Commons and Cooperatives: Greig de Peuter and Nick Dyer-Witheford

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 27

Commons and Cooperatives

Greig de Peuter and Nick Dyer-Witheford1

Abstract

In the last decade, the commons has become a prevalent theme


in discussions about collective but decentralized control over
resources. This paper is a preliminary exploration of the potential
linkages between commons and cooperatives through a discussion
of the worker cooperative as one example of a labour commons.
We view the worker coop as a response at once antagonistic and
accommodative to capitalism. This perspective is amplified through
a consideration of five aspects of an ideal-type worker
cooperativism: associated labour, workplace democracy, surplus
distribution, cooperation among cooperatives, and, controversially,
links between worker cooperatives and socialist states. We
conclude by suggesting that the radical potential of worker
cooperatives might be extended, theoretically and practically, by
elaborating connections with other commons struggles in a process
we term the circulation of the common.

Commoners and workers

In the last decade, talk of “commons,” “commoning,” and even


“commonwealth,” has become, well, common, on the left in discussions of
collective but decentralized control over resources ranging from farmlands to
fresh water, ocean fisheries, clean air, software code, and genetic information.2
Starting point for critical accounts of the commons is typically the historical
destruction of the collective land of pre-capitalist agricultural communities; in
Europe between the 16th and 18th centuries these were enclosed by mercantile
landlords eager to sell agricultural goods in an expanding world market. Such
enclosures were a crucial part of the process of primitive accumulation,
creating early capitalism’s dispossessed proletariat from displaced rural
populations. These commoners did not go quietly: enclosure faced “hydra-
headed” opposition, but these struggles were lost and largely forgotten.3

Interest in commons was revived by neoliberalism. Confronting the late-


twentieth century onrush of global capital, activists and theorists found in the
image of the commons a perspective from which to criticize privatization,
deregulation, and expropriation in numerous domains: land wars caused by the
continuing enclosure of farmlands and displacement of rural populations by

Greig de Peuter and Nick Dyer-Witheford, “Commons and Cooperatives,” Affinities: A Journal of
Radical Theory, Culture, and Action, Volume 4, Number 1, Summer 2010, pp. 30-56.
31

agribusiness, energy mega-projects and urban developers in Asia, Latin


America, and Africa; ecological struggles over issues from pesticide poisoning to
clear-cutting to species-extinctions and climate change; digital activism such as
the free and open-source software movements and ‘creative commons’
challenges to intellectual property law; and resistances to corporate ownership
of the genome of plants, animals, and humans. Commons has become a
concept connecting multifarious struggles against capital’s old but ongoing
primitive accumulation and its new horizons of futuristic, high-tech
accumulation.

Beyond resistance to enclosures, commons politics involve renewed attention


on the forms of association through which communities can govern shared
resources. The once powerful idea of “the tragedy of the commons”--which
claimed that, without the protection of private property rights, natural resources
will be degraded by neglect--has been not just challenged but reversed by
theorists proposing a “cornucopia of the commons” or “inverse commons” in
which collectives produce more robust, inventive results than commercial
entities.4 The vocabulary of commons has, moreover, provided anti-corporate
and anti-capitalist movements a way of talking about collective ownership
without invoking a bad history--without conjuring up “communism,”
conventionally narrowly understood as a command economy plus a repressive
state. Commons discourse resumes older discussions about “public goods,” but
breaks new ground, both in the range of ecological, biogenetic, and cultural
domains it addresses, and in its interest in the possibilities for the organization of
resources from below, rather than according to the models of command
economies or bureaucratic welfare states.

Commons politics, and the discourse around it, has its limitations. The term
commons has come to cover a proliferation of proposals, some highly radical,
but also some reformist, and others even potentially reactionary. As George
Caffentzis points out, neoliberal capital, confronting the debacle of free-market
policies, is turning to “Plan B”: limited versions of commons--be it carbon trading
models, community development schemes, biotechnology research, and open-
source practices--are introduced as subordinate aspects of a capitalist
economy.5 Here voluntary cooperation does not so much subvert capital as
subsidize it. Just as the original commons were an element within, rather than an
alternative to, a brutally coercive feudal order, so, too, in isolation, today’s
commons experiments may just supplement, not challenge, capitalist
exploitation. In addition, and germane to the focus of this article, while discourse
about commons is popular among environmental, digital, and biotechnological
activists, it is often disconnected from labour politics. Talk of commons less
frequently intersects with the lexicon of unions, solidarity, and strikes. It thus risks
being disassociated from issues of work and wealth, class and poverty--where
what is at stake is, still, capital’s denial of commonality via the private control of

Greig de Peuter & Nick Dyer-Witheford


32

the means of production. It is as an antidote to this rift that this article discusses
the worker cooperative as one form of labour commons.6

Worker cooperatives are a historically deep element in counter-capitalist


movements from the 19th and early 20th centuries, and are a resurgent
component in the contemporary search for economic assemblages alternative
to planet-wide capitalism. This paper suggests “the new cooperativism,” to use
the term framing this journal issue, be situated in the context of a wide set of
struggles over various forms of commons. Linking together commons and
cooperatives is, we believe, valuable on several counts. The history of the worker
cooperative movement provides a practical demonstration of the art of
collective association key to all commoning practices. It also offers an example
of decentralized control of common resources that potentially connects the
traditions of labour struggle to the modes of activism honed by both ecological
and networked radicals. At the same time, the scope and diversity of commons
activism indicates the broader currents for social change with which
cooperativism must be interwoven if it is to become part of “the coming
economies” beyond capital.7

Cooperatives can be seen as a response, at once antagonistic and


accommodative, to capitalism. This point is amplified in what follows through a
brief consideration of five aspects of ideal-type worker cooperative practice:
associated labour, workplace democracy, surplus redistribution, cooperation
among cooperatives, and, controversially, links between cooperatives and
socialist states. Elements of these constitute the worker coop as a labour
commons. We suggest in our conclusion, however, that the extension and
actualization of the radical potential of worker cooperatives requires
interconnection with other commons struggles--a process we term the
circulation of the common. Our essay’s perspective is Marxist, but one informed
by other traditions of anti-capitalism present in both commons and cooperative
struggles.

Associated labour

As capitalism enclosed the commons and destroyed traditional agrarian


communities, cooperatives were one form of collective organization that the
dispossessed proletariat adopted in an attempt to maintain its security and
dignity amid the hellish new industrial order. It was in response to “the social
dislocations of the industrial revolution” that in 1844 the most famous prototype
of cooperativism arose in Rochdale, England, the Rochdale Society of Equitable
Pioneers.8 Industrial wage labourers, unemployed craft workers, and customers
frustrated by commercial swindles discovered in the cooperative a means to
exercise greater collective control over production and consumption. By the
mid 1800s, cooperatives were an integral part of the social fabric of many

Commons and Cooperatives


33

English towns, spanning customer-owned retail stores to worker-owned factories


to free adult-education classes run by coop societies.

The same period saw a mix of enthusiastic and trenchant commentary on


cooperatives. Marx, in 1864, would laud the “cooperative movement, especially
the cooperative factories”:

The value of these great social experiments cannot be overrated.


By deed, instead of by argument, they have shown that production
on a large scale, and in accord with the behests of modern
science, may be carried on without the existence of a class of
masters employing a class of hands.9

Marx viewed the coop factories within a historical dialectic of social forms of
labour: the cooperatives demonstrated to him “that, like slave labour, like serf
labour, hired labour is but a transitory and inferior form, destined to disappear
before associated labour plying its toil with a willing hand, a ready mind, and a
joyous heart.”10

At a broader, strategic level, Marx was circumspect about the value of the
coops. “Excellent in principle” and “useful in practice,” he insisted “cooperative
labour,” confined to a “narrow circle of the casual efforts of private workman,
will never be able to arrest the growth in geometrical progression of monopoly,
to free the masses, nor even to perceptibly lighten the burden of their
miseries.”11 What Marx goes on to say--“To conquer political power has therefore
become the great duty of the working class”--perhaps helps to explain why
relatively few in the Marxian tradition would examine coops in the coming
decades.12 “Restricted to dwarfish forms,” Marx concluded, “the cooperative
system will never transform capitalist societies.”13

There is some dispute about the balance of positive and negative elements in
this complex assessment of coops.14 We will revisit Marx’s comments on the
shortcomings of the worker coop later. For the moment, we return to Marx’s
allusion to “associated labour” as a collective subjectivity animating the
cooperative factories.15 Picking up on a reference by Marx to a “mode of
production of associated labour,” Teinosuke Otani has spoken of “associated
labour” as work that “sheds the alienated guise it has had as wage labour.”16
Associated labour is, suggests Otani, voluntary (i.e. people are no longer forced
to work for a wage in order to exist); communal; consciously planned; on a
sufficient scale to mobilize “social productive power”; scientific (i.e. using
modern technologies); satisfying workers’ needs (i.e. as against the
subordination of those needs to the requirements of capital); and realizing
participants’ “species being,” or, broadly, their interconnection with other
humans.

Greig de Peuter & Nick Dyer-Witheford


34

The at least partial fit between associated labour and the worker cooperative is
noted by Michael Lebowitz. The power of capital, writes Lebowitz, derives from
“captur[ing] the fruits of cooperation.”17 In the capital-labour relation, he goes
on to say, “each wage labourer is an individual, isolated owner of labour-
power.” In contrast, in a worker coop where the business is collectively owned
and controlled, the individual no longer meets capital as an isolated seller of
their labour capacity, but, rather, confronts capital as associated power.
Moreover, rather than capital acting as “mediator for wage-labour,” the worker
cooperative replaces “capital as mediator … in the purchase of labour-
power.”18 As the Canadian Worker Coop Federation puts it: “In a worker coop
capital is the servant of the cooperative.”19 This apparent inversion of the power
relation between labour and capital has implications that extend to workers’
control over the labour process, in that associated cooperative labour also
replaces capital, says Lebowitz, “in the direction and supervision of
production.”20 Not immediately answerable to the managers of capital,
potentially “the whole nature of work can change”:

Workers can cooperate with each other to do their jobs well; they
can apply their knowledge about better ways to produce to
improve production both immediately and in the future; and, they
can end the division in the workplace between those who think and
those who do.21

Although Lebowitz is not dismissive of Marx’s own worry that cooperators can just
the same “become their own capitalist,” he also cites Marx’s more optimistic
view of worker coops as “practical demonstration that capital was not
necessary as mediator in social production,” and, as such, act as an example of
a “‘republican and beneficent system of the association of free and equal
producers.’”22

For a contemporary example of such a system, one could cite FaSinPat, an


abbreviation of Fábrica Sin Patrón, which translates as “factory without
bosses.”23 FaSinPat is a 400-member, worker-owned and -controlled ceramic tile
plant in Argentina. The context of its emergence was the collapse of the
country’s economy in 2001-2002, when the contradictions of Argentina’s
neoliberal restructuring exploded. During a lockout, workers self-organized
against their notoriously anti-labour employer, subverted their compliant union
bureaucracy, took the decision to illegally enter the factory, restarted
production independently, and adopted the assembly as a political model for
democratic decision-making in the workplace. After a protracted battle in the
courts, the tile workers were granted the right to operate as a cooperative.

Commons and Cooperatives


35

Assumption of the legal form of the coop made FaSinPat recognizable in the
eye of the state, thus providing some shelter to this enclave of self-management
within a national context in which job creation was a matter of survival. Here we
note that the “key need” to which the worker cooperative is said to respond is
that for “viable and meaningful employment for its members.”24 What is more,
however, is the broader set of principles associated with worker cooperativism,
including those of “self-help, democracy, equality, equity, and solidarity.”25
FaSinPat has been described as a factory put “at the service of the
community.”26 To take just one example, cooperators have directed portions of
their surplus toward the funding of the construction of a local health clinic.
Through acts of solidarity such as this, FaSinPat supports the needs of its
surrounding neighbourhood, the residents of which initially aided workers in the
reclamation of the plant from its former owner. FaSinPat has justifiably become
an icon of the autonomous power of associated labour in the wider currents of
self-management in Argentina today.27

Workplace democracy

“Democracy” was for the Rochdale Pioneers “the fundamental principle of


cooperation,” and “the principle most sharply differentiating cooperatives from
capitalist business.”28 Its strongest expression is when the division of worker and
owner is eradicated, where the worker cooperative is comprised not of
employer and employees, but rather of a membership of worker-owners who
collectively own the assets of the coop.29 In addition to collective ownership, the
worker coop is distinguished as a “democratically controlled” organization; this is
reflected, at the most basic level, in a commitment to equity, namely, one
person, one vote--as opposed to one’s capacity to make, and influence,
decisions being proportionate to one’s quantity of property.30 According to the
Canadian Worker Coop Federation: “Through the democratic governance of
the coop, all members have equal opportunity to affect the way the business is
run and to offer input on the decisions affecting their everyday work lives.”31

If cooperative workplace democracy extends the opportunity to the people


who work in a coop to govern its operation, how this plays out in practice of
course varies widely. Worker coop members generally elect a board of directors
drawn from the membership of the coop itself--unlike in a conventional capitalist
firm where employees have no say in the appointment of directors. Further to
this, a coop might devolve decision-making power in various ways. For example,
at the 400-member FaSinPat, there are thirty “work units,” each one electing a
committee representative who represents the department at coop wide weekly
assemblies attended by all workers, although workers collectively “vote to
approve or reject the departments’ proposals.”32 Assemblies address not only
production issues, but also “joint campaigns with other community groups.”33 At
Mondragón Corporación Cooperativa (MCC)--the famously successful inter-

Greig de Peuter & Nick Dyer-Witheford


36

cooperative group in the Basque Country with more than 150 coops and 85,000
workers34--each individual coop in the group has its own Governing Council,
and each coop elects delegates who in turn attend an annual meta-MCC
Governing Council assembly.35 Budget allocations, compensation policies, and
expansion plans are among the topics conceivably up for collective voting.

One of the main goals associated with worker cooperatives is said to be that of
“increasing democracy in the workplace.”36 One instance of this pertains to pay
equity. Historically, MCC, for example, has had in place a policy setting limits on
the disparity between the highest and lowest paid in a cooperative.37 Some
worker coops even practice almost complete pay equity despite differences in
skill sets or seniority, such as in many of Argentina’s worker-recuperated
enterprises.38 Where management is concerned, coop managers are generally
expected to take decisions in the light of cooperative principles.39 The broad
point of workplace democracy is, however, that the notion of member control
implies members possess a greater ability to shape the content of their job and
the environment in which it is performed--a commitment to dignity in work. In this
respect, a worker cooperative with a more radical membership might seek to
implement tactics for challenging a rigid division of labour by adopting a version
of what participatory economics theorists Michael Albert and Robin Hahnel term
a “balanced job complex” in which workers would perform a mix of roles so that
rewarding and onerous tasks are more equitably distributed.40

Providing “the best possible employment conditions for the members” is


regarded as one of the central goals of a worker cooperative.41 Critics point out,
however, that a philosophical commitment to workplace democracy does not
guarantee an experience of empowerment at work. Based on interviews with
shop floor worker-owners at MCC, for example, Sharryn Kasmir reports that
apathy, oppression, and hierarchy persist in these cooperative workplaces.42
Kasmir attributes this to a division of power that still tilts in favour of managers.
While this might suggest there is a place for a union, trade unionists and worker
cooperators have had a sometimes-tense relationship.43 Kasmir rejects the
assumption that labour unions are redundant in a worker coop, and, in the case
of MCC, worries that the discourse of cooperativism risks obviating class struggle,
separating coop workers from other segments of the working class, and
disproportionately rewarding managers. Hahnel likewise notes that although
representative democratic procedures are in place at MCC, there has been a
“drift toward greater managerial domination of decision making,” and,
moreover, the commitment to pay equity has been weakened, posing the risk
of the “reemergence of class divisions.”44

We can see both strengths and limits of worker coops’ self-definition in terms of
democracy by looking at one of the better-known social-democratic arguments
in support of worker-ownership. Against “corporate capitalism,” Robert Dahl’s

Commons and Cooperatives


37

case for “economic democracy” is based on a parallel he sees between the


state and the enterprise: both are a “political system,” in that each involves a
power relation between the governor and the governed.45 If this is accepted,
he asks, “is it not appropriate to insist that the relationship between governors
and governed (in the enterprise) should satisfy the criteria of the democratic
process--as we properly insist in the domain of the state?” Dahl reasons that if
democracy is deemed inappropriate in regard to enterprise, then it cannot be
justified at the level of the state either. In terms of worker ownership specifically,
for Dahl, a worker coop does not negate property rights but democratizes them,
in the process distributing wealth in a manner that reflects and fosters equity.
More broadly, Dahl suggests that the decentralization of control at the level of
the enterprise promotes democracy within but also beyond it by expanding
opportunities to participate in making decision on matters that affect one’s life.
Critics of coops, however, are not so certain about this diffusing influence, but
fear, rather, that the line of influence can run the other way, from the anti-
democracy of the market into the coop, corrupting its emancipatory promise:
this is a discussion we return to later.

Surplus distribution

One of the traits linking the worker coop to commons traditions concerns the
distribution of economic surplus. For George Holyoake, a nineteenth-century
historian of the British cooperative movement, the overriding cooperative
principle is that of the “distribution of profits to all those who had a hand in
generating them, including both consumers and employees.”46 Commitment to
distributive justice is embedded in the cooperative principle of “member
economic participation.”47 Put in Holyoake’s class-conscious terminology,
cooperativism is rooted in a belief that “[i]t is more reasonable and better for
society and progress that men (sic) should own capital than that capital should
own men (sic). Capital is the servant, men (sic) are the masters.”48 The worker
coop is an institution of the labour commons where worker-owners view surplus
as a product of their shared efforts, and, as such, ought to be distributed
equitably and democratically among those who created it.

Remuneration practices in coops vary widely. MCC, for example, uses the term
anticipos, rather than “wages,” to refer to the monies paid out at regular
intervals to individual worker-owners as an advance on anticipated earnings.
Other coops speak of a “draw” account to which dividends are deposited
regularly. In terms of setting compensation levels, some coops might take their
cue from private businesses operating in the same sector, others might adopt a
strict wage-equity policy as with some worker coops in Argentina, and others
still, especially those occupying a competitive industry and employing
managers, might impose a ceiling on the differential between the highest and
lowest paid occupational levels as with Mondragón.

Greig de Peuter & Nick Dyer-Witheford


38

Some studies have suggested that productivity in coops matches and


sometimes exceeds that of conventional firms.49 If, after wages and operational
expenses are covered, the coop has a surplus, this leaves the question of its
distribution. This surplus is likely to be modest on account of the cooperative
principle of “limited returns on capital.” How surplus is distributed in a
cooperative in practice varies of course. But, generally, and in keeping with the
cooperative commitment to workplace democracy, worker-owners decide on it
through collective mechanisms, and it will typically be set in a coop’s by-laws.
Theoretically, however, worker-owners may have the option to vote for an
increased individual bonus, or dividend, as a means of consuming the surplus.
The attractiveness of this option to individual cooperators would lead some
critics to fear that there is a tendency toward self-exploitation as coops come to
internalize capitalist behaviour. Marxist critics of coops might argue worker-
owners have a strong self-interested incentive to increase their individual return,
rather than to invest surplus in fixed capital or reserve savings to make the
enterprise more sustainable in the long run; this is one reason some statist
socialists who see merit in coops with regard to control of the labour process
might advocate publicly-owned worker-managed firms over full worker-
ownership.

To open up some of the issues around “surplus possibilities,” it is useful to turn to


MCC, probably the most famous of all contemporary worker cooperatives.50
Headquartered in the Basque region of Spain, MCC is an inter-cooperative
group of more than 150 worker-owned coops whose core activities range from
retailing groceries to manufacturing automotive parts. It maintains (for the time
being) the standard of socio-economic development that thousands of mostly
industrial coop workers have toiled to achieve in the Basque since the first coop
in the MCC network was launched in 1956 by a group of young engineers. They
did so under the leadership of Don José María Arizmendiarrieta, a Catholic priest
who advocated cooperativism as a strategy for the collective survival and self-
determination of the Basque people in response to widespread unemployment
and cultural repression under the then ruling fascist Franco regime.

MCC’s success can be attributed in part to the way this coop network has
managed its surpluses. At the meta-governance level of MCC’s General
Council, some time ago cooperators voted to implement policies pertaining to
the administration of the surplus that would counteract the risk to sustainability
posed by individual economic self-interest. Ten percent of MCC’s surplus,
following a Spanish law, is redirected toward charities, education, or culture,
etc. How the remainder is distributed is at the discretion of worker-owners. In the
current MCC model, 70% of the surplus is distributed as a dividend to individual
worker-owners’ individual capital accounts. Although the member can
withdraw the interest earned on the account, the principle amount is

Commons and Cooperatives


39

inaccessible until the member retires or resigns. Surplus is therefore used to


protect and promote job growth, arguably MCC’s modus operandi.

Today MCC is not only one of the ten top-earning corporate groups in Spain but
is increasingly internationalizing production through foreign direct investment in
emerging economies. In countries such as China and Hungary MCC operates
industrial affiliates as conventional capitalist firms--typically run by Basque
managers--in a familiar quest for reduced labour costs and for proximity to their
industrial clients. Relocation has strengthened the core coops’ competitiveness
on the world market. Those who view coop praxis through an anarchist lens of
the coherence of means and ends are, not surprisingly, deeply critical of MCC’s
globalization methods, seeing it as a drift away from cooperative principles.

Cooperation among cooperatives

This brings us to an issue central to our thesis about the need for cooperatives to
connect to other commons initiatives--that of coops’ relation to the wider
economic order. From the perspective of cultivating economic autonomy, the
development of links within the cooperative sector itself is of great significance.
The sixth principle in the Statement of Cooperative Identity is “cooperation
among cooperatives”--an ethos of mutual aid that encourages individual coops
to support one another and contribute to the development of a parallel
economy through practices of inter-cooperation.51 In this way, coops would
reduce their dependence on, and seek to gain autonomy from, conventional
capitalist enterprises; this is the movement-building aspect of cooperativism.

In addition to the formation of coop associations (e.g. International Cooperative


Alliance), one possible manifestation of cooperation among cooperatives is
inter-cooperative sourcing--the sourcing of products and services from other
coops. For instance, a consumer coop might have a purchasing policy in place
requiring employees always try sourcing a product from a coop supplier before
buying from a conventional firm. Similarly, a worker coop might seek to
concentrate on supplying other worker coops or consumer coops. These are
examples of a “cooperative economy,” in which an objective is “the creation of
a social structure capable of supplanting … profit-making industry.”52

Pragmatically, however, inter-cooperative sourcing can be a challenge, as it


can be time-intensive simply to find a coop seller; one can imagine, however, a
role for cooperatives associations to respond to this dilemma by creating a
coop-centered version of the Social Purchasing Portals currently used by a small
but growing number of city governments to connect purchasers and sellers who
are mutually commitment to “social economy” values.53

Greig de Peuter & Nick Dyer-Witheford


40

Another example of inter-coop cooperation is the development of means of


financing for coops. Under-capitalization is a chronic problem in the coop
sector; this explains the disproportionate number of worker-coops in lines of
business that are often more labour intensive rather than capital intensive.
Credit unions are hence of strategic importance in the development of a
cooperative sub-system. To see these dynamics at work we can turn again to
MCC. An ethos of inter-cooperation has been integral to Mondragón since its
early days. The success of MCC is often attributed to Caja Laboral, which was
positioned at a nodal point within a wider multifunctional coop to aggregate
coop surplus and to redistribute it to meet the needs of, and expand, the
network of coops.54 One of the premises behind Caja Laboral is that retaining
local jobs depends upon maintaining local control over savings. Caja Laboral
retains the surplus, and offers loans, at affordable interest rates, to new coops,
and also manages a fund that aids coops in periods of financial need. In
addition to these forms of direct financial support, Caja Laboral also offers MCC
coops “extensive research assistance on technologies, products, and markets,
(and) in-depth training in cooperative principles of management.”55 The new
coops that are supported with the collective’s surplus potentially provide
services or manufacture goods that serve the needs of other coops in the
network, and therefore reduce MCC’s reliance on external capitalist suppliers.

There are also examples of coops and associations based in the North
establishing education programs where groups of people visit the South and aid
communities in setting up coops, as an approach to cooperative international
development. MCC also demonstrates this; its Lanki project establishes links
between the coops in the Basque and small coops in the South:

The idea is to join forces and knowledge within the framework of an


inter-cooperation system, which was set up with the objective of
aiding comprehensive self-management processes focusing mainly
on grassroots economics organizations in the developing world. The
key which defines this new channel for cooperation is the
establishment of a bi-directional flow for these organizational
processes, which constitute the seeds for endogenous, sustainable
and equitable development.56

Practices of cooperation among coops suggest the possibility that within the
overall global system of capital a non-capitalist sub-system might grow its
counter-power, reduce reliance on the primary system, and potentially render it
redundant. In inter-coop cooperation we see at least a nascent possibility of
how the social product of the labour commons can contribute to the expansion
of a new system which seeks to continually enlarge its autonomy. Before
exploring this possibility further, however, we should look at the vexed issue of
worker coops’ relation to state socialist projects.

Commons and Cooperatives


41

State support

Marx, as we have seen, saw the cooperatives of the 19th century as important
and inspiring--but ultimately an inadequate strategy for supplanting capitalism.
Revolutionary energies ought to concentrate, he believed, on the taking of
state power. In looking forward to a post-capitalist society, however, Marx spoke
of how “cooperative labour ought to be developed to national dimensions,
and, consequently, to be fostered by national means.”57 This would become a
familiar socialist model in the 20th century: Lenin declared the “growth of
cooperation … identical with the growth of socialism”;58 Stalin insisted on more
direct state involvement in coops, which were regarded as a “school for
communism”;59 Mao made commune membership mandatory; and, next to the
hyper-centralization of the Soviet model, Tito promoted a comparatively
decentralized system of “workers’ self-management” in Yugoslavia in which
each worker belonged to a Basic Organization of Associated Labour.60

The legacy of worker coops in socialist states is controversial. Not least because
political autonomy and voluntary membership are among the longstanding
principles of cooperativism, while socialist models have subordinated these
values to state authority.61 It seems undeniable, however, that the creation,
maintenance, and proliferation of worker coops today depend on the
existence of state support of some kind. At minimum, there must be a legal
framework recognizing the cooperative as a legitimate form of enterprise.
Beyond this, governments may have varying levels of policy commitment to
support the development of cooperatives.62 In this regard, the contemporary
experiment in state-supported cooperativism that attracts most attention is the
“cooperative revolution” in Venezuela.63

Since the election of Hugo Chávez, cooperatives have become a prominent


part of Venezuela’s national economic policy.64 In 1999 the Venezuelan
constitution was revised to enshrine the state’s responsibility for the promotion
and protection of coops; in 2001 a Special Law on Cooperative Associations
was passed; and in 2003 the then newly created Ministry of Popular Economy
broadened the range of government support for coop development by, for
example, funding buy-outs and providing self-management training. When
Chávez took office, fewer than 1,000 coops were registered (representing about
20,000 members). By 2006, more than 100,000 coops were registered
(representing over one million members)--a third in commerce, restaurants, and
hotels; another third in transport, storage, and communications; and the rest
divided between agriculture, hunting and fishing, and manufacturing. While
most of these coops are small, an important subset is comprised of large
industrial cooperatives, which can be the result of a national expropriation
policy that targets bankrupted firms and converts them into coops.

Greig de Peuter & Nick Dyer-Witheford


42

The relationship between the Venezuelan state and individual cooperatives is


guided by the concept of “co-management.” Described as “an alternative to
capitalism,” Lebowitz contrasts co-management to the system of Yugoslav self-
management.65 In the latter, Lebowitz writes, “[t]he focus of workers within each
firm was on their own self-interest.… What was missing was a sense of solidarity
with society as a whole, a sense of responsibility to and responsibility for
society.”66 Although the Yugoslav enterprises were state-owned, and viewed as
social property, they functioned in the market and were driven by the interest of
the workers in the confines of an individual enterprise.

Co-management, by contrast, implies both solidarity with communities external


to the enterprise and state involvement in coop operations. Coops designated
“social production enterprises” are obliged to set aside a portion of their surplus
for local social uses; such policies regulating the distribution of surpluses attempt
to embed coops in their local community. Co-management also seeks to
achieve other policy objectives of the Venezuelan government, from
combating unemployment to fostering local economic-development
alternatives to dependency on foreign corporations. Above all perhaps, co-
management refers to a state ownership stake, especially in firms operating in
strategic industries; in expropriated plants in such industries, the ownership
arrangements are such that the state owns 51%, workers 49%. Expropriated
plants may be run by elected representatives of workers “alongside government
appointees.”67

Lebowitz contrasts the “triangle” of capitalism (private property, exploitation of


labour, and production for profit) to Chávez’s “elementary triangle of socialism”:
units of social property, social production organized by workers, and production
for the needs of communities:

Co-management implies a particular kind of partnership--a


partnership between the workers of an enterprise and society. Thus,
it stresses that enterprises do not belong to the workers alone--they
are meant to be operated in the interest of the whole society. In
other words, co-management is not intended only to remove the
self-interested capitalist, leaving in place self-interested workers;
rather, it is also meant to change the purpose of productive activity.
It means the effort to find ways both to allow for the development
of the full potential of workers and also for every member of society,
all working people, to be the beneficiaries of co-management.68

The limits, contradictions, and obstacles to co-management in Venezuela are


many. Venezuelan co-management is nonetheless perhaps the major
experiment in popular economic participation so far in the twenty-first century.

Commons and Cooperatives


43

Capitalist co-option or circulating common?

J.K. Gibson-Graham and their colleagues problematize what they see as a


“capitalocentrism” suffusing anti-capitalist discourse.69 It is suggested that the
categories of mode of production used by Marx are to be understood not as
“historic chronology but as a formal typology that could be present in any
combination.”70 A worker coop could thus be viewed as a “communal
enterprise” within and against capital’s dominant distributive logic to the extent
that in a worker cooperative “the workers who produce the wealth also
collectively appropriate and distribute the surplus associated with their
productive economic activity.”71 How surplus wealth is managed is, as we noted
earlier, one of the sharpest distinctions between a worker coop and a
conventional capitalist firm. Does this mean that worker-owners, in a situation
where common ownership over assets is combined with labour’s sovereignty
over the surplus, have transcended capitalist exploitation?72

Some would regard this line of questioning as naïve. Here it must be noted that
running throughout this paper is a familiar but fundamental point: that, from the
perspective of anti-capitalism, the worker coop is a deeply ambivalent
organizational form. The issue is not only that worker coops are vastly uneven in
terms of the political commitments animating them. Even more basic is the
ambiguity arising from how worker coops operate inside the wider capitalist
economy and therefore escape neither the discipline of the market nor the
hegemony of the commodity form.73 This market containment is one of the
reasons why the radical labour movement and some socialist theorists have
been skeptical of coops as a means to counteract capital.74 We have already
cited Marx’s critique of the tendency of cooperatives within capitalism to
assume “dwarfish forms.” The radical economist Robin Hahnel expands on this
concern:

[W]hen worker-owned firms must compete in goods, labour, and


financial markets with capitalist firms which adhere to the bottom
line there is relentless pressure on worker-owners to abandon
prioritizing the quality of work life and fair systems of compensation,
and to succumb to exploitative relations with suppliers, customers,
external parties, and the environment.75

Elements of a cooperative ethos can even be framed as a way of revitalizing


capitalism when capitalists confront declining productivity and employee
morale. Take, for example, the logic at play in Richard Reeves’ article “We Love
Capitalism,” published in The New Statesman: “The solution is this: for the people
who work in an enterprise to have a real financial stake in its long-term
performance. Firms in which employees are also the ‘co-owners’ are more

Greig de Peuter & Nick Dyer-Witheford


44

productive, with more engaged employees.” Reeves is careful to stress that this
is not about “reheated cooperatives,” but rather “the next-generation capitalist
business model.” He refers to this model as “socialism without the state”--or
“capitalism with more capitalists.”76

For worker coops to avert a co-optive fate they must be part of a larger vector
of transformation moving beyond capitalism. The failure of authoritarian state
socialism, the ascendancy of neoliberalism, and, recently, its catastrophic
financial crisis, have prompted a wave of new thinking about the form of such
system-change, such as the schematic models of “life after capitalism” offered
by Michael Albert, or the more fluid conceptualizations of a post-capitalist
politics proposed by Gibson-Graham.77 As a contribution to this discussion, we
propose the concept of “the circulation of the common.”78 It is, again, Marx
who provides our point of reference--not, however, so much as a theorist of the
seizure of state power but rather as an analyst of how modes of production
emerge, grow, and become self-perpetuating.

Marx deemed the “cell form” of capitalism to be the commodity, a good


produced for exchange between private owners.79 In the “circuit of capital” the
commodity is exchanged for money, which buys resources in turn transformed
into more commodities.80 This cycle is expressed in the formula, M_C – . . . P . . .
C' ─ M'. Money (M) purchases as commodities (C) labour, machinery, and raw
materials for production (P) to create new commodities (C') that are sold for
more money (M'), part of which is retained as profit, part used to purchase more
means of production to make more commodities; rinse and repeat. This
becomes an auto-catalytic, self-generating, boot-strapping process.

Within this circuit, there are different kinds of capital. The transformation of
commodities into money (C-M) is the role of mercantile capital; the production
of commodities by means of commodities (P) is conducted by industrial capital,
and the conversion of money capital into productive capital is the ostensible
task of financial capital (M-C). This is the growth mechanism that converts the
cell form of the commodity into what Marx termed more “complex and
composite” forms, an entire capitalist metabolism, the path from capital’s
molecular level to its molar manifestation. If we think of a rotating sphere not
only accelerating in velocity as its speeds its circulatory processes but
expanding in diameter as it fills more and more social and geographic space,
we have the image of global capital.

If the cellular form of capitalism is the commodity, the cellular form of society
beyond capital is, we suggest, the common. A commodity is a good produced
for exchange, a common a good produced to be shared. Exchange
presupposes private owners between whom it occurs. Sharing presupposes
collectivities within which it occurs. The circuit of the common traces how these

Commons and Cooperatives


45

collectivities--which we term association--organize shared resources into


productive ensembles that create more commons, which in turn provide the
basis for new associations. So in a rewritten circulation formula, C represents not
a Commodity but Commons, and the transformation is not into Money but
Association. The basic formula is therefore: A ─ C ─ A'. This can then be
elaborated into A ─ C . . . P . . . C' ─ A'.

Just as the circulation of capital subdivides into different types of capital--


mercantile, industrial, financial--we should recognize differing moments in the
circuit of the common. Let’s call them eco-social, networked, and labour
commons. Eco-social commons would be institutions managing the biosphere
not as a commercial resource, but as the shared basis for any continuing form of
human association--collective agencies for planetary climate control, fishery
reserves, protection of watersheds, and prevention of pollution. Eco-social
commons indicates that the same planning logic also encompasses
epidemiological and public health care provisions, regulation of the food
supply, biotechnological monitoring, all understood, again, not as strategic
opportunities for commercial exploitation, but as a precondition of species life.

By networked commons we mean communication systems that unleash, rather


than repress, the tendency of digital technologies to create non-rivalrous goods
and common pool resources that overflow intellectual property regimes. We are
thinking not merely of liberal “creative commons” initiatives, but of large-scale
adoption in public institutions of open-source practices; the remuneration of
cultural producers in ways that allow the relaxation of commercial intellectual-
property rights; plus the education and infrastructures that make access to peer-
to-peer systems a public utility as common as the telephone.

By labour commons we mean the democratized organization of productive and


reproductive work. And this brings us back to worker cooperatives, in which the
workplace is an organizational commons, the labour performed is a commoning
practice, and the surplus generated, a commonwealth. Worker coops would
not, we emphasize, be the sole component of a labour commons. Their growth
would have to go alongside (and could potentially be aided by) wider
measures; for example, we think that there is much to be said for the
combination of worker coops with a universal basic income, conceived not as a
glorified welfare handout, but as an acknowledgement of the contribution to
collective productivity of every life.81 But accompanying such a guarantee of
basic material conditions of dignity, worker cooperatives would, as an
expression of self-organized associated labour, be exemplary “cells” building a
larger commonwealth metabolism.

To speak of the circulation of the common is to propose connecting eco-social,


labour, and networked commons to reinforce and enable one another,

Greig de Peuter & Nick Dyer-Witheford


46

creating a circuit in which the common goods and services produced by


associations at one point in the circuit provide inputs and resources for
associations at another, making what Gibson-Graham call a “generative
commons.”82 So, for example, we can envisage large-scale eco-social planning
seeding various worker cooperatives and associative enterprises, which then in
turn generate the goods and services required for ecological, public health,
and welfare planning--including the non-rivalrous networked commons, a pool
of free knowledge and innovation to be used in turn in the planning and
production of the eco-social and labour commons.

The three moments in our model of the circulation of the commons--ecological,


labour and network or communicational--map onto the three moments of the
circulation of capital--financial, industrial, and mercantile--yet also signal a
profound alteration in their logic. While the financial circuit of capital defines
that system’s prime directive, making money from money, the ecological circuit
specifies a contrary priority, the preservation and enhancement of the
biospheric commons; where the industrial moment of capital’s circulation
concerns the appropriation of productive surpluses by owners, the labour
moment in commons circulation specifies the sharing of these surpluses by
workers and their communities; and while the mercantile moment of capital
hinges on commodity exchange as capital’s most important form of social
interaction, the communicational moment in the commons involves the dialogic
interaction necessary for democratic planning and an economics of
association. Thus the circuit of the common and the circuit of capital are
symmetrical yet shifted, homologous but displaced from one another by
transition to a set of alternative social priorities.

Theoretical and abstract as these formulations may sound, we find concrete


and practical demonstrations of the circulation of commons in the various
experiments in solidarity economics gaining traction in Latin America and
elsewhere.83 Brazil’s solidarity economy system, for example, arises from
movements of workers and landless peasants, infused by liberation theology
traditions, and by the history of quilombos (self-governing communities) of
escaped slaves. Strongest in agricultural production, the sector also includes
industrial, service, and software components. It links workers cooperatives and
self-managed enterprises with alternative financial institutions, consumer
cooperatives, and fair trade systems in an attempt to create a self-reinforcing
network of economic activities in which participants’ activities are informed by
an ethical and political sense of shared social responsibilities. The units of these
networks are conceived not just as individually following principles of social and
environmental justice, but providing inputs for each other, to create an inter-
cooperative, self-expanding system.

Commons and Cooperatives


47

Euclides Mance, a leading solidarity economist, writes of “socially based


cooperation networks” reinforcing their component parts until “progressive
boosting” enables them to move from a “secondary, palliative or
complementary sphere of activity” to a “socially hegemonic mode of
production.”84 This solidarity economy now garners some support, however
equivocal, from the Worker Party government elected in 2002, which, for
example, funds experiments in the development of digital tools not only to map
participant organizations, but also to track inputs, outputs, and wastes so that
the sector can be increasingly integrated and self-sufficient. The difficulties and
pitfalls faced by Brazilian solidarity economics under a Lula government that
often continues to follow neoliberal policies are manifest; nonetheless, it is a
striking example of the sort of cell-growth of commons envisaged here.85

Such a circulation of commons can only arise from the circulation of struggles,
that is, from social experiments created in resistance to the expanding
circulation of capital. As we noted at the outset, fights for commons--terrestrial,
networked, labour--are underway. The circulation of the common is a forward
projection of these contests; it is a concept of emergence. If capital is an
immense heap of commodities, commonism, as we envisage it, will be a
multiplication of commons. The idea of the circulation of the commons proposes
a systemic transformation, but starts small, with cellular model of commons and
association that is simple, even rudimentary. It then scales, at levels from the
domestic to the municipal to the planetary. The totality it envisages is a
multiplicitous one--a complex, composite non-capitalist society composed by
an interaction of different kinds of commons with distinct, specific logics.

This is not necessarily a model of changing the world without seizing power. The
role of the state in co-management initiatives, such of those of the Venezuelan
and Brazilian governments we noted earlier, may be vital in allowing the
circulation of commons to attain a critical mass. Our concept does, however,
suggest that growth and interconnection of the commons have to precede
such state interventions, to prefiguratively establish the necessary preconditions.
It must also grow beyond the moment of such direct interventions, in a
proliferation of self-starting components that exceeds centralized control. In this
sense, the idea of the circulation of the commons is a concept from and for the
Marxian tradition of autonomous free association.

Even as we acknowledge the many constraints on and co-options of worker


cooperatives, we think it unwise to dismiss their contribution to widening the
horizon of commons politics. Despite their contradictions, worker coop
experiments are part of a long tradition of troubling the subject of waged-labour
(associated labour), developing an ethics of production (workplace
democracy), sharing wealth produced in common (surplus distribution),
demonstrating the state can aid in the encouragement of alternatives to

Greig de Peuter & Nick Dyer-Witheford


48

capitalist enterprise (state support), and fostering a parallel, community


solidarity economy (cooperation among cooperatives). Furthering the radical
potential of these labour commons initiatives, rather than reducing them to
modest forms compatible with capitalism, depends, however, on worker coops
becoming part of a broader movement--what we term the circulation of the
common--with the explicit aim of creating not just more work but rather
workable alternatives to the dominant mode of production: cooperating to
produce not more jobs under capitalism, but more of life in common.

Commons and Cooperatives


49

Endnotes

1 Greig de Peuter is Assistant Professor in the Department of Communication


Studies at Wilfrid Laurier University. He is co-editor, with Mark Coté and Richard
J.F. Day, of Utopian Pedagogy: Radical Experiments Against Neoliberal
Globalization (University of Toronto Press, 2007). Nick Dyer-Witheford is Associate
Professor and Associate Dean in the Faculty of Information and Media Studies at
the University of Western Ontario. He is the author of Cyber-Marx: Cycles and
Circuits of Struggle in High-Technology Capitalism (University of Illinois Press,
1999). Together, Nick Dyer-Witheford and Greig de Peuter are the co-authors of
Games of Empire: Global Capitalism and Video Games (University of Minnesota
Press, 2009), and, with Stephen Kline, of Digital Play: The Interaction of Culture,
Technology, and Marketing (McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2003).
2 See, for example: Bollier, D. (2002). Silent theft: The private plunder of our

common wealth. New York: Routledge; Hardt, H. & Negri, A. (2009).


Commonwealth. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press; Holdren, N. & Shukaitis, S.
(Eds.). (2006). Re(in)fusing the commons. The Commoner, 11.
http://www.commoner.org.uk/index.php?p=24; Midnight Notes. (1992).
Midnight oil: Work, energy, war, 1973-1992. New York: Autonomedia; McMurtry,
J. (1999). The cancer stage of capitalism. London: Pluto; Shiva, V. (2005). Earth
democracy. Cambridge, MA: South End Press.
3 Linebaugh, P, and Rediker, M. (2000). The many-headed hydra: Sailors, slaves,

commoners and the hidden history of the revolutionary Atlantic. London: Verso.
4 Hardin, G. (1965). The tragedy of the commons. Science, 162, 1343-1348;

Bricklin, D. (2001). The cornucopia of the commons. In A. Oram (Ed.) Peer-to-


peer: Harnessing the power of disruptive technologies (pp. 59-63). Cambridge:
O’Reilly; Raymond, E. (2001). The cathedral and the bazaar: Musings on Linux
and open source by an accidental revolutionary. New York: O’Reilly Media.
5 Caffentzis, G. (2004). A tale of two conferences: Globalization, the crisis of

neoliberalism and question of the commons. Centre for Global Justice.


http://www.globaljusticecenter.org/papers/caffentzis.htm.
6 See: Zizek, S. (2009). How to begin from the beginning. New Left Review, 57, 43-

55. For an exception to the separation of commons and labour politics, see:
Waterman, P. (2003). All in common: A new/old slogan for international labour
and labor internationalism. The Commoner, 6.
http://www.ainfos.ca/03/jan/ainfos00533.html.
7 Day, R.J.F. (2005). Gramsci is dead: Anarchist currents in the newest social

movements. London and Toronto: Pluto and Between the Lines (p. 210).
8 Fairbairn, B. (1994). The meaning of Rochdale: The Rochdale Pioneers and the

cooperative principles. Saskatoon: Centre for the Study of Cooperatives,


University of Saskatchewan (p. 2).
9 Marx, K. (1992). The First International and after: Political writings, Volume 3.

London: Penguin (p. 79).


10 Ibid., p. 80.

Greig de Peuter & Nick Dyer-Witheford


50

11 Ibid.
12 Ibid.
13 K. Marx, cited in: Gibson-Graham, J.K. (2006). A postcapitalist politics.

Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press (pp. 108-109).


14 See: Jossa, B. (2005). Marx, Marxism, and the cooperative movement.

Cambridge Journal of Economics, 29, 3-18.


15 Marx, 1992, p. 80.
16 Otani, T. (2007, October 3-6). Labouring individuals and association. Paper

presented at Congrès Marx International, Paris, Sorbonne et Nanterre.


http://netx.u-paris10.fr/actuelmarx/cm5/com/M15_Marx_Otani.doc.
17 Lebowitz, M. (2003). Beyond capital: Marx’s political economy of the working

class. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, (pp. 88-89).


18 Ibid., p. 88.
19 Canadian Worker Coop Federation (n.d.). Statement of cooperative identity.

http://www.canadianworker.coop.
20 Lebowitz, 2003, pp. 88-89.
21 Lebowitz, M. (2005, October 24). Constructing co-management in Venezuela:

Contradictions along the path. Monthly Review Zine.


http://mrzine.monthlyreview.org/lebowitz241005.html.
22 K. Marx, cited in Lebowitz, 2003, pp. 88-89.
23 See: Trigona, M. (2006, July 13). Zanon: Worker managed production,

community and dignity. Toward Freedom.


http://towardfreedom.com/home/content/view/855/68/.
24 Canadian Worker Coop Federation.
25 Ibid.
26 M. Mendez, cited in Trigona.
27 See: Sitrin, M. (Ed.). (2006). Horizontalism: Voices of popular power in

Argentina. Oakland, CA: AK Press; Vieta, M. (2010). The social innovations of


autogestión in Argentina’s worker-recuperated enterprises: Cooperatively
reorganizing productive life in hard times. Labor Studies Journal, 35(4), published
online before print July 13, 2009, DOI: 10.1177/0160449X09337903.
28 Fairbairn, pp. 27-28.
29 Canadian Worker Coop Federation. (n.d.) What is a worker coop?

http://www.canadianworker.coop/worker-coop. Controversially, however,


worker cooperatives can also employ hired labour, which is an example of how
coops are antagonistic and accommodative to capital.
30 Ibid.
31 Ibid.
32 Hahnel, R. (2005). Economic justice and democracy: From competition to

cooperation. London: Routledge (p. 352).


33 Ibid.

Commons and Cooperatives


51

34 Mondragón Corporación Cooperativa. (2009). 2009 Annual Report.


http://www.mondragon-corporation.com/language/en-US/ENG/Economic-
Data/Yearly-Report.aspx
35 See: Bakaikoa, B., Errasti, A., & Begirstain, A. (2004). Governance of the

Mondragón Corporación Cooperativa. Annals of Public and Cooperative


Economics, 75(1), 61-87.
36 Canadian Worker Coop Federation, n.d., What is a worker coop?
37 Hahnel, p. 354.
38 See: Vieta. Also see: Ruggeri, A., Martinez, C., & Trinchero, H. (2005). Las

empresas recuperadas en la Argentina: Informe del segundo relevamiento del


programa. Buenos Aires: Facultad Abierta, Facultad de Filosofía y Letras,
Universidad de Buenos Aires, Programa de Transferencia Científico-Técnica con
Empresas Recuperadas por sus Trabajadores (UBACyT de Urgencia Social F-701).
39 See: International Cooperative Alliance (n.d.) Statement on cooperative

identity. http://www.ica.coop/coop/principles.html.
40 Albert, M. (2004). Parecon: Life after capitalism. London: Verso (pp.103-111);

Hahnel, p. 190.
41 Canadian Worker Coop Federation, n.d., What is a worker coop?
42 Kasmir, S. (1996). The myth of Mondragon: Cooperatives, politics, and working-

class life in a Basque town. New York: State University of New York Press.
43 See: Bell, D. (2006). Worker-owners and unions: Why can’t we just get along?

Dollars & Sense. http://www.dollarsandsense.org/archives/2006/0906bell.html.


44 Hahnel, pp. 354, 355.
45 Dahl, R.A. (1985). A preface to economic democracy. Berkeley, CA: University

of California Press, p. 115.


46 Fairbairn, p. 20.
47 International Cooperative Alliance.
48 G.J. Holyoake, cited in Fairbairn, p. 21.
49 See: Logue, J. & Yates, J.S. (2006). Cooperatives, worker-owned enterprises,

productivity and the International Labor Organization. Economic and Industrial


Democracy, 27(4), 686-690.
50 Gibson-Graham, pp. 101-126. For a celebratory account, see: Morrison, R.

(1997). We build the road as we travel: Mondragon, a cooperative social


system. Warner, NH: Essential. For a critical Marxian perspective, see: Kasmir.
Between these poles, see: Errasti, A.M., Heras, I., Bakaikoa, B., & Elgoibar, P.
(2003). The internationalization of cooperatives: The case of the Mondragon
Cooperative Corporation. Annals of Public and Cooperative Economics, 74(4),
553-584.
51 International Cooperative Alliance.
52 Pobihushchy, S. (2003, November 13-14). Establishing a cooperative economy.

Paper presented at Coop Life Conference, Montpelier, Vermont.


53 See the Canada Social Purchasing Portal at http://www.sppcanada.org.
54 See: Morrison. Also see: Hahnel, p. 354.

Greig de Peuter & Nick Dyer-Witheford


52

55 Hahnel, p. 354.
56 Lanki Cooperative Studies Institute. (n.d.). http://www.lanki.coop/home.
57 Marx, 1992, p. 80.
58 Lenin, V.I. (1965). On cooperation. In Collected works, Vol. 3 (pp. 467-75).

Moscow: Progress Publishers.


59 Griffin, A.T., & Soderquist, L.D. (1991). The Soviet cooperative before

Perestroika: The Leninist versus the Stalinist concept. The American Journal of
Comparative Law, 39, 599-609.
60 See: Kuljic, T. (2007). Yugoslavia’s workers’ self-management. In R. Oliver (Ed.),

Alternative economies, Alternative societies. Gdansk: Wyspa Institute of Art.


http://www.ressler.at/workers_self-management/.
61 International Cooperative Alliance.
62 See: Guadano, J.F. (2006). Structural changes in the development of

European Cooperative Societies. Annals of Public and CooperativeEeconomics,


77(1), 107-127.
63 Bowman, B. & Stone, B. (2006). Venezuela’s cooperative revolution: An

economic experiment is the hidden story behind Chávez’s “Bolivarian


Revolution.” Dollars & Sense.
http://www.dollarsandsense.org/archives/2006/0706bowmanstone.html.
64 The statistics in this paragraph are drawn from: Bowman & Stone.
65 Lebowitz, 2005.
66 Ibid.
67 Bowman & Stone.
68 Lebowitz, 2005.
69 Gibson-Graham. See also: Gibson-Graham, J.K., Resnick, S., & Wolff, R. (2001).

Toward a poststructuralist political economy. In J.K. Gibson-Graham, S. Resnick,


Stephen, & R. Wolff, (Eds.), Re/presenting class: Essays in postmodern Marxism
(pp. 1-22). Durham, NC: Duke University Press; Byrne, K. & Healy, S. (2006).
Cooperative subjects: Toward a post-fantasmatic enjoyment of the economy.
Rethinking Marxism, 18(2), 241-258.
70 Byrne & Healy, p. 253.
71 Ibid., p. 248. See also: Gibson-Graham, p. 101-126.
72 In We build the road as we travel, Morrison asserts that in a formal sense

worker coops “abolish wage-labour for the worker-owners” (p. 65).


73 See: McNally, D. (1993). Against the market: Political economy, market

socialism, and the Marxist critique. London: Verso.


74 See: Ollman, B. (Ed.). (1998). Market socialism: The debate among socialists.

London: Routledge.
75 Hahnel, p. 249.
76 Reeves, R. (2007, February 19). We love capitalism. The New Statesman.

http://www.newstatesman.com/200702190026.
77 Albert; Gibson-Graham.

Commons and Cooperatives


53

78 Dyer-Witheford, N. (2009). The circulation of the common. Paper posted to


Species-Beings blog on November 30, 2009.
http://commonism.wordpress.com/2009/11/30/the-circulation-of-the-common/.
79 Marx, K. (1977). Capital, Vol. I. New York: Vintage (p. 125).
80 Marx, K. (1981). Capital, Vol. II. New York: Vintage (p. 180).
81 See: Lucarelli, S. & Fumagalli, A. (2008). Basic income and productivity in

cognitive capitalism. Review of social economy, 66(1), 71-92.


82 Gibson-Graham, p. 125.
83 Miller, E. (2005). Solidarity economics: Strategies for building new economies

from the bottom-up and the inside-out. Posted to Grassroots Economic


Organizing website:
http://www.geo.coop/files/SolidarityEconomicsEthanMiller.pdf.
84 Mance, E.A. (2007). Solidarity economics. Turbulence 1 (2007).

http://turbulence.org.uk/turbulence-1/solidarity-economics.
85 The Green Worker Cooperatives Initiative (http://www.greenworker.coop) in

New York City is a contemporary North American small-scale example of the


wider possibilities we imagine in, in this case, connecting eco-social commons
and labour commons.

References

Albert, M. (2004). Parecon: Life after capitalism. London: Verso.


Bakaikoa, B., Errasti, A., & Begirstain, A. (2004). Governance of the Mondragón
Corporación Cooperativa. Annals of Public and Cooperative Economics,
75(1), 61-87.
Bell, D. (2006). Worker-owners and unions: Why can’t we just get along? Dollars &
Sense. http://www.dollarsandsense.org/archives/2006/0906bell.html
Bollier, D. (2002). Silent theft: The private plunder of our common wealth. New
York: Routledge.
Bowman, B. & Stone, B. (2006). Venezuela’s cooperative revolution: An
economic experiment is the hidden story behind Chávez’s “Bolivarian
Revolution.” Dollars & Sense.
http://www.dollarsandsense.org/archives/2006/0706bowmanstone.html
Boyle, J. (2002). The second enclosure movement and the construction of the
public domain. Daedalus, 13.
http://www.law.duke.edu/pd/papers/boyle.pdf
Bricklin, D. (2001). The cornucopia of the commons. In A. Oram (Ed.) Peer-to-
peer: Harnessing the power of disruptive technologies (pp. 59-63).
Cambridge: O’Reilly.
Byrne, K. & Healy, S. (2006). Cooperative subjects: Toward a post-fantasmatic
enjoyment of the economy. Rethinking Marxism, 18(2), 241-258.
Canadian Worker Coop Federation (n.d.). Statement of cooperative identity.
http://www.canadianworker.coop

Greig de Peuter & Nick Dyer-Witheford


54

Canadian Worker Coop Federation. (n.d.) What is a worker coop?


http://www.canadianworker.coop/worker-coop
Caffentzis, G. (2004). A tale of two conferences: Globalization, the crisis of
neoliberalism and question of the commons. Centre for Global Justice.
http://www.globaljusticecenter.org/papers/caffentzis.htm
Dahl, R.A. (1985). A preface to economic democracy. Berkeley, CA: University of
California Press.
Day, R.J.F. (2005). Gramsci is dead: Anarchist currents in the newest social
movements. London and Toronto: Pluto and Between the Lines.
De Angelis, M. (2006). Introduction to “Re(in)fusing the commons.” The
Commoner, 11. http://www.commoner.org.uk/#intro11
Dyer-Witheford, N. (2009). The circulation of the common. Paper posted to
Species-Beings blog on November 30, 2009.
http://commonism.wordpress.com/2009/11/30/the-circulation-of-the-
common/
Errasti, A.M., Heras, I., Bakaikoa, B., & Elgoibar, P. (2003). The internationalization
of cooperatives: The case of the Mondragon Cooperative Corporation.
Annals of Public and Cooperative Economics, 74(4), 553-584.
Evans, P. (2005). The new commons vs. the second enclosures movement:
Comments on an emerging agenda for development research. Studies in
Comparative International Development, 40(2), 85-94.
Fairbairn, B. (1994). The meaning of Rochdale: The Rochdale Pioneers and the
cooperative principles. Saskatoon: Centre for the Study of Cooperatives,
University of Saskatchewan.
Gibson-Graham, J.K. (2006). A postcapitalist politics. Minneapolis, MN: University
of Minnesota Press.
Gibson-Graham, J.K., Resnick, S., & Wolff, R. (2001). Toward a poststructuralist
political economy. In J.K. Gibson-Graham, S. Resnick, Stephen, & R. Wolff,
(Eds.), Re/presenting class: Essays in postmodern Marxism (pp. 1-22).
Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Goldman, M. (1998). Privatizing nature: Political struggles for the global
commons. London: Pluto.
Griffin, A.T., & Soderquist, L.D. (1991). The Soviet cooperative before Perestroika:
The Leninist versus the Stalinist concept. The American Journal of
Comparative Law, 39, 599-609.
Guadano, J.F. (2006). Structural changes in the development of European
Cooperative Societies. Annals of Public and CooperativeEeconomics,
77(1), 107-127.
Hahnel, R. (2005). Economic justice and democracy: From competition to
cooperation. London: Routledge.
Hardin, G. (1965). The tragedy of the commons. Science, 162, 1343-1348.
Hardt, M. & Negri, A. (2000). Empire. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Hardt, M. & Negri, A. (2009). Commonwealth. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

Commons and Cooperatives


55

Holdren, N. & Shukaitis, S. (Eds.). (2006). Re(in)fusing the commons. The


Commoner, 11. http://www.commoner.org.uk/index.php?p=24
Holyoake, G.J. (1879). History of cooperation in England. New York: AMS Press.
International Cooperative Alliance. (n.d.) Statement on cooperative identity.
http://www.ica.coop/coop/principles.html
Jossa, B. (2005). Marx, Marxism, and the cooperative movement. Cambridge
Journal of Economics, 29, 3-18.
Kasmir, S. (1996). The myth of Mondragon: Cooperatives, politics, and working-
class life in a Basque town. New York: State University of New York Press.
Kuljic, T. (2007). Yugoslavia’s workers’ self-management. In R. Oliver (Ed.),
Alternative economies, Alternative societies. Gdansk: Wyspa Institute of
Art. http://www.ressler.at/workers_self-management/
Lanki Cooperative Studies Institute. (n.d.). http://www.lanki.coop/home
Lebowitz, M. (2005, October 24). Constructing co-management in Venezuela:
Contradictions along the path. Monthly Review Zine.
http://mrzine.monthlyreview.org/lebowitz241005.html
Lebowitz, M. (2003). Beyond capital: Marx’s political economy of the working
class. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Lenin, V.I. (1965). On cooperation. In Collected works, Vol. 3 (pp. 467-75).
Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Linebaugh, P. & Rediker, M. (2000). The many-headed hydra: Sailors, slaves,
commoners and the hidden history of the revolutionary Atlantic. London:
Verso.
Logue, J. & Yates, J.S. (2006). Cooperatives, worker-owned enterprises,
productivity and the International Labor Organization. Economic and
Industrial Democracy, 27(4), 686-690.
Lucarelli, S. & Fumagalli, A. (2008). Basic income and productivity in cognitive
capitalism. Review of social economy, 66(1), 71-92.
Mance, E.A. (2007). Solidarity economics. Turbulence, 1.
http://turbulence.org.uk/turbulence-1/solidarity-economics
Marx, K. (1977). Capital, Vol. I. New York: Vintage.
Marx, K. (1981). Capital, Vol. II. New York: Vintage.
Marx, K. (1992). The First International and after: Political writings, Vol. 3. London:
Penguin.
McMurtry, J. (1999). The cancer stage of capitalism. London: Pluto.
McNally, D. (1993). Against the market: Political economy, market socialism, and
the Marxist critique. London: Verso.
Midnight Notes. (1992). Midnight oil: Work, energy, war, 1973-1992. New York:
Autonomedia.
Miller, E. (2005). Solidarity economics: Strategies for building new economies
from the bottom-up and the inside-out. Posted to Grassroots Economic
Organizing website:
http://www.geo.coop/files/SolidarityEconomicsEthanMiller.pdf

Greig de Peuter & Nick Dyer-Witheford


56

Mondragón Corporación Cooperativa. (2009). 2009 Annual Report.


http://www.mondragon-corporation.com/language/en-
US/ENG/Economic-Data/Yearly-Report.aspx
Morrison, R. (1997). We build the road as we travel: Mondragon, a cooperative
social system. Warner, NH: Essential.
Ollman, B. (Ed.). (1998). Market socialism: The debate among socialists. London:
Routledge.
Otani, T. (2007, October 3-6). Labouring individuals and association. Paper
presented at Congrès Marx International, Paris, Sorbonne et Nanterre.
http://netx.u-paris10.fr/actuelmarx/cm5/com/M15_Marx_Otani.doc
Pobihushchy, S. (2003, November 13-14). Establishing a cooperative economy.
Paper presented at Coop Life Conference, Montpelier, Vermont.
Raymond, E. (2001). The cathedral and the bazaar: Musings on Linux and open
source by an accidental revolutionary. New York: O’Reilly Media.
Reeves, R. (2007, February 19). We love capitalism. The New Statesman.
http://www.newstatesman.com/200702190026
Ruggeri, A., Martinez, C., & Trinchero, H. (2005). Las empresas recuperadas en la
Argentina: Informe del segundo relevamiento del programa. Buenos Aires:
Facultad Abierta, Facultad de Filosofía y Letras, Universidad de Buenos
Aires, Programa de Transferencia Científico-Técnica con Empresas
Recuperadas por sus Trabajadores (UBACyT de Urgencia Social F-701).
Shiva, V. (2005). Earth democracy. Cambridge, MA: South End Press.
Sitrin, M. (Ed.). (2006). Horizontalism: Voices of popular power in Argentina.
Oakland, CA: AK Press.
Trigona, M. (2006, July 13). Zanon: Worker managed production, community and
dignity. Toward Freedom.
http://towardfreedom.com/home/content/view/855/68/
Vieta, M. (2010). The social innovations of autogestión in Argentina’s worker-
recuperated enterprises: Cooperatively reorganizing productive life in
hard times. Labor Studies Journal, 35(4), published online before print July
13, 2009, DOI: 10.1177/0160449X09337903.
Waterman, P. (2003). All in common: A new/old slogan for international labour
and labor internationalism.” The Commoner, 6.
http://www.ainfos.ca/03/jan/ainfos00533.html
Zizek, S. (2009). How to begin from the beginning. New Left Review, 57, 43-55.

Greig de Peuter and Nick Dyer-Witheford, “Commons and Cooperatives,” Affinities: A Journal of
Radical Theory, Culture, and Action, Volume 4, Number 1, Summer 2010, pp. 30-56

Commons and Cooperatives

You might also like