Warring Soveriegns and Mimetic Rivals
Warring Soveriegns and Mimetic Rivals
Warring Soveriegns and Mimetic Rivals
ERIC WILSON
Abstract: My paper argues for the relevance of the French literary critic Rene Girard to
contemporary critical legal theory. In order to prove my thesis, I undertake a ‘dual’ reading of a
foundational text from the field of Law and Literature—William Golding’s Lord of the Flies—by
subjecting it to both a Hobbesian and Girardian interpretation. The relevance of Thomas Hobbes to
the novel is obvious—the ‘constitutional crisis’ faced by the Boys is an allegorical re-enactment of
Hobbes’ famous division between the Commonwealth-by-Institution (represented by Ralph and
Piggy) and the Commonwealth-by-Acquisition (represented by Jack and Roger). What is less obvious
is the manner in which the struggle over the political order of the island strictly parallels a sub-
textual mimetic rivalry between the two boy-sovereigns, Ralph and Jack. Employing Girard’s as a
supplementary reading to Hobbes’, a much more challenging interpretation of the novel may be
offered: the mimetic rivalry between the two Boys replicates the mimetic dynamic between the
competing forms government that they symbolize, subverting any absolute distinction between
liberal and dictatorial forms of the State. The narrative core of the novel is a ‘double story arc’: the
movement from the representational theory of language (Hobbes) to the anti-representational
theory of substitution (Girard) and the movement from Social Contract (the conch) to the sacrificial
mechanism (the scapegoat).
‘As far back as we can go in History we find that the two signs of
Man are a capacity to kill and a belief in God.’—William Golding
‘Violence is the heart and soul of the sacred.’—Rene Girard
Lord of the Flies (1954) is one of the greatest allegorical novels of the 20th Century, so much
so that it serves as a veritable secondary school primer for literary symbolism (‘the conch
signifies…’, ‘the pig’s head represents…’, ‘Jack stands for…’). My first encounter with
William Golding’s magnificent but interminably nebulous novel took place when my father,
cautionary fable of what happens when the thin veneer of civilisation is stripped away; in
other words, an allegory, or even a metaphysical thriller, about the always tenuous
barbarism. My father’s superficial but not inaccurate characterisation was strongly endorsed
on numerous occasions by the cheerfully verbose Golding, who, in innumerable scholarly and
popular interviews, also counselled his readers as to the essentially moral nature of his text; to
cite just one example, ‘The theme [of Lord of the Flies] is an attempt to trace the defects of
society back to the defects of human nature. The moral [sic] is that the shape of a society
must depend on the ethical nature of the individual and not on any political system…The
whole book is symbolic in nature.’1 I grew up, eventually, and turned my directions towards
result, when I revisited Lord of the Flies many years later, I knew enough, or had been ruined
enough, to throw down the gauntlet to my father’s inherently moralistic reading (I had also
read enough Lacan by this time to realise that I will spend my entire life in an utterly
desperate but wholly futile effort to obtain the Phallus). For I knew now that Golding had lied
(so had my father, but he didn’t know it)—the events described in the novel do not detail the
collapse of civilisation; rather, they outline the process by which Golding’s version of ‘the
Lost Boys’, now radically immersed within the State of Nature and unknowingly following
the social logic of community, mimetically re-enact the true sequence of cultural formation.
Rather than destroy civilisation they overthrow the foundations of a false model of social
being and invent for themselves an original, and self-sustaining, aboriginal society. In short, I
read Lord of the Flies as a satire of Thomas Hobbes’ theory of the State of Nature and the
Social Contract as the foundation of legal and political order (‘Society’) clandestinely
1 Golding cited in Howard S. Babb, The Novels of William Golding (Toledo, The Ohio State University Press,
1970), 7. For Golding as moralist, see Samuel Haynes, ‘William Golding’s Lord of the Flies’, in James R. Baker
(ed.), Critical Essays on William Golding (Boston, G.K. Hall & Co., 1988), 13-21.
3
‘The theme of Lord of the Flies is grief, sheer grief, grief, grief, grief.’—William Golding
Arguably the single greatest work of British political philosophy, Thomas Hobbes’ Leviathan
(1651) takes its name from the allegorical sea-monster, or Beast, cited in The Book of Job.
Very much like William Golding was to do three hundred years later, Hobbes is meticulous
And thus I have brought to an end my Discourse of Civill and Ecclesiasticall Government,
occasioned by the disorders of the present time [the Puritan Revolution], without partiality,
without application, and without other designe, than to set before mens eyes the mutuall
Relation between Protection and Obedience; of which the condition of Humane Nature, and
the Laws Divine, (both Naturall and Positive) require an inviolable observation.2
Although wide ranging in scope, today almost the entirety of the text is ignored; our
contemporary interest is focused primarily upon Chapters XIII and XIV of Book One (‘Of
Man’) and Chapter XVII of Book Two (‘Of Common-Wealth’) where Hobbes provides the
reader with what we take to be the core, and defining, elements of his theory of
constitutionality. The first such expression is well known: ‘Hereby it is manifest that during
the time men live without a common power to keep them all in awe, they are in that condition
that is called War, and such a war is of every men against every man.’3 The second is even
more famous.
Whatsoever therefore is consequent to a time of War, where every man is enemy to every
man; the same is consequent to the time wherein men live without other security, than what
their own strength, and their invention shall furnish them with all…and [what] is worst of all
[in such a condition], continual fear, and danger of violent death; and the life of man, solitary,
poor, nasty, brutish, and short.4
2 Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, Edited by Richard Tuck, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1991), 491.
(fully corrected 1651 edition, Cambridge University Library, Syn.3.65.1)
make the uncanny discovery that the latter is an almost point-for-point poetical
embellishment of the former. Take, for example, the description of the original communal
mingling of the Boys following their stranding upon the nameless island provided in Chapter
Some [of the children] were naked and carrying their clothes; others half-naked, or more-or-
less dressed, in school uniforms; grey, blue, fawn, jacketed or jerseyed. There were badges,
mottoes even, stripes of color in stockings and pullovers. Their heads clustered above the
trunks in the green shade; heads brown, fair, black, chestnut, sandy, mouse-colored; heads
muttering, whispering, heads full of eyes that watched Ralph and speculated. Something was
being done.6
Note how the complex narrative of the first chapter manages to both encapsulate Hobbes’
foundational concerns and successfully anticipates (or ‘foreshadows’) all of the Hobbesian
themes that will play themselves out to the homicidal end of the later chapters. The first is the
focus on the apparently representational nature of language; the iconic conch is the ‘natural’
symbol of authority/reason as embedded within the landscape (‘Let him be the chief with the
trumpet-thing.’7). The second is that the ‘State of Nature’ is identical to the absence of the
‘common power’. The third is that the successful creation of the ‘common power’ guarantees
the elimination of that self-same State of Nature. The first thing that the Boys must do is to
establish some rules (‘That’s why Ralph made a meeting. So as we can decide what to do.’8),
including the maintenance of the all-important bonfire that will be used to perpetually
of democratic assembly and structured debate both signified by the holding of the conch, the
master-sign of political reason. In short, they all voluntarily enter into a political compact
5 William Golding, Lord of the Flies (London, Faber and Faber, 1954), 1-29, generally. (original edition)
premised upon the act of conveyance of their freedom (signified by isolation) towards the
group, or, less charitably, the crowd; for Hobbes, the ‘mutual transferring of Right is that
which men call CONTRACT.’9 As the Boys discover for themselves, the entering into the
Social Contract is the foundational act that creates the legal and political community; ‘To lay
down a man’s right to anything, is to divest himself of the liberty of hindering another of his
own right to the same.’10 Matters are immediately complicated, however, by the intuitive
realisation that pure democracy is inadequate: the state of emergency (‘We’ve got to decide
about being rescued’11), a life or death situation compounded by the absence of any grown-
Hobbes put it
The only way to erect such a Common Power, as may be able to defend men from the
invasion of foreigners and the injuries of one another…is to confer all their power and
strength upon one Man, or upon one Assembly of men, that may reduce all their own Wills by
plurality of voices into one Will; which is as much to say, to appoint one Man, or Assembly
of men, to bear their Person; and every one to own, and acknowledge himself to be the author
of whatsoever he that bears their Person , shall act, or cause to act, in those things which
concern the common peace and safety; and therein to submit their Wills, everyone to his
Will, and their Judgments to his Judgment. This is more than consent or concordance; it is a
real unity to them all, in one and the same person, made by the contract of every man with
every man, in such a manner as if every man should say to every man, I authorize and give
up my right of governing myself to this man, or to this assembly of men, on this condition,
that you give up your right to him, and authorize all of his actions in like manner. This done,
the multitude so united in one person, is called a Commonwealth…This is the generation of
that great LEVIATHAN, or…of that Mortal God.13
For anyone who is familiar with Leviathan, or the great Beast from the Waters, the paradox at
chthonic work in the novel is in clear view: with Hobbes the completion of the Social
Contract which is identical with the suspension of the State of Nature constitutes the true
descent, colloquially known as ‘the downward spiral into violence’. Read (somewhat
didactically) from a Law and Literature perspective, Lord of the Flies forces us to consider
whether the contractarian theory of the foundation of Law is adequate and whether
‘something else’ besides rational (and self-interested) contracting is necessary to explain the
existence and nature of the State. As the saga of the Boys goes on to show, violence cannot
be ‘suspended’ by the act of contract alone; it must be assimilated directly into the
community by means of symbolic transference. And as the unruly protagonists learn for
themselves, the successful completion of the legal and political order (‘the State’) can only
Religion. The established (or permissible) Church cannot be separated from the State; rather,
Man is a fallen being. He is gripped by original sin. His nature is sinful and his state
perilous. I accept the theology and admit the triteness; but what is trite is true; and a truism
can become more than a truism when it is a belief passionately held.—William Golding
The most remarkable feature of Leviathan (and the one that cost its author the most in his
later life) was its uncompromising exclusion of Religion from political discourse; the Social
Government.
From this consolidation of the Right Politique, and Ecclesiastique in Christian Soveraigns, it
is evident, they have all manner of Powers over their Subjects, that can be given to man, for
the government of men’s externall actions, both in Policy and Religion; and may make such
Laws, as themselves shall judge fittest, for the government of their own Subjects, both as they
7
are the Common-wealth, and as they are the Church: for both State, and Church are the same
men.14
Two of the four books of Leviathan are devoted to organised Religion and the Church15; yet
in this text, unlike elsewhere in his writings, Hobbes’ sole concern is with the relative value
of civil Religion: not only the strict separation of private conscience from public speech, but
belief, or language, is itself void of persuasive value, the poetical expression of mere
subjective opinion and unruly passion.16 My problem here is that my close reading of Lord of
the Flies accepts the text as an allegorical acting out of the political imaginary of the cultural
logic of the Social Contract, culminating in the establishment of the ‘cult’ of the Beast. We
also know that Religion formed an essential part of Golding’s abiding concern as an author.
challenging anthropological model of cultural formation that privileges Religion as the source
proposition that Religion is the true foundation of Society. 17 Much of Girard’s work
15 Book Three, ‘Of a Christian Common-Wealth’, 255-415, and Book Four, ‘Of the Kingdome of Darknesse’,
or, more simply, Roman Catholicism, 417-82. .
16 See for example Chapter XXXI of Book Three, ‘Of the Kingdom of God By Nature’, wherein Hobbes
restricts proper religious speech to that uniformity of public worship governed directly by civil law; Hobbes,
245-54.
17 Rene Girard, Violence and the Sacred, Translated by Patrick Gregory (Baltimore, The Johns Hopkins Press,
1977), generally. See Michael Kirwan, Discovering Girard (Chicago, A Cowley Publications Book, 2005) in
general, especially 43-50.
Functionalist sociology of religion and Freud’s cultural criticism (primarily Totem and
The efficiency of our judicial system conceals the problem [of violence], and the elimination
of the problem conceals from us the role played by religion. The air of mystery that primitive
societies acquire for us is undoubtedly due in large part to this misunderstanding. It is
undoubtedly responsible for our extreme views of these societies, our insistence on
portraying them alternately as vastly superior or flagrantly inferior to our own. One factor
alone might well be responsible for our oscillation between extremes, our radical evaluations:
the absence in [‘primitive’] societies of a judicial system…If we compare societies that
adhere to a judicial system with societies that practice sacrificial rites, the difference between
the two is such that we can indeed consider the absence or presence of these [judicial]
institutions as a basis for distinguishing primitive societies from ‘civilised’ ones.18
The foundational, but thoroughly repressed, continuity between the modern and the archaic is
of course a classic trope of Freudian psycho-analysis. Yet, Girard largely eschews the
Freudian theory of drive, or instinct (Trieb), finding greater insight in the application of
translation of Freud’s late metapsychology into the referential terms of Emile Durkheim’s
notion of function: ‘The purpose of the sacrifice is to restore harmony to the community, to
reinforce the social fabric. Everything else derives from that.’19 For Girard, the ‘fundamental
truth about violence’ is that, ‘if left unappeased, violence will accumulate until it overflows
its confines and floods the surrounding area. The role of sacrifice is to stem this rising tide of
indiscriminate substitutions and redirect violence into “proper” channels.’20 Key to the
success of the sacrificial mechanism is its status as ritual which is invariably a ‘re-enactment
of a “prior event”.’21 Since every ritual is a re-enactment, its governing logic is mimesis, the
ritual is both a representation and a substitution for an earlier crisis of violence. But this
21 Burton Mack, ‘Introduction: Religion and Ritual’ in Robert G. Hammerton-Kelly (ed.), Violent Origins:
Walter Burkert, Rene Girard, and Jonathan Z. Smith on Ritual Killing and Cultural Formation (Stanford,
Stanford University Press, 1987), 8.
9
governing logic is anti-representational: under the sign of substitution, all differences are
abolished and any one thing can be traded for and replaced with any other thing. In Girard’s
case the vital ritualistic dimension of the sacrificial mechanism is the mimetic evocation of an
In Girard’s view, every ritual bears the traces of a double movement: the re-invocation of the
past event and the projection of that earlier event’s cathartic effect into future time. The ‘prior
event’ that all ritual killings represent through mimetic substitution is a collective murder, an
act of mob violence. ‘“Sacrifice” then becomes a term that can be used to refer to the
complex phenomenon of the collective killing of a human victim, its mythic rationalization,
and its ritualization.’23 Collective murder mediated by ritual is the true beginning of human
culture and the scapegoat is the first cultural artefact of human history.24 The necessary
precondition for the historical survival of the community is the successful exorcism of the
unclean spirit of revenge. This is secured through the periodic enactment of the rituals of the
designated victim (the scapegoat) which successfully broke the cycle of retributive violence.
23 Mack (n 21), 8.
24 Girard (n 17), generally. ‘All systems that give structure to human society have been generated from [the
scapegoat mechanism]: language, kinship systems, taboos, codes of etiquette, patterns of exchange, rites, and
civil institutions. Thus a theory of sacrifice has produced a comprehensive account of human social formation,
religion, and culture.’ Mack (n 21), 7.
The first of several obvious questions to be asked here is: why, exactly, is the will-to-
violence so virulent? Girard’s answer is that the ferocity of social violence is structurally
embedded within the form of its transmission, best understood as a form of contagion.
Why does the spirit of revenge, wherever it breaks out, constitute such an intolerable
menace? Perhaps because the only satisfactory revenge for spilt blood is spilling the blood of
the killer; and in the blood feud there is no clear distinction between the act for which the
killer is being punished and the punishment itself. Vengeance professes to be an act of
reprisal, and every reprisal calls for another reprisal. The crime to which the act of vengeance
addresses itself is almost never an unprecedented offense; in almost every case it has been
committed in revenge for some prior crime.25
Homo Sapiens, unlike other animals, is assumed by Girard to lack a genetically inscribed
the human community can be nothing else other than endemic, or contagious; since the ‘only
answer to murder is another murder, cycles of reciprocal retaliation create unending series of
revenge-killings. To bring the series to an end, a “final” killing is necessary. The final killing
is achieved in the “mechanism of the surrogate victim.”’26 On one level, this is nothing more
than an exceptionally elegant and sophisticated restatement of the principle of vendetta, the
26 Mack (n 21), 8.
Language counts. The phrase ‘interminable, infinitely repetitive process’ directly evokes
Thanatos, or the ‘death-drive’. As I have already pointed out, Girard rejects Freud’s theory of
sexuality; however, he clearly appropriates the unconscious logic of a certain kind of desire
Vengeance is a vicious circle whose effect on primitive societies can only be surmised. For us
the circle has been broken. We owe our good fortune to one of our social institutions above
all: our judicial system, which serves to deflect the menace of vengeance. The system does
not suppress vengeance; rather, it effectively limits it to a single act of reprisal, enacted by a
sovereign authority specializing in this particular function. The decisions of the judiciary are
invariably presented as the final word on vengeance.28
For us moderns, justice-as-revenge has been effectively superseded by, or, in less Hegelian
terms, thoroughly sublimated into the universalist rule of law and the impersonal formalism
of due process. I would expect the contemporary reader to tolerate Girard’s assumptions
concerning the archaic genealogy of judicial Modernity, although our prejudice would be in
favour of the irreversibility of the long progressive narrative of over-coming: any deviation
from, or reversal of, the global course of rationalist rehabilitation can be nothing other than
barbarism. I think that what the typical reader would unreservedly reject is Girard’s
valorisation of Theology as the vital cultural mechanism at work in the human drama. After
years of the middle-brow media sponsored ‘War on Religion’ (Christopher Hitchens, Richard
Dawkins, A.C. Grayling et al)—which, I suspect, is merely one of the propagandistic wings
terms as the ‘War on the Fear of Unexpected Death’)—our common inclination to view
Religion as the master-sign of social dysfunction and cultural pathology would make such a
According to Girard, people ‘can dispose of their violence more efficiently if they regard the
process not as something emanating from within themselves, but as a necessity imposed from
without, a divine decree whose least infraction calls down terrible punishment.’29 From this it
follows that when ‘we minimize the dangers implicit in vengeance we risk losing sight of the
true function of sacrifice.’30 We need to examine with care that process Girard posits at the
core of primitive religion as the ‘circuit-breaker’ that pre-empts the contagion of violence
the scapegoat. The internal cultural logic of the mechanism operates by means of the mimetic
who is symbolically re-constituted as the contagious and contaminating source of all hatred
and vengeance—that social dysfunction which Hobbes pointedly identified with ‘Grief’.31
This explains the most obvious, and well known, characteristic of the sacrificial victim: its
impurity (pollution; stain) as a sin-bearing object.32 Out of necessity, the scapegoat must
always be socially marginal in some way, an ‘expendable’ victim, human or animal, whose
death will not cause violence to rebound because no one will bother to avenge them but
which, for whatever reason, can serve as the focus of universal opprobrium.
31 See below.
32 Which is one of the crucial demarcations between ‘primitive’ religions and the later Hellenistic paganisms
and monotheistic faiths; for Girard the transformation of the status of the victim is the master-sign of a
revolution in civilisation. In the ‘primitive phase’ of Religion, the victim itself is impure or contaminated in
some way, and purification, always communal, is achieved through the sacrifice/expulsion/destruction of the
surrogate. But, beginning with Greek Tragedy and the later Hebrew prophets, such as in the Book of Job (the
spawning ground of Leviathan), the victim becomes elevated through the inversion of the binary logic of
impurity/purity: the victim, beloved of God(s) is him or herself inherently pure but becomes an object of
supernatural power and value (the original meaning of pollution, meaning a dangerous magic) by drawing unto
themselves the collective impurity of the group. See Girard (n 17) in general and Rene Girard, Job: The Victim
and His People, Translated by Yvonne Freccero (London, The Athlone Press, 1987), generally.
13
All our sacrificial victims, whether chosen from one of the human categories [slave; prisoner;
captive] or…from the animal realm, are invariably distinguishable from the non-sacrificeable
beings by one essential characteristic: between these victims and the community a crucial
link is missing, so they can be exposed to violence without fear of reprisal. Their death does
not automatically entail an act of vengeance. The considerable importance this freedom from
reprisal has for the sacrificial process makes us understand that sacrifice is primarily an act of
violence without risk of vengeance…The desire to commit an act of violence on those near us
cannot be suppressed without a conflict; we must divert that impulse, therefore, toward the
sacrificial victim, the creature we can strike down without fear of reprisal, since he lacks a
champion.33
On another level, one of unexpected depth, the scapegoat is always the object of a ‘double’
transference: not only is the victim chosen to be the bearer of the collective sins of the
community through some inherent flaw of its nature, but, through the projection of sin into
the alien object the community (temporarily) releases itself from its capacity for violence,
which remains eternally latent. The ‘psychic price’ to be paid for this ritualistic transference
is high: if sacrifice is the essence of Religion (and Religion is the essence of community),
then the social body must constantly repress its self-awareness of the violence of its own
origins, precisely because, as Hobbes intuited, we adhere to the group precisely in order to
subdue the violence within (strife) and to shield ourselves from the threat of the outside
(war). This collective act of repression usually seeks some sort of outlet through emotional or
symbolic displacement, a process that is historically without end, because, in accordance with
the logic of atavism, the recapitulation of ‘primitive’ traits within the more ‘advanced’
organism (biological or cultural) will always work to undermine the stable (and stabilising)
From a Law and Literature perspective, this dilemma is most evident in the liminality, or
reversibility, that operates between both ‘public’ and ‘private’ justice and between natural
Vocabulary is perhaps more revealing here than judicial theories. Once the concept of
interminable revenge has been formally rejected, it is referred to as private vengeance. The
33 Girard (n 17), 13.
term implies the existence of a public vengeance, a counterpart never made explicit. By
definition, primitive societies have only private vengeance. Thus, public vengeance is the
exclusive property of well-policed societies, and our society calls it the judicial system.34
It should now be obvious why Girard’s highly original theory of mimesis serves as the
radically disassociated from facts, the scapegoat is both profoundly true (cultural; subjective)
and completely false (material; objective) at the same moment. Richard Tuck’s excellent
The problem which exercised Hobbes, almost alone among the theorists of his time, was that
even if men are basically self-protective and therefore in principle pacific towards one
another, their independency of judgment about the world will lead to conflict. His proposed
solution was therefore to eliminate independent judgment about most matters of fact. Natural
man, he argued, would see the necessity for everyone to transfer their individual judgment in
cases of uncertainty to a common-decision-maker, whose opinion about what constitutes a
threat would be conclusive.35
Hobbes is clearly situated within the classical episteme of the 17th century, signified by the
unreliable but they can be assigned precise evidentiary value through the correct perception
by and operation of an irreducible Mind that itself is devoid of constituent parts.36 Technically
Hobbes was a nominalist; like Descartes, he was extremely sceptical concerning the validity
of sensory knowledge.37 However, as Tuck has pointed out, Hobbes, also like Descartes, was
concerned to ‘emphasise that a mind can know, without any doubt, whatever went on purely
within itself. He put into this category all language—which he took to be the labelling of our
36 ‘Thus the camera obscura is inseparable from a certain metaphysics of interiority: it is a figure of both the
observer who is a nominally free sovereign and a privatized subject confined in a quasi-domestic space, cut off
from a public exterior world.’ Jonathan Crary, Techniques of the Observer: On Vision and Modernity in the
Nineteenth Century (Cambridge, Mass MIT Press, 1990), 39; see also 25-66.
take the time to read Book One of Leviathan, where Hobbes lays out his representational
theory of language consisting of three distinct propositions. The first, and most foundational,
is a radical but simplistic Empiricism: sensation is the source of all human knowledge.
The Originall of them all [the Thoughts of Men], is that which we call SENSE; (For if there
is no conception in a man’s mind, which hath not at first, totally, or by parts, been begotten
upon organs of Sense). The rest are derived from the original…All which qualities called
Sensible, are in the object that causeth them, but so many several notions of the matter, by
which it presseth our organs diversely.40
grounding.
For it is most true that Cicero sayth of [the Philosophers] somewhere; that there can be
nothing so absurd, but may be found in the books of Philosophers. And the reason is
manifest. For there is not one of them that begins his ratiocination from the Definitions, or
Explications of the names they are to use; which is a method that hath been used onely in
Geometry[41]; whose Conclusions have thereby been made indisputable. The first cause of
Absurd conclusions I ascribe to the want of Method; in that they begin not their Ratiocination
from Definitions; that is, from settled significations of their words: as if they could cast
account, without knowing the value of the numerall words, one, two, three…By this it
appears that Reason is not as Sense, and Memory, borne with us; nor gotten by Experience
onely, as Prudence is; but attained by Industry; first in apt imposing of Names; and secondly
by getting a good and orderly Method in proceeding from the Elements, which are Names, to
Assertions made by Connexion of one of them to another, till we come to a knowledge of all
the Consequences of names appertaining to the subject in hand; and that is it, men call
SCIENCE.42
41 Compare this with Hobbes (n 2) 28: Geometry ‘is the onely Science that it hath pleased God hitherto to
bestow upon Mankind.’
political. Even if neither of the above were true (and it is vital to note the internal frisson, or
tensions, that run throughout Leviathan), the political and social utility of the enforcement of
standard (-ised) judgment makes objectivity and certainty indispensable (even if, perhaps,
practically unattainable): the Sovereign is a beast of discourse, the censor of the process of
naming (denotation), with the regulation and guaranteeing of ‘proper’ speech the highest
mark of Sovereignty.
There being nothing simply and absolutely; nor any common Rule of Good and Evill, to be
taken from the nature of the objects themselves43; but from the Person of the man (where
there is no Common-Wealth) or, (in a Common-Wealth,) from the Person that representeth it;
or from an Arbitrator or Judge, whom men disagreeing shall by consent set up, and make his
sentence the Rule thereof [44]… [the multitude shall] therein…submit their Wills, everyone to
his Will, and their Judgments, to his Judgment.45
Therefore, the core of Girard’s challenge to Hobbes lies not so much with an anti-
representational theory versus a representational one, but rather with the critical interrogation
intelligible is ultimately impractical, for even if Hobbes succeeds in demonstrating the first
and the second propositions (a very tall order) he must necessarily fail with the third. Hobbes’
The social functionality of the sacrificial mechanism depends upon the operation of a literally
45 Hobbes (n 2), 120. Although the term was not developed prior to David Hume in the mid-18th Century, it is
fairly clear that Hobbes’ dilemma is essentially that of the Is verus Ought dichotomy: even if it were possible to
self-ground Reason along the foundational principles elucidated by Hobbes it does not follow, from that fact
alone, that anyone is actually bound (contractually or otherwise) to follow them. Geometers may really speak
the truth, but the vulgar crowd is still governed by its ‘base passions’—only direct Executive Action will do the
job of enforcing the uniform rules of correct speech.
17
hated/feared/unclean/ugly = scapegoat); ‘Violence and the sacred are inseparable. But the
of violence to move from one object to another—is hidden from sight by the awesome
machinery of ritual.’46
As the reader knows full well, throughout the Lord of the Flies it is the hapless Piggy who
matters of fact’. He acts as the ‘reality principle’ (‘So now we can decide on what’s what.’47)
to Ralph’s dithering (i.e., bound by democratic procedure) chief. He is also the novel’s
paramount scapegoat and its most dramatic sacrificial victim48: his own name literally speaks
his fate. The central narrative drama of Lord of the Flies is the working through to the horrific
The narrative spine of Lord of the Flies is a logical sequence of three separate acts of murder
48 The excruciating and prolonged set-up of Piggy’s death by a politically incited mob, self-consciously
manipulated by Jack and Roger, takes up almost the whole of Chapter Eleven, ‘Castle Rock’. See Golding (n 5),
187-202. It is also blackly comic: take, for example Piggy’s ‘asking for it’ remark on page 189: ‘“I’m going to
him [Jack] with this conch in my hands.”’ Simon, by contrast, is completely dismembered in less than one page
at 168. Strikingly, the text spends far more time on the transmogrification of his mutilated carcass than on the
actual moment of death which, because it is a spontaneous action by the crowd, is temporally compressed and
‘muddled’ as both sensation and memory. See below.
49 With the exception of the appropriately nameless mulberry-faced boy, the announcer of the presence of the
Beast (and, therefore, the author of the violence to come), the accidental victim of the contagion of violence via
the conflagration/immolation mediated by the crowd, and the direct precursor of the parade of sacrificial victims
to come. His catastrophic exit, an enforced disappearance in effect, encapsulates the entirety of the mimetic
discourse of the text. ‘The older boys first noticed the child when he resisted. There was a group of little boys
urging him forward and he did not want to go. He was a shrimp of a boy, about six years old, and one side of his
significance, all of which mimetically repeat the co-evolution of both the State and Religion.
The first victim is Simon, a key member of the Ralph-Piggy faction, who serves the
archetype for the other two victims precisely because his manner of death is the simplest (or
most primitive): the ignorant and blind (or arbitrary) violence of the crowd, classically known
Simon during the ritualistic frenzy of the crowd’s celebration of the hunt is the act that,
ironically, is misinterpreted (or misnamed) by the Boy’s as the gesture that temporarily
exorcizes the Beast, whom the reader is now aware is really the body of a jet-fighter pilot
whose parachute has become entangled in the trees. As Simon is dismembered in frenzy after
having been mistakenly identified as the Beast by the crowd, the ‘real’ Beast undertakes his
Now a great wind blew the wind sideways, cascading the water from the forest trees. On the
mountain-top the parachute filled and moved; the figure slid, rose to its feet, spun, swayed
down through a vastness of wet air and trod with ungainly feet the tops of the high trees;
falling, still falling, it sank towards the beach and the boys rushed screaming into the
darkness. The parachute took the figure forward, furrowing the lagoon, and bumped it over
the reef and out to sea.52
Wholly consistent with Girard, the ‘accidental’ victim, involuntarily butchered in Dionysian
frenzy, is subsequently sanctified: the murder of the victim ‘solves’ the immediate crisis (the
Beast leaves the island after the cathartic discharge of group violence), so that the victim is
face was blotted out by a mulberry-coloured birthmark. He stood now, warped out of the perpendicular by the
fierce light of publicity, and he bored into the course grass with one toe. He was muttering and about to cry.’ He
would be well advised to do so; as the anthropologically ‘hip’ reader is immediately aware, the kid is doomed.
And it is none other than Piggy, the pivotal victim of the sacrificial drama to unfold, who proclaims his
extermination—perhaps out of an act of unconscious identification. ‘“The little ’un—‘gasped Piggy—“him with
the mark on his face, I don’t see him. Where is he now?” The crowd was as silent as death…A tree exploded in
the fire like a bomb. Tall swathes of creepers rose for a moment into view, agonized, and went down again. The
little boys screamed at them…”The little ’un had a mark on his—face—where is—he now? I tell you I don’t see
him.” The boys looked at each other fearfully, unbelieving…Beneath them, on the unfriendly side of the
mountain, the drum-roll continued.’ Golding (n 5), 33-4 and 46-7. In creative writing classes we call this ‘fore-
shadowing’.
invested with supernatural power after the fact.53 But most important is that Simon is re-cast
as a scapegoat only after his death; the ‘fault’ (sin) of the wrongful murder is retroactively
attributed to the victim himself. This constitutes the core of the ‘morning after’ conversation
between Ralph and Piggy, who, as we should expect, is the one Boy most in denial over the
‘Oh Piggy!’
Ralph’s voice, low and stricken, stopped Piggy’s gestures. Ralph, cradling the conch rocked
himself to and fro.’
‘Don’t you understand Piggy? The things we did—.’…
Ralph continued to rock to and fro.
‘It was an accident,’ said Piggy suddenly, ‘that’s what it was. An accident.’ His voice shrilled
again. ‘Coming in the dark—he had no business crawling like that out of the dark. He was
batty. He asked for it.’ He gesticulated widely again.
‘It was an accident—.’
‘You didn’t see what they did.’
‘Look, Ralph. We got to forget this. We can’t do no good thinking about it, see?’55
Pregnant with meaning, the dialogue is most notable for juxtaposing the ritualistic features of
the diasparagmos with the beginning of the end of Hobbesian political reason: the conch as
53 ‘Dismemberment is emblematic of triumph and resurrection; it reflects the operation of the surrogate victim,
the transformation of maleficent violence in beneficent violence.’ Girard (n 17), 286.This is clearly elaborated in
one of the most beautiful passages in the novel, where Simon’s mutilated cadaver is invested with the spectral
luminosity of the micro-animals of the Deep. Golding (n 5), 169-70.
clearly infantile manner. What announces itself in a steadily growing crescendo is that the
nameless nature of the Beast—artificially created through a series of misperceptions and un-
regulated speech—is the unassimilable thing that forces a fatal crisis of representation
identical with an alteration of the island Common-Wealth. Golding’s mixture of the political
with the epistemic is the narrative motor of the second, and far more elaborate sacrificial act,
At this point it is worthwhile to discuss Girard’s theory of the scapegoat in a bit more
detail.
Strictly speaking, there is no essential difference between animal sacrifice and human
sacrifice, and in many cases one is substituted for the other. Our tendency to insist on
differences that have little reality when discussing the institution of sacrifice—our reluctance,
for example, to equate animal with human sacrifice—is undoubtedly a factor in the
extraordinary misunderstandings that still persist in that area of human culture…all victims,
even the animal ones, bear a certain resemblance to the object they replace; otherwise the
violent impulse would remain unsatisfied.56
And what are the characteristics of the scapegoat that determines his/her identification and
selection?
From within the group, one person is separated out as victim. The selection is arbitrary and
spontaneous, though there are requisites. The victim must be recognizable as a surrogate for
the guilty party (or parties, and ultimately for the group itself); he must be vulnerable, unable
to retaliate, without champions to continue the vengeful violence; and there must be
unanimity within the group that he is the one at fault. When this unanimity is achieved the
victim is treated as a criminal, killed, and expelled. This brings the violence to an end. The
group has redirected its aggressions and its members are now able to cooperate.57
The irony that is normally missed by those who advocate a moral reading of the novel,
ordinarily the same crowd who frequently interpret Piggy as the allegorical personification of
the ‘voice of Reason’ or the ‘reality principle’ ( a kind of ‘failed hero’), is that it is precisely
these characteristics that render him the ideal object of the scapegoating mechanism. His gory
56 Girard (n 17), 10-11.
57 Mack (n 21), 8.
21
death in Chapter Eleven (‘Castle Rock’58) at the hands of the atavistic crowd as a sacrificial
killing that doubles as a political assassination59 is the perfect allegorical expression of the
radical insufficiency of political reason. As we have already seen, in Chapter Ten of the novel
(‘The Shell and the Glasses’60) Piggy is depicted as the bearer of false consciousness,
precisely because he is the one who most ferociously denies the logic of the sacrificial
murder of Simon. Piggy’s fatal error is that he believes that the rationality underlying the
expressed in perhaps the most famous passage of the novel: ‘And in the middle of them, with
filthy body, matted hair, and unwiped nose, Ralph wept for the end of innocence, the
darkness of men’s heart, and the fall through the air of the true, wise friend called Piggy.’ 61
Therefore, his ‘fall, which the by now thoroughly traumatised Ralph weeps over, is not just
his literal fall to his physical death, but an allegorical ‘fall’: the de-construction of
Humankind as rationally contracting agents. But the narrative groundwork for this convulsive
act is established much earlier, in Chapter Five, ‘Beast from the Water’,62 in which the
Chapter Five is the moment of intractable political crisis which is the mirroring of an even
more foundational crisis of knowledge: the failure to arrive at a final determination of the
nature (or ‘name’) of the Beast. As far as I am aware, no commentator has paid sufficient
attention to the pivotal speech delivered to the assembly by Maurice, a shadowy character
like Jack’s indecipherable lieutenant Roger but one who is vaguely within the Ralph-Piggy
58 Golding (n 19), 187-202.
of the Hobbesian Sovereign Ralph calls an ‘emergency session’ of the assembly in order to
reaffirm the binding nature of democratic decision-making.63 (It also provides him with a
Sovereignty: ‘He was searching his mind for simple words so that even the littluns64 would
understand what the assembly was about. Later, perhaps, practiced debaters—Jack, Maurice,
Piggy—would use their whole art to twist the meeting; but now at the beginning the subject
of the debate must be laid out clearly.’)65 But once democracy is invoked, everything turns
He [Ralph] moved the conch gently, looking beyond them at nothing, remembering the
beastie, the snake, the fire, the talk of fear.
‘Then people started getting frightened.’…
‘We’ve got to talk about this fear and decide there’s nothing in it. I’m frightened myself,
sometimes; only that’s nonsense! Like bogies. Then, when we’ve decided, we can start again
and be careful about things like fire.’67
The assembly scene is Golding’s ultimate riposte to both the representational theory of
language in general and to the Hobbes’ prescriptive regime of the correct, or principled, use
demonstrates.
63 Golding (n 5), 81-4.
66 Literally. One of the reason why Ralph convenes the Assembly is to establish some new rules about public
sanitation as the Boys have been using the gathering spot as a latrine: ‘We’ve got to use the rocks again. This
place is getting dirty.’ Golding (n 5), 86. It is widely underappreciated how scatological the Lord of the Flies is;
images of dirt, filth and blood populate the landscape. The constant referencing of the ‘dirty’ clearly signifies
the latent violence of the community (impurity) which is unconsciously awaiting the collective cleansing effect
(purification) of the ritualistic sacrifice. But I also believe that the scatological imagery also invokes the latent,
and ultimately ineradicable violence of Nature itself, a cosmic tapestry of overlapping predator-prey
relationships. For a discussion of the scatological in the novel, see L.L. Dickson, ‘Lord of the Flies’, in Harold
Bloom (ed.), William Golding’s Lord of the Flies New Edition (Infobase Publishing, 2008), 51-2. In the hands
of a master, even fecal matter may be allegorical.
Argument started again. Ralph held out the glittering conch and Maurice took it obediently.
The meeting subsided.
‘I mean when Jack says you can be frightened because people are frightened anyway that’s
all right. But when he says there’s only pigs on the island I expect he’s right but he doesn’t
know, not really, not certainly I mean’—Maurice took a breath—‘My daddy says there’s
things, what d’you call ’em that make ink—squids—that are hundreds of yards long and eat
whales whole.’ He paused again and laughed gaily.’ I don’t believe in the beast of course. As
Piggy says, life’s scientific, but we don’t know, do we? Not certainly, I mean—’69
It is an inconvenient truth that the successful operation of the logic of exclusion (or reasoning
a priori) is wholly contingent upon the completion of the system of knowledge being
deployed. Maurice’s epistemic ‘slide’ is the true turning point of the political narrative: no
one can agree upon the correct use of language leading to an act of secession based upon the
Someone shouted.
‘A squid couldn’t come up out of the water!’
‘Could.’
‘Couldn’t’.
In a moment the platform was full of arguing, gesticulating shadows. To Ralph, seated, this
seemed the breaking-up of sanity. Fear, beasts, no general agreement that the fire was all-
important: and when one tried to get the thing straight the argument sheered off, bringing up
fresh, unpleasant matter…The world, that understandable and lawful world, was slipping
away. Once there was this and that; and now…70
The stage is now set for the irreversible descent into political violence—a crisis that can only
be fully resolved through the elevation of the sacrificial mechanism raised to institutional
68 A nice patriarchal touch that makes Maurice’s rhetorical subversion that much more fatal; the ‘trace’ of the
grown-ups.
‘We persist in disregarding the power of violence in human societies; that is why we are
reluctant to admit that violence and the sacred are one and the same thing.’—Rene Girard
As Ralph himself memorably puts it, ‘Things are breaking up. I don’t understand why. We
began well; we were happy. And then—’71 The lethal power struggle between Ralph and Jack
that makes up the second half of the novel appears easy to understand in terms of my analysis
so far: Ralph names the Beast wrongly (he uses the wrong language), while Jack identifies
the enemy correctly and establishes his chiefdom.72 The problem is that they are both wrong.
The Boys, like Hobbes, are focused upon external reality, the object of representational
discourse; but as the Lord of the Flies himself (a visceral incarnation of Beelzebub) makes
clear to Simon during his mystic or epileptic trance (take your pick) in Chapter Eight, the fear
of the Beast is nothing more than the externalised projection of the latent fear induced by the
social order: ‘You knew, didn’t you? I’m part of you? Close, close, close! I’m the reason why
it’s no go? Why things are what they are?’73 The real question is why does ‘the break up’ (or
the downward spiral into violence) begin only after the Social Contract has been entered into
and the answer is because the contract alone is inadequate to expel the latent violence from
within the community. The unexpurgated remnant of violence forms the sinews of the novel’s
second narrative thread that entwines itself around the public procession of scapegoats: the
unrequited libidinal (mimetic) rivalry between the two candidates for the chieftainship, Ralph
and Jack.
He [Ralph] argued unconvincingly that they would let him alone; perhaps even make an
outlaw of him. But then the fatal unreasoning knowledge came to him again. The breaking of
the conch and the deaths of Piggy and Simon lay over the island like a vapor. These painted
71 Golding (n 5), 87.
72 I am certain that the reader by this time will be aware of the obvious applicability of the radical, if not
nihilistic, constitutional theories of Carl Schmitt to Golding’s novel. I am equally aware of them, but I simply
lack the space to pursue them here. I hope to do so on another occasion.
savages would go further and further. Then there was that indefinable connection between
himself and Jack; who therefore would never let him alone; never.74
In superficially political terms, Jack is the personification of the military power, which
always rests upon the residual threat of and use of violence, that aspect of the Executive that
is the most likely source of dictatorship. The need to hunt and kill the Beast provides the
perfect rationalisation for Jack to expand his ‘emergency powers’ at the expense of the
democratic governance through consultation, debate, and the ‘correct’ use of political and
legal speech, symbolised by his possession of the conch—the discovery of the conch having
been shown in Chapter One to be identical with the invention of the community. On a deeper
and more interesting level, both Jack and Ralph allegorically represent the contending forms
of the legal and political order; or, as Golding suggestively puts it, ‘Jack and Ralph smiled at
Readers unfamiliar with Leviathan may be surprised to learn that Hobbes offers two
competing versions of the Commonwealth either of which may be borne by the thoroughly
personalized nature of Hobbesian SovereigntySovereign: ‘And he that carries this Person [of
the community] is called Sovereign, and said to have Sovereign Power; and everyone besides,
his Subject.’76 Even more surprising is the stance of strict neutrality that Hobbes assumes vis-
The attaining to this Sovereign Power is by two ways. One, by natural force; as when a man
makes his children to submit themselves, and their children [in turn], to his government, as
being able to destroy them if they refuse; or by war subdues his enemies to his will, giving
them their lives on that condition. The other, is when men agree among themselves to submit
to some Man, or Assembly of men, voluntarily, on confidence to be protected by him against
This passage does great ‘violence’ to our 21st century Human Rights-driven sensibilities:
Hobbes is postulating a strict equivalence between the democratic and authoritarian forms of
was founded upon the Social Contract whereas we collectively (or metaphysically) refuse to
recognise the non-liberal State as a rightful Sovereign. But on Golding’s island this
Acquisition.
On a strictly political reading of the novel, the obvious problem emerges: given their
different political identities, both material and symbolic, should not Ralph and Jack be
enemies? Instead, Golding insists upon their friendship and mutual admiration for each other.
At the return Ralph found himself alone on a limb with Jack and they grinned at each other,
sharing the burden. Once more, amid the breeze, the shouting, the slanting sunlight on the
high mountain, was shed that glamour, that strange invisible light of friendship, adventure
and content.
‘Almost too heavy.’
Jack grinned back.
‘Not for the two of us.’ 78
Part of the answer is that Golding is ironically subverting the ‘bright-line distinction’ that we
normally accept as separating democracy from tyranny. As with Hobbes, Golding sees the
relationship between the Assembly and the One Man as inherently fluid, as the individual’s
submitting to any form of political and legal structure necessarily involves the surrender of
liberty, identical with the earlier act of conveyance of liberty to the Sovereign in exchange for
life. Golding, however, goes beyond Hobbes through his literary deployment of the cultural
logic of ritualistic sacrifice: all forms of political order require the internalisation and then
outward projection of that immortal violence based upon the eternal recurrence of rivalry and
imitation. Nowhere in Lord of the Flies is the logic of mimetic rivalry more clearly
allegorised than through the narrative positioning of Ralph and Jack as doubles, each
instinctual ‘appetites’ such as self-preservation or fear-of-death, Man, for Girard, ‘is the
creature who does not know what to desire, and he turns to others in order to make up his
mind. We desire what others desire because we imitate their desires.’79 Golding stages an
Ralph is now the model and Jack the thwarted imitator. For Girard, this is the moment of
catastrophe.
What are the consequences of imitation when, instead of patterning our desires according to
the suggestion of some cultural model, we imitate one another in our choice of desirable
objects? The model is anyone who suggests an object of desire to anyone else by desiring that
object himself. The model and his imitator desire the same object, and they necessarily
interfere with each other.81
79 Rene Girard, ‘Generative Scapegoating’ in Robert G. Hammerton-Kelly (ed.), Violent Origins: Walter
Burkert, Rene Girard, and Jonathan Z. Smith on Ritual Killing and Cultural Formation (Stanford, Stanford
University Press, 1987), 122.
with others, desire will invariably ‘mutate’ into a condition of irrepressible mimetic rivalry
between the ‘doubles’. If Girard’s theory of mimetic desire is correct, then the entrance into
the Hobbesian Social Contract guarantees that violence will escalate precisely because inter-
personal conflict is generated through the rivalry over possession of objects that are desired
by the group.
As I imitate the desire of my neighbour, I reach for the object he is already reaching for, and
we prevent each other from appropriating this object. His relation to my desire parallels my
relation to his, and the more we cross each other, the more stubbornly we imitate each other.
My interference intensifies his desire, just as his interference intensifies mine. This process of
positive feedback can only lead to physical and other forms of violence. Violence is the
continuation of mimetic desire by violent means…Violence is a symmetrical, reciprocal
process because it is mimetic.82
Girard’s concern with the mimetic nature of desire (the libido understood in a non-Freudian
sense) closely matches Hobbes’ abiding concern with the socially disruptive effects of the
passion of envy, discussed at fair length in Chapter XIII (‘Of the Naturall Condition of
Mankind, as concerning their Felicity and Misery’) where that particular vice is
From this [natural] equality of ability, arises equality of hope in the attainment of our
objectives. And therefore if any two men desire the same thing, which nevertheless they
cannot both enjoy, they become enemies; and in the way to their end, (which is principally
their own conservation, and sometimes their delectation only), endeavor to destroy, or subdue
one another.83
Not only is envy unavoidable given the social existence of Man (necessary for self-
preservation), but its ability to inflict misery is almost unrivalled among the passions.
81 Girard (n 79), 122. The obvious homoerotic allusions in Golding’s text merely reinforces this vial point: ‘
Like violence, sexual desire tends to fasten upon surrogate objects if the object to which it was originally
attracted remains inaccessible; it willingly accepts substitutes.’ Girard (n 17), 35.
Again, men have no pleasure (but on the contrary a great deal of griefe) in keeping company
where there is no power able to over-awe them all. For every man expects that his companion
should value him at the same rate he sets upon himself: and upon all signs of contempt, or
under-valuing, naturally endeavors, as far as he dares (which amongst them that have no
power to keep them subdued, is far enough to make them destroy each other), to extort a
greater value from his critics by gift; and from others, by the example. So that in the nature of
man, we find three principall causes of quarrel. First, Competition; Secondly, Diffidence
[Self-Assertion]; Thirdly, Glory.84
Girard, as we know, proposes a grand solution to this eternal grief: the ritualistic sacrifice of
the scapegoat.
The real solution to the problem of vengeance must lie in the very unyielding intensity of
mimetic rivalry. It must lie within murderous violence itself…The ‘scapegoat’ or unanimous-
victimage hypothesis satisfies this requirement. When mimetic violence permeates an entire
group and reaches a climatic intensity, it generates a form of collective victimage that tends
toward unanimity precisely because of the participant’s heightened mimetic susceptibility. 85
But Piggy puts it better: ‘“…I know there isn’t no fear…Unless we get frightened of
people.”’87
Here, Golding appears to follow Hobbes strictly in assuming that fear is the primary motive
society, which renders fully consistent with both texts Girard’s defining insight that the
through the re-direction of community wide violence towards the properly identified and
named scapegoat.
an inherently political and legal act. It establishes Jack’s absolute (and unrivalled) leadership
violence that will create the ‘truer’ community than the one premised upon the false (and by
now falsified) notion of the Social Contract. Most important of all, Jack’s (and Roger’s) tribal
society self-consciously utilises Religion and Theology, unlike Ralph’s Assembly which
In the silence that followed each savage flinched away from his individual memory.
‘No! How could we—kill—it?’
Half-relieved, half-daunted by the implication of further terrors, the savages murmured again.
‘So leave the mountain alone,’ said the Chief, solemnly, ‘and give [the Beast] the head if you
go hunting again.’…
‘I expect the beast disguised itself.’
‘Perhaps,’ said the Chief. A theological speculation presented itself. ‘We’d better keep on the
right side of him, anyhow. You can’t tell what he might do.’89
While it is clear that the establishment of Jack’s rule of One Man is concurrent with the
creation of a native Religion, it is frequently underappreciated that Jack and his hunters are
88 Admittedly, Golding’s narrative does some violence to the integrity of my close reading: as Girard makes
clear, the rival himself can never act as the victim, for the killing of the rival will perpetuate the cycle of
vengeance through retaliation (it will also appear too much like a ‘mere’ homicide); ordinarily another person,
or, even better, an animal is substituted for the rival who is then only ‘mimetically’ killed. What I can rely on
here is another of Girard’s observations: that the animal-surrogate selected will always bear a physical
resemblance to the original object. In Chapter Eight, ‘A Gift for the Darkness’, Jack impales the head of the sow
on a stick that is sharpened at both ends—the pig’s head later mutates into the ‘Lord of the Flies’ while, of
course, remaining a pig, which naturally reminds us of Piggy. The impaling of Ralph’s head on the stick
sharpened at both ends mimetically evokes Piggy, the bearer of the false consciousness of secular rationality and
the archetypal victim. So, in effect, the by now fully ritualistic killing of Ralph will be the re-enactment of the
foundational murder of Piggy/pig, with whom Ralph bears an almost fraternal similarity (Ralph = Piggy = pig)
and who is now the stand-in for Jack’s true enemy, the ‘atheistick’ Social Contract. (It is interesting to note that
in Chapter Eight at 138, Jack makes the following comment about Ralph: ‘“He’s like Piggy. He says things like
Piggy. He isn’t a proper chief.”’) And, of course, in the end all of Ralph’s followers have deserted him, meaning
that there is no one to avenge him; he becomes something of an obsolete rival. Strikingly, Golding inverts the
historical progression here: the offering of human-surrogates for an original animal victim. The correct mimetic
sequence should have been from Simon to Ralph to Piggy to the pig/Lord of the Flies, but this would have
presented too many narrative difficulties and threatened the all-important ‘moral of the story’. Girard (n 17), 11.
the progenitors of a nativist culture, specifically a form of body-art, the (re-) discovery of
Jack planned his new face. He made one cheek and one eye-socket white, then rubbed red
over the other half of his face and slashed a black bar of charcoal across from right ear to left
jaw. He looked in the mere for his reflection, but his breathing troubled the mirror…
He knelt, holding the shell of water. A rounded patch of sunlight fell on his face and a
brightness appeared in the depths of the water. He looked in astonishment, no longer at
himself but at an awesome stranger…He began to dance and his laughter became a
bloodthirsty snarling. He capered towards Bill and the mask was a thing on its own, behind
which Jack hid, liberated from shame and self-consciousness…The mask compelled them.90
Jack’s impulsive act both represents and successfully solves Ralph’s great political dilemma,
which is exactly the same as Hobbes’: monopolising the act of judgment through the proper
naming of things.
Ralph turned to the chief’s seat. They had never had an assembly so late before. That was
why the place looked so different. Normally the underside of the green roof was lit by a
tangle of golden reflections, and their faces were lit upside down, like—thought Ralph, when
you hold an electric torch in your hand. But now the sun was slanting in at one side, so that
the shadows were where they ought to be. Again he fell into that strange mood of speculation
that was so foreign to him. If faces were different when lit from above or below—what was a
face? What was anything?91
Which is exactly what you get for trying to enforce the Social Contract on an island that is
haunted; or, more precisely, where things do not objectively equate with the words we assign
them.
Strange things happened at midday. The glittering sea rose up, moved apart in planes of
blatant impossibility; the coral reef and the few, stunted palms that clung to the more elevated
parts would float up to the sky, would quiver, be plucked apart, run like rain-drops on a wire
or be repeated as in an odd succession of mirrors. Sometimes land loomed where there was
no land and flicked out like a bubble as the children watched. Piggy discounted all this
learnedly as a ‘mirage’; and since no boy could reach even the reef over the stretch of water
where the snapped sharks waited, they grew accustomed to mysteries and ignored them, just
as they ignored the miraculous throbbing stars. At midday the illusions merged into the sky
and there the sun gazed down like an angry eye.92
naming is order, as Hobbes shows in his brief disquisition on Adam and the naming of the
animals.93 But since the Boys are unconsciously governed by the logic of mimetic
substitution, nothing definitive about Nature can ever be definitively or conclusively said. As
Hobbes expresses it, ‘Naturall sense and imagination are not subject to absurdity. Nature it
selfe cannot erre: and as men abound in copiousnesse of language; so they become more
wise, or more mad than ordinary.’94 Or as Golding conveys it through the poetic imagination
that is immune to absurdity, ‘A flurry of wind made the palms talk and the noise seemed very
loud now that darkness and silence made it so noticeable. Two grey trunks rubbed each other
G. A Counter-Intuitive Conclusion
The orthodox reading of Lord of the Flies is very similar to any superficial reading of
Sigmund Freud’s Civilisation and Its Discontents: without the rule of law, or the presence of
the super-ego, ‘Man’ will naturally regress into savagery—or the domain of the Id. I have
argued, however, that the true twins to Golding’s text are Hobbes’ Leviathan and Girard’s
Violence and the Sacred. It is not the case that the Boys regress; rather, they unconsciously
act out the mimetic logic of cultural formation by transforming themselves into a real, but
‘primitive’ society, collectively undergoing not a descent but a kind of ascent. The island of
Piggy is a ‘bubble’ of false consciousness, bounded by the infinite envelope of the irrational,
A sliver of moon rose over the horizon, hardly large enough to make a path of light even
when it sat right down on the water; but there were other lights in the sky, that moved fast,
winked, or went out, though not even a faint popping came down from a battle fought at ten
miles height.97
The Beast that descends, the dead fighter-pilot who, as Golding helpfully explains to us,
represents the intrusion of History into the hermetically sealed of the Hobbesian thought
But a sign came down from the world of grown-ups, though at the time there was no child
awake to read it. There was a sudden bright explosion and a corkscrew trail across the sky;
then darkness again and stars. There was a speck above the island, a figure dropping swiftly
beneath a parachute, a figure that hung with dangling limbs. The changing winds of various
altitudes took the figure where they would. Then, three miles up, the wind steadied it and
bore it in a descending curve round the sky and swept it in a great arc in a great slant across
the reef and the lagoon towards the mountain. The figure fell and crumpled among the blue
flowers of the mountain-side, but now there was a gentle breeze at this height too and the
parachute flopped and banged and pulled…When the breeze blew the lines would strain taut
and some accident of this pull lifted the head and chest upright so that the figure seemed to
peer across the brow of the mountain. Then, each time the wind dropped, the lines would
slacken and the figure bow forward again, sinking its head between its knees. So as the stars
moved across the sky, the figure sat on the mountain-top and bowed and sank and bowed
again.100
98 Peter Edgerly Firchow, Modern Utopian Fictions: from H.G. Wells to Iris Murdoch (Washington D.C., The
Catholic University of America Press, 2007), 149.
the collective authors of the atomic warfare that envelops the children, yields the
Acquisition. The real reason why the Boys are the prisoners (or victims) of History is due not
to the weakness of civilisation but to its central and defining paradox: the political economy
of the Modern is the atavistic descendant of the sacrificial economy of the Paleolithic. And
like all first rate comedians, Golding saves his best joke for last.
He [Ralph] staggered to his feet, tensed for more terrors, and looked up at a huge peaked cap.
It was a white-topped cap, and above the green shade of the peak was a crown, an anchor,
gold foliage. He saw white drill, epaulettes, a revolver, a row of gilt buttons down the front of
a uniform.
A naval officer stood on the sand, looking down at Ralph in wary astonishment. On the beach
behind him was a cutter, her bows hauled up and held by two ratings. In the stern-sheets
another rating held a sub-machine gun.
The ululation faltered and died away.101
The deus ex machina-style entrance of the Navy Officer constitutes the novel’s ultimate
mimetic substitution: not the resurrection of Piggy but the trans-figuration of Jack. Ralph’s
encounter with the Man-in-Uniform (Jack as grown-up) on the beach reveals the truth of the
historical (and legal) line of succession from the ‘primitive’ to the ‘modern’ society, both
premised upon the ritualistic deployment of violence. The ululation stops because the arc of
102 Golding (n 5), 224. A final observation: on an island full of British schoolboys, only Jack and the naval
officer make any reference to their nationality. In the beginning Jack says: ‘“I agree with Ralph. We’ve got to
have rules and obey them. After all, we’re not savages. We’re English; and the English are the best at
everything. So we’ve got to do the right things.”’ At the end, the man-in-uniform says: ‘“I should have thought,”
said the officer as he visualized the search before him, “I should have thought that a pack of British boys—
you’re all British aren’t you?—would have been able to put up a better show than that—I mean—”’. Golding (n
5), 42 and 224.
35
Eric Wilson is a senior lecturer of law at Monash University, Melbourne, Australia. In 1991
he completed his Doctorate in the history of early modern Europe under the supervision of
Robert Scribner, Clare College, Cambridge. In 2005 he received the degree of Doctor of
Juridical Science (S.J.D.) from the University of Melbourne. He is the author of The Savage
Republic: De Indis of Hugo Grotius, Republicanism, and Dutch Hegemony in the Early
Modern World System (c.1600-1619), published by Martinus Nijhoff in 2008. He is the editor
of a series of works on critical criminology, the first volume of which was published by Pluto
Press in 2009 as Government of the Shadows: Parapolitics and Criminal Sovereignty. The
second volume in the series, The Dual State: Parapolitics, Carl Schmitt and the National
Security State Complex, was published by Ashgate in late 2012. He is currently preparing the
third volume, which is a study of the covert origins and dimensions of the French and
American wars in Viet Nam. His research interests include Law and Literature, the
comparative law of Southeast Asia, critical jurisprudence, the history and philosophy of
international law, and critical criminology.