image of its outside, its limits, its frame.21
Krauss uses the movement between a figure and its ground as the basis for an
understanding of modern art and its apprehension. Indeed, Krauss developed
her figure-ground scheme specifically as a criticism of Greenberg’s separatist
38 Figural Philology
These materials [which are] well characterized, suggestive and even demanding
in relation to the forms of art, on which they exercise a sort of attraction, find
themselves in the forms of art, in return, profoundly modified […] the life of
matter is being metamorphosed.29
One can conclude from the discussion so far that the figural situation is a
split one, consisting of a movement between the form that is delineated and the
material reality of that delineated segment. It is this movement between the two
figural members, a movement between two synchronically existing realities,
that we refer to as figural dynamics. The figural situation is, thus, not expressive
of ‘formal values’, nor is it an incorporation of an explicitly lingual meaning
‘in’ the material or visual signs. Rather, as Pierre Francastel has suggested, ‘The
figurative sign is a meeting-place of values that are infinitely richer than we
imagine when we insist on considering them as equivalents to other forms of
signs or of images which are capable of replacing them.’30 The meaning of the
figural situation does not evolve from the fact that it signifies equivalent or
analogous signs. Rather, the suggestion here is that the meaning of the figural
situation is as material as it is historical, and, more explicitly, that this meaning
has to do with the past reality of the work.
Second, unlike the eidos, the figure necessarily entails a dynamics, movement
and change, and it is therefore better to talk of figural dynamics, or figural
mechanics, rather than of the ‘figure’ as such. Figura has a special relation to
the Greek notion of plasis, or change of form. Third, though the figure is based
on a gesture of delineation, it implies some three-dimensional situation and
corporeality. Finally, a figure is a serial creature; the isolation of a figure on a
surface must be performed as a successive drawing of some line of duration and
continuation. Thus, a figure can be transfigured and configured in time, through
eras, mediums, traditions, etc. As such, the best Greek parallels to the Latin
figura are morphe and typos. And the discussion of the figure is best located in
a hylomorphic domain in which change of form makes for the reality of things.
Hence, one can differentiate between two basic pictorial ‘modes’: form and
figure. Where the form would be equivalent to a schematic prototype, to what
Riegl referred to as a grammar of the visual arts, the figure functions rather
as a serial manufacture of forms within a certain continuous field (matter,
territory, space, culture, language, tradition, etc.). Where an eidetic transcen-
dental platform includes abstract plastic categories, working as grammatical
prototypes (as for example the golden section, the ancient structure of the
Basilica, perspectival construction, the Holy Cross, pyramidal composition, or
indeed any other iconographical type), a figure expresses rather the deviation
between such a prototype and a specific work or monument, a deviation
embodying a movement back and forth from the supposed prototypical
schema. This figural movement cannot be registered except as a mutation in
an underlying eidos.
Francastel offers a precise definition of form in the plastic arts:
What constitutes the form of a work is not the details, but the ensemble […]
the form is not the sum of the details integrated in the ensemble which consti-
tutes the work, it does not pertain to the level of elements and of contents,
but to the level of principles, that is to say structures. It is identified with the
organizing scheme that suggests the assemblage of the elements, being chosen
as significatives not because of their conformity with heteroclite models, taken
from the outside, but in consideration of their relation with the specific rules
of the organizing scheme. The form is related not to the pulses coming from
the exterior world – the domain of perception – but to the principles of the
cohesion of the system – to a problematics of the imaginary.33
To paraphrase: the form of the work of art is its cohesive construction, acting as
an imaginary ‘totality’. At the same time, the figure embodies not the cohesive
42 Figural Philology
Only the series enables the prototype to exist, without the series the prototype
will rest a ‘chef-d’oeuvre inconnu’. We do not propose to limit the history of art to
the (study of) prototypes, creators of forms. The recognition of the role and of the
history of the arts demands, at the same time, the study of series and of models.35
The figure registers the survival and mutation of forms from medium to
medium, age to age, ‘generation’ to ‘generation’, but also from a mind into a
matter and back again. It is the passage, or transmission itself, that a figure
captures. A few decades before Francastel, Henri Focillon dedicated a chapter
of his Vie des forms to the life of forms in the realm of spirit or mind.36 Focillon
writes: ‘to have consciousness, is to have a form’,37 and ‘To a certain order of
forms corresponds a certain order of spirits.’38 An elaboration of Focillon’s
terminology would suggest that to any figural series there corresponds a certain
formal order.
A work of art registers within itself not only a prototype or a model, like
schemes of harmony or of the presentation of space, but also a movement of
deviation from this model. A work of art is a result of the integration of subse-
quent and supplementary factors (those that are not known in advance and
are not declaratively or literally announced in manifestos or artists’ manuals)
into a process of the repetition and variation of a formal prototype. It is only
in a retrospective view of the artistic process that a figural structure can be
unearthed; and this structure relates not only to the engendering form but also
to the process of realization.
In the pictorial domain, where a form has the status of a model or a genre (a
‘grammar’ in the Rieglian sense) which is actualized and realized in the artwork,
Forms and figures: Two fundamental modes of pictorial production 43
In his Gedanken über die Nachahmung der griechischen Werke in der Malerei
und Bildhauerkunst (1755),42 Johann Joachim Winckelmann, mentioned in the
first chapter as one of the pioneers of the relation between philology and art
history, discussed Michelangelo’s technique of transferring a small model into a
full ‘Figur’.43 In this process, which Winckelmann reconstructs by following the
writings of Giorgio Vasari, Michelangelo used a quadrate container of water with
a scale of heights of the water level, in which a small model, the prototype, was
set; then, level by level, water was poured on the model, allowing Michelangelo
to capture and transfer, slice by slice, as in a topographical map, the exact
extension of his model and its inner variations, thus transferring, gradually, the
relation between the model and the container to the full-size sculpture. Here
Winckelmann describes a process of the transmission of forms, from one matter
to another and from one scale to another, in a process performed through
the delineation of silhouettes and their relation to the frame of the container.
According to this reconstruction, what enabled Michelangelo to make the trans-
ference of a model from scale to scale and from matter to matter was a figural
situation: a delineated surface within an encompassing frame.
The domain of pictorial production not only forms part of the domain of
human production at large, but also participates in the plastic domain, a domain
that was recently underlined most notably by Catherine Malabou.44 Human
production includes modes of production that are neither pictorial nor plastic,
for example literature or music. Yet art of any media engages with the plastic
mutation of reality and the ways in which things are distinguished from that
which surrounds them. It is necessary then to say a few words about what is
understood here by ‘plastic’. Plastic production is a production of space through
space; as Pierre Francastel wrote in 1965: ‘All the plastic arts are the arts of
space […] every plastic sign is, as a consequence, spatial […] it is therefore
important to study the plastic form in the function of the notion of space.’45
In the German tradition of art theory, at least from Herder’s in the eighteenth
century up to Badt’s ‘Wesen der Plastik’, ‘Plastik’ is used in a more limited
manner denoting specifically sculptural, three-dimensional works. The present
work, however, refers to the ‘plastic’ in the more general sense pertaining to the
extensive (spatial) dimension of creation. In this sense plastic things are the
spatial foundation of optical perception. This was also the opinion of Kurt Badt’s
Forms and figures: Two fundamental modes of pictorial production 45
‘Wesen der Plastik’ from 1962.46 In this essay, Badt concentrated on the place of
sculpture, the creation of ‘stereometric bodies’ (stereometrische Grundkörper47),
as fundamentally decisive for ‘plastic life’ (plastischces Leben); nevertheless he
emphasizes that the discussion regarding the plastic domain pertains also to
painting and to the other ‘visual’ arts. The word ‘plastic’ is derived from the
Greek word πλάξ, meaning surface, plate or level; πλασις comes from the verb
‘to form’ or the noun ‘figure’, and πλάστός means ‘formed’ or ‘fabricated’, mostly
in soft or elastic matter like clay.48 Plastic action means causing a change in a
given material capable of receiving and absorbing that change. It is a movement
(performed or initiated usually by a hand or an arm of some sort, as Focillon
emphasized49) by which a piece of material acquires a shape, a form, through its
movement with other or more material. In Roman times, Pliny the Elder in his
Parva Naturalia, book 35,50 discussed the invention of the plastic art (plasticen,
plastae) based on moulding in clay. His story goes back to Butades, a potter
from Sicyon, at Corinth, who had a daughter,
who was in love with a young man; and she, when he was going abroad, drew in
outline on the wall the shadow of his face thrown by a lamp. Her father pressed
clay on this and made a relief, which he hardened by exposure to fire with the
rest of his pottery […] because of Butades modelers get their Greek name of
plastae.51
Sight reveals merely shapes, but touch alone reveals bodies […] What is light
able to paint upon our eyes? That which can be painted: pictures [Bilder] […]
But they can only draw what is there – a surface, the most diverse visible objects
ranged alongside one another. Things lying behind each other, solid, heavy
objects can no more be given to the eye than the lover concealed behind a
hanging or the miller singing away in his windmill can be painted on a canvas
[…] Every object reveals just so much of itself to me as the mirror before me
46 Figural Philology
reveals of myself. That is, the figure, the frontal aspect. In order to know that I
am more than this I must employ my other senses, or deduce that there is more
by means of ideas.52
What interests us here is the passage between the figure and the body; the
manner in which the flat delineated surface receives its reason and meaning.
Further on in Plastik, Herder asks: ‘Is it not our plastic sense that enables us
to transform the line back into a body, the flat figure back into a rounded and
living form?’53 Therefore, according to Herder, and similarly to Pliny, it is the
assignment of the plastic arts to ‘return’ that which is perceived as a flat image
into a full, tangible bodily figure.
Adrian Stokes suggested a similar differentiation between moulded and flat
plasticity in the twentieth century. He distinguished between moulding, aligned
with plasticity, and carving. Where moulding consists basically of adding,
pushing and squeezing a material, carving consists of severing, by a cutting
gesture, from a given surface, accentuating and realizing the matter’s own spatial
existence. As Stokes writes:
One can say at once of modeling forms (as opposed to carving forms) in the
widest sense, that they are without restraint: I mean that they can well be
the perfect embodiment of conception: whereas, in the process of carving,
conception is all the time adjusted to the life that the sculptor feels beneath
his tool. The mind that is intent on plasticity often expresses in sculpture the
sense of rhythm, the mental pulse. Plastic objects, though they are objects,
often betray a tempo. Carving conception, on the other hand, causes its object,
the solid bit of space, to be more spatial still. Temporal significance, instead
of being incorporated in space, is here turned into space and thus is shown in
immediate form, deprived of rhythm. Modeling conception, untrammeled by
the restraint that reverence for objects as solid space inspires, may turn to many
kinds of extreme.54
working with lumps and stains (modelling). Plastic reality is a ‘well’, piercing its
way deep into corporeal matter, from which one may draw the pictorial potion,
quenching the thirst of thought. In the present work, it is less the sheer possi-
bility of the matter to be formed and more the manner in which figural activity
produces both things and meanings that lies at the heart of the discussion. In
other words, at issue here is the pictorial domain of production. But can a plastic
pictorial figural dynamics be integrated into the sciences of history, into the
humanities? The next chapter explores the ways in which plasticity and pictures
inform and shape historical meaning.
48
4
the twentieth century, in the following sequence: as the artwork was gradually
identified with the synthetic sensual viewing experience, the validity of the
affinity between a synthetic cohesiveness of impressions and the truth (either of
external things or of ideas) was weakened, being superseded by an accentuation
of the inner qualities of artistic products themeselves. Martin Jay has shown
that throughout the twentieth century an explicit unease (up to a ‘denigration’)
was expressed regarding the act of vision, widely defined.7 As part of this traced
narrative, Idea and ‘Figura’ both indeed examined the relationship between
pictures and truth, and while Idea reconstructed a genealogy of the problem,
‘Figura’ suggested a possible resolution. If in Panofsky’s Idea truth is presented
as the carrier of the value of the picture, then in Auerbach’s ‘Figura’ it is historical
reality which is presented as an instrument of validation.
Being based on a lingual practice, a philological understanding of the history
of art should entail a certain amount of suspicion regarding the image. As such,
it will be to some extent iconoclastic, in the sense that images are a necessary
yet not sufficient instrument to articulate truth. Byzantine iconoclasm, which
issued from the Hebraic prohibition on the production of images in the Ten
Commandments, was active mostly between the eighth and tenth centuries.
Within it one finds elaborate discussions of the status and the legitimacy of
the use of imagery, notably in religious practice.8 The second council of Nicea
(787) declared a renewed confidence in the religious icon, though iconoclast
controversies continued well into the tenth century.9 While the iconoclasts
condemned the production and the usage of imagery in religious liturgy, the
‘iconophiles’ (sometimes referred to as ‘iconodules’), among them John of
Damascus (645–749)10 and Theodor of Studion (759–826),11 produced written
defences of religious icons and images in general. The iconophiles insisted on
the pious character of the reverence of icons, and even declared iconoclasm
itself as heretical.12 The iconophile authors were careful not to argue for the
picture’s self-validity; instead, they examined and shaped the mechanics of
icon usage, enabling the icon to serve as a liturgical instrument, embodying
a distance between man and the divine.13 It was by way of a realist argument
of hierarchical distance between the prototype and the type that the icon was
re-evaluated and legitimized. A similar, balanced and cautious attitude to the
use of pictures can also serve a philological approach to the history of art.
An earlier ancient view of art exhibiting an iconoclastic tendency was, of
course, that of Plato. Panofsky opens his Idea with the Platonic disqualification
of produced mimesis,14 and goes on to examine the way in which this archaic
rejection actually established the history of the western theory of art and was
Pictorial validities in art and history 51
conserved by it. The tradition of art theory thus can be regarded as icono-
philic in nature, in the sense that it tried to come to terms with the Platonic
iconoclastic position. Panofsky’s Idea articulates the problem of the European
pictorial tradition in iconophilic terms, relevant to the discussion regarding the
heretical danger that is to be found in the image.
Based on the Platonic hiatus between image and truth and its neo-Platonic
healing, the iconophilic western theory of art insisted on the eidetic content of
artistic images. The discussion in Auerbach’s ‘Figura’, a decade later, displaced
the question of the eidetic contents of pictures onto the question of the plastic
mechanics of historical reality (geschichtliche Wirklichkeit).15 The figure, as
Auerbach describes its transmutations, has its reality neither in the εἶδος nor
in a schematic unity of possible experience and the transcendental ideas that
regulate it, but rather in the extension of the past itself, construed in terms of
rehearsal, restoration, narration and realization (Erfüllung).16
Michael Podro has referred to Idea as ‘a book which should perhaps be seen
as both a reflection upon [Panofsky’s] own thought and upon the past’.17 As
just mentioned, Panofsky organized the book around the Platonic iconoclastic
rejection of the produced picture, grounded in the transcendent status of the
εἶδος. According to Panofsky, Platonic truth is foreign to art (Kunstfremde),18
yet it is exactly this foreignness, according to his narrative, that served as the
subject matter for the entire history of the theory of art, from the Roman period
to the Baroque and up to the nineteenth century. Panofsky demonstrated that
throughout the history of the western theory of art, from Plotinus (c. 205–70)
to Gian Pietro Bellori (1613–96), the artwork has been valued as a mimesis of
eidetic truth by the (artistic) Idea. The question as to whether truth is located
in the soul of the artist, in objective reality, or in the art of the past, was
secondary to the central consistent argument underlying the development of
the European theory of art: what gives the work of art its value is its capacity to
imitate truth, via eidetic forms. Panofsky’s essay is concerned with the unending
task of reconciling art with truth, and the assumption of a Platonic schism
between the two is also the kernel for the Panofskyan iconophile argument.
Panofsky traces the historical transmutations of the relation between the plastic
picture (plastisches Bild) and truth, incorporated by the artistic Idea. European
52 Figural Philology
theory of art used the concept of the Idea as the bearer of the original Platonic
cohesiveness-of-strangers between art and truth. One should note that the
Greek language differentiates between eidos (εἶδος) and idea (ιδέα), and this
difference marks the same foreignness that Panofsky discussed: where eidos
denotes absolute and eternal forms, ‘idea’ denotes apparent manifestations of
these forms, for example in beautiful harmonic relations. Next in this etymo-
logico-ontological chain lies Eydolon (εἴδωλον), which denotes the illusionist,
imaginary, deceiving, idolatrous appearance.19 The development of this Platonic
topos in the western theory of art, in Panofsky’s version, culminated in the possi-
bility of a Kantian categorical set of plastic values, constituting the fundamental
concepts (Grundbegriffe) of the science of art, and replacing the function of the
classical artistic Idea.20 The Idea gives an artwork its value, even its ‘truth’ value,
but it also bestows value on the picture’s depicted reality. As we will see, this
truth-value of pictures also continued to interest Panofsky in his later writings.
Indeed, the rift between truth and art, exemplified by the problem of the
truth-value of art, serves as one of the central foundations of the history of the
theory of artistic production. But this rift is only the preamble to another crisis
Panofsky exposes, that between truth and reality.
Panofsky’s Idea traces the process by which the ‘Idea’ became a validating
instrument for pictures: when artworks imitate an Idea, their relation to truth
is guaranteed. Gradually, during the sixteenth century, it had become clear that
the agent responsible for the imitation of the Idea was the creative artist himself
and that the Idea was immanent to the mind of this artistic creative subject. The
Idea, then, in Panofsky’s story, does not belong to ‘reality’ but to the creative
agent, be it the divine creator or the human artist.
An evident general theme of Idea, and of Panofsky’s earlier works in general,
is the ambiguous status of reality, or of historical reality to use Auerbach’s term,
in the process of researching works of art. Even when discussing the realist
tendencies of the Renaissance theory of art, Panofsky is interested more in the
way the schematization of reality finds its seat in the inner ideas of the artist, and
with the subject–object copula that is achieved through it, than in the notion of
reality itself and its relation to the creative act.
As is well known and will be elaborated upon later, Panofsky’s method had
strong connections with the neo-Kantian school. One of the typical traits of
Pictorial validities in art and history 53
Written by Auerbach during his exile in Istanbul, ‘Figura’ is similar in style and
scope to Panofsky’s Idea. Indeed, Auerbach refers to the latter work in a footnote
to the second part of his essay.29 Yet ‘Figura’ could be seen as implicitly standing
in a polemical relation with Panofsky’s Idea. The polemic has implications for
the understanding of antiquity, regarding the way to read neo-Platonism, as
well as for the problem of meaning in the humanities. ‘Figura’ undertakes both
a genealogical and an etymological survey of the unit of the figure. While both
Panofsky and Auerbach begin their inquiries with classical texts from Greco-
Roman late antiquity, the chronological borders of ‘Figura’ are narrower than
those of Idea: they extend from the first century bce to the late middle ages (the
so-called ‘proto-Renaissance’, taking place in fourteenth-century Italy), while
Idea continues into the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. Indeed, whereas
Idea preserves a problem originating in the Greek texts, Auerbach’s ‘Figura’
explores a conceptual scheme issuing from and essentially pertaining to Latin
civilization, the terrain defining Romance philology. Elsewhere in Auerbach’s
writings, especially in Mimesis,30 it is apparent that the realist impulse inherent
in the figura as he presents it already existed in the Old Testament, and that
the figure continued to play a central role in western art after the fourteenth
century, especially in the nineteenth century.31
If in Idea it is the topos of the ‘Idea’ that conserves through the ages the
‘eidetic’ status of beauty, then in ‘Figura’ the Idea of beauty is laid aside and
the εἶδος is replaced by the Latin figura.32 Figura is the etymological source
for the word Fictor, engendering also the terms factum, pictorial, factory and
fiction.33 The figura carries heretical connotations, as from the beginnings of
its deployment it was related to historical, dynamic material reality. Yet as
Giambatista Vico,34 Auerbach’s influential ancestor, had argued, in Latin the
Pictorial validities in art and history 55
words truth (verum) and fact (factum) are very close, if not synonyms.35 Human
truth, in Vico, as well as in Auerbach, refers to what man has made, and the
figura is the vessel in which the fact has been realized and has endured through
the ages. Otherwise put, the figure relates to a manufactured past, presented as
a series of historical realities. Thus, the term figura entails the restoration of the
alliance between the domain of plastic reality and truth, the same alliance whose
crisis Panofsky uncovered in Idea.
Auerbach argues that the essence of the shift between the Greek and the
Roman paradigms consists in the fact that the Latin word figura was used as
a translation for the numerous terms used to describe ‘forms’ in the Greek
language, and therefore does not have one single Greek source. It could be
used as a synonym for terms as schema (σχῆμα), plasis (πλάσις), morphe
(μορϕή), eydolon (εἴδωλον), eidos and tupos (τύπος).36 Therefore, the Latin figura
combined a plurality of Greek notions that differentiated between the versions
and nuances of ‘having a form’. The figure denotes that mobility of forms. In
its early manifestations the word figura, according to Auerbach, carried the
following meanings and connotations: sensuality, carnality, variation of form,
ornament, manner, aspect, corporality and transmutability. Notably, the early
usages of the word are dated to the same historical moment as the appearance
of philology itself, the first century bce of the Roman Empire, which witnessed
the passage from the Latin into Greek and back again. Auerbach begins by
exploring the ways in which the term figura appeared in the writings of Varro
(116–27 bce), Cicero (106–43 bce) and Lucretius (c. 97–55 bce) around the
first century bce, referring to the physical, concrete aspect of things.37 In Cicero,
one also finds the use of the term in the vocabulary of oratory and rhetoric.38 In
Quintilian’s writings (35–c. 96 ce), a substantial theory of the rhetorical figure
was developed.39 But according to Auerbach it was in the writings of the Church
Fathers that the full figural structure came into being. In the texts of Paulus and
Augustine the figural structure referred to the affinity between the New and the
Old Testaments.40 The New Testament rehearses scenes and elements of the Old
Testament, and the old is a ‘real prophecy’ of the new one. The use of figural
dynamics was a central tool for the clarification of this affinity and continu-
ation between the old and the new. For example, the biblical figure of Joshua is
considered a (pre-)figuration of Christ, but symmetrically Christ can become a
figurative couple of Joshua only if both are considered as historical figures, as
historical realities; therefore, even if there might be doubt regarding the reality
of the historical ‘person’ of Joshua, there is no doubt as to the past reality of the
historical figure of Joshua, which is validated by the figural realization. Thus,
56 Figural Philology
This Science [i.e. Vico’s New Science] proceeds exactly like geometry, which,
as it contemplates the world of dimensions or constructs it from its elements,
makes that world for itself, but the reality of our Science is as much greater [than
that of geometry] as is that of the orders which pertain to the affair of men than
that of points, lines, planes and shapes.43
be distinguished from the icon, as the figure is devoid of the magical and/or
divine force with which the symbol and the icon are endowed in their tradi-
tional definitions.47 In short, the distinguishing mark of the figure is its realist
character, which is neither strictly indexical nor symbolical.
As just noted, the full figural structure is first encountered in the texts of the
Church Fathers, wherein the figure receives its explicit historical sense: ‘Figura
is something real and historical which announces something else that is also
real and historical.’48 The figure is a plastic entity that remains real, specific and
concrete even when it is integrated into serial classifications. Its two elements
(the ‘pre-figure’ and the figure) always retain their specific ‘real’ character.
Furthermore, figures do not consist of one singular element, rather the figure
participates in a figural series, quasi-synthesizing at least two historical realities,
but not achieving a full comprehensive, organic synthesis, unity or Aufhebung.
As mentioned earlier, in Panofsky’s essay the concept of the Idea itself
behaves much like an Auerbachian figure: it is a plastic form, existing in
a dynamic of variation, anticipation and retroaction throughout the ages.
Panofsky’s philological excavation in Idea consists of a regression towards and
a restoration of a generic problem to be located in the past of the genealogical
story. The Auerbachian figural narrative, in its turn, adds to the conservation
of the generic problem the effective factuality of past reality. This fuller figural
mode appears a little later on Panofsky’s works.
Panofsky’s Idea implies a problematic attitude towards the notion of reality,
a notion that is one of the chief concerns of Auerbach’s ‘Figura’. For Auerbach,
real means first and foremost historical. This leads to the question of the realist
impulse in both essays, serving as their iconophilic kernel. The reading of
Auerbach suggested here differs from standard interpretations of his realism,
which see it as representational. The last (2003) English translation of the
subtitle of Auerbach’s Mimesis gives it as: The Representation of Reality in Western
Literature.49 But the translation of ‘Darstellung’ as ‘representation’ is not the only
one possible; it would be better translated as presentation; and the translation of
dargestellte Wirkclichkeit as ‘representation of reality’, rather than as ‘presented
reality’ is questionable as well. The alternative translation of ‘Darstellung’ as
presentation would emphasize the dimension of production, design or display,
which, taking into account Auerbach’s Viconian attitude towards history, may
58 Figural Philology
Both Idea and ‘Figura’ employ realist argumentation in their restorative narration
of the legitimacy of pictorial signs. For Panofsky, Platonic realism paves the
way for a neo-Kantian reconstruction of the transcendental subject of artistic
experience; Auerbachs’ realism,50 on the other hand, is more Aristotelian in
emphasizing a relation between capacity (dynamis) and realization (energia) in
which the reality of the past has a pre-established validity that the figure realizes
and validates. In Auerbach’s method, historical reality behaves similarly to
Aristotelian nature, in which the τέλος (aim, end) of things comes to be realized
by the dynamics of change of place.51 This nature consists of the durational
movement between occurrence and rehearsal, consisting in a spatialization of
the historical temporal flow.
Michael Holquist has Auerbach’s realism as representational, but as argued
above this is does not fit well with Auerbach’s presentational motivation.52
Perhaps it would be better to describe Auerbach’s realism as a methodical
realism, to borrow a term from the neo-Thomist philosopher Étienne Gilson
(1844–1978).53 It is a methodical realism in the sense that it postulates the past
reality of a work as necessary for a specific philological inquiry; and this postu-
lated reality of the past is confirmed and validated through historical reality,
apprehended and maintained by the researcher. It is a realism whose reference
is the past reality of works, enacted, presented and realized by historical
reality. The methodic bias also points to the fact that it is a realism regarding a
specific problem, encountered by the researcher, demanding a certain amount
of regulation in order for the inquiry to proceed.54 Within the confines of the
examination of a specific problem, the reality of the past transmutations of a
Pictorial validities in art and history 59
subject and object, Auerbach’s figura is a copula between two separate historical
realities, being both subjects and objects, to be read a posteriori as chained in
a series. The question of reality in Auerbach is first and foremost of a historio-
graphical nature.
Finally, Panofsky’s and Auerbach’s interest in the Renaissance also stemmed
from the philological tendency they shared with Aby Warburg, as will be
shown in the Chapter 6. Both were intrigued by the Renaissance rehearsal and
restoration of antiquity. The Renaissance itself, then, is examined as a figural
phenomenon, establishing a figural series between itself, Roman antiquity,
classical antiquity and, for Auerbach, also the Old Testament and nineteenth-
century literature. Notwithstanding the emphasis on Renaissance themes, the
long duration of the medieval age and its terms haunts the history of both the
figure and of philological rationality.
Iconophilic method
The readings in Panofsky’s Idea and Auerbach’s ‘Figura’ amount to the restor
ation of a latent iconoclastic debate within the humanities during the first half of
the twentieth century. Both express a concern regarding the pictorial, and take
upon themselves the task of justifying the use of pictures as cognitive agents. In
neither case, however, does the picture stand as a sovereign entity. In Panofsky,
the iconoclast rift between image and truth lies at the base of the western theory
of art; while Auerbach suggested an iconophilic alternative in which the figure
stands for the validity of past realities. In the Panofskyan version, we encounter
an approach to the plastic domain that is inherently epistemological: the work
of art is considered an agent of knowing. In Auerbach’s version, the structure
of remembrance and restoration is presented as preceding any knowledge. A
synthesis of the methods of Panofsky and Auerbach, and especially of their
approaches to the plastic domain, may pave the way for an iconophilic method
that promotes the possibility of that domain serving as a vessel for dealing with
the past.
In Idea, Panofsky deploys the iconophilic efforts of the history of the theory
of art, leading to a transcendental schematization of artistic production itself.
Auerbach, in his turn, suggests exchanging truth for factum and beauty for
character. Instead of opposing truth to reality, in Auerbach’s ‘Figura’ reality is
truth, inasmuch as we consider reality as that which has been made. Therefore,
the Auerbachian concept of the figura can be regarded as a response to
Pictorial validities in art and history 61
form within a form,11 a form around a form; the ‘figure’ is always established in
a relation to that which is ‘not figure’, or ground. Therefore, figural dynamics
contains a bilateral movement from a form to a platform and back again.
Deleuze also emphasized the importance of the platform, which he called
‘l’aplat’ (translated into English as ‘field’), to the dynamics of the figure. For
Deleuze, writing about the paintings of Francis Bacon, the platform is one of
‘uniform and motionless color’.12 But in the version proposed here, the platform
includes essentially also the matter from which the work, and hence the figure,
is made.
In the figural kinetics, a ‘matching’ between a type and a prototype takes
place. In this process both parties, both contoured forms, can be considered
as each other’s beginnings (ἀρχή), in the sense that they mutually support
and generate each other. As was suggested earlier, this figural situation has
an affinity with the well-known fable regarding the invention of painting or
drawing related in Pliny the Elder’s Natural History, which actually concerned
the origin of moulded figures.13 In this fable, a young Corinthian girl draws on
a wall the silhouette of her departing beloved, after which her father moulds a
relief of the young man’s figure in clay. Figural kinetics is a regressive, retrograde
motion of serial delineation. It is regressive, since its starting point is an image,
a reflection, a form, a picture, and the figural dynamics delineate the form’s
position, i.e. supply the form with a support and a place. The figural movement
is thus two-way: from the platform to the form, and from the form back to the
platform. For Deleuze, again referring to Bacon, ‘the movement of the figure
going towards the structure […] at the limit, tends to dissipate into the fields of
color’.14 The figure dissipates not only into the fields of colour, but also into the
material reality of the platform. This complements the neo-Platonic paradigm of
the form which is found within matter, being revealed, released and uncovered
by the artist.15 In the figural model, by contrast, that which is uncovered also
returns to that which carries it. The figural prototype is not the departing young
man himself, but the gesture of drawing his contours on the wall. The figural
series occurs when an affinity is formed between at least two delineated surfaces,
for example between the wall-painted silhouette and the moulded figure. This
iteration itself, when distinguished as such, generates a figural situation.
The figural dynamics produce a plastic definition in the sense of a distin-
guishing border (ὁρισμός), grasping the thing’s reality (ουσία), by supplying
it with a definition (λόγος). The plastic definition relates to moving bodies,
and delineates their outline (πέρας)16 at a given moment, isolating them from
their surroundings.17 In this way, the figural situation denotes the place (τόπος)
Sub figuralitate historiæ 65
of a thing. In his Physics, Aristotle defined the place as the inner surface of a
thing that contains another moving thing.18 The figure occurs at the borderline
between a moving thing and another thing through which the former passes.
The support, the ground or the platform could be considered a place of passage
for the moving body.
The distinction, the ‘isolation’, of the figured slice from its carrying surface
necessarily produces the effect of depth, involving a differentiation between a
front and a back, a stage and a back-stage, as we saw in the previous chapter.
Being involved in the production of material things, the figure is essentially
linked to corporeality (as Deleuze also emphasized19). This could consist in
gestures of production (drawing a line on a wall, cutting a material, etc.) or
other bodily movements that the figural gesture captures and registers. A third
material aspect of the figural plastic situation is the matter of the surface upon
or from which the figure is made: wall, paper, linen, etc. The figure’s corporeality
operates on the line of the contour, where the limits of a body or a thing are
drawn. Therefore, the figural place is the meeting place of at least two corpo-
realities: the body of the producer (e.g. the Corinthian girl) and the produced
thing (the line on the wall).
Rather than being an image, the figure is the surface upon which the
formation of images in enabled.20 The figure is the actual elementary gesture
of the production of an image and of imagination (Einbildungskraft). It is
therefore a concrete material reality, enabling and supporting the synthesis of
the imagination. Because it exists primarily as corporeal and only subsequently
as a sensed image, the figure itself does not have to be actually seen in order for
it to be real; hence approaches to art that base the figure on sensual experience
are not pertinent to our inquiry. Note also that in the Auerbachian under-
standing of the figure, the figural relation (like that between Joshua and Jesus)
exists hidden in the womb of history; it is the task of man to uncover the figural
message and make it distinct.
The figure is posited where the synthetic possibility of the imagination is
enabled: where Descartes located the sensus communis and Kant what he called
the ‘figural synthesis’ (figürliche Synthesis);21 this will be discussed further in
Chapter 7. Both Descartes and Kant isolated this figural surface upon which
the primary inscription of the contact between humans and things is registered
before it becomes a differentiated sense-perception phenomenon. The figure’s
matter is an inscription of an elementary, corporeal memory.
Though it involves separations, distinctions and delineations, in order to
conceive of a figure one must also effect a synthetic operation, binding and
66 Figural Philology
holding together both separated forms. The centrality of this synthetic intuition
to the practice of iconology will also be discussed in Chapter 7.22 Synthetic
intuition conceives simultaneously the identifiable form and the surface upon
which it rests. It is a delineated territory within and upon a certain surface.
The figural line portrays the inner boundary of a surface. In the case of the
silhouette, the presence of the projected thing or body is denoted by the figure,
though this thing or body is not entirely present in the delineated figure itself.
As Pascal put it in his Pensées, ‘Figure porte absence et presence’:23 Figure carries
both presence and absence. Even when it contains reality, some part of this
reality is missing or covered, that is to say not directly attainable. Indeed, figural
realism is a partial realism, in the sense that only a part of the reality of the thing
is maintained by the figure. The intuition that captures the figure works in retro-
spect, after a body has moved, and after this movement has caused something
else to move; it is an anamnesic process, a mnemonic operation whose task is to
discover a certain movement occurring in the past.24
The figure is not exactly an image then, but, as suggested in Chapter 2,
neither is it exactly a form. A figure is not a form in the sense of an Idea or an
εἶδος; rather, the figure is the condensation of a transmission of a form. A figure
is produced when a form is transfigured, that is to say moved, transferred, from
carrier to carrier, from vessel to vessel, as in the transfiguration episode in the
New Testament, when Christ is transfigured into a vision in the sky before the
eyes of his followers (Mt. 17.1-9; Mk 9.2-8; Lk. 9.28-36). Returning again to the
Aristotelian terminology, the figure pertains more to the genre (γένος) than
to the form (εἶδος) of a thing or a work and also to genre in its most general
Aristotelian definition,25 as a continuous series of realizations of a certain form.
It is closer to the morphe, more than to an eternal Eidos, as it is always bound
up with matter and can, therefore, cohere within a hylomorphistic framework.26
To return to Pliny’s fable: when the amorous girl draws the line on the wall,
what is retained is the past reality of her departing beloved. The girl’s father,
according to the legend, then moulds in clay the young man’s figure after the
outline or the contour on the wall. While passing from platform to platform,
from place to place, the figural delineation proceeds not only forwards in time,
but also backwards, not only extending, but also contracting and not only
expanding, but also sinking downwards into the depth of that which was, that
is to say into the reality of the past. The figure testifies to the shape of a past
action. A bodily movement acted and changed a thing (a wall, clay, etc.), thereby
producing a work. It is this productive bodily movement, this gesture, that the
figure captures: the outlines of a movement.
Sub figuralitate historiæ 67
We turn now to consider the ‘lingual’ understanding of the figure, a field that,
at first glance, seems quite distant from the discussion revolving around the
plastic figure. But only if it proves possible to merge the two poles of the figural
structure, the plastic and the lingual, can we begin to conceive of a figural
philology that would synthesize thought, history and plasticity and the other
name, which could be iconology.
As mentioned earlier, Auerbach returns to first-century bce Rome in order
to deploy his genealogy of figura. In the Roman texts, figura appeared for the
most part as a rhetorical term, attesting to language’s capacity to persuade and to
claim validity.27 From Roman times to the twentieth century, we find a consistent
affiliation of figural persuasion with the formal mechanics of language, such as
repetition, metaphor and phrasing, i.e. linguistic style, as distinguished from
the literal, semantic meaning of a linguistic articulation.28 These are the famous
rhetorical tropes, among which the figure is central.29 This non-literal, but rather
dynamizing character of the figure appears in seventeenth-century French
theory of rhetoric and linguistics, as well as in the twentieth century in the
elaborations of Gérard Genette (b. 1930).30 Along with its rhetorical character,
the figure also assumed theological meaning in Christianity. To revisit what was
presented in previous chapters, in the figuration principle of Christian theology,
two separate and concrete historical realities are connected retroactively as
realizing the same truth.31 The figural regression enables one to read the past as a
‘Realprophetie’, in which an ancient historical reality is considered as analogical
in some way to a later historical reality. This post-factum repetition supports
and validates a theologically acclaimed truth, for example, Christian salvation.
Yet the analogy between Joshua and Jesus, for instance, involves neither a
similarity in their concrete appearances, nor in their ‘inner forms’ (e.g. the fact
that both were human beings); rather, what binds them together into a figure is
an aspect of their character, related to their actions. Auerbach insisted that the
figural unit preserves the difference of the two concrete realities connected. The
figure repeats a manner of action (a modus operandi) in two realities separated
in time and space. The figural kinetics are a repetition of a gesture, like writing
or drawing on a wall, for example. What is figural is not the repetition of that
which is drawn (or represented), but the drawing-gesture itself, i.e. it is not the
repetition of a depicted theme (which will become the subject of iconography),
but rather of a set of gestures regarding a theme. The delineation of the figural
movement is possible only in retrospect. The next step, therefore, is to examine
68 Figural Philology
What then might be a synthetic model of the figure that would account for both
its aspects? The relationship between the two surfaces existing in the plastic
figure, the form and the platform, is analogous to the dual structure of the figure
as Auerbach presented it. Both cases involve an affinity between two realities,
an affinity that sustains a bilateral causation. In this causal relation both the
respective parties can be viewed as prior to and also subsequent to each other.
In order to conceive of the relationship between the two realities one should
proceed in a regressive movement, in which one reality is considered as the
cause or the beginning and the other as a result or a product. It is similar to
the relation existing between a body and clothing: at the same time as a body
is a carrier of clothing, that clothing also ‘defines’ the borders of the body. The
platform in the plastic figural structure, also designated above as the prototype
(or arché), is analogical to the past historical reality in Auerbach’s account of
the figural structure. Retroactively, this historical platform is registered and
realized as the carrier of the mark of the type. The form (or the type in the
plastic model of the figure) is analogical to the later object, which is usually what
the researcher (the philologist, iconologist or art historian) encounters: a text, a
work of art, a monument, etc.
When engaging in a philological inquiry, one starts from the type, seeking to
read it, name it, define it. Analogically to the paradigm of the Corinthian girl,
the desire to read originates in the possessive impulse, the wish to protect the
work from sinking into the depths of forgetfulness.32 But in order for the work
to remain, a regressive procedure of determining a prototype is required – a
prototype that will serve as the work’s cause, surface, platform or arché. The
prototype functions as a background, carrying the type and and making it
meaningful. Figural meaning is, therefore, to be found in the form of a making-
gesture that is repeated in history. The figural procedure begins with a detail,33
isolated within an encountered work. In order for the researcher to read a
text or a work regressively, she has to encounter some problem or detail that
demands to be defined (or better defined). Auerbach referred to this detail as
the philological Ansatz,34 an element that serves as the starting point, initiating
Sub figuralitate historiæ 69
the philological restoration, but which also serves as the Archimedean point of
the inquiry. As will be examined in the next chapter, Aby Warburg’s art history
was highly focused on the demands posed by the incomprehensible details
of artworks, such as floating garments or background allegorical elements in
paintings.35 Without the detail as a starting point, there could be no philological
thought process. It may be a part, a corner of the image, which somehow appears
as unreadable and, therefore, demands the activation of the ‘philological gaze’. It
is the detail that is not entirely ‘in its right place’. Something that must be better
located, better placed, better defined, better read. In order to be able to read it,
the philologist must discover the affinity between the fragment and a former
historical reality, giving them a redefinition or an outline, a place in history.
Indeed, for Pascal,36 but also in the canonical Christian structure, the figure was
understood as a message or a code, which can be read only retroactively, with
the aid of another historical reality. History then could read itself backwards
through the figural structure. In this sense, the later historical reality is read by
the older one, at the same time as the older serves as the delineator of the later.
Just as the historical reality of Jesus helps us to read anew the figure of Joshua,
so, too, does the reality of Joshua affirm the arrival of Christ, as if to say ‘the
truth was already there, although we did not yet see it clearly’.37 Thus, in history,
nothing is hidden; everything is revealed, reachable, a ‘donnée immediate de
la conscience’38 as Henri Bergson would have called it, only that one must,
in response to the shame of a certain detail, reforge the instruments that will
be proper and especially adjusted to its reading. It is because of the inherent
partiality of the human reading ability that the figure appears in the first place.
The elastical pictoriality of the res extensa, arriving for us, retrospectively, in the
figural mode, suggests the principle of a philological rationality and method.39
Yet one has to bear in mind that the two realities never unite completely in the
figural situation. As Genette observed, the figure always includes a gap between
the letter and the sense (‘entre le lettre et le sense’)40 or between the signifier and
the signified (‘entre le signifiant et le signifié’).41
One of Auerbach’s important arguments is that the realism of the figure
is related to the presentation of the past. The realism of the figural dynamics
appears when a certain fragment of the past is heightened and sustained
by a non-temporal dogma, treated as a truth for as long as it can sustain a
tenable thesis in the course of a certain inquiry. A methodical realism such
as is attempted in the present study is one in which the past reality of a work
is assumed as certain and real, as a factum, but only in so far as it is part of a
certain line of inquiry. Methodical realism would refer first and foremost to the
70 Figural Philology
reality of the Ansatz: the specific detail of the work that demands definition,
inaugurating the methodical process. It is an element of a work that may appear
to be part of something else, to belong to another work, and that, therefore,
needs be researched and distinguished in the depths of historical space. Earlier,
we mentioned Étienne Gilson’s 1935 notion of ‘methodical realism’,42 which
posits the apprehension of things together with the problems pertaining to them
as prior to any reflective process. Methodical realism has a Thomist, Aristotelian
origin, assuming not only the reality of things and their movements, but also
the ability of the mind to figure and formulate these moving things, even if not
to ‘represent’ them to their fullest extent. Gilson describes his realist position
thus: reality is, only when things are known. Or, when a mind knows a thing,
there is reality. With regard to the historical inquiry into produced things, we
could say: only from within the limits of a certain problem, question or inquiry,
can truth – historical, philological truth – be distilled. The reality contained
in the figural procedure is the reality of the knowledge of a work’s principle
of production or modus operandi, which is immediately given to us when we
encounter the work. The truth that the figure entails is that which is contained
in the very act of distinguishing a detail from a work. Methodical realism then
possesses, validates and affirms the reality of works.
The ‘matter’ (hyle) from which the figure is made, according to Auerbach,
is ‘historical reality’ (Geschichtliche Wirklichkeit);43 and in a complementary
manner, historical reality possesses figural reference (Figuraldeutung).44 The
realism that is to be found in the figure is historical in nature.45 But what is the
nature of the affinity between the reality to which the figure points and the truth
for which it is supposed to stand? And how should we understand the term
‘historical reality’?
In regard to the figural dynamics we can differentiate between three terms:
historical reality, historical meaning and past reality. What Auerbach calls
‘historical reality’ can be understood as a synthesis of the historical meaning
and the past reality of the work under discussion. Historical reality is to be
distinguished from historical meaning, which can be understood as the return
of a mode of action. Historical meaning is a realization (Erfüllung, in Auerbach’s
terms) of that mode of action. Better, historical meaning is a re-realization
– a repeating realization. If, in an Aristotelian hylomorphist sense, every
production is a realization, then we can return again to the terms of nineteenth-
century philology and say, after Boeckh and Usener, that ‘Philologie ist […]
Reproduktion des Produzierten’,46 and determine historical meaning as retro-
poiesis. It is the realization of a knowledge that has been latent in the action of
Sub figuralitate historiæ 71
a certain character, a realization that is the outcome of the fact that an action
is identified as repeated in two distinct realities that together form the figure.
Historical meaning presupposes the past reality of works, the fact of their
having been produced in the past and of their endurance through the ages.
The figure takes its validity from the assumption that at least two works were
produced. Joshua and Jesus both already were, that is the status of both is a past
status.
Figuraldeutung refers to reality as a past reality and is based on an intuition of
this past reality. The past reality of the work is that which permanently enables
a return and rehearsal, enduring through the different presentations that have
returned to it and restored it. Following the Viconian principle adopted by
Auerbach – that man can know only what he has himself made47 – it is the past
reality of works that sustains the certainty that can be achieved in the figural
practice of philology. The repeating activity that is distinguished in being
rehearsed is the historical meaning of the work; and the past reality of the
work is the durational sequence of rehearsals of the prototype upon the grid
of historical reality. Finally, the philologist himself rehearses what repeats in
history, continuing the dynamics of realization.
Aristotelian terminologies can also help in trying to pinpoint the realism
of the figure. The latter is a result of a search for definition and delineation,
a classification of a thing or a work. Its best parallel is the morphe (μορϕή),
which is defined as that which limits the moving matter (ὕλη). Things or bodies
are cohesive, hylomorphic units of morphe and matter.48 The two historical
realities in the figure serve as each other’s definition: the later historical reality is
considered as the essence, as that which entails the important part of the earlier
reality, just as the earlier is considered as a partial presentation of the later. Both,
then, should be considered as standing in an analogous relation to one another.
But what is the precise nature of this analogy?
It is difficult to determine exactly the nature of the definition that the figure
gives: certainly, it is not a definition at the level of the Eidos. Sometimes, it
contains an analogy in the name (such as Jehoshua–Jeshua), which will point us
in the direction of a paronyme (an analogy between two terms resulting from
an irregular change of a trait);49 indeed, many philological inquiries are actually
based on the structure of paronyme. Certainly, the figural analogy always refers
to specific cases from the textual history, but it seems to me that in most cases
what is repeating in the figure is a mode of action, a form of comportment,
which is presented as similar or comparable. The two realities that combine in
the figural unit are often personal characters, and what establishes the figural
72 Figural Philology
is the relationship between the two realities a causal one: Joshua did not produce
causally the appearance of Jesus within the historical narrative; rather, figural
causality is a retroactive process internal to the writing of history. The later
member of the figural couple produces the figurality of its former member. And
the figure results from a situation in which a certain historical reality knows
unconsciously and implicitly how to do something, without actually acknow
ledging having this knowledge. In other words, the figural series involves a
non-intented repetition: Joshua did not know that he was carrying the quality
that Jesus would carry, nor did he intend to carry that quality. Virgil did not
know Dante, yet in the figural mechanics Virgil knew something that Dante also
knew, something that enabled Virgil and Dante to ‘meet’ in the Divine Comedy
and to march together through the circles of purgatory, hell and heaven.
Finally, it must be stressed that a figure is identical neither with a ‘work’,
nor with an ‘artwork’. The figure rather begins with a detail, a fragment of a
work, which is read as a rehearsal of a former historical reality and this restor
ation declares itself to be a sort of distinguishing of the principle – the modus
operandi – of a work. This supports the establishing of a work’s definition,
localization or delineation. The figural rehearsal functions within the frames
of reference of philological and iconological inquiry and it is not certain that it
could function in any other kind of inquiry. This figural inquiry regards not the
work ‘in itself ’, but the enduring participation of a work in traditions, presen-
tations and (mis)readings. But before turning to the iconological table itself,
the relation between Panofsky’s and Warburg’s iconologies will be discussed,
focusing on the character of the space that the figure opens, as essential to both
iconology and philology.
74
6
The previous chapter outlined the way in which the figure arranges the past,
making it readable and approachable, thereby drawing together plastic and
philological realities. Chapter 6 aims to show how the spatialization of history,
constituting historical reality at large, forms the basis of philological rationality.
We will begin with Panofsky’s examination of historical time and historical
space, before moving on to discuss what Aby Warburg referred to as the ‘philo-
logical gaze’. In so far as this gaze can be understood as laden with a spatializing
responsibility, it will allow us to establish an affinity between the two authors
regarding the spatializing character of the historical examination of the past.
Both Warburg and Panofsky were part of the Hamburg ‘Renaissance’ during
the first-quarter of the twentieth century.1 Though Panofsky worked indepen-
dently in the art history department of the newly founded University of
Hamburg, he maintained close relations with Warburg’s Kulturwissenschaftliche
Bibliothek. Panofsky’s key works from the 1920s – Dürers ‘Melencolia 1’.
Eine Quellen- und Typengeschichtliche Untersuchung (1923; co-authored with
Fritz Saxl (1890–1948)),2 Idea (1924)3 and ‘Die Perspektive als “symbolische
Form” ’ (1927)4 – were published by the Warburg Library. The often-taken-for-
granted affinity between Panofsky’s and Warburg’s art histories has rarely been
commented upon, however.5 This chapter seeks to furnish a platform for the
possibility of such a commentary.
Panofsky published his study ‘Über die vier Meister von Reims’ in the Jahrbuch
für Kunstgeschichte, in 1927, when he was already teaching at the University of
Hamburg. In that same year, Warburg announced the initiation of the picture
atlas Mnemosyne, constructed not far away in the same city.6 At the end of his
essay, Panofsky turned his attention to the problem of defining historical time,
and this section later became known as ‘Reflections on Historical Time’.7
76 Figural Philology
In this short text, referring explicitly to ‘Das Problem des historischen Zeit’ by
Georg Simmel (1858–1918),8 Panofsky was interested in the principles defining
the problem of time in the history of art. What he says about historical time can
be applied to the workings of the philological gaze, as conceived by Warburg, who
also talked about a spatial ‘widening of the borders’ of the history of art.9 Panofsky
linked the problem of historical time to that of historical space: ‘Thus it turns out
that each instance of historical time is dependent upon a specific historical space,
except that […] this historical space has as little to do with geographical space as
historical time does with astronomical time.’10 Thus, before being able to define
what historical time is, one must inquire about historical space. Historical space,
Panofsky insists, is not synonymous with natural space, and this non-natural
space is the sole possible approach to historical time. Panofsky’s general claim
is that historical space is built out of particular superpositions of frames of
reference, for which natural homogeneous time and space provide the support.
Panofsky points to the fact that the document or the work must be furnished
with a spatio-temporal framing, and that this framing is intermingled with,
yet distinguishable from, physical or natural spatio-temporality. Historical
time-space according is determined, first and foremost, by artworks. The
spatio-temporal historical fabric is therefore weaved around the Ansatzpuenkte
(starting, anchoring points) of works and artworks. This spatio-temporal
historical reality is a continuous one: a net of references extending throughout
history. Panofsky and Warburg consistently referred to a continuous historical
domain, extending from antiquity to modern times, which, for them, is the
ground of art historical inquiry.11 Though leaning on the Kantian theory of
space and time, Panofskyan historical space-time differs from it in the sense
that while for Kant space and time are a priori forms of intuition, Panofsky
says explicitly that historical space and time are a posteriori, or determined in
retrospect:
One might say that this order can only be realized after the fact, in other words,
through a reanchoring of the historically qualified frames of reference within
the course of homogeneous natural time and in the breadth of homogeneous
natural space.12
The fact that a content is in time, does not make it historical; the fact that it
is understood, does not suffice either to make it historical. It is only when the
two cross each other, where the content is temporalized on the basis of an
un-temporal understanding, that the content is historical.20
Finally, according to Simmel, two other factors support the reading of an event
as a historical atom: First, it must be located in a sequential series.21 Second, it
must be considered as a living unity (Einheit).22
In his ‘Reflections on Historical Time’, Panofsky is attentive to Simmel’s
formulations. Nevertheless, several decisive differences are to be underlined:
what Simmel delineates as the un-timely, Panofsky delineates as spatial. This
is a difference Panofsky himself raised in a note referring to Simmel’s essay.23
Furthermore, Panofsky transports Simmel’s notions of unity (Einheit), under-
standing (Verstehen) and life to the field of art. It is artistic style and the
aesthetic resistance of a specific work that are determining for the art historical
spatio-termporal reality. Because of the primary importance of spatiality and
spatialization in Panofsky’s account, it is the question of historical simultaneity
that arises much more often in his reading. It seems that this question
became increasingly important in Panofsky’s work, up to his Gothic Architecture
and Scholasticism of 1951. On numerous occasions he deployed a model of
simultaneity in order to articulate a certain moment of change or a mark of
distinction carried by an artwork. This combination of simultaneity and tempo-
rality appeared also in the work of Aby Warburg.
Iconological space: Panofsky with Warburg 79
to preserve the life of antiquity by tracing the trails of themes, motifs and
forms in their survival and transfiguration through ages and cultures. In 1905,
Warburg presented a lecture on Dürer to a gathering of ‘German Philologists
and Educators’.29 His research on the diachronic transfigurations of atom-units
of the pathos-formulae combining meaning and form, his well-known attention
to the details and nuances of works of art, his inquiry into and criticism of the
humanist tradition and the transfiguration of the ancient world in European
culture, all reflect a clear philological disciplinary practice.30 In his student
years at Bonn, Warburg attended the lectures of Hermann Usener, an influ-
ential turn-of-the-century philologist.31 Besides examining the relation between
mythological figures and archaic moments of overwhelming experience,
which was decisive in Warburg’s formulation of the concept of the pathos
formula, Usener was also interested in drawing uniting and separating lines
between philology and history,32 a task whose traces are detectable in Warburg’s
projects. While in Bonn, Warburg was also forming friendships with his fellow
students Adolph Goldschmidt and Wilhelm Vöge, two future mentors of Erwin
Panofsky.33 In a letter to his parents, written a few weeks after arriving at Bonn
to begin his university training, Warburg wrote: ‘I get enough philosophy in
Usener’s course. Professor Justi, the chief man for art history, I shall take next
term, after having done my proper philological studies.’34 Warburg therefore
noted the philosophical character of Usener’s lessons, and the link between
philosophy and philology, both appearing to the young Warburg as necessary
preparatory knowledge for his art historical studies. Usener’s conception of the
formation of ‘God names’ as expressions resulting from physico-psychological
agitation in face of the powers of nature was decisive for Warburg’s furnishing
of the concept of the pathos formula.35 Another philological reference has been
suggested by Anna Guillemin, who demonstrated an affinity between Warburg’s
work and that of the vitalist Crocean philologist Karl Voßler.36 These are but a
few examples out of many of how Warburg’s path crossed with the philological
disciplines of his time.
By the end of the nineteenth century, philological discourse began to
develop vitalist tendencies. Warburg’s use of the notion of the Nachleben itself
corresponds with the notion of life and its survival or, better said, after-life
and the vitalist component of his art history has been well researched. Both
Usener and Voßler are to be counted among the practitioners of vitalism or
Lebensphilosophie, around 1900, a movement in which Nietzsche’s work played
a central part.37 But the Dionysian, anti-rational tendency, which appears in
Warburg, Voßler and Nietzsche,38 should be placed within the framework of
Iconological space: Panofsky with Warburg 81
the issue of the status of antiquity and its survival in and meaning for western
culture as it was addressed by philology. Nietzsche’s vitalism stood at the
heart of one of the most important philological controversies of his time. His
Birth of Tragedy was the product of an uneasy dialogue with the discipline of
Greek philology and was criticized by the most influential Greek philologist of
the time, Ulrich von Willamowitz-Moellendorff, insinuating that Nietzsche’s
imprecise method threatened to spoil the discipline of Greek philology at
large.39 Nietzsche’s readings of antiquity are explicitly and declaratively biased;
they labour to remember what is needed and important, but also to forget that
which is not,40 an attitude that is anti-historicist (as it does not commemorate
history for its own sake), and which comes close to a figural reading that
cuts and pastes historical fragments according to a pre-established thesis,
demanding validation. Nietzsche’s view of antique art, most evident in Birth of
Tragedy, urges a return to the intensive dynamics of artistic production. Around
the time of the publication of the Birth of Tragedy, in the first half of 1870,
Nietzsche composed a draft essay, ‘Wir Philologen’.41 In this piece, he affiliated
himself with the philologist’s vocation, his critical attitude regarding the state
of philological scholarship notwithstanding. He called for a radical rethinking
and refounding of philology: it would only be capable of being born again if the
philologists added to their knowledge of the past a redetermination of their own
selves and values.42
Nietzsche, Usener, Voßler and, indeed, Warburg were all practising versions
of philological questioning imbued with Lebensphilosophie. They were all inter-
ested in the manner in which the production of signs is related to situations
of vital agitation and the survival of Urformen: Dyonisian dynamics in the
case of Nietzsche, the powers of nature in the case of Usener, and Creation
(Schöpfung) in the case of Voßler. This vitalist tendency also included notable
approaches to history and to the past and the notions of the survival and
afterlife of forms have, in themselves, a vitalist character. Philological vitalism
can hence be understood as a reaction to the crisis of historicism that shook
and re-established the foundation of the humanities throughout the nineteenth
century. The archaic origin of culture gradually came to be conceived as
having a vitalist core, establishing and forming an event (Urereignis), indeci-
pherable and never consumed and ‘temporality’ itself a sibling concept to
‘life’, time being the key to understanding the phenomenon of life. When
history dedicated itself to this vital archaism of time, it became historicism,
premised on a belief in the historical essence of human existence. In Warburg’s
work, this manifested itself in the notion of an Urbild, which is prior to and
82 Figural Philology
You feel prompted to follow her [i.e. The Nymph] like a winged idea [wie
einer geflügelten Idee] through all the spheres in a platonic frenzy of love; I feel
compelled [mich zwingt sie, literally ‘she forces me’] to turn my philologician’s
gaze to the ground [Boden] from which she rose and to ask with surprise: Is this
strangely delicate plant really rooted in the sober florentine soil [Erdboden]?51
Notably, Warburg contrasts his own philological gaze with his friend’s Platonic,
idealist one. So the gaze of philology, in Warburg’s view, is non-Platonic and
non-idealist.52 If the Platonic gaze is drawn to lofty ‘eidetic’ eroticism, the gaze of
philology tries to uncover the soil (Erdboden) of the image. Philology looks for
roots, for the ratio of a poietic thing. The philological gaze then sees through the
picture; it tries to break through its captivating allure and capture its cause, its
principle, its ἀρχή. The philologist’s gaze is not an indifferent, naive, or passive
one. It is neither the gaze of the ‘natural’ standing-point, nor of a phenomeno-
logical, descriptive, reflexive sensitivity. The philological gaze is an educated
gaze – a gaze established in a tradition; it is therefore a gaze imbued with
history, a gaze that has already seen, a gaze with a past, an ‘aged-gaze’, having a
mnemonic capacity. The philological gaze is the gaze that is assumed to know
84 Figural Philology
something a priori regarding its object, perhaps not in the sense of a Kantian set
of categories, but rather in the sense of a knowledge of predecessors, precursors
and precedents, a generic knowledge. One may note that Warburg chose to use
the term ‘philological gaze’ rather than historical gaze or hermeneutical gaze to
qualify his position in relation to that of his friend.
The philologist’s gaze is, therefore, not the gaze that produces a pathos
formula, but rather the gaze that recognizes a pathos formula in a given work. In
as much as the pathos formula is the result of a more virginal gaze, unprepared
for the confrontation with a certain natural force, the philological gaze is better
protected against such traumatic encounters with a threatening exterior. It is
the gaze that is capable of identifying the danger to be found within the picture,
the archaic point incubating therein and allowing the work to be deconstructed
from within. Being prepared for the encounter with the erotic seduction of the
alluring image, it is able to return images to their roots. The philological gaze
complements the gaze that produces the pathos formula: where the former
freezes the threatening movement of the powers of nature, the philological gaze
reopens the image in order to put the frozen formula once again into motion.
If the pathos formula receives a dangerous reality, then the philological gaze
returns this received reality to its own ground, and restores pictorial reality to
its own cause. As Warburg states in the introduction to the Mnemosyne, his is
indeed the iconology of the ‘Zwischenraum’, which opens between two kinds of
‘posing-causes’ (Ursachensetzung): the pictorial (bildhafter) and the signfying
(zeichenmäßiger).53 This iconological interspace, as articulated by Warburg,
fits the basic pendulum movement of the figure, as presented in the previous
chapter. And it is by weaving around the picture a net of signified meanings that
iconology ‘rationalizes’ the image.
In the following chapter, I note the affinity between Warburg’s philological
gaze and what Panofsky, in his iconological table of 1939, called ‘synthetic
intuition’. Essentially, this gaze captures the distance between a work and its past,
a past that is remembered and ‘contracted’ by the work. To use an Aristotelian–
Thomist term that will also be discussed later, the philological gaze is produced
by a habitus (or ἕξις), an acquired capacity to see (backwards) through time.
For Warburg, the root of the image is split. On the one hand, there are
the historical material, social and economic conditions of the production of
a certain work; thus, for example, Ghirlandaio’s ‘Nymph’ is interpreted as an
expression of the non-pious mentality of the city banking families of fifteenth-
century Florence. On the other hand, the second root of the image is the pathos
formula, the archaic type that re-emerges through different ages, cultures and
Iconological space: Panofsky with Warburg 85
‘iconological synthesis’ (to use the title of two of Warburg’s notice-boxes).76 The
synthesis of the pathos formula and the philological gaze forms what one could
call a synthesis of art-historical spatio-temporal reality. We will now turn to
Panofsky’s 1955 version of his 1939 iconological table in order to examine what
this iconological synthesis of framing and spatializing history entails.
90
7
based on a transcendental foundation for the science of art in Idea, in his later
period he was occupied with specific artworks, as well as with deciphering key
moments in the history of plastic genres and schools. In his iconological period,
Panofsky tended to relax his earlier striving for a systematic Kantian epistem
ology at the same time as the philological tendencies of his work became more
clear, though he never completely abandoned his Kantian creed.
Generally, the concepts and terms that Panofsky deploys in his iconological
table originated in turn-of-the-century neo-Kantian thought regarding the
historical sciences. But his special arrangement of these terms exposed their
neo-Platonist and hylomorphist kernels. It seems as if Panofsky’s work at this
intermediary stage, while still leaning on neo-Kantian terms, launched a new
project of distilling the iconical concreteness of a historical moment, i.e. an
investigation of the way in which historical reality arrives before the researcher
in a pictured, figured mode. As with any iconophilic position, Panofsky’s project
also carries an iconoclastic shadow, in the sense that it poses an ‘idea’ (or in the
terms of the iconological table, a ‘symbolical value’) as the originating principle
of the meaning of a work. That is to say, the meaning of the picture is to be found
in its inner eidetic sense, and not, as is suggested by the Auerbachian theory of
the figure, exclusively in relation to another historical reality. In emphasizing
the synthetic character of iconology, two central elements of the table will be
highlighted: first the notion of ‘symbolical value’, recalling not only Cassirerian
but also Rickertian neo-Kantianism; second, the concept of ‘synthetic intuition’,
defined by Panofsky as the fundamental gesture of iconological inquiry.
Synthesis
Genus (or race) is used (a) When there is a continuous generation of things
of the same type; e.g. ‘as long as the human race exists’ means ‘as long as the
generation of human being is continuous.’ (b) Of anything from which things
derive their being as the prime mover of them into being.9
This level of iconological synthesis thus refers to tradition and to the successive
dynamics of types, which depends on some determined notion of a ‘classic’ or
an ‘ideal’. It is, therefore, characterized by a permanent striving towards a renais-
sance, a striving that was to be Panofsky’s object of scrutiny in his Renaissance
and Renascences in Western Art (1960).10 This synthesis embodies the longing
for a rebirth of the source of a generic series, which, according to the methods
of Warburg, Panofsky and Auerbach (and of philological rationality in general)
lies at the root of history. (Auerbach’s discussion of the ‘figure’, as we have seen,
focused on the manner in which the history of western culture is activated by
the mechanism of the rebirth of types, with ultimate reference to a final rebirth,
a ‘second coming’ or redemption, as in the Christian structure of pre-figuration.
Can an iconological gesture be such a second coming?)
This triple iconological synthesis is not only structured according to the
requirements of art historical activity, but is also exemplified by this discipline,
its being the only historical inquiry whose objects and subjects are distinctively
formal and plastic. Nevertheless, the iconological structure can also pertain to
historical research in general, in so far as all humanities disciplines share the
gesture delineating the containment of one form by another.
The figural synthesis of historical reality in the iconology table 95
Already in his Idea and in other earlier writings, Panofsky forged the tools for
understanding both ‘symbolical value’ and ‘synthetic intuition’. Symbolical value
actually parallels the notion of the idea in Idea; it supplies the eidetic element
that binds the specific work to a generating ἀρχή. Symmetrically, the artist, the
viewer or the researcher synthesizes at least two forms – the picture and the
genre to which it pertains – in order to conceive of a symbolical value.
Iconological synthesis can be viewed as the restoration of a definition of
a work. The restoration synthesizes at least two spatial locations and at least
two temporal moments (those of the work discussed and those of another
work, which is being used in order to identify the first); hence it depends on a
foundational synthesis of space and time. Panofsky describes both artistic and
iconological activities as imbued with evaluation and synthesis. The rationality
at work in Panofsky’s corpus clearly has a Kantian character, and within this
rationality the structure of the faculty of judgement (Urteilskraft) is especially
relevant. In the first introduction to the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant specifies
that reason is first and foremost an appointed judge.11 And this juridical reason
is synthetic: it establishes a relation, a ratio, between at least two elements, of
which one is considered as a particular or an example, and the other as the
universal to which the example belongs.
forms, which he based on the notion of synthesis. He explains thus the nature
of synthesis: ‘The analytical logic of pure identity broadens itself into a synthetic
logic, at whose core stands the question regarding the possible binding, relation
and correlation of dissimilars.’14
Cassirerian synthetic logic emphasizes the judgemental structure of
synthesis, an emphasis taken from Kant. Like for Kant, the faculty of judgement
is essentially synthetic, its task being ‘the subsumption of the particular under
the general’.15 Cassirer followed Kant and linked synthetic judgement with
symbolical activity:
Around 1900, the concept of value played a major role in the redefinition
of the historical sciences, especially within neo-Kantian circles. The origins of
value-philosophy go back to the beginning of the nineteenth century, in the
philosophy of Hermann Lotze (1817–81). Lotze could be considered one of
Panofsky’s distant ancestors, since he was the teacher of Wilhelm Windelband,
the founder of the Southwest school of neo-Kantianism, who, in turn, taught
Heinrich Rickert, one of Panofsky’s teachers in Freiburg and also one of his
doctoral examiners.19 For Lotze, ‘the kingdom of Values’ (Reich des Werten)
was the object of inquiry of philosophy,20 which amounts to a ‘system of
meanings’ (System der Bedeutungen). For Lotze, value was the highest principle
of synthesis.21
Bruno Bauch was a notable neo-Kantian follower of this Lotzean tradition
and also a contemporary of Panofsky. In 1923, Bauch gave a definition of value
in his book Wahrheit, Wert und Wirklichkeit.22 Like Lotze, he saw the estab-
lishment of values as the highest philosophical task and, according to Hans
Sluga, ‘considered his own contribution […] the discovery that values, like
the objects of theoretical knowledge, were not simply a plurality but stood in
relations and were objective only in this relatedness’.23
The affinity between values and ideas – supporting that between the
Kantian conception of judgement and Platonic Ideenlehre, which had as its
founding example Paul Natorp’s Platos Ideenlhere of 1903 – characterizes the
neo-Kantianism of both Bauch and Panofsky. Already in Lotze, the idea had
been considered as an absolute value, binding a plurality of beings, turning
synthetic pluralities into totalities of values (Werttotalität).24 In his 1926 Die
Idee,25 Bauch, offering a mixture of neo-Kantianism, Lotzianism and Platonism,
again posited the responsibility of constructing values (i.e. regulative ideas) as
philosophy’s highest task – but only ‘truth’, as the highest and absolute value,
posits unending duties. Panofsky’s symbolical values, by contrast, do not obey
any such absolute truth; rather, the regulative ideas in his method function as
‘an ideal to which we try to approximate our understanding of a work of art’.26
Panofsky’s iconological meaning, like Simmel’s historical truth, is necessarily
problem related;27 it is therefore the instrument or the product of historical
method, but not its ultimate goal, which is to be found in the iconological
synthesis.
The subject of value in nineteenth-century German philosophy developed
out of the fundamental problem of the definition of reality after Kant.28 Being
the product of judgement, value’s main function is to bind a particular and a
universal. Thus the history of the concept of value during the nineteenth century
98 Figural Philology
stemmed from the binding of the particular and the universal in Kant’s Kritik
der Urteilskraft. For Wilhelm Windelband writing later in his career, ‘value’ is
the subject matter of the historical sciences. For him, something has value only
inasmuch as it has occurred only once.29 He coined the term ‘idiographic’ for the
kind of rationality that has as its object the historical value of the singular event.
Exclusive to the historical sciences, idiographic rationality does not determine
universal laws but rather describes unique and singular complexes and ‘valued’
processes. In this framework, ‘value’ is as close as one gets to a general concept
or law, i.e. values are the organizing agency of historical, idiographic ration-
ality. Not only strict neo-Kantians, but also cultural historians affiliated with
neo-Kantianism, such as Georg Simmel and Ernst Troeltsch, located values as
the fundamental tool of historical inquiry. And because, as Rickert determines,
values are inherently non-real,30 the object of the historical sciences (i.e. the
work, the thing) cannot be a reality. Simmel argued similarly, in a Kantian
fashion, against ‘naiver Realismus’ in history.31 History can merely aspire to
construct a synthesis of values, Weltanschauungen,32 or, in Simmel’s elaborated
version, to give form to (Umformung) the chaotic stream of history by the
use of the unities of values. For Rickert, Simmel and Troeltsch it was obvious
that the values with which history is occupied are first and foremost cultural
values,33 Kulturwerthe being the products of the cultural sciences:34 ‘Cultural
value is the historical universal (Allgemeine), which is gradually developed only
in the individual singularity, through which it is realized.’35 Indeed, it was the
neo-Kantian Rickertian orientation that established the understanding of the
humanities as the sciences of culture (Kulturwissenschaften), rather than as the
sciences of the spirit (Geisteswissenschaften), according to the definition given
by Wilhelm Dilthey.36 On this point, Panofsky, directing his iconology to the
general history of cultural symptoms, is closer to the Southwest neo-Kantian
school than he is to any kind of idealism or Diltheyan Geistesgeschichte. Within
this framework, Panofsky’s ‘symbolical values’ should be understood as unities
of meaning. At this level, then, Panofsky does not yet achieve his humanist
ideal, which will be better accounted for in the subsequent levels of iconological
synthesis.
Thus far, Panofsky’s iconological terminology has been shown to be
continuous with the neo-Kantianism of Windelband, Rickert and Simmel,
at least to the same extent that it is continuous with the neo-Kantianism of
Cassirer. As such, any attempt to link Panofsky’s neo-Kantian agenda exclu-
sively with Cassirerian symbolical forms will offer only a partial view of the
matter.37
The figural synthesis of historical reality in the iconology table 99
The core of the diagnostic activity of synthetic intuition is the location of the
given work within a comprehensive series, enabling the naming of the piece by
noting its subject, time and place of production (for example, ‘this is the fresco
“The Triumph of Galatea” which Raphael (1483–1520) painted in 1511 in Villa
Farnesina in Rome’).
The figural synthesis of historical reality in the iconology table 101
Figural synthesis
Even if term ‘synthetic intuition’ does not appear explicitly in Kant, the first
Critique contains another term that will support a Kantian reading of the icono-
logical table, namely, figürliche Synthesis (translated into English as ‘figurative
synthesis’),60 or synthesis speciosa, as differentiated from synthesis intellectualis.
Figural synthesis, according to Kant, has an a priori plastic capacity:
The scholastic philosophers could use the ideas of Aristotle and merge them
with their own system, and the medieval poets could borrow freely from the
classical authors, but no medieval mind could think of classical philology.1
Erwin Panofsky
Can the history of art be considered an integral organ of the humanities? This
is the question that animates the present chapter, addressing twentieth-century
Romance philology and the manner in which this branch of philology involves
plastic dynamics. It will be suggested that Panofsky’s iconological method can
be relocated within the school of Romance philology, drawing on similarities
in methods and objects of inquiry. Panofsky knew both Auerbach and Spitzer,
German-Jewish scholars in exile in the United States, like Panofsky himself.2
Leaving the biographical facts aside, this chapter will focus on the methodical
aspects of the work of these authors. At a secondary level, the suggestion
here is that philology and, in particular, Romance philology, entails, among
its numerous other tasks, a shaping of a habitus, or a hexis (ἕξις), to use the
Greek-Aristotelian term. The claim is that philological research operates as
a mechanism whose task is to preserve the capacity to recollect human works.
Thomas Steinfeld has demonstrated the extent to which philological practice
should be regarded as a habitus, as a structure constructing and shaping a human
character.3 Hans Ulrich Gumbrecht, in his 2003 book, The Powers of Philology,
outlined a rationality that one could describe as philological, offering a view
of philology as a capacity, that is to say as a dynamis.4 The modest extension
of Steinfeld’s and Gumbrecht’s proposals undertaken here will emphasize the
conception of philological practice as a habitus that is basically anamnetic –
or a habitus of recollection. As the philological recollective mechanism does
not strictly belong to personal memory, it can be seen as relating to what Jan
Assmann called ‘cultural memory’ (Das kulturelle Gedächtnis). As he explains:
106 Figural Philology
the one, after which the one we need habitually occurs. This is also the reason
why we hunt the next in the series, starting our thoughts from the present
or from another point in time, and from something similar, from something
contrary, or from something closely connected […] In this way, then, men seek,
and, even when not seeking, they recollect in this way, when the movement
happens after another.16
A starting point must be taken. This is why people sometimes seem to recollect
from ‘places’. The reason is that they proceed quickly from one to the other, for
instance, from milk to white, from white to air, and from this to moist, from
which autumn is recalled, if this is the season that one is seeking.21
For Aristotle, recollection happens only when the recollector recovers the series
of movements by his own capacities; and when this does not happen, then the
case is no longer one of recollection but rather a relearning.22 Again, Assman’s
concept of cultural memory allows us to think of recollection occurring not in
the specific mind of the individual but rather through the products, records
Philology’s recollective habitus: Panofsky with Spitzer, Auerbach and Curtius 109
There are, we would say, two profoundly distinct memories: the one, fixed in
the organism, is none other than the ensemble of the mechanisms, construed
intelligibly, assuring a comfortable copy with numerous possible interpellations.
[…] The other is true memory. Coexisting with consciousness, it re-takes and
aligns, one after the other, all our states according to the measure in which they
are produced, allowing any fact its place […] really moving in the definitive
past, and not, like the first [memory] in a present which permanently begins.24
In the present work, we have underlined the importance of the figural element in
the philological techniques of memory. The second, ‘real’ Bergsonian memory
and Aristotle’s recollection point to this possibility of the figuration of the past.
The latter presupposes the gap that separates the process of the inquiry itself
from its sought-after past. This differentiation is also that between memory
understood as repetition and memory understood as an activity of distinction;
110 Figural Philology
The Spitzerian etymon emerges as the DNA of humanist humanism, the kernel
of what he calls ‘universalistic ratio.’ Characterized in ‘Linguistics and Literary
History’ as the ‘radix of the soul’, the etymon not only holds up the world of
literary work and serves as the connective tissue of theocratic unity, it also
operates as the weapon of last resort in the war against cultural barbarism.30
Finally, Ernst Robert Curtius proposed the term ‘topoi’ to refer to the
figural formulae informing human history.31 Topoi, as figures and etymons,
are elemental units, travelling, repeating and mutating through ages and
cultures, forming the spine of poetical traditions, and enabling the formation
of philological readings.32 Curtius refers to the topoi as ‘primordial-relations’
(‘Urverhältnisse’) of human existence, explicitly characterizing them as ‘form-
elements’ (‘Form-Elemente’). Curtius’s topoi are similar to Warburg’s ‘pathos
formulae’, to which Curtius himself referred in an essay from 1950.33 The
similarity lies in the fact that both express an attitude of man towards the
cosmos, and both form the consonants, or the leitmotifs, of artistic traditions.
After a topos is established and deployed, the task of philology is to preserve the
unity of its series and to articulate its meaning. The hyle, the matter from which
philology constructs its building blocs, nevertheless, is not history in general,
but rather the history of humanist tradition.
The work of Panofsky, Auerbach, Spitzer and Curtius is concerned not only
with themes belonging to the humanist tradition but also with the definition of
humanism as such. Indeed, Panofsky chose to open his Meaning in the Visual
Arts with an essay on the history of art as a humanistic discipline.34 In this
rather late essay, written in 1940, Panofsky presented his credo of integrating art
history into the humanist framework, based on a particular conception of the
human being: ‘Man is indeed the only animal to leave records behind him, for
he is the only animal whose products “recall to mind” an idea distinct from their
material existence.’35 Thus, according to Panofsky the signs of men have a recol-
lective function and this function is what makes signs human. He continues:
‘Man’s signs and structures are records because, or rather in so far as, they express
ideas separated from, yet realized by, the process of signalling and building.’ For
112 Figural Philology
Panofsky then, symbols are considered a recollective tool, the object of which is
to recover an idea embodied in, yet distinct from, these very signs. Notably, this
link binds Panofsky’s conception of the symbol with that of Warburg, for whom
symbols were also considered essentially as mechanisms of memory and were
enhanced by a ‘function of memorial capacity’ (gedächtnismäßige Funktion).36
Nevertheless, the above quoted sentence also reveals the difference between
the two iconologists: if Warburg’s concept of memory is radically continuous,
Panofsky’s model is rather disjunctive. That is to say, the Panofskyan model
is one of exteriority: the eidetic origin of the series lies in an idea, which is to
be distinguished from the series of symbols itself; the Warburgian model of
the symbol, on the other hand, is continuous: it locates the beginning of the
series in an always present material moving-force. Panofsky’s method suggests
a disjunctive model of figuration, on the basis of its hylomophic starting point;
that is, the model of a form distinct from cultural matter yet shaping it.37 For
Panofsky, not only are ideas distinct from the signs carrying them, but also a
certain culture is to be inherently distinguished from the signs it recovers. That
is to say, Panofsky was very much aware of the ways in which the humanist
tradition is constructed from separate units, being bounded by the force of
artistic production. And even if the iconologist must be primarily occupied with
restoring the continuous series of formal repetitions and appropriations, she
must also take care to investigate that which separates two historical moments
at the same time. The history of art, according to Panofsky, has a recollective
character, at the beginning of which stands an idea, external to the series
itself. This idea, in Panofsky’s inquiries, but also in Spitzer’s for example, stems
from the reality of ‘antiquity’. This, or the ‘archaic’, is conceived as generating a
starting point for the tradition of human productions. In the last paragraph of
Chapter 2 of Renaissance and Renascences in Western Art, Panofsky refers to the
ambivalent relation to antiquity:
The middle ages had left antiquity unburied and alternately galvanized and
exorcised its corps. The Renaissance stood weeping at its grave and tried to
resurrect its soul. […] This is why the mediaeval concept of the Antique was
so concrete and at the same time so incomplete and distorted; whereas the
modern one, gradually developed during the last three or four hundred years,
is comprehensive and consistent but, if I may say so, abstract. And permanent.
Resurrected souls are intangible but have the advantage of immortality and
omnipresence. Therefore the role of classical antiquity after the Renaissance is
somewhat elusive but, on the other hand, pervasive – and changeable only with
a change in our civilization as such.38
Philology’s recollective habitus: Panofsky with Spitzer, Auerbach and Curtius 113
Hylomorphist humanism
of the Renaissance’. The humanist tradition forms the conceptual and material
core of the work of all three main authors discussed here.44 There is something
like a ‘human figure’ to be discerned in their methods, a figure that is constantly
portrayed, examined and sampled in their writings. And it is this human figure
that is is sought after in the philological anamnetic process.
Panofsky describes humanism as harbouring an ambivalent attitude, which
‘can be defined as the conviction of the dignity of man, based on both the
insistence on human values (rationality and freedom) and the acceptance
of human limitations (fallibility and frailty)’. He concludes: ‘The humanist,
then, rejects authority. But he respects tradition.’45 Panofsky’s understanding
of humanism thus leans primarily on a drawing of a line – a line supporting
the human figure both from above and from below. Man is limited but also
shaped by his own actions and gestures, by their extension and rehearsal; the
humanists’ habitus seeks to shape man through his relation with his past, or
with the tradition that he respects and remembers. This respect for tradition
serves also as a mark of human limitation, in the sense that the relation to the
transmitted past must be maintained and developed; it cannot be assumed
as a pre-given spontaneous capacity. Romance philology’s pedagogic method
emphasizes the partial, limited, fragile character of the philological application.
Human actions and the products that issue from them, embedded in the web
of history, produce figures that are repeated, condensed, but also hidden or
forgotten, finally to be re-excavated and re-distinguished, always only partially,
by the philological process.
Here, Curtius distinguishes between inquiries into texts and inquiries into
artistic works: the text has a permanent existence which can always be recon-
sulted, whereas ‘things’, owing to their plastic – and one should add, material,
historical – singularity, are much more difficult to make present within an
inquiry. Disjunction is brought up, then, by this material-historical gap, and the
gap is materialized in the plastic object. As Curtius suggests, the art-product,
indeed, makes evident and accentuates an existing gap in any encounter between
man and his ‘records’. This gap is not absent when the records are texts; rather
it remains more latent. It is the gap created between the individual researcher
in his specific historical place and the specific work he recovers. Curtius is
pointing to the fact that plastic and textual records prescribe a different recol-
lective habitus. For the written record, the past in its essential form exists
whenever a copy of the original is achieved. For the plastic record, the past is
attainable in making physical contact with the original. Texts, therefore, provide
the philologist with the possibility of establishing continuity in his processes of
recollection; while for the archaeologist or the art historian there is always a gap,
116 Figural Philology
a deviation between the present and the past that copies cannot do away with.
The iconologist stands exactly between the textual philologist and the material
archaeologist, treating the artwork itself as a mediating crossing-point between
the hyle of ever-singular material histories and the eternal consistency and avail-
ability of texts.
As noted above, Panofsky’s view was that ideas are exterior to the records of
man, though they are capable of being realized by these very same records. The
realization of an exterior form, then, is central to this model of understanding
the human. Realizations of forms by matter lie at the heart of the original
antique-Aristotelian hylomorphist model.47 And realization (Erfüllung) is also
central to Auerbach’s concept of ‘Figura’. In the figural structure, history itself
functions as a retroactive engine of reminiscence, as the figure binds a certain
segment of history, or historical reality, with another previous segment – as for
example with Christ and his prefiguration in the biblical figure of Joshua. Christ
is the realization of that which was already noted in the former historical reality
of the Old Testament. Thus, Figural realization carries within itself not only the
difference between the two moments, but also an unbridgeable gap, caused by
the particularity of historical moments.
Elastic hylomorphism
What can be the humanistic, the spiritual value of this […] juggling with word
forms? […] [a]n etymology introduces meaning into the meaningless: in our
case, the evolution of two words in time – that is, a piece of linguistic history
– has been cleared up. What seemed an agglomeration of mere sounds now
appears motivated.48
The etymon figures out the chaotic hyletic reservoir of inscriptions and signs
inherent in historical documents. In Panofsky’s writings, the hylomorphist
thread appears in his discussions of both neo-Platonism49 and scholasticism.50
In most of his writings, Panofsky demonstrated a hylomorphic understanding
Philology’s recollective habitus: Panofsky with Spitzer, Auerbach and Curtius 117
of the arts. For example, already in ‘The Concept of Artistic Volition’, written in
1920, he wrote: ‘Art […] is a discussion aimed at the achievement of valid results
that objectifies and realizes a formative force, using material which has to be
mastered.’51 And in Gothic Architecture and Scholasticism, about three decades
later, he broadened this hylomorphist model to include the domain of human
behaviour, by defining art as a habit-forming force.52 Panofsky’s entire corpus
may be regarded as a companion to western art, through the exploration of
the traditions preserving antique hylomorphist models in neo-Platonism and
scholasticism.
A final aspect of the hylomorphist conception of signs is its realism. Even
when a disjunction exists between the sign and its recalled thought, still, that
which is recalled is not considered to be a mere phantasy, but is understood
as referring to a specific and real referent. In ‘Art History as a Humanistic
Discipline’, discussing the records man leaves behind him, Panofsky refers
the reader to ‘Sign and Symbol’, an essay by the neo-Thomist thinker Jacques
Maritain, published in 1937 in the Journal of the Warburg Institute. Maritain
outlines a modern Thomistic understanding of signs, insisting on the reality
that is contained and shaped them:
The movement towards the sign or the image, says Saint Thomas Aquinas
following Aristotle, is exactly the same as the movement towards the object
itself […] Thus in the formal-objective order the sign is a very remarkable thing,
and it is only the routine of our culture which prevents our marvelling at it.53
constitutes the first element in the recollective series. The philologist must then
rely on his habitual familiarity54 with traditions, types, usages and attitudes in
order to restore a series of movements that make it possible to distinguish the
archaic atom of the inquiry. Panofsky used the term synthetic intuition to refer
to this special gesture which grasps, in a frail and fallible gesture, a segment of
history as shaped by the work in question.55 In this way, the philological habitus
can be viewed as a self-shaping in which the philologist simultaneously figures-
out the humanity of both himself and his past.
9
Around the turn of the last century an abundant literature was dedicated to
the theory and practice of Byzantine iconoclasm. Hans Belting’s Bild und
Kult (1990), Moshe Barash’s Icon (1992), Marie-José Mondzain’s, Image, icône,
économie (1996), Charles Barber’s Figure and Likeness (2002), Bruno Latour and
Peter Weibel’s Iconoclash (2002), Michael Kelly’s Iconoclasm in Aesthetics (2003),
and significant parts of William J. Thomas Mitchell’s What Do Pictures Want?
(2005),5 are several examples out of many of this return to the iconic.6 Yet, most
Figural content and the past as a res extensa 121
if not all of these inquiries highlighted the question of the image, whereas our
attempt here is rather to think about the Prototype and the manner in which
it is realized in a type. Through the prism of the Byzantine icon, a picture
subordinated to and standing for a privileged reality, we can see the outlines of
a realist basis for the theory of figuration. Byzantine iconism suggests a model
of inquiry into artworks in which no absolute sovereignty is bestowed upon
the image (or icon); rather, artworks are legitimized and validated only by a
real referent, allowing the picture to serve as a starting point for an inquiry,
eventually making possible the production of a figure.
Theories of the icon support the idea of the regulated legitimacy of pictures,
based on the legitimation of the content or meaning they carry. Here we will
examine the extent to which iconology reflects the essential structures and
premises of the theoretical comprehension of icons within an iconophilic
framework. It must be emphasized from the beginning that such a framework
does not have to promulgate the supremacy of the image; on the contrary,
iconophilic discourse was developed as an apologetic, restorative project, taking
seriously the iconoclastic suspicion regarding images, and referring to icons
first and foremost as instruments, as working tools. In the context of Byzantine
iconoclasm, iconophilic discourse should be understood as adopting an ‘even
though’ position: taking into account the dangers to be found in pictorial
practice, it tries to gauge the limits and the possible profits coming out of such
a praxis. As was suggested in the previous few chapters, iconology seeks an
understanding of the ‘content/value/meaning’ (Inhalt/Wert/Bedeutung) of an
artwork.7 For that purpose, Panofsky’s iconological model posited art history as
a humanist eruditio8 involving the realm of ideas and the history of philosophy,
traversing and mapping the extended domain of human production, at the
centre of which there are always artworks and philosophical dispositions that
meet one other. Hence, for example, in his Studies in Iconology Panofsky explored
the ways in which works by distinguished Renaissance artists such as Titian and
Michelangelo corresponded with or interpreted the philosophical tropes of their
time.9 Works demanding identification led Panofsky into the excavation of long-
standing traditions of analogies between ideas and pictorial marks.10 Most of
these iconological trails traced the survival of Greek and Roman art, mythology
and philosophy through to the modern era, thus raising issues related to the
rise of humanism. But one possible weakness of many iconological inquiries
is their tendency to present the inner meaning (symbolical value) of a work in
terms of a ‘worldview’, a philosopheme rather than a philosophical articulation,
using it as an illustrative tool for clarifying the visual cipher. In such cases both
122 Figural Philology
the critical view of philosophical ideas and the singularity and specificity of the
picture may be compromised.
Many objections were raised against this Panofskyan proposition of forming
an alliance between art and thought, objections arising out of an anxiety about
the possible occlusion of the reality of the work by abstract ideas.11 Frequently,
such arguments accuse Panofsky of a sort of heresy with respect to the authentic
visual and sensual presence of artworks, in favour of an adherence to the allure
of abstract ideas. One possible response to these arguments is suggested by a
defence of the iconological method as an iconic practice, in the Byzantine sense
of the word, resting on the necessary assumption of a reality that incubates and
motivates a work and its endurance through history. In striving to define the
reality of the work, an iconological investigation participates in this reality and
affects it. Enhancing the iconological method with elements derived from the
theory of the Byzantine icon may enable a better understanding of the ‘meaning’
involved in such an iconological reading. In Warburg’s terms, one can ask in
what way could winged ideas be grounded by a philological gaze? For our
purposes, it is not ideas but rather the past reality of a work that functions as the
referent of iconology, and the figure is equivalent neither to the artwork nor to
its image, but is rather the product of an adherence to that past reality, created by
the formation of a figure between two historical realities. In this framework, the
past is to be considered as an extended reality, enabling human retrospection
and retroaction. This reality of this past can be viewed as a kind of nature:
Auerbach reminded us that ‘Vico insisted that man has no nature other than his
history.’12 Following the philological gaze with a Bergsonian eye, one can view
the human past as an extended and extending, flexible, plastic and elastic nature,
preserved, enhanced and reformed by any human work or deed. This produced,
historical, extended nature is the referent, or the ‘thing’, that is the target of the
method defended here. However, this reality of the past is not yet identical with
the particular things that are the object of art historical inquiries.
A distinction still needs to be established, then, between the reality of the past as
a general res extensa and the specific work that stands before the researcher. We
must, therefore, return to the object of iconological inquiry, and to the question
of its nature and character. In the iconological table, the iconological given13 is
considered only in so far as it is capable of serving as a starting point for the
Figural content and the past as a res extensa 123
the figural restoration. This kind of reading presupposes a ratio between the
restoration of that which can be known (accepted historical habitudes and
readings) and that which one cannot know but which is the distinguishing
mark of the work.18 The approximate figuration of the latter can be performed
only as a new figure, one that has not yet been delineated by traditions of
iconography, genres, styles or habitudes, and which is, indeed, rarely to be seen
in art historical inquiries.
The iconic-figural situation thus consists of a dual structure in which one
side of the operation is restorative and comparative, and the other stands as a
cut in the extended web of historical reality. This duality between extension and
distinction is characteristic of the tradition known as French spiritualism, active
mostly in the nineteenth century.19 It involves not merely a mind–body dualism,
but rather a change–resistance dualism, in which change is correlated with the
activity of spirit (i.e. with thought), and resistance or persistence with extended
reality.20 Iconological activity, if it is to be viewed as iconic, should take charge
of working with this kind of duality.
Figural recollection, therefore, works like a bridge between the philologist and
the thing s/he investigates. The figure binds a certain scientific moment with
a certain productive moment in the past. It embodies, therefore, the distance
between the two moments. One should thus address the process of marking
a distance between the researcher and the thing he researches. This spatial
construction can be approached through two complementary spatial models:
the iconic and the perspectival. What would be the equivalent in historical
research? There one would treat past reality as a first and preliminary prototype,
which is unarticulable in its very essence. What can be approached, instead, is the
historical reality of works, a complex reality in itself. The historical reality of the
work is a synthesis between historical meaning and the past reality of the work.
Art historical research, understood as figuration, seeks a retroactive synthesis of
the historical reality of the work. The past reality of the work, including its distin-
guishing mark, as noted above, can only be approached approximately, it cannot
be defined in a positive manner or plainly and literally seen.23 In developing a
spatial vocabulary to discuss iconology and iconism, a comparison between
perspectival construction and iconic spatiality may support the sought-after
126 Figural Philology
the visible concrete signs that are not its mimetic replicas, but rather gestures
of distanciation and hierarchy between the prototype and the type. Between
the surface of the ground and the surface of the paint there exists a distance,
a depth, residing even in the most flat colour-filled painting, a distance that is
not illusionistic but material and historical, as it records the successive acts of
distancing that the specific work has participated in.
Where Panofsky emphasized the humanistic aspects of the construction of
perspective,31 Marion sees perspective as pertaining to a substantial subordin
ation of the human to a theological infinite. Perspective, according to Marion,
does not adhere only to the visible; rather, it acts as the paradox of the visible:
the coexistence of ideal space and real space, a coexistence existing also in the
structure of the icon. The vanishing point in perspectival painting is an empty
point, embodying no object, manifesting invisible ideal space in the midst of
the painterly real space. In this way, conical perspective spatiality, according
to Marion, is not merely an artificial formalization of seeing, but a substantial
iconic mode, defined as a procedure of distancing. If for Marion perspectival
distancing is radical and infinite in its nature and scope (as the radical distance
embodied in the icon takes one from the type to the prototype), for Panofsky the
function of perspectival construction is mainly a regulative one, embodying the
humanist equilibrium between subject and object. Panofsky observed that both
subjectivism and objectivism are opposite poles of the same tendency, which is
an empirical one:
Historically the word humanitas has had two clearly distinguishable meanings,
the first arising from a contrast between man and what is less than man; the
128 Figural Philology
second, between man and what is more. In the first case humanitas means a
value, in the second, a limitation.33
And concluded:
Humanism, then, and its modern incarnation in the humanities, are both based
on the assumption of Archimedean criteria, rationalizing between speculation
and fact, between capacity and limitation. In short, a humanist position,
according to Panofsky, is a regulative one. This Kantian trust in ‘regulative
ideas’ was already apparent in Panofsky’s ‘Der Begriff des Kunstwollens’,35 in
which the Archimedean point was introduced as the basis for an examination
of historical artistic works.36 This Archimedean point should be located outside
the chaotic and multiple hyle of historical data, and should serve as a regulative
point of reference for the relative point of view. The Archimedean point parallels
the vanishing point in perspectival construction, as Panofsky presented it. The
spatial construction of pictorial perspective requires an exterior vanishing
point, which will be the support for the concentration of the optico-spatial
cone of rays, embodying the receding of infinite, ‘ideal’ space. Panofsky
demonstrated that some centralizing factor is essential to all western models of
space-presentation, at least from ancient Greece to eighteenth-century Europe.
But even if the systematized perspectival model, at its Renaissance apex, was
an embodiment of infinite distance, it was nevertheless placed, located and
designed within the rational parameters of the conditions of this construction of
spatial experience. It is ‘infinity not only prefigured in God, but indeed actually
embodied in empirical reality’.37 And thus, perspective, on Panofsky’s account,
interiorizes and domesticates the infinite: ‘The history of perspective may be
understood with equal justice as a triumph of the distancing and objectifying
sense of the real, and as the triumph of the distance-denying human struggle
for control.’38
For Panofsky the vanishing point is an agent of the human capacity to
organize the human world both a priori and a posteriori. And as a structure of
meaning, perspectival construction situates an invisible element at the centre
of the spatial composition. Perspectival history sustains a spatial metaphorics
of ‘insideness’. The infinite is interiorized in the pictorial world-space, similarly
Figural content and the past as a res extensa 129
For the iconic iconologist, engaged in figuring out a work, even the most
contemporary artwork exists as a past reality, as something that has been
produced and seen already, even if only a moment ago. This past reality is
only representable as a system of coordinates. For Panofsky, historical time,
and more precisely historical moments of simultaneity, are ‘created not by the
coincidence [Zusammenfallen] of two or more isolated phenomena in a natural
point in time but rather merely by the coincidence of two or more frames of
reference [Bezugssysteme] in one […] stretch of time’.43 Again fully neo-Kantian
at this point, Panofsky posits frames of reference as an absolute condition for the
existence of the past as history. For an iconic iconologist, however, the reality of
the past permeates any set of conditions of possibility. He therefore adopts an
iconoclastic attitude, both towards considerations of artworks as self-sufficient
images and towards the schematic habitudes available for the construction of
the past. One should emphasize, as Marion does,44 that iconoclasm is an iconic
doctrine of the picture, occupied with limiting the usages of its visibility. The
icon, according to the council of Nicea II (787),45 demands respect, but not
adoration. Therefore in iconical philology, one would respect the work for its
capacity to initiate a search, but one would neither consecrate it as such, nor
consecrate the historical clarification of its meaning. Iconical philology would
employ a valuable picture or monument to produce the figure as capturing the
work’s two prototypes, instead of adoring the picture or its style in their own
right. This kind of adherence grants the past its resistance as reality.
At the end of the process, what a figural philology attempts to describe is
the historical reality of a work. Thus the object of the iconic iconologist should
no longer be identified with the artwork per se, but rather with its moment of
generation, that is to say, with the work’s realization at some point in the past.
From the point of view of the iconic iconologist, the figure restores a hitherto
unnoticed change in thought systems, generated by the production of the
Figural content and the past as a res extensa 131
researched work. And we would suggest that this historical reality can only
be positively articulated as a new thought. Human works of all kinds carry
a past, but plastic works carry this past in the most explicit manner. Figural
iconology, according to these guidelines, would view philosophy and art history
as inseparable, as it seeks to demonstrate how a certain work implies a precise
change in thought.46
The distance between the reality of the past and the historical
reality of a work
Since one of the tasks of the present inquiry is to tackle the question of
historicism, it is necessary to articulate what we understand by the historical
reality of a work of art. It should be differentiated first from the reality of the
past, which is the referent of philology. An iconic approach demands a further
acknowledgement of the distance between the two prototypes of a work, namely,
its past reality and its historical meaning. Without maintaining this distance
art history will not produce a figure but rather what could be conceived, if
somewhat severely, as an idol. The difference between icon and idol, Marion
suggests, consists in the fact that the icon sustains a distance between the
prototype and the type, while in the idolic situation this distance collapses.
An idol, according to Marion, is an image that lacks any distance separating
the unseen and the visible, unlike the icon, which is in itself a distantiating
instrument between the two. In Christian theology, the figure, though not
considered as sacred as the icon, is, nevertheless, not defined as idolatrous and
is, therefore, allowed to be used in theological procedures.47 The suggestion here
is that we think of art history as carrying such a figural task. The figural position
is respectful of the reality of the past, yet it does not amount to a full iconic
embodiment of it. Going a step further, we can suggest that the historical reality
of the work is itself synthesized by the two different elements: the historical
meaning and the past reality of a work. The past reality requires the examination
and reconsideration of the accepted narratives regarding the specific work or
regarding similar works that could be considered as participating in the same
genre. The historical reality of the work is not identical with an inaccessible
Kantian ‘thing’; rather, past reality is always subject to refiguration, eternally
given to rehabilitation and restoration. Iconical philology, presupposing the past
reality of the work, aspires to restore the work’s historical reality at a hitherto
unidentified place on the extended surface of spatio-temporal historical reality.
132 Figural Philology
This kind of procedure will modestly take part in examining and re-examining
the history of philosophy, of ideas and of thoughts.
Artworks always come to us carrying a demand for restoration – above
all, a restoration of their generation. We can only begin to tackle this demand
by trying to match the artwork with some earlier or later realities by using
pre-established, habitual systems of categories or accepted histories of styles
and schools. Iconic philology’s task would be thereafter to question those
systems themselves. The figure, like the work itself, does not mimic, express or
complete an idea. Rather, it restores a hitherto unseen past reality in the history
of thoughts. The figure constructs a series of unseens, errors of interpretation or
distinctive changes, while trying to approach the generic reality of the work as
an Archimedean point. Hence we return to the following enigmatic paragraph
in which Panofsky proposes synthetic intuition as the main tool of the icono-
logical procedure:
we wish to get hold of those basic principles which underlie the choice and
presentation of motifs […] To grasp these principles we need a mental faculty
comparable to that of a diagnostician – a faculty which I cannot describe better
than by the rather discredited term ‘synthetic intuition’ and which may be better
developed in a talented layman than in an erudite scholar […] just so […] must
our synthetic intuition be corrected by an insight into the manner in which,
under varying historical conditions, the general and essential tendencies of the
human mind were expressed by specific themes and concepts […] It is in the
search for intrinsic meanings or content that the various humanistic disciplines
meet on a common plane.48
It is here that Panofsky points in the direction of the thesis of the present work:
the fourth level of iconology is the figural one, and iconology can become
historical only after it has been philological. In order to articulate the work’s
historical reality one has to go beyond, or rather leave behind, the historicist
creed, and propose a formula, a logos, which a work should have been saying.
This approach, finally, is iconical, in the sense that it respects and works with
pictures and images in order to catch a glimpse of a saying that is extra-
historical, to reach an Archimedean point – as Panofsky had already delineated
in his 1920 essay on Riegl, with which the trail of the present work began. This is
achieved by synthetic intuition, the epistemic gesture that Panofsky introduced
in his iconological table essay. Synthetic intuition restores the work neither as
‘seen’ nor as ‘unseen’, but rather as seen-again, re-seen. This figural philological
restoration enacts a double, simultaneous critique of the history of thought and
the history of works, by which the reality of the past is unearthed, recollected
and thought anew.
The figure not only extends between two historical realities, it also restores two
roots or prototypes of the historical reality of a work: (1) the historical meaning
embedded in it; and (2) the work’s past reality, which is carried by the way in
which it survived following its production by affecting and leaving its mark on
other works. As we have said, the two prototypes of the work are different from
the visual existence of the work, but in two different ways: the first functions as
a background, the other as a trail of survival; and it is the task of the philological
figure to embody the distance between the two.
One might thus propose replacing the French term ‘espacement’ with a
neologism: ‘espassément’, past-spacing. Espassément denotes the existence of the
134 Figural Philology
past as the res extensa, existing as matter, distinct from the res cogitans, as the
thought of the iconologist, both held together across this distance by figuration.
Espassément, the distancing ratio of figuration, is thus the central instrument of
a figural philology.
Conclusion: Towards a figural philology
Following the footprints of Erwin Panofsky, this book has explored the possi-
bility of a philological approach to the history of art, or a philology of a figural
type. In conclusion, the general, speculative lines implied by this approach will
be presented. In so doing, we must at certain points deviate from the Panofskyan
line. Moreover, we must bear in mind Panofsky’s ambivalence with regard to the
possibility of there being any kind of comprehensive method for the history
of art. As he wrote in a letter in 1958: ‘I discuss method only under extreme
provocation and believe that, while it is wholesome and at times necessary to
think about what one is trying to do, methodology should never be erected into
a discipline in its own right.’1 Hence the guidelines articulated in what follows
are not intended as a set of generally applicable rules, but rather as coordinates
for the direction of the mind in matters of figural philology.
The domain
The work of philology, validating the past reality of works with the help of
the historical meanings of habitudes, manifests a presentational conception
of the past reality of works of art, in the sense that repetition, rehearsal and
restoration distinguish available trails with which it is possible to shape and
narrate this reality. The philologist’s task is to establish the historical reality of
the work, by a process of identifying and deploying historical meanings, that is
to say, essential tendencies or mental habits. To this end, the philologist must
Conclusion: Towards a figural philology 137
assume the past reality of the things he investigates; that is, he adheres to the
continuous survival of things throughout history. This certainty regarding the
past duration of the investigated work (i.e. the work’s past reality) serves the
philologist as a platform upon which to read, regressively, the net of habitudes
along the figural series that he forms, striving to restore the work’s historical
reality, including and approaching, yet never positively naming, the work’s
mark of distinction.
Philological production
Figural synthesis
Distinctive realism
Untemporal history
Moderate historicism
the past through the free play of the imagination. Instead, figural philology’s
double restoration would include: (1) the restoration of the ‘having been’ of the
work; its past reality, following trails of homologies, representations, copies,
citations and moments of transmission; and (2) the restoration of monuments as
they deserve to be read, with their proper reading, and their distinctive marks.
This proper manner is the mode in which thought can distinguish a
monument as forming a figure together with a certain theoretical work. Hence,
in Aristotelian terms, a figural philology is located not only between history
and tragedy but also between history and philosophy. One could say that
philology is more philosophical than history, in the same sense that poetry is
more philosophical than history: both seek to present processes in reasonably
readable terms, not necessarily as they were. The working of figural philology
conforms to Windelband’s guidelines for ‘idiographic’ sciences,14 describing
valuable singularities. But, according to Panofsky’s iconology, an understanding
of the singularity is only achieved when a thing pertains to a certain series, to
a certain genre. This is enabled when a monument is rewarded with a proper
match, and thereby endowed with a moral affirmation, an affirmation of ‘so it
would be proper’, supported by the deployment of the work’s past reality and its
historical meaning.
Panofsky
Though Panofsky himself wished only to be affiliated with teachers who were
art historians (Vöge, Goldschmidt, Riegl, Dvořák and Schlosser), we have
here gone further in attempting to diagnose Panofsky’s peculiar ‘mental habit’.
This, according to the argument presented above, would definitely qualify as
philological, and in terms of the general history of concepts, would consist of
a mixture of hylomorphism and neo-Kantian value-based historicism. This
mixture, we have argued, describes best Panofsky’s method throughout its
various mutations. It produced a genuine philological enterprise, tracing the
passages of meaningful forms in history. In general terms, Panofsky can indeed
be placed among the later generation of Romance philologists (Auerbach,
Spitzer and Curtius), for several reasons, but most centrally because of this
generation’s combination of the ‘positivist morphological’ and the ‘historical-
cultural’ schools of nineteenth-century philology.
On this basis, we can view Panofsky’s endeavour, perhaps like any philo-
logical project, as inherently educational and edifying. Working on a moral
142 Figural Philology
platform, he persisted not only in his respect for tradition,15 but also in his
maintenance of a bond between the history of poiesis and the history of theory.
This may supply a basis for understanding Panofsky’s various studies of specific
historical characters, such as Abbot Suger, Galileo Galilei and Erasmus,16 who
were, in themselves, embodying the link between theory and poiesis. These
authors tipped their respective theological, scientific and philosophical hats
to works of art, in a gesture of courtesy at a distance. As did Panofsky himself.
Notes
Chapter 1
1 Ernst Renan, L’avenir de la science: Pensées de 1848 (Paris, 1890), 141, quoted in
Edward W. Said, ‘Renan’s Philological Laboratory’, in Hellmut Flashar, Mayotte
Bollack and Heinz Wismann (eds), Philologie et herméneutique au 19ieme siècle II
(Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 1983), 195.
2 See: Jan Ziolkowski (ed.), On Philology (University Park: Pennsylvania State
University Press, 1990); Hans Ulrich Gumbrecht, The Powers of Philology:
Dynamics of Textual Scholarship (Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press, 2003);
Pascal Hummel, Philologus auctor: le philologue et son œuvre (Bern, Berlin
and Brussels: P. Lang, 2003); A. Gurd, Iphigenias at Aulis: Textual Multiplicity,
Radical Philology (Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 2005); Jürgen
Paul Schwindt (ed.), Was ist eine philologische Frage? Beiträge zu Erkundung
einer theoretischen Einstellung (Frankfut am Main: Suhrkamp, 2009); Kai
Bremer and Uwe Wirth (eds), Texte zur modernen Philologie (Ditzingen:
Reclam, 2010); Karlheinz Barck and Martin Treml (eds), Erich Auerbach –
Geschichte und Aktualität eines europäischen Philologen (Berlin: Kulturverlag
Kadmos, 2007).
3 Paul de Man, ‘The Return to Philology’, in The Resistance to Theory (Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 1986), 3–26.
4 Most notably by Friedrich Nietzsche. On this see Said, ‘Renans’s Philological
Laboratory’, 194–5.
5 August Boeckh, ‘Die Idee der Philologie oder ihr Begriff, Umfang und höchster
Zweck’, in Enzyklopädie und Methodenlehre der philologischen Wissenchaften
[c. 1877], vol. 1 (Stuttgart: B. G. Teubner, 1966), 23–5; Ulrich von Wilamowitz-
Moellendorff, Geschichte der Philologie [1921] (Stuttgart and Leipzig:
B. G. Teubner, 1998), 1–6; John Glucker, From Sylvester to the Elders of Zion:
Introduction to Philology [in Hebrew] (Jerusalem: Carmel, 2011), 75–6.
6 Boeckh, ‘Idee der Philologie’, 3–33; Pierre Swiggers, ‘Les debuts et l’évolution de
la philologie romane, surtout en Allemagne’, in Sylvain Auroux (ed.), History of
the Language Sciences: An International Handbook on the Evolution of the Study
of Language from the Beginnings to the Present, vol. 2 (Berlin: de Gruyter, 2001),
1272–86.
7 See: Richard Walzer, ‘New Light on the Arabic Translations of Aristotle’, Oriens 6:1
144 Notes
(June 1953): 91–142; Alexandra Liameri and Vanda Zajko (eds), Translation and
the Classic (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008).
8 Boeckh, ‘Idee der Philologie’, 12, 24; Georg Curtius, ‘Über die Geschichte und
Aufgabe der Philologie’ [1862], in Ausgewählte Reden und Vorträge (Leipzig:
Verlag von S. Hirzel, 1886), 117–21.
9 An elaborated account of the relationship between painting and humanist
scholarship can be found in Michael Baxandall, Giotto and the Orators: Humanist
Observers of Painting in Italy and the Discovery of Pictorial Composition,
1350–1450 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1971).
10 See Erwin Panofsky, Renaissance and Renascences in Western Art (Stockholm:
Almqvist & Wiksell, 1972 [1960]).
11 Michael Podro has remarked on the trans-cultural potential of Panofsky’s
iconology. See his The Critical Historians of Art (New Haven and London: Yale
University Press, 1982), 186.
12 Erwin Panofsky, ‘The Neoplatonic Movement in Florence and North Italy
(Bandinelli and Titian)’, and ‘The Neoplatonic Movement and Michelangelo’, in
Studies in Iconology (New York and London: Icon, Harper and Row, 1962 [1939]),
129–230.
13 See: Robert S. Leventhal, ‘The Emergence of Philological Discourse in the German
States 1770–1810’, in The Disciplines of Interpretation: Lessing, Herder, Schlegel and
Hermeneutics in Germany 1750–1800 (Berlin and Amsterdam: Walter de Gruyter,
1994), 235–55; Ingo Gildenhard, ‘Philologia Perennis? Classical Scholarship
and Functional Differentiation’, in I. Gildenhard and M. Ruehl (eds), Out of
Arcadia: Classics and Politics in Germany in the Age of Burckhardt, Nietzsche and
Wilamowitz (London: Institute of Classical Studies, 2003), 161–204.
14 See Thora Ilin Bayer and Donald Phillip Verene, Keys to the New Science:
Translations, Commentaries and Essays (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2009),
30–1, 45–6. See also Auerbach’s translation and commentaries: Giambattista Vico,
Die Neue Wissenschaft – über die gemeinschaftliche Natur der Völke (München:
Allgemeine Verlagsanstalt, 1924).
15 For Auerbach’s main writings concerning Vico, see: Erich Auerbach, ‘Giambattista
Vico und die Idee der Philologie’ [1936], in Gesammelte Aufsätze zur romanischen
Philologie, ed. F. Schalk (Bern: Francke, 1967), 233–41; ‘Vico and Aesthetic
Historism’, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 8:2 (December 1949): 110–18;
‘Vico und der Volksgeist’ [1955], in Gesammelte Aufsätze, 242–50.
16 Karl Löwith, Vicos Grundsatz: verum et factum convertuntur – Seine theologische
Prämisse und deren säkulare Konsequenzen (Heidelberg: Carl Winter
Universitätsverlag, 1968); James C. Morrison, ‘Vico’s Principle of Verum is Factum
and the Problem of Historicism’, Journal of the History of Ideas 39:4 (October
1978), 579–95; David Marshall has argued for the need to differentiate better
Notes 145
the Relationship of Art History and Art Theory: Towards the Possibility of a
Fundamental System of Concepts for a Science of Art’, trans. Katharina Lorenz
and Jas Elsner, Critical Inquiry 35 (Autumn 2008): 47.
75 For a criticism of hylomorphism in nature and in human production and
technics, developed in France at about the same time as Panofsky was bringing
his iconology to fruition, see Gilbert Simondon, L’individuation à la lumière des
notions de forme et d’information [1957] (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France,
1964).
Chapter 2
1 For several examples out of many possible others, see Erwin Panofsky,
Korrespondenz 1910–1968. Eine kommentierte Auswahl in fünf Bänden, ed. Dieter
Wuttke (Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz Verlag, 2001), vol. 3, 664 (25 January 1955);
860–1 (23 November 1955); 965 (26 April 1956); vol. 4, 396–7 (19 December
1958).
2 Erwin Panofsky, Korrespondenz, vol. 5, 639 (Letter to Robert Marichal, 22 March
1965).
3 On Focillon and morphology, see Maddalena Mazzocut-Mis, Forma come destino,
Henri Focillon et il pensiero morfologico nell’estetica francese della prima metà del
Novecento (Florence: Alinea Editrice, 1998). I am thankful to Kerstin Thomas for
pointing out the relevance of this work.
4 David Summers, ‘Meaning in the Visual Arts as a Humanistic Discipline’, in Irvin
Lavin (ed.), Meaning in the Visual Arts: Views From Outside (Princeton: The
Institute for Advanced Study, 1995), 12–13.
5 Panofsky, Korrespondenz, vol. 3, 664 (Panofsky to J. de Coo, Museum Mayer van
den Bergh, Antwerpen, 25 January 1955).
6 Panofsky, Die deutsche Plastik des elften bis dreizehnten Jahrhunderts, 2 vols
(Munich: Kurt Wolff, 1924).
7 Panofsky, ‘Das Problem des Stils in der bildenden Kunst’ [1915], Deutschprachige
Aufsätze II, ed. Martin Warnke and Karen Michels (Berlin: Akademie Verlag,
1998), 1109–18.
8 Michael Podro, The Critical Historians of Art (New Haven and London: Yale
University Press, 1982), 179–85; Michael Ann Holly, ‘Panofsky and Riegl’, in Erwin
Panofsky and the Foundations of Art History (Ithaca: Cornell University Press,
1984), 69–96; Margaret Iversen, Alois Riegl: Art History and Theory (Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press, 1993), 152ff; Allister Neher, ‘ “The Concept of the Kunstwollen”:
Neo-Kantianism and Erwin Panofsky’s Early Art Theoretical Essays’, Word and
Image 20:1 (January–March 2004), 41–51; Frederic J. Schwartz, ‘Panofsky and
Notes 151
Sedlmayr: The Options’, Blind Spots: Critical Theory and the History of Art in
Twentieth-century Germany (New Haven and London: Yale University Press,
2005), 146–51.
9 Neher, ‘The Concept of the Kunstwollen’, 44–6.
10 This issue was discussed in Erwin Panofsky, ‘Über das Verhältnis der
Kunstgeschichte zur Kunsttheorie. Ein Beitrag zu der Erörtung über die Möglichkeit
kunstwissenschaftlicher Grundbegriffe’ [1924], Deutschsprachige Aufstätze II,
1035–63; ‘On the Relationship Between Art History and Art Theory: Towards
the Possibility of a Fundamental System of Concepts of a Science of Art’, trans.
Katharina Lorenz and Jas Elsner, Critical Inquiry 35 (Autumn 2008): 43–71.
11 Panofsky, ‘Zum Problem der Beschreibung und Inhaltsdeutung von Werken der
bildenden Kunste’, Aufsätze zu Grundfragen der Kunstwissenschaft, ed. Hariolf
Oberer and Egon Verhezen (Berlin: B. Hessling, 1964), 93.
12 Panofsky, ‘The Concept of Artistic Volition’, trans. Kenneth J. Northcott and Joel
Snyder, Critical Inquiry 8:1 (Autumn 1981): 33.
13 Panofsky, ‘Der Begriff des Kunstwollens (1920)’, Aufsätze zu Grundfragen der
Kunstwissenschaft, 44.
14 Panofsky discusses hylomorphism in his Habilitationsschrift, Die
Gestaltungsprinzipien Michelangelos (Berlin and New York: Walter de Gruyter,
2014), 197–219.
15 Adi Efal, ‘Reality as the Cause of Art: Alois Riegl and Neo-Kantian Realism’,
Journal of Art Historiography 3 (December 2010), http://arthistoriography.files.
wordpress.com/2011/02/media_183171_en.pdf (accessed 14 July 2016).
16 For example Henri Zerner, ‘L’histoire de l’art d’Alois Riegl: un formalism tactique’,
Critique 339–40 (August–September 1975), 941.
17 Michael Gubser, ‘Theodor von Sickel and the Institute for Austrian Historical
Research’, Time’s Visible Surface: Alois Riegl and the Discourse on History and
Temporality in Fin-de-Siècle Vienna (Detroit: Wayne State University Press, 2006),
77–88.
18 Ibid., 82–3.
19 See Sebastiano Timpanaro, The Genesis of Lachmann’s Method, trans. Glenn W.
Most (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 2005).
20 Alois Riegl, Historische Grammatik der bildenden Künste, ed. Karl M. Swoboda
and Otto Pächt (Graz: Böhlau, 1996); Alois Riegl, Historical Grammar of the
Visual Arts, trans. Jacqueline E. Jung (New York: Zone Books, 2004).
21 Theodor Lewandowski, Linguistishces Wörterbuch (Heidelberg: Quelle und Meyer,
1984), 388–9.
22 R. Meringer et al. (eds), Wörter und Sachen: Kulturhistorische Zeitschrift für Sprach
und Sachforschung, vol. 1 (Heidelberg: Carl Winters Universitätsbuchhandlung,
1909); Spitzer contributed an essay in the third issue of this journal, in 1912;
152 Notes
42 Alois Riegl, ‘Der Moderne Denkmalskultus sein Wesen und seine Entstehung,
(1903)’, Gesammelte Aufsätze (Augsburg-Wien: Benno Filser Verlag, 1928),
144–93. On this essay, see: Gubser, ‘History and the Perception of Monuments’,
Time’s Visible Surface, 141–50; Diana Reynolds Cordilione, ‘The Advantages and
Disadvantages of Art history for Life: Alois Riegl and Historicism’, Journal of
Art Historiography 3 (December 2010), http://arthistoriography.files.wordpress.
com/2011/02/media_183170_en.pdf (accessed 14 July 2016); Adi Efal, ‘Riegl’s
Concept of Age-value and the Challenge of Historicism in Art History’, Art
History Supplement 5 (December 2011), https://drive.google.com/folderview?id=
0B3m6FPZNWpExfl9JSjkwRzlxa3hzR043amlSSVJmWWhGQzZjZXpwTl96WEZ
fZ0szTlF1aWM&usp=sharing (accessed 14 July 2016).
43 Efal, ‘Riegl’s Concept of Age-value’.
44 Karen A. Lang, ‘The Experience of Time and the Time of History: Riegl’s
Age-value and Benjamin’s Aura’, in Chaos and Cosmos: On the Image in Aesthetics
and Art History (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2006), 135–78.
45 Alois Riegl, ‘The Modern Cult of Monuments: Its Essence and its Developments’,
trans. Karin Bruckner and Karen Williams, in Nicholas Stanley Price
(ed.), Historical Philosophical issues in the Conservation of Cultural Heritage
(Harvard: Paul Getty Trust, 1996), 77.
46 Riegl, ‘Der Moderne Denkmalkultus’, Gesammelte Aufsätze, 172.
47 See, for example: Georg Dehio, Alois Riegl and Georg Mörsch, Konservieren, nicht
Restaurieren: Streitschriften zur Denkmalpflege um 1900 (Braunschweig: Vieweg,
1988); Ernst Bacher (ed.), Kunstwerk oder Denkmal? Alois Riegls Schriften zu
Denkmalphlege (Köln and Weimar: Böhlau, 1995).
48 Efal, ‘Reality as the Cause of Art’, 6–7, 13.
49 Riegl, ‘Kunstgeschichte und Universalgeschichte’, in Gesammelte Aufsätze, 9:
‘Zwishen Wellenberg und Wellental liegt ein toter Punkt, in welchem die Extreme
sich berühren.’
50 Erwin Panofsky, ‘Das Mittelmaß’, Die theoretische Kunstlehre Albrecht Dürers
(Dürers Ästhetik), Dissertation (Berlin: Georg Reimer, 1914), 21–3.
51 Panofsky, ‘The Concept of Artistic Volition’, 30.
52 Panofsky, ‘Begriff des Kunstwollens’, 42.
53 Erwin Panofsky, Gothic Architecture and Scholasticism (New York: Meridian
Publishing, 1957 [1951]).
54 Riegl, ‘Naturwerk und Kunstwert I’, Gesammelte Aufsätze, 63.
55 Efal, ‘Reality as the Cause of Art’; Efal, ‘Riegl’s Concept of Age-value’.
56 Erwin Panofsky, ‘Original und Faksimilerreproduktion’ [1930], Deutschsprachige
Aufstäze II, 1078–91.
57 Ibid., 1080.
58 Riegl, ‘Der moderne Denkmalkultus’, Gesammelte Aufsätze, 172.
154 Notes
Chapter 3
13 Henri Focillon, Vie des formes (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1943).
14 Riegl, Historical Grammar of the Visual Arts, 187; Historische Grammatik der
bildenden Künste, 129: ‘Alle Dinge in der Natur sind geformt, d.h. sie erstrecken
sich nach den drei Dimensionen der Höhe, Breite und Tiefe.’
15 Panofsky, ‘Kunstgeschichte zur Kunsttheorie’, 132; ‘Art History and Art Theory’, 47.
16 Gotthold Ephraim Lessing, Laokoon. Über die Grenzen der Malerei und Poesie
[1766] (Stuttgart: Reclam, 1964); Wölfflin, Grundbegriffe, 1979; Greenberg,
‘Towards a Newer Laocoon.’
17 Adrian Stokes, ‘Stones of Rimini’ [1935], in Critical Writings, vol. 1 (London:
Thames and Hudson, 1978), 228–59.
18 Kurt Badt, Raumphantasien und Raumillusionen. Das Wesen der Plastik (Köln:
Dumont, 1963).
19 Descartes, ‘Rules for the Direction of the Mind’, in Philosophical Writings, 64.
20 Erich Auerbach, ‘Figura’, Archivum Romanicum 22 (1938): 436–89; ‘Figura’,
in Scenes From the Drama of European Literature. Six Essays (Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 1984). It is telling, and supportive of the thesis of
the present book, that Auerbach intended ‘Figura’ to be published in the journal
of the Warburg Institute, meaning that he himself saw his essay as belonging to
the iconological tradition of inquiry. The editors of the journal, though, finding
the essay fitting in style and topic, declined to publish it since it was too long
and written in German. See Elizabeth Sears, ‘Warburg Institute Archive: General
Correspondence’, Common Knowledge, eds A. Grafton and J. F. Hamburger, 18:1
Special issue (Winter 2012): 47–8.
21 Rosalind Krauss, The Optical Unconscious (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993),
13–17.
22 Gilles Deleuze, Francis Bacon. Logique de la sensation, 2 vols (Paris: La Vue le
Texte, 1981); Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation, trans. D. W. Smith (New York
and London: Continuum, 2004). In further quotations from this source, I cite the
French pagination first, followed by the English.
23 Deleuze, Francis Bacon, 65–71/99–110.
24 Deleuze, Francis Bacon, 71/110.
25 Deleuze, Francis Bacon, 9/173.
26 Jean-François Lyotard, Discours, Figure (Paris: Klinsieck, 1971).
27 Sabine Hiebsch, Auerbachs Figura ecclesiae: Lea und Rachel in Luthers
Genesispredigten (Münster: Lit Verlag, 2002), 49–51.
28 Stokes, ‘Stones’, 230.
29 My translation. Focillon, Vie, 52, 53: ‘ces matières si bien caractérisées, si
suggestives et même si exigeante à l’égard des formes de l’art, sur lesquelles elles
exercent une sorte d’attrait, s’en trouvent, par un retour, profondément modifiées
[…] la vie apparente de la matière s’est métamorphosée.’
156 Notes
30 Francastel, Réalité figurative, 97–8: ‘Le signe figuratif est un lieu où se rencontrent
des valeurs infiniment plus riches qu’on ne l’imagine lorsqu’on se borne à le
considérer comme un équivalent sous d’autres formes de signes ou d’images
susceptible de le remplacer.’
31 Panofsky, Idea – Ein Beitrag zur Begriffsgeschichte der älteren Kunsttheorie.
32 Deleuze, Francis Bacon, 9–10/2–3.
33 Francastel, Réalité figurative, 105. ‘Ce qui constitue la forme d’une ouvrage, ce ne
sont pas les détails, c’est l’ensemble […] Cependent la forme n’est pas la somme
des détails intégrés dans l’ensemble qui constitue l’œuvre, elle n’appartient pas au
niveau des éléments et des contenus mais au niveau des principes, c’est-à-dire
des structures. Elles s’identifient avec le schème d’organisation qui suggère
l’assemblage des éléments, choisis comme significatifs non pas en raison de leur
conformité à des modèles hétéroclites, tirés du dehors, mais en considération de
leur liaison avec les lois propres du schème organisateur. La forme est donc liée
non aux impulsions venues du monde extérieur – au domaine de la perception –
mais aux principes de cohésion du système – à une problématique de l’imaginaire.’
34 Aristotle, Metaphysics V, The Metaphysics Books I–IX. trans. Hugh Tredennick
(London and Cambdridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003), 284–7
(1024a30–1024b16).
35 Francastel, Réalite figurative, 105. ‘La série seule fait exister le prototype, qui sans
cela demeurerait le chef-d’oeuvre inconnu. On ne propose pas de limiter l’histoire
des arts à celle des prototypes créatuers de formes. La connaissance du role et de
l’histoire des arts exige, à la fois, l’étude des séries et des modeles.’
36 Focillon, Vie, 67–100.
37 Ibid., 68: ‘Prendre conscience, c’est prendre forme.’
38 Ibid., 75: ‘à un certain ordre des formes correspond un certain ordre des esprits’.
39 Richard Woodfield (ed.), Framing Formalism: Riegl’s Work (New York and
London: Routledge, 2001).
40 See Adi Efal, ‘Reality as the Cause of Art: Alois Riegl and Neo-Kantian Realism’,
Journal of Art Historiography 3 (December 2010), http://arthistoriography.files.
wordpress.com/2011/02/media_183171_en.pdf (accessed 14 July 2016).
41 Focillon, Vie, 22–3: ‘Les formes, en leurs divers états, ne sont certes pas
suspendues dans une zone abstraite, au-desus de la terre, au-dessus de l’homme.
Elles se mêlent à la vie, d’où elles viennet, traduissant dans l’espace certains
mouvements de l’esprit.’
42 Johann Joachim Winckelmann, Gedanken über die Nachahmung der griechischen
Werke in der Malerei und Bildhauerkunst (Stuttgart: Reclam, 1969 [1755]), 29–31.
43 Ibid.
44 Catharine Malabou (ed.), Plasticité (Paris: Léo Scheer, 2000).
45 Francastel, Réalité figurative, 127: ‘Tous les arts plastiques sont des arts de l’espace.
Notes 157
[…] Tout signe plastique est par conséquent spatial. […] Il est donc capital
d’étudier la Forme plastique en fonction de la notion d’espace.’
46 The original text was given as a lecture in the Warburg Institute London, in 1940.
Badt, Raumphantasien und Raumillusionen, 135–64.
47 Ibid., 140.
48 Hermann Menge-Güthling, Enzyklopädisches Wörterbuch der griechischen und
deutschen Sprache, Band I (Berlin: Langescheid, 1962), 558.
49 Focillon, ‘Éloge de la main’, Vie, 103–28.
50 Pliny the Elder, Natural History, books 33–5, trans. H. Rackham (London and
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1952), 370–3.
51 Ibid., 373.
52 Herder, Plastik, 9–10; Herder, Sculpture, 35–6.
53 Herder, Sculpture, 65; Herder, Plastik, 65: ‘… gehört nun nicht noch immer der
plastische Sinn dazu, die Linie wieder in Körper, die platte Figur in eine runde
lebende Gestalt zu verwandeln?’
54 Stokes, ‘Stones’, 235.
Chapter 4
1 Erwin Panofsky, Idea – Ein Beitrag zur Begriffsgeschichte der älteren Kunsttheorie
(Berlin: Verlag Bruno Hessling GMBH, 1975 [1924]); Idea: A Concept in Art
Theory, trans. Joseph J. S. Peake (New York and London: Icon Editions, 1968).
2 Erich Auerbach, ‘Figura’, Archivum Romanicum 22 (1938): 436–89; ‘Figura’, in
Scenes from the Drama of European Literature. Six Essays (Minneapolis: University
of Minnesota Press, 1984), 11–76. When referring below to both Panofsky’s and
Auerbach’s essays, I give the German pagination first, followed by the English.
3 Michael Kelly, Iconoclasm in Aesthetics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2003).
4 Ibid., 96.
5 See Otto Gerhard Oexle (ed.), Krise des Historismus – Krise der Wirklichkeit.
Wissenschaft, Kunst und Literatur 1880–1932 (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and
Ruprecht, 2007).
6 See: Jacques Rancière, Le partag e du sensible-esthétique et politique (Paris: La
fabrique-éditions, 2000); Le destin des images (Paris: La fabrique-éditions, 2003);
Malaise dans l’esthétique (Paris: Galilée, 2004).
7 Martin Jay, Downcast Eyes: The Denigration of Vision in Twentieth-Century French
Thought (Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1993).
8 For a study of Byzantine iconoclasm see Marie-José Mondzain, Image, Icon,
Economy: The Byzantine Origins of the Contemporary Imaginary, trans. R. Franses
158 Notes
35 Giambatistta Vico, ‘On Verum and Factum’, Selected Writings, ed. and trans.
Leon Pompa (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 50–6. See
also Karl Löwith, Vicos Grundsatz:verum et factum convertuntur – Seine
theologische Prämisse und deren säkulare Konsequenzen (Heidelberg: Carl Winter
Universitätsverlag, 1968).
36 Auerbach, ‘Figura’, 438–39/14–16.
37 Ibid., 437–44/11–21.
38 Ibid., 442–4/18–21.
39 Ibid., 447–50/25–8.
40 Ibid., 450–64/28–49.
41 White, ‘Auerbach’s Literary History’, 88–9.
42 Vico, Selected Writings, 75–6. For a quasi-realist (known as anti-realist) conception
of the past, leaning on a geometrical grid, reminding one of Descartes’ res extensa,
see Michael Dummett, Truth and the Past (New York: Columbia University Press,
2004), 46–52.
43 Vico, Selected Writings, 206; Vico, Die Neue Wissenschaft, 139.
44 Vico, Selected Writings, 61, 75: ‘We might demonstrate by synthesis, i.e. we should
make truths rather than discover them.’
45 Auerbach himself notes the important part synthesis plays in his philological
method, see Auerbach, ‘Introduction: Purpose and Method’, Literary Language
and its Public, 17–18. See also Leopold Waizbort, ‘Erich Auerbach im Kontext der
Historismus debatt’, in Erich Auerbach – Geschichte und Aktualität, 17–18.
46 Auerbach, ‘Figura’, 469–70, 478/54–5; Auerbach, ‘Typological Symbolism in
Medieval Literature’, Yale French Studies 9 – Symbol and Symbolism (New York:
Kraus Reprint Corporation, 1965), 6–7; Jesse M. Gellrich, ‘Figura, Allegory
and the Question of History’, in Literary History and the Challenge of Philology,
107–23.
47 Auerbach, ‘Figura’, 471–2/56–7.
48 Ibid., 451/29.
49 Auerbach, Mimesis.
50 On Auerbach’s Realism see: Ernst Müller, ‘Auerbachs Realismus’, in Erich Auerbach
– Geschichte und Aktualität, 268–71; Luiz Costa Lima, ‘Zwischen Realismus und
Figuration: Auerbachs dezentrierter Realismus’, in Erich Auerbach – Geschichte
und Aktualität, 255–67.
51 On place see Aristotle, The Physics, vol. 1, trans. Philip H. Wicksteed and Francis
Cornford (London and Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1957 [1929]),
276–315 (208a27–212a30).
52 Michael Holquist, ‘The Last European: Erich Auerbach as Precursor in the History
of Cultural Criticism’, Modern Language Quarterly 54:3 (September 1993): 374–9.
Barry Maine has suggested a more plausible interpretation of Auerbach’s realism,
Notes 161
Chapter 5
36 Pascal, Pensées, 442 (§299): ‘La figure a été faite sur la vérité, et la vérité a été
reconnue sur la figure’; 200 (§299): ‘La lettre tue. Tout arrivait en figures.’
37 Deleuze has noted that the operation of the figure is to render visible invisible
forces. Deleuze, Francis Bacon, 40/58: ‘Il semble que, dans l’histoire de la
peinture, les Figures de Bacon soient une de réponses le plus merveilleuses à la
question: comment rendre visible des forces invisible? C’est même la fonction
primordiale des Figures’; ‘Bacon’s Figures seem to be one of the most marvelous
responses of the history of painting to the question, how can one make invisible
forces visible?’
38 Henri Bergson, Essai sur les données immédiates de la conscience [1888], Œuvres,
ed. André Robinet (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1959), 1–157.
39 On the plasticity of Auerbach’s philology, see Hans Ulrich Gumbrecht, ‘Was Erich
Auerbach für eine „Philologische Frage“ hielt’, in Jürgen Paul Schwindt (ed.), Was
ist eine philologische Frage? Beiträge zu Erkundung einer theoretischen Einstellung
(Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 2009), 282–3.
40 Genette, ‘Figures’, 207.
41 Ibid., 209.
42 Étienne Gilson, Le réalisme méthodique (Paris: Pierre Téqui Éditeur, 2007
[1935]).
43 Auerbach, ‘Figura’, 451/29.
44 Ibid., 465–6/50–1. In the English translation, the expression is ‘figural
interpretation’.
45 See: Frankt Ankersmit, ‘Why Realism? Auerbach on the Representation of Reality’,
Poetics Today 20:1 (Spring 1999): 59–62; Hayden White, ‘Auerbach’s Literary
History: Figural Casuation and Modernism Historicism’, Figural Realism: Studies
in the Mimesis Effect (Baltimore and London: Johns Hopkins University Press,
1999), 87–100.
46 Hermann Usener, ‘Philologie und Geschichtswissenschaft’, Vorträge und Aufsätze
(Leipzig und Berlin: B. G. Teubner, 1907), 9.
47 Erich Auerbach, ‘Introduction: Purpose and Method’, in Literary Language and
its Public in Late Latin Antiquity and in the Middle Ages (London: Routledge and
Kegan Paul, 1965), 7.
48 Charlotte Witt, ‘Hylomorphism in Aristotle’, Journal of Philosophy 84:11
(November 1987): 673–9; Höffe, Aristoteles-Lexikon, 369–70.
49 Höffe, Aristoteles-Lexikon, 425–6.
50 Descartes, Regulæ, 413; ‘Rules’, 40.
51 Descartes, Regulæ, 413; ‘Rules’, 41.
52 Walter Benjamin, Das Passagen Werk, ed. Rolf Tiedman, vol. 1 (Frankfurt
am Main: Suhrkamp, 1981), 578 (N3, I): ‘Nur dialektische Bilder sind echt
geschichtliche, d.h. nicht archaische Bilder.’
Notes 165
Chapter 6
1 Emily J. Levine, ‘Sokrates an der Elbe? Erwin Panofsky und die Hamburger Schule
der Kunstgeschichte in den 1920er Jahren’, Zeitgeschichte in Hamburg Nachrichten
aus der Forschungsstelle für Zeitgeschichte in Hamburg (Hamburg: Forschungsstelle
für Zeitgeschichte, 2008), 27–40.
2 Erwin Panofsky and Fritz Saxl, Dürers ‘Melencolia I’. Eine Quellen- und
Typengeschichliche Untersuchung (Berlin: Studien der Bibliothek Warburg (2),
1923).
3 First appeared in the series Studien der Bibliothek Warburg (Leipzig and Berlin,
1924).
4 First appeared as ‘Die Perspektive als „symbolische Form“ ‘, in the Vorträge der
Bibliothek Waburg 1924–1925 (Leipzig and Berlin, 1927), 258–33.
5 Michael Ann Holly’s seminal book on the intellectual contexts of Panofsky’s
work does not include a chapter on Panofsky’s affinity with Warburg (Michael
Ann Holly, Erwin Panofsky and the Foundations of Art History [Ithaca: Cornell
University Press, 1984]). For available discussions see Audrey Rieber, ‘L’oeuvre
d’art comme symptôme: Panofsky et Warburg’, in Art, histoire et signification
(Paris: L’Harmattan, 2012), 61–105; Silvia Ferretti, Cassirer, Panofsky and Warburg.
Symbol, Art and History, trans. Richard Pierce (New Haven and London: Yale
University Press, 1989); Peter Schmidt, Aby M. Warburg und die Ikonologie
(Bamberg: Stefen Wendel Verlag, 1989); Erik Frossmann, ‘Ikonologie und
allgemeine Kunstgeschichte (1966)’, in Ekkehard Kaemmerling (ed.), Ikonographie
und Ikonologie. Theorien. Entwicklung. Probleme (Köln: Dumont Buchverlag,
1973), 257–300.
6 See Ernst Gombrich, Aby Warburg: An Intellectual Biography (London: Warburg
Institute, 1970), 283.
7 Erwin Panofsky, ‘Reflections on Historical Time’, trans. Johanna Bauman, Critical
Inquiry 30 (Summer 2004): 691–701; ‘Zum Problem der historischen Zeit’, in
Aufsätze zu Grundfragen der Kunstwissenschaft, ed. Hariolf Oberer and Egon
Verheyen (Berlin: B. Hessling, 1985), 77–83.
8 Georg Simmel, ‘Das Probelm des hitorischen Zeit’, in Brücke und Tür. Essays
des Philosophischen zur Geschichte, Religion, Kunst und Gesellschaft [1903], ed.
Michael Landmann (Stuttgart: Koehler, 1957), 43–58.
9 Aby Warburg, Werke in einem Band, ed. Martin Treml, Sgrid Weigel and Perdita
Ladwig (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 2010), 396: ‘… wollte ich mir ein
Plädoyer erlauben zugunsten einer methodischen Grenzerweiterung unserer
Kunstwissenschaft in stofflicher und räumlicher Beziehung’.
10 Panofsky, ‘Historical Time’, 695; ‘historischen Zeit’, 78.
11 Warburg, Werke, 636: ‘Die Kunsthistorie ist freilich nicht gewohnt, die
166 Notes
zum Unbedeutenden uim Werk von Usener, Warburg und Benjamin (Tübingen:
Max Niemezer Verlag, 1987), 67–113.
36 Anna Guillemin, ‘The Style of Linguistics: Aby Warburg, Karl Voßler, and
Hermann Osthoff ’, Journal of the History of Ideas 69:4 (October 2008): 605–26.
37 Matthew Rampley, ‘From Symbol to Allegory: Aby Warburg’s Theory of Art’, The
Art Bulletin 79 (March 1997): 46–7. See also Aby Warbrug, ‘Schlussitzung der
Burckhardt Uebung’, Werke, 695–9.
38 James I. Porter, Nietzsche and the Philology of the Future (Stanford: Stanford
University Press, 2000); Christian Benne, Nietzsche und die historisch-kritische
Philologie (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 2005).
39 See Karlfried Gründer (ed.), Der Streit um Nietzsches ‘Geburt der Tragödie’: Die
Schriften von E. Rohde, R. Wagner, U. v. Wilamowitz-Moellendorff (Hildesheim:
Olms, 1989).
40 As Nietzsche argued in his famous Vom Nutzen und Nachteil der Historie für das
Leben [1874] (Stuttgart: Reclam Verlag, 2005).
41 Friedrich Nietzsche, ‘Wir Philologen’, Werke in drei Bänden, ed. Karl Schlechta,
vol. 3 (München & Wien: Hanser, 1999 [1956]), 323–32.
42 Ibid., 330–2.
43 Claudia Wedepohl, ‘Von der „Pathosformel“ zum Gebärdensprachatls. Dürers Tod
des Orpheus und Warburgs Arbeit an einer ausdruckstheoretisch begründeten
Kulturgeschichte’, Die Entfesselte Antike, Aby Warburg und die Geburt der
Pathosformel, ed. Marcus A. Hurttig and Thomas Ketelsen (Köln: Wallraf-
Richartz-Museum and Fondation Corboud, 2012), 45–6.
44 See Paolo D’Angelo, ‘Aby Warburg e Benedetto Croce’, Aby Warburg e la cultura
italiana, ed. Claudia Cieri Via and Micol Forti (Roma e Milano: Sapienza
Università di Roma, 2009), 15–26.
45 The boxes are to be found in the Warburg archive of the Warburg Institute,
London, noted as WIA III.2.1.2k/51/5. Important to note: Warburg located
Bergson within the rubric of ‘pragmatic philosophy’. The material to be found in
the specific location in the box is mostly related either to the general reception
of Bergson, or to the moral and political consequences of his philosophy.
Remarkably, it seems that Warburg was not compelled to investigate Bergson’s
notions of duration, the virtual, or even his conception of memory.
46 On Warburg and physiological aspects of memory, see Stefan Rieger, ‘Richard
Semon und/oder Aby Warburg. Mneme und/oder Mnemosyne’, in Deutsche
Vierteljahren Schrift für Literaturwissenschaft und Geistesgeschichte (Stuttgart und
Weimar, 1998), 245–63.
47 I noted the following items in Warburg’s private ex libris: Frank Grandjean, Une
révolution dans la philosophie, la doctrine de M. Henri Bergson (Genève: Librairie
Atar, 1913), purchased 1913; Hans Driesch, Henri Bergson, der biologische
Notes 169
57 Henri Bergson, La pensée et le mouvant [1934], in Œuvres, 1420: ‘Il y a une réalité
extérieure et pourtant donnée immédiatement à notre esprit […] Cette réalité est
mobilité.’
58 Aby Warburg, ‘Sandro Botticellis Geburt der Venus und Frühling [1893]‘, Werke,
39: ‘In der vorligenden Arbeit wird der Versuch gemacht, zum Vergleiche mit
den bekannten mythologischen Bildern des Sandro Botticelli, der „Geburt der
Venus“ und de „Frühling“ die entsprechenden Vorstellungen der gleichzeitigen
kunsttheoretischen und poetischen Litteratur heranzuziehen um auf diese
Weise das, was die Kümstler des Quattrocento an de Antike „interessierte“,
klarzulegen. Es lässt sich nämlich hierbei Schritt bei Schritt verfolgen, wie die
Künstler und deren Berather in „der Antike“ ein gesteigetrte äussere Bewegung
verlangendes Vorbild sahen und sich an antike Vorbilder anlehnten, wenn es
sich um Darstellung äusserlich bewegten Beiwerks – der Gewandung und der
Harre – handelte.’ Aby Warburg, ‘Sandro Boticelli’s Birth of Venus and Spring: An
Examination of Concepts of Antiquity in the Italian Early Renaissance’ [1893],
in The Renewal of Pagan Antiquity, ed. and trans. David Britt (Los Angeles: Getty
Research Institute, 1999), 89: ‘This work sets out to adduce, for purposes of
comparison with Sandro Boticelli’s celebrated mythological painting, the Birth of
Venus and Spring, the analogous ideas that appear in contemporary art theory
and poetic literature, and thus to exemplify what it was about antiquity that
“interested” the artists of the Quatrocento. It is possible to trace, step by step, how
the artists and their advisers recognized “the antique” as a model that demanded
an intensification of outward movement, and how they turned to antique
sources whenever accessory forms – those of garments and of hair – were to be
represented in motion.’
59 See Rieger, ‘Richard Semon und/oder Aby Warburg’.
60 On the relationship between figuration and movement, see Gottfried Boehm,
Gabriele Brandtstetter and Achatz von Müller (eds), Figur und Figuration: Studien
zu Wahrnehmung und Wissen (Munich: Fink Verlag, 2007).
61 On this see Richard Terdiman, Present Past: Modernity and the Memory Crisis
(Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1993).
62 Alexander Nigel and Christopher S. Wood, ‘Interventions: Toward a New Model
of Renaissance Anachronism’, The Art Bulletin 87:3 (Summer 2005): 403–15.
63 On philology and generic mobility see Bernard Cerquiglini, Éloge de la variante:
Histoire critique de la philologie (Paris: Seuil, 1989).
64 See Georges Didi-Huberman, L’image survivante. Histoire de l’art et temps des
fantômes selon Aby Warburg (Paris: Éditions de Minuit, 2002), 82–96.
65 Erich Auerbach, ‘Figura’ [1938], Gesammelte Aufsätze zur romanischen Philologie
(Bern: Francke, 1967), 55–92; ‘Figura’, in Scenes from the Drama of European
Literature. Six Essays (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984), 11–78.
Notes 171
66 Auerbach, ‘Figura’, 65–74; ‘Figura’, 28–49. See also Karlfried Gründer, Figur und
Geschichte: Johann Georg Hamanns ‘Biblische Betrachtungen’ als Ansatz einer
Geschichtsphilosophie (Freiburg and Munich: Albert, 1958).
67 Warburg, Werke, 631 (‘Präfiguriert’).
68 See Salvatore Settis, ‘Pathos ed Ethos, morfologia e funzione’, Moderna. Semestrale
di Teoria e Critica della Letteratura 6:2 (2004): 23–34.
69 As in Aby Warburg, ‘Francesco Sassettis Letztwillige Verfügung’ [1907], Werke,
234–80.
70 See: Edgar Wind, ‘Warburg’s Begriff der Kulturwissenschaft und seine Bedeutung
für Ästhetik’, Zeitschrift für Ästhetik und allgemeine Kunstwissenschaft 25
(Beilagehaft) (1931): 163–79; ‘Warburg’s Concept of Kulturwissenschaft and its
Meaning for Aesthetics’, in The Eloquence of Symbols: Studies in Humanist Art
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), 21–35; Matthew Rampley, The Remembrance
of Things Past: On Aby Warburg and Walter Benjamin (Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz
Verlag, 2000).
71 Auerbach referred to his philological project as deploying a drama. See Erich
Auerbach, Literary Language and its Public in Late Latin Antiquity and in the
Middle Ages (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1965), 7; Literatursprache und
Publikum in der lateinischen Spätantike und im Mittelalter (Bern: Francke, 1958),
10.
72 See also Martin Jesinghausen-Lauster, ‘Die Warburg Bibliothek als Problem’,
Die Suche nach der symbolischen Form. Der Kreis um die Kulturwissenschaftliche
Bibliothek Warburg (Baden-Baden: Verlag Valentin Koerner, 1985), 151–217.
73 Diers, ‘Warburg and the Warburgian Tradition’, 63, 67.
74 Michael Podro, The Critical Historians of Art (New Haven and London: Yale
University Press, 1982), 205.
75 Warburg noted: ‘Art history must remain a history’, diary entry of 12 February
1917, Tagebuch 3.1 (London: The Warburg Institue), 885, as quoted in Diers,
‘Warburg and the Warburgian Tradition’, 66.
76 ‘Ikonologie – Synthese’, Warburg Institute Archive, WIA III 2.1.2k/6 and WIA III
2.1.2k/7.
Chapter 7
3 Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood
(New York: Cambridge University Press, 2007), 210; Kritik der reinen Vernunft
[1781] (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 2003), 154 (B103): ‘Ich verstehe aber
unter Synthesis in der allgemeinsten Bedeutung die Handlung, verschiedene
Vorstellungen zu einander hinzuzuthun und ihre Mannigfaltigkeit in einer
Erkenntniß zu begreifen.’
4 Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft, 154; Critique of Pure Reason, 211: ‘die bloße
Wirkung der Einbildungskraft.’
5 Panofsky, ‘Iconography and Iconology’, 32.
6 Ibid., 38.
7 See Margit Atz, Organische Kunstbetrachtung bei Schelling (Würzburg-Aumühle:
Konrad Triltsch Verlag 1940); Judith Schlanger, Les métaphores de l’organisme
(Paris: Éditions L’Harmattan, 1971).
8 Aristotle, The Categories, On Interpretation, Prior Analytics, trans. Harold P. Cooke
and Hugh Tredennick (London and Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
1967), 22–5 (2b6–2b36).
9 Aristotle, Metaphysics V(Δ) The Metaphysics Books I–IX, trans. Hugh Tredennick
(London and Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1956), 284–5 (1024a).
10 Erwin Panofsky, Renaissance and Renascences in Western Art [1960] (New York
and London: Harper & Row Publishers, 1969).
11 Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft, 19 (BXIII): ‘bestallten Richters’.
12 Michael Ann Holly, Panofsky and the Foundations of Art History (Ithaca and
London: Cornell University Press, 1984), 114–57. See also Sylvia Ferretti, Cassirer,
Panofsky, Warburg: Symbol, Art and History, trans. R. Pierce (New Haven: Yale
University Press, 1989).
13 Erwin Panofsky, ‘Perspektive als symbolische Form’ [1927], in Aufsätze zu
Grundfragen der Kunstwissenschaft, ed. Hariolf Oberer und Egon Verhezen
(Berlin: B. Hessling, 1964), 99–167; Perspective as Symbolic Form, trans.
Christopher S. Wood (New York: Zone Books, 1991 [1972]).
14 My translation. ‘Die analytische Logik der reinen Identität hat sich damit zu einer
synthetischen Logik erweitert, in deren Mittelpunkt die Frage nach der möglichen
Verbindung, der Relation und Korrelation der Verschiedenen steht.’ Ernst Cassirer,
‘Zur Logik des Symbolbegriff ’, Wesen und Wirkung des Symbolbegriffs (Oxford and
Darmstadt: Bruno Cassirer, 1956), first published in Theoria 4–2 (August 1938):
145–75, 206.
15 Immanuel Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, trans. Paul Guyer and
Eric Matthews (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 8; Kritik der
Urteilskraft [1790] (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 2003), 16 (BXXI): ‘Urteilskraft
überhaupt ist das Vermögen, das Besondere als enthalten unter dem Allgemeinen
zu denken.’
Notes 173
of Concepts for a Science of art’, trans. Katharina Lorenz and Jas Elsner, Critical
Inquiry 35 (Autumn 2008): 45. See also Panofsky’s conclusion of Idea 71–2/126.
47 Panofsky, ‘Verhältnis der Kunstgeschichte zur Kunsttheorie’, 51; ‘Relationship of
Art History and Art Theory’, 47.
48 Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft, 153–5 (B102–104); Critique of Pure Reason,
210–11.
49 Erich Auerbach, ‘Introduction: Purpose and Method’, Literary Language and its
Public in Late Latin Antiquity and in the Middle Ages, trans. Ralph Manheim
(London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1965), 7.
50 Actually, already in Idea Panofsky had made use, passim, of a very similar
term – not synthetic intuition, but rather ‘intuitional synthesis’; Panofsky, Idea
36/65.
51 Aristotle, Metaphysics IX (Z), The Metaphysics Books I–IX, trans. Hugh Tredennick
(London and Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1956); 470–3 (1051b17–
1052a4); Aristotle, On the Soul, Parva Naturalia, On Breath, trans. W. S. Hett
(London and Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1957), 164–77 (III 4–5,
429a10–430a25).
52 Henri Bergson, ‘Introduction à la métaphysique’, La pensée et le mouvant, in
his Œuvres, ed. André Robinet (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1959),
1432: ‘Mais l’intuition métaphysique, quoiqu’on n’y puisse arriver qu’à force de
connaissances matérielles, est tout autre chose que le résumé ou la synthèse de ces
connaissances.’
53 Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph von Schelling (1775–1854), ‘System des
transcendentalen Idealismus’ [1800], in Schriften, vol. 1 (Frankfurt am Main:
Suhrkamp, 1985), 500–8.
54 Otfried Höffe (ed.), Aristoteles-Lexikon (Stuttgart: Alfred Kröner Verlag, 2005),
384.
55 A close equivalent is to be found in Martin Buber’s dialogical philosophy, where
he uses in German the term ‘synthetische Anschauung’: Martin Buber, Urdistanz
und Beziehung (Heidelberg: Lambert Schnieder 1978), 16–17. There is more work
to be done regarding the relation of this peculiar term with the neo-Thomistic
school as well as with the work of Croce and his followers.
56 Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft, 116–22 (B59–B66); Critique of Pure Reason,
168–71.
57 Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft, 155 (B104); Critique of Pure Reason, 211.
58 Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft, 127 (B73); Critique of Pure Reason, 192.
59 Erwin Panofsky, ‘Reflections on Historical Time’, trans. Johanna Bauman, Critical
Inquiry 30 (Summer 2004): 696; ‘Zum Problem der historischen Zeit’ [1927],
Aufsätze zu Grundfragen der Kunstwissenschaft, 78.
60 Kant, Kritk der reinen Vernunft, 192 (B151); Critique of Pure Reason, 256.
176 Notes
Chapter 8
1 Erwin Panofsky, Studies in Iconology (New York and London: Icon, Harper and
Row, 1962 [1939]), 27; Meaning in the Visual Arts (Garden City, NY: Doubleday
Anchor, 1955), 51.
2 Panofsky immigrated permanently to the United States in 1934, Spitzer in 1936
and Auerbach in 1947.
3 Thomas Steinfeld, Der leidenschaftliche Buchhalter, Philologie als Lebensform
(Wien: Carl Hanser Verlag, 2004).
4 Hans Ulrich Gumbrecht, The Powers of Philology: Dynamics of Textual Scholarship
(Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press, 2003).
5 My translation. Jan Assmann, Das kulturelle Gedächtnis. Schrift, Erinnerung und
politische Identität in frühen Hochkulturen [1992] (Munich: Beck, 2013), 19–20.
6 Leo Spitzer, Linguistics and Literary History. Essays in Stylistics (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1948), 15–66, 147–69: ‘Muttersprache und
Muttererziehung’, ‘Ratio > Race’.
7 Erwin Panofsky, ‘Dürers Stellung zur Antike’, Aufsätze zu Grundfragen der
Kunstwissenschaft, ed. Hariolf Oberer and Egon Verhezen (Berlin: B. Hessling,
1964), 247–311; ‘Albrecht Dürer and Classical Antiquity’, in Meaning in the Visual
Arts, 236–94.
8 Erich Auerbach, ‘Philologie der Weltliteratur’ [1955], Gesammelte Aufsätze zur
romanischen Philologie (Bern and Munich: Franke Verlag, 1967), 301–10.
9 Aristotle and David Bloch, Aristotle on Memory and Recollection: Text, Translation,
Interpretation and Reception in Western Scholasticism (Leiden and Boston: Brill,
2007), 1–19.
10 Ibid., 80–2.
11 Ibid., 24–7, 43 [449b10–15; 449b26–8]; Richard Sorabji, Aristotle on Memory
(Providence: Brown University Press, 1972), 13–14.
12 Aristotle and Bloch, Memory and Recollection, 80 (449b24–25, 451a14–16).
13 Ibid., 36–7 (451a20).
Notes 177
zweitens, jene topoi sind Anzeichen einer veränderten Seelenlage; Anzeichen, die
auf keine andere Weise greifbar sind.’
33 Curtius, ‘Antike Pathosformeln in der Literatur des Mittelalters’, Gesammelte
Aufsätze, 23–7. See also Dieter Wuttke (ed.), Kosmopolis der Wissenschaft, E. R.
Curtius und das Warburg Institute. Briefe und andere Dokumente (Baden-Baden:
Koerner Verlag, 1989). Curtius dedicated his Europäische Literatur und Lateinische
Mittelalter to the memory of Aby Warburg.
34 Panofsky, Meaning in the Visual Arts, 1–25.
35 Ibid., 5.
36 Aby Warburg, Werke in einem Band, eds Martin Treml, Sgrid Weigel and Perdita
Ladwig (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Verlag, 2010), 638.
37 Panofsky’s disjunctive method of cultural transformation is highlighted in
Hartmut Böhme et al. (eds), Transformation: Ein Konzept zur Erforschung
kulturellen Wandels (Munich: Fink, 2011), 49.
38 Erwin Panofsky, Renaissance and Renascences in Western Art (New York and
London: Harper & Row Publishers, 1972 [1960]), 113.
39 Erich Auerbach, Mimesis: The Representation of Reality in Western Literature,
trans. W. R. Trask (Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2003),
271–96; Mimesis. Dargestellte Wirklichkeit in der Abendländischen Literature
[1946] (Bern: Francke Verlag, 1959), 285–311. In further citations I give the
English page reference first, followed by the German.
40 Auerbach, Mimesis, 293/279.
41 Auerbach, Mimesis, 292/277: ‘so daß die […] Arbeitsweise Montaignes, die dem
Wandel seines Wesens elastisch folgt, im Grunde eine strenge experimentelle
Methode ist.’ See also Frank-Rutger Hausmann, ‘Michel de Montaigne, Erich
Auerbachs Mimesis und Erich Auerbachs literaturwissenschaftliche Methode’, in
Walter Busch and Gerfart Pickerodt (eds), Wahrnehmen, Lesen, Deuten: Erich
Auerbachs Lektüre der Moderne (Frankfurt am Main: Vitorio Klostermann, 1998),
224–37.
42 Auerbach, Mimesis, 292/80.
43 Panofsky, Aufsätze zu Grundfragen, 247–311; ‘The History and Theory of Human
Proportions as a Reflection of the History of Styles’, in Meaning in the Visual Arts,
55–107.
44 See: Apter, ‘The Human in the Humanities’; Alexander Gelley, ‘Robert Curtius:
Topology and Critical Method’, MLN 81:5 (December 1966), 585–6; Timothy
Hampton, ‘“Comment a nom”: Humanism and Literary Knowledge in Auerbach
and Rabelais’, Representations 119:1 (Summer 2012): 37–59; Spitzer, Linguistics and
Literary History, 24–5.
45 Panofsky, Meaning in the Visual Arts, 2–3.
46 My translation. Curtius, Europäische Literatur, 24–5; quoted also in Wuttke,
Notes 179
Kosmopolis, 368–70: ‘Für die Literatur ist alle Vergangenheit Gegenwart, oder
kann es doch werden. […] Ich kann den Homer und den Platon zu jeder Stunde
vornehmen, ich „habe“ ihn dann und hab ihn ganz. Er existiert in unzähligen
exemplaren. Der Parthenon und die Peterskirche sind nur einmal da, ich kann sie
mir durch Photographien nur partiell und schattenhaft anschaulich machen. Aber
die Photographien geben mir keinen Marmor, ich kann sich nicht abtasten und nicht
darin spazierengehen, wie ich es in der Odysee oder der Divina Commedia kann.
Im Buch ist die Dichtung real gegenwärtig. Einen Tizian „habe“ ich weder in der
Photographie noch in der vollendesten Kopie […] Das Buch ist realer als das Bild […]
Ein Buch ist, abgesehen von allem anderen, ein „Text.“ Man versteht ihn oder versteht
ihn nicht. Er enthält vielleicht „schwierige“ Stellen. Man braucht eine Technik, um sie
zu enträtseln. Sie heißt Philologie […] Die “Kunstwissenschaft” hat es leichter.’
47 In a lecture given at the University of Cologne, 11 December 2012, entitled Anima
forma corporis – der Beitrag des Hylemorphismus zum Leib-Seele-Problem, Andreas
Speer presented a concept of transformative Hylomorphism that inspired the
elaborations of hylomorphism in the present book.
48 Spitzer, Linguistics and Literary History, 6.
49 Panofsky, ‘The Neoplatonic Movement in Florence and North Italy (Bandinelli
and Titian)’, and ‘The Neoplatonic Movement and Michelangelo’, in Studies in
Iconology, 171–230.
50 Erwin Panofsky, Gothic Architecture and Scholasticism (New York: Meridian, 1957
[1951]).
51 Erwin Panofsky, ‘The Concept of Artistic Volition’, trans. Kenneth J. Northcott
and Joel Snyder, Critical Inquiry 8:1 (Autumn 1981): 33; Aufsätze zu Grundfragen,
1034: ‘Die Kunst ist […] die auf gültige Ergebnisse abzielende, verwirklichende
und objektivierende Auseinandersetzung einer formenden Kraft mit einem zu
bewältigenden Stoff.’
52 Panofsky, Gothic Architecture and Scholasticism, 21.
53 Jacques Maritain, ‘Sign and Symbol’, trans. Mary Morris, Journal of the Warburg
Institute 1:1 (July 1937): 7.
54 Panofsky, Meaning in the Visual Arts, 41: ‘Familiarity with objects and events,
familiarity with specific themes and concepts, familiarity with the essential
tendencies of the human mind.’
55 Ibid.
Chapter 9
Verhezen (Berlin: B. Hessling, 1964), 64; ‘On the Relationship of Art History
and Art Theory: Towards the Possibility of a Fundamental System of Concepts
for a Science of Art’, trans. Katharina Lorenz and Jas Elsner, Critical Inquiry 35
(Autumn 2008): 63.
2 Alain Roger, ‘Le schème et le symbole dans l’œuvre de Panofsky’, in Erwin
Panofsky: Cahiers pour un temps (Paris: Centre Georges Pompidou, 1983), 56.
3 Michael Podro, The Critical Historians of Art (New Haven and London: Yale
University Press, 1982), 178, 185–6.
4 See Francis Haskell, History and its Images: Art and the Interpretation of the Past
(New Haven: Yale University Press, 1993).
5 Hans Belting, Bild und Kult: eine Geschichte des Bildes vor dem Zeitalter der Kunst
(Munich: Beck, 1990); Likeness and Presence: A History of the Image before the
Era of Art, trans. Edmund Jephcott (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990);
Moshe Barasch, Icon: Studies in the History of an Idea (New York: New York
University Press, 1992); Marie-José Mondzain, Image, icône, économie: Les sources
byzantines de l’imaginaire contemporain (Paris: Seuil, 1996); Image, Icon, Economy:
The Byzantine Origins of the Contemporary Imaginary, trans. Rico Franses
(Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2005); Charles Barber, Figure and Likeness:
On the Limits of Representation in Byzantine Iconoclasm (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 2002); Bruno Latour and Peter Weibel (eds), Iconoclash: Beyond
the Image Wars in Science, Religion and Art (Cambridge, MA and London: MIT
Press, 2002); Michael Kelly, Iconoclasm in Aesthetics (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2003); W. J. T. Mitchell, ‘Offending Images’, and ‘Totemism,
Fetishism, Idolatry’, in What do Pictures Want? The Lives and Loves of Images
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005), 125–44, 188–96.
6 See also Antony Eastmond and Liz James (eds), Icon and Word: The Power of
Images in Byzantium. Studies presented to Robin Cormack (Aldershot: Ashgate,
2003); Jeff Johnson and Anne McClanan (eds), Negating the Image: Case Studies in
Iconoclasm (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2005).
7 Erwin Panofsky, ‘Iconography and Iconology: An Introduction to the Study
of Renaissance Art’, Meaning in the Visual Arts (Garden City, NY: Doubleday
Anchor, 1955), 38–41; W. S. Heckscher, ‘Die Genesis der Ikonologie’, in Ekkehard
Kammerling (ed.), Ikonographie und Ikonologie – Theorien-Entwicklung-Probleme
(Köln: Dumont Buchverlag 1973), 112–64.
8 See Panofsky, ‘History of Art as a Humanistic Discipline’, Meaning in the Visual
Arts, 25.
9 Erwin Panofsky, Studies in Iconology (New York and London: Icon, Harper and
Row, 1962 [1939]).
10 André Chastel, ‘Erwin Panofsky: Rigueur et Système’, in Louis Marin, Erwin
Panofsky: Cahiers pour un temps, 19.
Notes 181
11 See, for example: Michael Ann Holly, ‘Later Work: An Iconological Perspective’,
in Panofsky and the Foundations of Art History (Ithaca and London: Cornell
University Press 1984), 159–93; Otto Pächt, ‘Kritik der Ikonologie’ [1977], in
Ikonographie und Ikonologie, 353–77.
12 Erich Auerbach, ‘Introduction: Purpose and Method’, Literary Language and its
Public in Late Latin Antiquity and in the Middle Ages (London: Routledge and
Kegan Paul, 1965), 9.
13 On the art historical given, see Johannes Eichner, Das Problem des Gegebenen in
der Kunstgeschichte (Halle: Max Niemeyer, 1914).
14 Central examples of this tendency can be found throughout Panofsky’s Meaning in
the Visual Arts, as well as in his earlier ‘Die Perspektive als “symbolische Form” ’,
Vorträge der Bibliothek Warburg 1924–1925 (Leipzig und Berlin: Bibliothek
Warburg, 1927), reprinted in Aufsätze zu Grundfragen der Kunstwissenschaft,
99–168, translated into English as Perspective as Symbolic Form, trans. C. S. Wood
(New York: Zone Books, 1991).
15 Erwin Panofsky, ‘Zum Problem der Beschreibung und Inhaltsbedeutung
von Werken der bildenden Kunst’ [1932], Aufsätze zu Grundfragen der
Kunstwissenschaft, 93–5; Panofsky, ‘Iconography and Iconology’, 41.
16 F. E. Peters, Greek Philosophical Terms: A Historical Lexicon (New York: New York
University Press, 1967), 37–8.
17 See Thomas Steinfeld, ‘Skepsis. Über August Boeckh, die Wissenschaft der
unendlichen Approximation und das Glück der mangelnden Vollendung’, in Jürgen
Paul Schwindt (ed.), Was ist eine philologische Frage? Beiträge zur Erkundung einer
theoretischen Einstellung (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 2009), 211–26.
18 René Descartes, ‘Regulæ Ad Directionem Ingenii’, Œuvres de Descartes, eds
Ch. Adam and P. Tannery (Paris: Vrin, 1964), vol. X, 468 (Regula XIX).
19 See Dominique Janicaud, Ravaisson et la métaphysique. Une généalogie du
spiritualisme française [1969] (Paris: Vrin, 1997).
20 On dualism in the French spiritualist tradition, see, for example: Janicaud,
Ravaisson et la métaphysique, 201–4; Pierre Montebello, La décomposition de la
pensée – dualité et empirisme transcendantal chez Maine de Biran (Grenoble: Du
Levant, 1994); Frédéric Worms, Bergson et les deux sens de la vie (Paris: Presses
Universitaries de France, 2004).
21 Jean-Luc Marion, De surcroît: Études sur les phénomenes saturés (Paris: Presses
Universitaries de France, 2001), 131; In Excess: Studies of Saturated Phenomena,
trans. Robert Horner and Vincent Berraud (New York: Fordham University Press,
2004), 105.
22 Jean-Luc Marion, La croisée du visible (Paris: Presses Universitaries de France,
1996), 16; The Crossing of the Visible, trans. James K. A. Smith (Stanford: Stanford
University Press, 2004), 4.
182 Notes
23 See Jean-Luc Marion, L’idole et la distance. Cinq études (Paris: Bernard Grasset
1977), 180–253; The Idol and Distance. Five Studies, trans. Thomas A. Carlson
(New York: Fordham University Press 2001), 137–95.
24 Marion, La croisée, 12–13, 19, 26–7; Crossing, 2, 6, 11–12. On this point Marion’s
views stand in one line with those of Hubert Damisch in his L’origine de la
perspective (Paris: Flammarion, 1987); The Origin of Perspective, trans. John
Goodman (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995).
25 These two notions are taken from Karl Mannheim. See Panofsky, ‘Zum Problem
der Beschreibung und Inhaltsbedeutung’, 93.
26 Ibid., 95.
27 Erwin Panofsky, Renaissance and Renascences in Western Art (New York and
London: Harper & Row Publishers, 1972 [1960]), 120.
28 Marion, La croisée, 75; Crossing, 41.
29 Marion, La croisée, 68–73; Crossing, 37–9.
30 Marion, La croisée, 72; Crossing, 39.
31 Panofsky, ‘Perspektive als „symbolische Form”’, 123–4; Perspective as Symbolic
Form, 67–8.
32 Panofsky, ‘Perspektive als «symbolische Form’, 125–6; Perspective as Symbolic
Form, 71.
33 Panofsky, ‘History of Art as a Humanistic Discipline’, 1.
34 Ibid., 2.
35 Erwin Panofsky, ‘Der Begriff des Kunstwollens’ [1920], Aufsätze zu Grundfragen
der Kunstwissenschaft, 29–43; ‘The Concept of Artistic Volition’, trans. Kenneth J.
Northcott and Joel Snyder, Critical Inquiry 8:1 (Autumn 1981): 17–33.
36 See also Allister Neher, ‘“The Concept of Kunstwollen”, Neo-Kantianism, and
Erwin Panofsky’s Early Art Theoretical Essays’, Word and Image 20:1 (January–
March 2004): 41–51.
37 Panofsky, ‘Perspektive als „symbolische Form” ’, 122; Perspective as Symbolic Form,
65.
38 Panofsky, ‘Perspektive als „symbolische Form” ’, 123; Perspective as Symbolic Form,
67.
39 Panofsky, ‘Zum Problem der Beschreibung und Inhaltsbedeutung’, 92. Panofsky’s
reference to Heidegger is to the latter’s Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik (1929).
40 Panofsky, ‘Iconography and Iconology’, 40.
41 Panofsky, ‘Perspektive als “symbolische Form” ’, 123; Perspective as Symbolic Form,
67.
42 Panofsky, ‘Iconography and Iconology’, 28.
43 Panofsky, ‘Reflections on Historical Time’ [c. 1927], trans. J. Baumann, Critical
Inquiry 30 (Summer 2004): 699; ‘Zum Problem der historischen Zeit’, Aufsätze zur
Grundfragen der Kunstwissenschaft, 81.
Notes 183
Conclusion
10 Karen A. Lang, Chaos and Cosmos: On the Image in Aesthetics and Art History
(Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2006), 35–8.
11 Giambatistta Vico, ‘On Verum and Factum’, in Selected Writings, ed. and trans.
Leon Pompa (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 50–6.
12 Erich Auerbach, Mimesis. Dargestellte Wirklichkeit in der Abendländischen
Literature (Bern: Francke Verlag, 1946), 497; Mimesis: The Representation of Reality
in Western Literature, trans. W. R. Trask (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
2003), 557. On Auerbach’s relation to historicism, see Leopold Waizbort, ‘Erich
Auerbach im Kontext der Historismusdebatte’, in Karlheinz Barck and Martin
Treml eds, Erich Auerbach – Geschichte und Aktualität (Berlin: Kulturverlag
Kadmos, 2007), 281–97.
13 Leopold von Ranke, Geschichten der romanischen und germanischen Völker von
1494 bis 1514 [1824] (Leipzig: Duncker und Humblot 1874), VII.
14 Wilhelm Windelband, ‘Geschichte und Naturwissenschaft (Straßburger
Rektoratsrede 1894)’, in Hans Ludwig Ollig (ed.), Neukantisniamus. Texte
(Stuttgart: Phillip Reclam, 1982), 167; ‘Rectoral Address: History and Natural
Science’, trans. Guy Oakes, History and Theory 19:2 (February 1980): 176.
15 Panofsky, ‘The History of Art as a Humanistic Discipline’, in Meaning in the Visual
Arts, 3.
16 Erwin Panofsky, ‘Abbot Suger of St.-Denis’ [1946], in Meaning in the Visual Arts,
108–45; ‘Galileo as a Critic of the Arts: Aesthetic Attitude and Scientific Thought’,
Isis 47:1 (March 1956): 3–15; ‘Erasmus and the Visual Arts’, Journal of the Warburg
and the Courtauld Institutes 32 (1969): 200–27.
Bibliography
Auerbach, Erich, ‘Vico and Aesthetic Historism’, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism
8:2 (December 1949): 110–18.
Auerbach, Erich, Literatursprache und Publikum in der lateinischen Spätantike und im
Mittelalter (Bern: Francke, 1958).
Auerbach, Erich, Mimesis. Dargestellte Wirklichkeit in der Abendländischen Literature
(Bern: Francke Verlag, 1959 [1946]).
Auerbach, Erich, Literary Language and its Public in Late Latin Antiquity and in the
Middle Ages (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1965).
Auerbach, Erich, ‘Typological Symbolism in Medieval Literature’, Yale French Studies 9
(New York: Kraus Reprint Corporation, 1965), 3–9.
Auerbach, Erich, Gesammelte Aufsätze zur romanischen Philologie (Bern and Munich:
Franke Verlag, 1967).
Auerbach, Erich, ‘Philology and Weltliterature’, trans. Edward Said, The Centennial
Review 8:1 (Winter 1969): 1–17.
Auerbach, Erich, Scenes from the Drama of European Literature. Six Essays
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984).
Auerbach, Erich, Mimesis: The Representation of Reality in Western Literature, trans.
W. R. Trask (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2003).
Bacher, Ernst, ed., Kunstwerk oder Denkmal? Alois Riegls Schriften zur Denkmalpflege
(Vienna: Böhlau, 1995).
Badt, Kurt, Raumphantasien und Raumillusionen. Das Wesen der Plastik (Köln:
Dumont, 1963).
Baldinucci, Filippo, Vita des Gio. Lorenzo Bernini, mit Übersetzung und Kommentar von
Alois Riegl, eds Arthur Burda and Oskar Pollak (Wien: Verlag von Anton Schroll,
1912).
Bamberger, Fritz, Untersuchungen zur Entstehung des Wertproblems in der Philosophie
des 19. Jahrhunderts, I – Lotze (Halle a.s.: Neimeyer Verlag, 1924).
Barasch, Moshe, Icon: Studies in the History of an Idea (New York and London: New
York University Press, 1992).
Barber, Charles, Figure and Likeness: On the Limits of Representation in Byzantine
Iconoclasm (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2002).
Barck, Karlheinz and Martin Treml, eds, Erich Auerbach – Geschitchte und Aktualität
eines europäischen Philologen (Berlin: Kulturverlag Kadmos, 2007).
Bätschmann, Oskar, ‘Logos in der Geschichte. Erwin Panofsky Ikonologie’, in Lorenz
Dittmann, ed., Kategorien und Methoden der deutschen Kunstgeschichte 1900–1930
(Stuttgart: Steiner, 1985), 89–112.
Bätschmann, Oskar, ‘“Pan deus Arcadiæ venit.” Panofsky und Poussin’, in Bruno
Reudenbach, ed., Erwin Panofsky – Beiträge des Symposions Hamburg 1992 (Berlin:
Akademie Verlag, 1994), 71–82.
Bauch, Bruno, Wahrheit, Wert und Wirklichkeit (Leipzig: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1923).
Bauch, Bruno, Die Idee (Leipzig: Verlag Emmanuel Reinicke, 1926).
Baxandall, Michael, Giotto and the Orators: Humanist Observers of Painting in Italy and
Bibliography 187
the Discovery of Pictorial Composition 1350–1450 (Oxford and New York: Oxford
University Press, 1971).
Baxandall, Michael, Painting and Experience in Fifteenth-Century Italy (Oxford and
New York: Oxford University Press, 1972).
Bayer, Thora Ilin and Donald Phillip Verene, Keys to the New Science: Translations,
Commentaries and Essays (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2009).
Belting, Hans, Bild und Kult: eine Geschichte des Bildes vor dem Zeitalter der Kunst
(Munich: Beck, 1990).
Belting, Hans, Likeness and Presence: A History of the Image before the Era of Art, trans.
Edmund Jephcott (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990).
Benjamin, Walter, Gesammelte Schriften, ed, Hella Tiedemann-Bartels (Frankfurt am
Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1972).
Benjamin, Walter, Das Passagen Werk, ed. Rolf Tiedman, 2 vols (Frankfurt am Main:
Suhrkamp Verlag, 1981).
Benne, Christian, Nietzsche und die historisch-kritische Philologie (Berlin: Walter de
Gruyter, 2005).
Bergson, Henri, Œuvres (Essai sur les données immédiates de la conscience [1888],
Matiere et mémoire [1896], Le rire [1900], L’évolution créatrice [1906], L’énérgie
spirituelle [1919], Les deux sources de la morale et de la religion [1932], La pensée
et le mouvant [1934]), ed. André Robinet (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France,
1959).
Bergson, Henri, Matière et Mémoire [1896] (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France,
2012).
Beyrodt, Wolfgang, ed., Kunsttheorie und Kunstgeschichte des 19. Jahrhunderts in
Deutschland, Texte und Dokumente (Stuttgart: Reclam, 1982).
de Biran, Maine, Influence de l’habitude sur la faculté de penser (Paris: Presses
Universitaires de France, 1954 [c. 1799–1802]).
Boeckh, August, Enzyklopädie und Methodenlehre der philologischen Wissenchaften
[c. 1877], vol. 1, Formale Theorie der philologischen Wissenschaft (Stuttgart: B. G.
Teubner, 1966).
Boehm, Gottfried, Gabriele Brandtstetter and Achatz von Müller, eds, Figur
und Figuration: Studien zu Wahrnehmung und Wissen (Munich: Fink Verlag,
2007).
Böhme, Hartmut, Lutz Bergemann, Martin Dönike, Albert Schirmeister, Georg
Toepfer, Walter Marco and Julia Weitbrecht, eds, Transformation: Ein Konzept zur
Erforschung kulturellen Wandels (Paderbon: Fink, 2011).
Bloch, David, ed., Aristotle on Memory and Recollection. Text, Translation,
Interpretation and Reception in Western Scholasticism (Leiden and Boston: Brill
2007).
Breen, Katharine, Imagining an English Reading Public 1150–1400 (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2010).
188 Bibliography
Flashar, Hellmut, Karlfried Grüder and Axel E. A. Horstmann, eds, Philologie und
Hermeneutik im 19. Jahrhundert (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1979).
Flashar, Hellmut, Mayotte Bollack and Heinz Wismann, eds, Philologie et
herméneutique au 19ieme siècle (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1983).
Focillon Henri, Vie des forms [1934] (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1995).
Fontanier, Pierre, Les figures du discours (Paris: Flammarion, 1968).
Forgione, Nancy, ‘“The Shadow Only”: Shadow and Silhouette in Late Nineteenth-
Century Paris’, Art Bulletin 81:3 (September 1999): 490–512.
Foucault, Michel, Les mots et les choses, une archéologie des sciences humaines (Paris:
Éditions Gallimard, 1966).
Francastel, Pierre, La réalité figurative. Éléments structurels de sociologie de l’art (Paris:
Gonthier, 1965).
Francastel, Pierre, La figure et le lieu. L’ordre visuel du Quatrocento (Paris: Gallimard, 1967).
Ginzburg, Carlo, Clues, Myths, and the Historical Method (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins
University Press, 1992 [1989]).
Gjesdal, Kristin, ‘Hermeneutics and Philology: A Reconsideration of Gadamer’s
Critique of Schleiermacher’, Journal of the History of Philosophy 14:1 (2006): 133–56.
Gelley, Alexander, ‘Robert Curtius: Topology and Critical Method’, MLN 81:5
(December 1966): 579–94.
Gellrich, Jesse M., ‘Figura, Allegory and the Question of History’, in Seth Lerer, ed.,
Literary History and the Challenge of Philology: The Legacy of Erich Auerbach
(Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1996), 107–23.
Genette, Gérard, Figures I (Paris: Éditions du Seuil, 1966).
Gildenhard, Ingo and M. Ruehl, eds, Out of Arcadia: Classics and Politics in Germany
in the Age of Burckhardt, Nietzsche and Wilamowitz (London: Institute of Classical
Studies, 2003).
Gilson, Étienne, Le réalisme méthodique (Paris: Pierre Téqui éditeur, 2007 [1935]).
Gilson, Étienne, Introduction aux arts du beau (Paris: Vrin, 1998).
Glucker, John, From Sylvester to the Elders of Zion: Introduction to Philology [in
Hebrew] (Jerusalem: Carmel, 2011).
Gombrich, Ernst, Aby Warburg: An Intellectual Biography (London: Warburg Institute,
1970).
Gombrich, Ernst, Symbolic Images: Studies in the Art of the Renaissance 2 (London:
Phaidon Press, 1972).
Green, Geoffrey, Literary Criticism and the Structure of History: Erich Auerbach and Leo
Spitzer (Lincoln and London: University of Nebraska Press, 1982).
Greenberg, Clement, The Collected Essays and Criticism, ed. John O’Brian (Chicago and
London: Chicago University Press, 1988).
Grosse, Ernst Ulrich, ‘Curtius et les topoi’, in Jeanne Bem et André Guyaux, eds, Ernst
Robert Curtius et l’idée d’Europe (Paris: Champion 1995), 91–106.
Gründer, Karlfried, ed., Der Streit um Nietzsches ‘Geburt der Tragödie’: Die Schriften
von E. Rohde, R. Wagner, U. v. Wilamowitz-Moellendorff (Hildesheim: Olms, 1989).
Bibliography 191
Gubser, Michael, Time’s Visible Surface: Alois Riegl and the Discourse on History and
Temporality in Fin-de-Siècle Vienna (Detroit: Wayne State University Press, 2006).
Guillemin, Anna, ‘The Style of Linguistics: Aby Warburg, Karl Voßler, and Hermann
Osthoff ’, Journal of the History of Ideas 69:4 (October 2008): 605–26.
Gumbrecht, Hans Ulrich, The Powers of Philology: Dynamics of Textual Scholarship
(Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press, 2003).
Gumbrecht, Hans Ulrich, ‘Was Erich Auerbach fuer eine „Philologische Frage“ hielt’, in
Jürgen Paul Schwindt, ed., Was ist eine philologische Frage? Beiträge zu Erkundung
einer theoretischen Einstellung (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 2009), 275–87.
Gurd, A., Iphigenias at Aulis. Textual Multiplicity, Radical Philology (Ithaca and
London: Cornell University Press, 2005).
Hampton, Timothy, ‘“Comment a nom”: Humanism and Literary Knowledge in
Auerbach and Rabelais”, Representations 119:1 (Summer 2012): 37–59,
Harpham, Geoffrey Galt, ‘Roots, Races and the Return to Philology’, Representations
106 (Spring 2009): 34–62.
Hart, Joan, ‘Erwin Panofsky and Karl Manheim: A Dialogue on Interpretation’, Critical
Inquiry 19 (Spring 1993): 534–66.
Hartog, François, ‘The Double Fate of the Classics’, Critical Inquiry 35 (Summer 2009):
964–79.
Hasenmueller, Christine, ‘Panofsky, Iconography, and Semiotics’, The Journal of
Aesthetics and Art Criticism 36:3 (Spring 1978): 289–301.
Haskell, Francis, History and its Images: Art and the Interpretation of the Past (New
Haven: Yale University Press, 1993).
Hegel, G. W. F., Wissenschaft der Logik, ed. Georg Lasson, 2 vols (Leipzig: Felix Meiner
Verlag, 1951).
Heller, Dorothee, Wörter und Sachen: Grundlagen einer Historiographie der Fachsprache
Forschung (Tübingen: Gunther Narr Verlag, 1998).
Herder, Johann Gottfried von, Plastik (Riga: Johann Friedrich Hartknoch, 1778).
Herder, Johann Gottfried von, Sculpture: Some Observations on Shape and Form from
Pygmalion’s Creative Dread, trans. Jason Geiger (Chicago and London: University of
Chicago Press, 2002).
Hiebsch, Sabine, Auerbach Figura ecclesiae: Lea und Rachel in Luthers Genesispredigten
(Münster: Lit Verlag, 2002).
Hildebrand, Adolf von, Das Problem der Form in der Bildenden Kunst [1901]
(Strassburg: Heitz & Mündel, 1918 [4 Aufl.]).
Höffe, Ottfried, ed., Aristoteles-Lexikon (Stuttgart: Alfred Kröner Verlag, 2005).
Holdheim, W. Wolfgang, ‘The Hermeneutic Significance of Auerbach’s Ansatz’, New
Literary History 16:3 (Spring 1985): 627–31.
Holly, Michael Ann, Erwin Panofsky and the Foundations of Art History (Ithaca: Cornell
University Press, 1984).
Holly, Michael Ann, Past Looking: Historical Imagination and the Rhetoric of the Image
(Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1996).
192 Bibliography
Holquist, Michael, ‘The Last European: Erich Auerbach as Precursor in the History of
Cultural Criticism’, Modern Language Quarterly 54:3 (September 1993): 371–91.
Holzhey, Helmut, ‘Vom Nutzen und Nachteil des Wertbegriffs in der
Kulturphilosophie’, in Peter Ulrich Merz Benz und Ursula Renz, eds, Ethik oder
Ästhetik? Zur Aktualität der neukantianisehen Kulturphilosophie (Würzburg:
Königshausen und Neumann, 2004), 71–86.
Hummel, Pascal, Philologus auctor: le philologist et son œuvre (Bern, Berlin and
Brussels: P. Lang, 2003).
Hurttig, Marcus Andrew, ed., Die entfesselte Antike. Aby Warburg und die Geburt der
Pathosformel in Hamburg (Hamburg: Hamburg Kunsthalle, 2011).
Hurttig, Marcus Andrew and Thomas Ketelsen, eds, Die Entfesselte Antike, Aby
Warburg und die Geburt der Pathosformel (Köln: Wallraf-Richartz-Museum and
Fondation Corboud, 2012).
Iversen, Margaret, Alois Riegl: Art History and Theory (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,
1993).
Janicaud, Dominique, Ravaisson et la métaphysique. Une généalogie du spiritualisme
français (Paris: Vrin 1997 [1969]).
Jay, Martin, Downcast Eyes: The Denigration of Vision in Twentieth-Century French
Thought (Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1993).
Jeff Johnson and Anne McClanan, eds, Negating the Image: Case Studies in Iconoclasm
(Aldershot: Ashgate, 2005).
Jesinghausen-Lauster, Martin, Die Suche nach der symbolischen Form. Der Kreis um die
kulturwissenschaftliche Bibliothek Warburg (Baden-Baden: Verlag Valentin Koerner,
1985).
Johnson, Jeff and Anne McClanan, eds, Negating the Image: Case Studies in Iconoclasm
(Aldershot: Ashgate, 2005).
Kaemmerling, Ekkehard, ed., Ikonographie und Ikonologie. Theorien. Entwicklung.
Probleme (Köln: Dumont Buchverlag, 1973).
Kant, Immanuel, Kritik der reinen Vernunft (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 2003 [1781]).
Kant, Immanuel, Kritik der Urteilskraft (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 2003 [1790]).
Kant, Immanuel, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood (New
York: Cambridge University Press, 2007).
Kant, Immanuel, Critique of the Power of Judgment, trans. Paul Guyer and Eric
Matthews (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009).
Kany, Roland, Mnemosyne als Programm. Geschichte, Errinerung und die Andacht zum
Unbedeutenden uim Werk von Usener, Warburg und Benjamin (Tübingen: Niemeyer,
1987).
Kelly, Michael, Iconoclasm in Aesthetics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2003).
Krauss, Rosalind, The Optical Unconscious (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993).
Kreft, Christine, Adolph Goldschmidt und Aby M. Warburg. Freundschaft und
kunstwissenschaftliches Engagement (Weimar: VDG, 2010).
Bibliography 193
Man, Paul de, The Resistance to Theory (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,
1986).
Mandowsky, Erna, Untersuchungen zur Iconologie des Cesare Ripa, Dissertation,
Philosophisches Fakultät Hamburg (Hamburg: H. Proctor, 1934).
Marin, Louis, ‘Panofsky et Poussin en Arcadie’, in Erwin Panofsky. Cahiers pour un
temps (Paris: Centre Georges Pompidou, 1983), 151–66.
Marin, Louis, ‘La figurabilité du visuel: la Veronique ou la question du Portrait à Port
Royal’, Nouvelle Revue de la psychanalyse 35 (1987): 51–65.
Marin, Louis, ‘Figurability of the Visual: The Veronica or the Question of the Portrait
at Port Royal’, New Literary History 22:2 (Spring 1991): 281–96.
Marion, Jean-Luc, Sur L’ontologie grise de Descartes (Paris: Vrin, 1975).
Marion, Jean-Luc, L’idole et la distance. Cinq études (Paris: Bernard Grasset, 1977).
Marion, Jean-Luc, La croisée du visible (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1996).
Marion, Jean-Luc, De surcroît: Études sur les phénomenes saturés (Paris: Presses
Universitaries de France, 2001).
Marion, Jean-Luc, The Idol and Distance. Five Studies, trans. Thomas A. Carlson (New
York: Fordham University Press, 2001).
Marion, Jean-Luc, In Excess: Studies of Saturated Phenomena, trans. Robert Horner and
Vincent Berraud (New York: Fordham University Press, 2004).
Marion, Jean-Luc, The Crossing of the Visible, trans. James K. A. Smith (Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 2004).
Maritain, Jacques, ‘Sign and Symbol’, trans. Mary Morris, Journal of the Warburg
Institute 1:1 (July 1937): 1–11.
Marshall, David L., Vico and the Transformation of Rhetoric in Early Modern Europe
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010).
Mazzocut-Mis, Maddalena, Forma come destino, Henri Focillon et il pensiero
morfologico nell’estetica francese della prima metà del Novecento (Florence: Alinea
Editrice, 1998).
Menge-Güthling, Hermann, Enzyklopädisches Wörterbuch der griechischen und
deutschen Sprache, vol. I (Berlin: Langenscheid, 1962).
Meringer, R., W., Meyer-Lücke, R. Much, J. J. Mikkola and M. Murko, eds, Wörter
und Sachen: Kultuhistorische Zeitschrift für Sprach- und Sachforschung, vol. 1
(Heidelberg: Carl Winters Universitätsbuchhandlung, 1909).
Meur, Diane, ‘Auerbach und Vico: die unausgesprochene Auseinandersetzung’, in
Karlheinz Barck and Martin Treml, eds. Erich Auerbach – Geschitchte und Aktualität
eines europäischen Philologen (Berlin: Kulturverlag Kadmos, 2007), 57–70.
Michaud, Phillipe-Alain, Aby Warburg et l’image en mouvement (Paris: Macula,
1998).
Michaud, Phillipe-Alain, Aby Warburg and the Image in Motion, trans. Sophie Hawkes
(New York: Zone Books, 2007).
Mitchell, W. J. T., Iconology: Image, Text, Ideology (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1986).
Bibliography 195
Panofsky, Erwin, Studies in Iconology (New York and London: Icon, Harper and Row,
1962 [1939]).
Panofsky, Erwin, Aufsätze zu Grundfragen der Kunstwissenschaft, ed. Hariolf Oberer
und Egon Verhezen (Berlin: B. Hessling, 1964).
Panofsky, Erwin, Idea: A Concept in Art Theory, trans. Joseph J. S. Peake (New York
and London: Icon Editions, 1968).
Panofsky, Erwin, ‘Probleme der Kunstgeschichte’ [1927], Idea VII (1988): 7–14.
Panofsky, Erwin, ‘Wilhelm Vöge: A Biographical Memoir’, trans. Ernest C. Hassold, The
Art Journal 28:1 (Autumn 1968): 27–37.
Panofsky, Erwin, ‘Erasmus and the Visual Arts’, Journal of the Warburg and the
Courtauld Institutes 32 (1969): 200–27.
Panofsky, Erwin, Renaissance and Renascences in Western Art (New York and London:
Harper & Row Publishers, 1972 [1960]).
Panofsky, Erwin, Idea – Ein Beitrag zur Begriffsgeschichte der älteren Kunsttheorie
(Berlin: Verlag Bruno Hessling GMBH, 1975 [1924]).
Panofsky, Erwin, ‘The Concept of Artistic Volition’, trans. Kenneth J. Northcott and Joel
Snyder, Critical Inquiry 8:1 (Autumn 1981): 17–33.
Panofsky, Erwin, Perspective as Symbolic Form, trans. Christopher Wood (New York:
Zone Books, 1991 [1927]).
Panofsky, Erwin, Three Essays on Style, ed. Irvin Lavin (Cambridge and London:
Cambridge University Press, 1995).
Panofsky, Erwin, Deutschsprachige Aufstäze, vol. I and II, eds Martin Warnke and
Karen Michels (Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 1998).
Panofsky, Erwin, Korrespondenz 1910–1968. Eine kommentierte Auswahl in fünf
Bänden, ed. Dieter Wuttke (Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz Verlag, 2001).
Panofsky, Erwin, ‘Reflections on Historical Time’, trans. Johanna Bauman, Critical
Inquiry 30 (Summer 2004): 691–701.
Panofsky, Erwin, ‘On the Relationship of Art History and Art Theory: Towards the
Possibility of a Fundamental System of Concepts for a Science of Art’, trans.
Katharina Lorenz and Jas Elsner, Critical Inquiry 35 (Autumn 2008): 43–71.
Panofsky, Erwin, ‘On the Problem of Describing and Interpreting Works of the Visual
Arts’, trans. Jas Elsner and Katharina Lorenz, Critical Inquiry 38:3 (Spring 2012):
476–80.
Panofsky, Erwin, and Fritz Saxl, Dürers “Melencolia I”. Eine Quellen- und
Typengeschichliche Untersuchung (Berlin: Studien der Bibliothek Warburg (2), 1923).
Pascal, Blaise, Pensées (Paris: Librairie Général Française, 2000).
Peters, F. E., Greek Philosophical Terms: A Historical Lexicon (New York: New York
University Press, 1967).
Pliny the Elder, Natural History IX, trans. H. Rackham (Cambridge, MA and London:
Harvard University Press, 1952).
Podro, Michael, The Critical Historians of Art (New Haven and London: Yale University
Press, 1982).
Bibliography 197
Polanyi, Michael, The Tacit Dimension (New York: Anchor Books, 1967).
Porter, James I., Nietzsche and the Philology of the Future (Stanford: Stanford University
Press, 2000).
Porter, James I., ‘Erich Auerbach and the Judaizing of Philology’, Critical Inquiry 35
(Autumn 2008): 115–47.
Pöschl, Viktor, ‘Nietzsche und die klassische Philologie‘, in Hellmut Flashar, Mayotte
Bollack and Heinz Wissman, eds, Philologie et Hermeneutik um 19. Jarhundert
(Göttingen: Wandenhöck and Ruprecht, 1983), 141–55.
Rampley, Matthew, ‘From Symbol to Allegory: Aby Warburg’s Theory of Art’, The Art
Bulletin 79 (March 1997): 41–55.
Rampley, Matthew, The Remembrance of Things Past: On Aby Warburg and Walter
Benjamin (Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz Verlag, 2000).
Rancière, Jacques, Le partage du sensible-esthétique et politique (Paris: La fabrique-
éditions, 2000).
Rancière, Jacques, Le destin des images (Paris: La frabrique-éditions, 2003).
Rancière, Jacques, Malaise dans l’esthétique (Paris: Galilée, 2004).
Ranke, Leopold von, Geschichten der romanischen und germanischen Völker von 1494
bis 1514 (Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot, 1874 [1824]).
Raulff, Ulrich, Wilde Energien. Vier Versuche zu Aby Warburg (Goettingen: Wallstein
Verlag, 2003).
Ravaisson, Félix, De l’habitude [1838], Métaphysique et morale [1893] (Paris: Presses
Universitaires de France, 1999).
Reynolds Cordilione, Diana, ‘The Advantages and Disadvantages of Art History
of Life: Alois Riegl and Historicism’, Journal of Art Historiography 3 (December
2010). Available online: http://arthistoriography.files.wordpress.com/2011/02/
media_183170_en.pdf (accessed 14 July 2016).
Rickert, Heinrich, Kulturwissenschaft und Naturwissenschaft (Freiburg, Leipzig und
Tübingen: Verlag von J. C. B Mohr [Paul Siebeck], 1899).
Rickert, Heinrich, Allgemeine Grundlegung der Philosophie (Tübingen: Verlag von
J. C. B. Mohr [Paul Siebeck], 1921).
Rickert, Heinrich, Die Probleme der Geschichtsphilosophie – eine Einführung
(Heidelberg: Carl Winters Universitätsbuchhandlung, 1924 [1904]).
Ricoeur, Paul, La mémoire, l’histoire, l’oubli (Paris: Seuil, 2000).
Rieber, Audrey, Art, histoire et signification. Un essai d’épistémologie d’histoire de l’art
autour de l’iconologie d’Erwin Panofsky (Paris: L’Harmattan, 2012).
Rieger, Stefan, ‘Richard Semon und/oder Aby Warburg. Mneme und/ode Mnemosyne’,
Deutsche Vierteljahrsschrift für Literaturwissenschaft und Geistesgeschichte 72 (1998):
245–63.
Riegl, Alois, Spätromische Kunstindustrie (Vienna: Der Österr Staatsdruckerei in Wien,
1926 [1901]).
Riegl, Alois, Gesammelte Aufsätze (Augsburg-Wien: Benno Filser Verlag, 1928).
Riegl, Alois, Historische Grammatik der bildenden Künste (Graz-Köln: Boehlau, 1966).
198 Bibliography
Riegl, Alois, Late Roman Art-Industry, trans. R. Winks (Rome: Giorgio Betschneider
Editore, 1985).
Riegl, Alois, ‘The Modern Cult of Monuments: Its Essence and its Developments’, in
Nicholas Stanley Price, ed., Historical Philosophical Issues in the Conservation of
Cultural Heritage, trans. Karin Bruckner and Karen Williams (Harvard: Paul Getty
Trust, 1996), 69–83.
Riegl, Alois, Historical Grammar of the Visual Arts, trans. Jacqueline E. Jung (New
York: Zone Books, 2004).
Riegl, Alois, Die Gestaltungsprincipien Michelangelos, besonders in ihrem Verhaeltnis
zu denen Raffaels [1920], ed. Gerda Panofsky (Berlin and Boston: De Gruyter,
2014).
Ripa, Cesare, Iconologia. Overo descrittione di diverse imagini cavate dall’antichità, e di
propria invention (Hildesheim: Olms, 1984 [c. 1603]).
Rodi, Frithjof, ‘“Erkenntnis der Erkannten” – August Boeckhs Grundformel der
hermeneutischen Wissenschaften’, in Hellmut Flashar, Mayotte Bollack and Heinz
Wissman, eds, Philologie et Hermeneutik II (Göttingen: Wandenhöck and Ruprecht,
1983), 68–83.
Roger, Alain, ‘Le schème et le symbole dans l’œuvre de Panofsky’, in Erwin Panofsky.
Cahiers pour un temps (Paris: Centre Georges Pompidou, 1983).
Rosenblum, Robert, ‘The Origin of Painting: A Problem in the Iconography of
Romantic Classicism’, Art Bulletin 39:4 (December 1957): 279–90.
Rückert, Claudia, ‘Adolph Goldschmidt im Jahre 1928 – Lehrer, Organisator,
Netzwerker’, in Horst Bredekamp and Adam S. Labuda, eds, In der Mitte Berlins,
200 Jahre Kunstgeschichte an der Humboldt-Universität (Berlin: Gebr. Mann Verlag,
2010), 103–16.
Said, Edward W., ‘Renan’s Philological Laboratory’, in Hellmut Flashar, Mayotte Bollack
and Heinz Wismann, eds, Philologie et herméneutique au 19ieme siècle (Göttingen:
Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 1983), 186–214.
Said, Edward W., ‘Erich Auerbach, Critic of the Earthly World’, Boundary 2 31:2
(Summer 2004): 11–34.
Sauerlander, Willibald, ‘From Stilus to Style: Reflections on the Fate of a Notion’, Art
History 6:3 (September 1983): 253–70,
Sauerlander, Willibald, ‘En face des barbares et à écart des dévots, l’humanisme
médiéval d’Henri Focillon’, in Mathias Waschek, ed., Relire Focillon (Paris: Louvre et
ensb-a, 1996), 53–74.
Schäfer, Hans-Michael, Die Kulturwissenschaftliche Bibliothek Warburg: Geschichte und
Persönlichkeiten der Bibliothek Warburg (Berlin: Logos Verlag, 2005).
Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph von, Schriften, vol. 1 (Frankfurt am Main:
Suhrkamp, 1985).
Schlanger, Judith, Les métaphores de l’organisme (Paris: L’Harmattan, 1971).
Schlegel, Friedrich, Kritische Ausgabe, ed. Ernst Behler (Paderborn, München, Wien:
Schönigh, 1959–90).
Bibliography 199
Schlosser, Julius von, Die Kunstliteratur: ein Handbuch zur Quellenkunde der neueren
Kunstgeschichte (Wien: Schroll, 1924).
Schlosser, Julius von, Stilgeschichte und Sprachgeschichte der bildenden Kunst. Ein
Rückblick (München: Verlag d. Bayerische Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1935).
Schmidt, Peter, Aby M. Warburg und die Ikonologie (Bamberg: Stefen Wendel Verlag,
1989).
Schwartz, Frederic J., Blind Spots: Critical Theory and the History of Art in Twentieth-
century Germany (New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 2005),
Schwindt, Jürgen Paul, ed., Was ist eine philologische Frage? Beiträge zu Erkundung
einer theoretischen Einstellung (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 2009).
Sears, Elizabeth, ‘Warburg Institute Archive: General Correspondence’, Common
Knowledge, eds A. Grafton and J. F. Hamburger, 18:1, special issue (Winter 2012):
32–49.
Seidel, Hermann, Wert und Wirklichkeit in der Philosophie Heinrich Rickerts (Bonn:
H. Bouvier Verlag, 1968).
Senderowicz, Yaron, ‘Figurative Synthesis and Synthetic a priori Knowledge’, The
Review of Metaphysics 57 (June 2004): 755–85.
Settis, Salvatore, ‘Pathos ed Ethos, morfologia e funzione’, Moderna. Semestrale di
Teoria e Critica della Letteratura 6:2 (2004): 23–34.
Simmel, Georg, Brücke und Tür. Essays des Philosophen zur Geschichte, Kunst, Religion
und Gesellschaft, ed. Michael Landmann (Stuttgart: Koehler, 1957).
Simmel, Georg, Kant, Die Probleme der Geschichtsphilosophie [1905/07], eds Guy Oaks
and Kurt Röttgers (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1997).
Simondon, Gilbert, L’individuation à la lumière des notions de forme et d’information
[1957] (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1964).
Sluga, Hans, Heidegger’s Crisis: Philosophy and Politics in Nazi Germany (Cambridge,
MA and London: Harvard University Press, 1993).
Sorabji, Richard, Aristotle on Memory (Providence: Brown University Press, 1972).
Speer, Andreas, ‘Beyond Art and Beauty: In Search of the Object of Philosophical
Aesthetics’, International Journal of Philosophical Studies 8:1 (2000): 73–88.
Spitzer, Leo, Linguistics and Literary History. Essays in Stylistics (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1948).
Steinfeld, Thomas, Der leidenschaftliche Buchhalter, Philologie als Lebensform (Wien:
Carl Hanser Verlag, 2004).
Stierle, Karlheinz, ‘Altertumswissenschaftliche Hermeneutik und die Entstehung der
Neuphilologie’, in Hellmut Flashar, Mayotte Bollack and Heinz Wissman, eds,
Philologie et Hermeneutik II (Göttingen: Wandenhöck and Ruprecht, 1983), 260–88.
Stokes, Adrian, Critical Writings (London: Thames & Hudson, 1978).
Strohschneider-Kohrs, Ingrid, ‘Textauslegung und hermeneutischer Zirkel – Zur
Innovation des Interpretationsbegriffes von August Boeckh’, in Hellmut Flashar,
Mayotte Bollack and Heinz Wismann, eds, Philologie et herméneutique au 19ieme
siècle (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 1983), 84–102
200 Bibliography
Barck and Martin Treml, eds, Erich Auerbach – Geschichte und Aktualität (Berlin:
Kulturverlag Kadmos, 2007), 281–97.
Walzer, Richard, ‘New Light on the Arabic Translations of Aristotle’, Oriens 6:1 (June
1953): 91–142.
Warburg, Aby, The Renewal of Pagan Antiquity, trans. David Britt (Los Angeles: Getty
Research Institute, 1999).
Warburg, Aby, Werke in einem Band, eds Martin Treml, Sigrid Weigel and Perdita
Ladwig (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Verlag, 2010).
White, Hayden, Figural Realism: Studies in the Mimesis Effect (Baltimore and London:
Johns Hopkins University Press, 1999).
Wiehl, Reiner, ‘Schleiermachers Hermeneutik – Ihre Bedeutung für die Philologie
in Theorie und Praxis’, in Flashar, Gründer and Horstmann, eds, Philologie und
Hermeneutik im 19. Jahrhundert (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1979),
32–68.
Wilamowics-Moellendorff, Ulrich von, Geschichte der Philologie [1921] (Stuttgart and
Leipzig: B. G. Teubner, 1998).
Winckelmann, Johann Joachim, Gedanken über die Nachahmung der griechischen
Werke in der Malerei und Bildhauerkunst (Stuttgart: Reclam Verlag, 1995 [1755]).
Wind, Edgar, ‘Warburg’s Begriff der Kulturwissenschaft und seine Bedeutung für
Ästhetik’, Zeitschrift für Ästhetik und allgemeine Kunstwissenschaft 25 (Beilagehaft,
1931), 163–79.
Wind, Edgar, ‘Some Points of Contact Between History and the Natural Science’,
in Raymond Klibansky and Herbert James Paton, eds, Philosophy and
History. Essays Presented to Ernst Cassirer (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1936),
255–64.
Wind, Edgar, Pagan Mysteries in the Renaissance (London: Faber & Faber, 1958).
Wind, Edgar, The Eloquence of Symbols: Studies in Humanist Art (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1983).
Wind, Edgar, Ästhetischer und Kunstwissenschaftlicher Gegendstand, Ein Beitrag zur
Methodologie der Kunstgeschichte, ed. Pablo Schneider (Hamburg: Philo Fine Art,
2011 [1922]).
Windelband, Wilhelm, ‘Geschichte und Naturwissenschaft’, in Hans-Ludwig Ollig, ed.,
Neukantianismus. Texte (Stuttgart: Phillip Reclam, 1982), 164–73.
Windelband, Wilhelm, ‘Rectoral Address. 1893’, trans. Guy Oakes, History and Theory
19:2 (February 1980): 169–85.
Wissmann, Heinz, ‘Les études platoniciennes au 19ème siècle’, in Hellmut Flashar,
Mayotte Bollack and Heinz Wissman, eds, Philologie et Hermeneutik II (Göttingen:
Wandenhöck and Ruprecht, 1983), 490–513.
Witt, Charlotte, ‘Hylomorphism in Aristotle’, The Journal of Philosophy 84:11
(November 1987): 673–9.
Wölfflin, Heinrich, Kunstgeschichtliche Grundbegriffe. Das Problem der Stilentwicklung
in der neueren Kunst [1915], 16 Aufl. (Basel: Schwabe Verlag, 1979).
202 Bibliography
Woodfield, Richard, ed., Framing Formalism: Riegl’s Work (New York and London:
Routledge, 2001).
Worms, Frédéric, Bergson et les deux sens de la vie (Paris: Presses Universitaires de
France, 2004).
Wuttke, Dieter, ed., Kosmopolis der Wissenschaft, E. R. Curtius und das Warburg
Institute. Briefe und andere Dokumente (Baden-Baden: Koerner Verlag, 1989).
Wuttke, Dieter, Dazwischen: Kulturwissenschaft auf Warburgs Spuren, 2 vols (Baden-
Baden: Koerner, 1996).
Yates, Frances, The Art of Memory (London: Pimlico, 1966).
Zerner, Henri, ‘L’histoire de l’art d’Alois Riegl: un formalism tactique’, Critique 339–40
(August–September 1975): 940–52.
Ziolkowski, Jan (ed), On Philology (University Park: Pennsylvania State University
Press, 1990).
Index
factum 4, 10–11, 54–5, 60, 67, 69, 101, historicism 11–12, 17, 21, 49, 81–2, 88,
139–40 126, 131, 133, 140–41
Ficino, Marsilio 59 history, historical reality (geschichtliche
figural dynamics 29, 35–6, 38, 40–41, 47, Wirklichkeit) 9, 27, 30, 43, 49–52,
55, 59, 64, 69–70, 77, 87, 137, 139 56, 58, 67–73, 75–8, 85, 88, 91–104,
figural situation 37–40, 42–4, 63–4, 69, 124 115–16, 119–20, 124–5, 130–31,
figural synthesis 65, 77, 91–104, 137–8 133, 135–40
figurative 40, 55 Holly, Michael Ann 16, 95
Focillon, Henri 13, 15, 35–6, 39, 42–3, 45 humanism 3–5, 7–9, 13–14, 59, 80, 86, 88,
form, forms 2, 5, 8–11, 14, 16–17, 21, 98–9, 104, 110–14, 116–17, 121,
23–4, 27, 29, 33–47, 51–2, 55–7, 126–8, 132
61–4, 66–7, 68, 71, 75, 78, 80–82, hylomorphism 3, 7, 10, 14, 17–18, 39, 41,
93–6, 98–9, 102–3, 106–7, 110–12, 66, 70–71, 91–2, 113–14, 116–18,
115–17, 123, 130, 136–7, 141 119, 136, 141
formalism 15–16, 33–6, 38, 43
Foucault, Michel 8 iconism 49, 120–23, 125
Francastel, Pierre 33, 36, 40–42, 44, 63 iconoclasm 49–52, 60–61, 92, 120–22,
fundamental concepts (Grundbegriffe) 52 130
iconology 4, 12–15, 17–21, 23, 25–6, 28,
gaze 11, 69, 75–6, 82–9, 122, 124, 139 30, 36, 49, 54, 56, 59, 61, 66–8, 73,
Genette, Gérard 67, 69 75–89, 91–104, 105, 112–13, 116,
genus, genre 3, 7, 9–10, 28, 33, 42, 66, 88, 119–26, 129–34, 138, 141
92, 94–5, 123–4, 131, 138, 141 iconophiles, iconodules 49–51, 53–4, 57,
geschichtliche Wirklichkeit see history, 60–62, 92, 104, 120–21
historical reality Idea 51–4, 57, 59, 61, 66, 120
gesture 25, 30, 36, 41, 46, 54, 61–8, 92–4, ideal 5, 8–9, 82–3, 86, 94, 97–8, 127–8,
123–7, 138 138
Ghirlandaio, Domenico 83–5 idiographic 98, 100, 141
Gilson, Etienne 58, 70 idol 52, 119, 131
Goldschmidt, Adolph 15, 80, 141 image 13, 37, 40, 46, 49–51, 53, 56, 64–6,
Gombrich, Ernst 13, 83 69, 72, 82–5, 87–8, 107, 115, 117,
grammar 5, 7, 13, 16–20, 25–6, 30, 34–5, 119–22, 124–5, 129–31, 133, 136
41–2 imaginary 41–2, 52
Greenberg, Clement 34–8 imitation (Nachahmung) 5, 51–2, 59,
Grimm, Jakob 6, 18–20 113–14, 128, 140
ground 16, 37–9, 43, 61, 64–5, 76, 83–6, interpretation 10–13, 17, 23–4, 27, 33, 57,
88, 124, 127 84, 92–3, 99, 120–21, 123, 127, 129,
Grundbegriffe, see fundamental concepts 132–3
Gumbrecht, Hans Ulrich 105 intuition (Anschauung) 6, 33, 61–2, 66, 71,
76–7, 84, 92–3, 95–6, 99–104, 109,
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 72 115, 118, 123, 132–3
Herder, Johann Gottfried von 34–5, 44–6
heresy 122 Jay, Martin 50
Hermann, Jakob 5, 12 Jesus 65, 67, 69, 71–3, 139
hermeneutics 8, 11–12, 18, 78, 84, 129, 132 John of Damascus 50, 126
Heyne, Christian Gottlob 5 Jolles, Johannes Andreas 83
hierarchical distance 50, 126 Joshua 55, 65, 67, 69, 71–3, 116, 139
Hildebrand, Adolf von 34 judgement 8, 53, 95–7, 101–2, 104
Index 205
Kant, Immanuel 5, 12–13, 16, 52, 59, 65, Nachahmung see imitation
76–7, 84, 92, 95, 97–8, 100–104, narrative 27, 39, 50–51, 53–4, 57–8, 61–2,
119, 127–9, 131 73, 110, 115, 131
Krauss, Rosalind 36–8, 63 Natorp, Paul 53, 97
Kulturgeschichte 8–9 neo-Kantianism 11–12, 14, 16, 18, 25, 27,
Kulturwissenschaft 9, 30, 53, 98 30, 52–4, 58, 61, 78, 91–2, 95–8,
Kunstwollen 15–18, 21–2, 27–31, 128 101, 119, 126–7, 130, 137, 141
neo-Platonism 3, 51, 54, 64, 92, 96, 104,
Lachmann, Karl 5, 18, 20 116–17, 126
Lebensphilosophie see vitalism Neuphilologie 6–7
Lhote, André 63 Nicea, Council of 50, 130
Lotze, Rudolf Hermann 97 Nietzsche, Friedrich 7, 12, 80–81, 103
Lucretius 55 nonseen 133–4
Lyotard, Jean-François 38, 63
object 2, 4, 7–8, 10, 12, 21, 22–4, 28, 30,
Malabou, Catherine 44 37, 43, 45–6, 52, 59–60, 68, 84,
Mannheim, Karl 17, 91, 96 93–7, 100, 107–8, 115, 117, 126–7,
Marin, Louis 63 132, 135
Marion, Jean-Luc 120, 124, 126–7, 129–31 Old Testament 54–5, 60, 116
matter 14, 17, 34–5, 39, 41–7, 64–6, ontology 14, 52
70–71, 109, 111–12, 116–17, 124,
126, 134, 139 Paris, Gaston 6
meaning 5, 8, 10–12, 14, 16–17, 22–4, Pascal, Blaise 66, 69
26–30, 38–40, 45–7, 54–5, 58, 61, pathos-formulae 30, 80, 82, 84–9, 111
67–73, 80–81, 83–4, 91–3, 95–9, perspective 88, 95, 123, 126–9
104, 106, 111, 115, 116–17, 120–33, pictorial 1, 12–13, 24, 33–47, 49–63, 69,
135–8, 140–41 84, 86, 120–21, 126–8, 132
memory, mnemonic 10, 24, 26–7, 65, 66, place 27–8, 37, 43, 45, 56, 58, 64–6, 69,
82–3, 85, 87, 105–10, 112 86, 100–101, 108–10, 115, 120, 131,
metaphysics 4, 27, 82, 110, 129 138
method 1, 2, 4–5, 8–10, 14, 15–22, 24, plastics 1, 3, 8, 14, 15–19, 24–5, 28, 31,
27–8, 30–31, 36, 52, 54, 56, 58–62, 33–9, 41, 43–7, 51–5, 57, 60, 62,
69–70, 72, 78, 81, 91–4, 97, 104, 63–5, 67–8, 75, 87, 92–4, 100,
105–8, 112–14, 119, 122, 135–6, 102–5, 110, 115–17, 119, 122–3,
139, 141 131, 136, 139
mimesis 50–51, 53, 61, 127 Plato 3, 6, 18, 40, 50–53, 58, 61, 83, 91,
mistranslation 13 95–6, 115, 126
modeling 46 plenitude 14
modus operandi 12, 67, 70, 73 Pliny the Elder 45–6, 64, 66
monuments 1, 15–31, 41, 54, 68, 93, 125, Plotinus 51, 61, 101
130, 135–6, 139–41 Podro, Michael 16, 51, 88, 120
morphe 41, 55, 66, 71 poiesis 4, 9–12, 70, 83, 101, 137, 142
movement, dynamics 2, 6–7, 17, 28, 34–7, Poussin, Nicolas 13
40–43, 45, 54, 58, 64–8, 70, 84–5, presentation (Darstellung) 42, 57–8, 71,
87–8, 107–8, 113–14, 116–18, 124, 73, 87, 96, 123, 127–8, 136, 139–40
128 production see poiesis
mutation 19, 26, 34, 41–2, 44, 111, 123, prototype 9–12, 40–42, 44, 50, 64, 68,
139, 141 71, 82, 85, 87, 101, 104, 113, 121,
mythology 3, 7, 80, 101, 121 123–7, 129–31, 133
206 Index
unconscious 37–8, 73 Warburg, Aby 6–8, 10, 13, 15–16, 19, 30,
understanding 4, 6, 10, 17, 23–4, 33, 35, 36, 60, 69, 73, 75–89, 94, 110–12,
37, 42, 50, 54, 59, 63, 65, 67, 78, 81, 115, 117, 122–3, 125, 140
94–5, 97–8, 101–4, 114–17, 120–22, Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, Ulrich von 6–7
132, 140–42 Winckelmann, Johan Joachim 5, 44
Usener, Hermann 7, 19, 70, 80–81, 85 Wind, Edgar 13, 36
Windelband, Wilhelm 12, 30, 91, 97–100,
validation 50, 52, 55–9, 67, 70, 81, 86, 88, 141
120–21, 136–7, 139–40 Wolf, Friedrich Augustus 5–6
value 7, 12, 26–8, 30–31, 35, 39–40, Wölfflin, Henrich 15–17, 36
50–53, 58–60, 92, 94–100, 121, 141 work 2, 4, 9–10, 12, 16, 18, 20, 22–4,
vanishing point 125–30 26–31, 34, 36, 40–42, 51, 58–62, 64,
Varro 55 66, 68–73, 76–8, 84–8, 92–5, 97–8,
verum 4, 11, 55, 101, 139 100–102, 104, 109–110, 113, 115,
Vico, Giambattista 4, 9–11, 54–7, 59, 71, 117–18, 119–27, 129–33, 135–41
101, 122, 137, 139 worldview 121, 126
vitalism (Lebensphilosophie) 80–81, 86–7 Wörter und Sachen 19–20, 25
Vöge, Wilhelm 15, 80, 141
Volk 6 Yates, Frances 110
Voßler, Karl 8, 20, 80–81