5 Bidet Capital
5 Bidet Capital
5 Bidet Capital
Capital as read by
Moishe Postone:
Alchemy or Astrology?
Jacques Bidet
Abstract: Moishe Postone’s book Time, Work, and Social Domination (1993) is
intended to be a Hegelian interpretation of Marx’s Capital. Capital is the great subject
that moves itself under the impulse of value. Its “movement” is related not to class
relations nor to the market, which is supposedly external to labour, but rather to the
temporal constraint inherent in a dialectic proper to value, one that binds everybody
to an infinite process of abstract labour. This reign of value destroys the concrete
world of use values, and Postone argues that this will be the case until we become
aware of the contradiction between what capitalist society is and the possibilities it
opens. According to the author, such an exposition interprets Capital more on the
basis of its rough draft, Grundrisse, as opposed fifteen years of re- elaboration which
followed. The following discussion is based on confusions regarding the main
Marxian concepts of labour, domination, value, valorization, abstract, and
production.
55
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Capital as read by Moishe Postone: Alchemy or Astrology?
How Marx argued regarding the abolition of the market is well known. He
emphasized that in large industrial firms it is no longer the market that prevails but an
alternative rationality founded on organization: not the a posteriori rebalancing of
supply and demand, but an a priori which fits together the means and the ends.
Since inter-capitalist competition always tends toward concentration, one could
envision that there would ultimately be only one firm per branch. Of course, this
tendency would always remain subject to counter-tendencies. Still, it announced a
possible end of capitalism. Workers are “more and more numerous, instructed and
organized by the process of production itself,” as Marx puts it in the penultimate
chapter of volume one its real conclusion. They would eventually appropriate the
whole of the means of production, and thus would engage in an organized economy
as planned by all citizen-producers. This is certainly what revolutionaries of the
twentieth century understood. The division between socialists and communists was
in part due to disagreements on this very topic. In the West, at least, it is true that
both sides were rather pragmatic. In the eyes of “orthodoxy,” however, the capitalist
market, historically, had to give way to the communist organization of the “associated
producers,” and private ownership of the means of production would be overthrown
by their collective appropriation. This was the pivotal point regarding the concept of
“revolution”. However, over the course of the decades, the market turned out to be an
indispensable element of rationality in a complex economy. The Soviets tried in vain
to integrate this into “socialism”; the Chinese succeeded, but only by bringing about,
at the same time, capitalism… We will not dwell on this historical sequence here, but
instead on the theoretical-philosophical debates about Marx’s conceptualization that
developed in this context and that are still continuing to this day.
Against the backdrop of this issue in the history of Marxism, a return to Capital took
place in the 1960s. Within this conceptual framework, the relation between the
market and socialism could only be analysed on the basis of the relations between
the market and capitalism. Here one can agree that this was not just a matter for
specialists nor a matter for insiders or erudite. What was at stake was determining
whether the market and capitalism could be dissociated from each other: more
specifically, if a non-capitalist use of the market could be made. Obviously, this
56
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Capital as read by Moishe Postone: Alchemy or Astrology?
entailed a whole host of political, legal, cultural, etc. problems. It is certainly difficult to
mobilize Marx in favour of the market… Except if one notes his discussion at the
beginning of Capital, in a first section, which is dedicated to the logic of commodity
production and its rationality, distinguishes this logic from a proper capitalist logic.
From here on it is a matter of determining how, in this theory, the relationship
between the market and capital, should be understood: that is how is the
“transformation,” Verwandlung, from one to the other, is understood through the
course of Marx’s discussion. “Dialectical” analyses, in vogue in Marxism at that time,
tended to interpret it in terms of a relation of continuity and immanence. In a rather
“orthodox” way these interpretations favoured the idea that the abolition of capital
presupposed the abolition of the market. This question takes on a more “dramatic”
allure when, at the neoliberal era, commodification without limits was embraced.
Paradoxically, within Marxism itself, a new discourse also appeared which founded
the contradictions of capitalism as residing in the market categories themselves:
namely within the relationship between use value and value. The considerable
reception that this view continues to receive in philosophical Marxist circles today
suggests that it deserves careful attention.
In fact, although this is one Marxist approach among others, none, to my
thinking, succeeds in responding to the questions left open by Marx. Economists are
readily content with the idea, certainly present in Marx, that when one passes from
the analysis of the market to that of capital one proceeds from a more abstract level
to a more concrete, more “determined” one. Philosophers – at least, on a standard
reading that one can find even in the wake of Althusser – imagine that Marx begins in
his first section with the “surface” of relations of production, more precisely, with
relations of exchange among individuals in the market, before getting to the
“essence,” to the relation of class exploitation discussed in section three which is
dedicated to the proper capitalist process of production, that is, surplus value. The
distinctive feature of the “dialectical” current, which is notably found in the works of
Helmut Reichelt (1970) and Hans-Georg Backhaus (1997) focuses on “value,” which
is also found, albeit differently in Robert Kurz’s, Neue Wertkritik and Christopher
Arthur’s, New Dialectic. In my opinion, there are three difficulties with this trend: firstly,
it becomes impossible to apprehend the rationality of the market (within its limits);
secondly, the logic proper to capitalism tends to get dissolved into an enigmatic
dynamic of value; and lastly, the pathologies inherent in organization (those of
“socialism”) get conflated with those of the market.
57
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Capital as read by Moishe Postone: Alchemy or Astrology?
Moishe Postone is today one of the emblematic figures of this approach, which he
takes to an extreme. At the beginning of the 1980s he made an astonishing
discovery: Great Subject of modern history is not “Proletariat,” as one might have
thought, but “Capital,” the great Whole which both moves itself and within which we
are moved. This paradigm, which he attributes to Marx, allows him to reveal the logic
of a capitalism which takes hold of our lives and our time, involving them in a
productivism without limit, always accelerating toward a horizon of “abstract value”
ignoring the use values that constitute any reasonable life. In my opinion, if Postone’s
work merits our attention, it is because it displays – as if enlarged with a
philosophical magnifying glass – the political disarray among Marx’s inheritors in
front of the all-encompassing power of neoliberalism. Presenting his doctrine as a
simple “interpretation” of Capital, Postone takes on a humble posture of an exegete
who has no criticism to make of the master. He expresses “Marx’s thought”: a
rhetorical stratagem that is only made possible by the authority that Marx enjoys until
today. To be clear, only a meticulous conceptual decoding can reveal the nature and
function of the transmutations which are covertly made by Postone. In this
investigation, I will highlight Capital’s theoretical framework, setting aside my critics
of it. Ultimately the point here is less to criticize Postone than, doing so, to reinvest
and question Marx’s work.
Lukács – an essential reference for Postone – frees us, he says, from “traditional
Marxism,” which understood capitalism essentially in terms of class relations,
structured by private ownership of the means of production and a economy and
“relations of domination (…) in terms of class domination and exploitation.”(Postone
2009, 7). He shifts “the center of gravity of the critique of capitalism” to the “salient
features” of the twentieth century: not exploitation, but rather, market reification. He
changes the emphasis from surplus value to value itself. In this way, he furnishes us
with a critique of capitalism that is “much larger and more profound” (Postone 2011,
64-5). However, Postone calls for a reversal of Lukács’s schema. This is because, in
truth, the Great Subject is not the Proletariat but Capital (Postone 1993, 80sq). This is
what Hegelian Spirit, der Geist, refers to: this totality, this ‘substance’ that moves itself
and is ‘subject’, “causa sui”, self-grounding, self-mediating, and objectified”. Marx
supposedly provided us with a historical interpretation of it (Postone 1993, 156-7).
Postone, in fact, surreptitiously plunges us into an entirely different theoretical
58
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Capital as read by Moishe Postone: Alchemy or Astrology?
universe, no longer that of class relations, but of a productive and oppressive Great
Whole. This form “of abstract, impersonal domination,” he writes, is not (ultimately)
grounded in any person, class or institution “. “Society, as the quasi-independent,
abstract, universal Other that stands opposed to the individuals and exerts an
impersonal compulsion on them” (Postone 1993, 158-9). This constraint is not so
much that of exploitation, but rather, it is first and foremost that of “value”. How
should this formulation be understood?
Marx, as we know, wanted to establish that capitalism is not reducible to the
exchange relations that it presupposes. He defines capital as a process of
“valorization” that is realized in a process of exploitation, leading to an accumulation
of surplus value. Postone attributes to value itself the logic of self-valorization that
Marx attributes to capital. For Postone, capital is nothing other than the supreme
realization of value. The decisive concept is thus that of “value,” an abstract quantity,
supposedly the product of an “abstract time,” and existing only to increase itself.
Overcoming capitalism would thus no longer be realized by the abolition of
exploitation, private property and the capitalist market but by, ultimately, by the
abolition of “value” itself. This can certainly seem consistent with what Capital
teaches us: value, being a market category, would disappear once the market is
“abolished” and socialism is established. But, according to Marx, within this new
social logic it would still be necessary to settle the question of the time required for
production; because, he said, “every economy is an economy of time”. Thus, the
problem of time would become “more urgent than ever”. For Postone, by contrast, it
is this temporal constraint itself that must be abolished. For him, socialism will
change nothing about it. Ultimately, it is the tyranny of an “abstract time”, which is the
result of an “abstract labour,” that must be abolished.
Postone understands value and capital in terms of each other, as in a
dialectical relationship. Value only realizes itself into surplus value. It “is not
essentially a market category” (Postone 1993, 123): it can only be grasped on the
basis of capital, in which it realizes itself. Correlatively, the historical dynamic of
capitalism is nothing more that of value. It implements the “law of value” that,
according to him, consists in “the interaction of value and material wealth, abstract
labour and concrete labour” (Postone 1993, 291). Value “prefigures” capitalism’s
central trait: “it needs to accumulate permanently” (ibid.). It is thus the true “social
mediation”. It forms the very “substance” of the “alienated social relations under
capitalism”. And “as social mediation, value is constituted by (abstract) labour alone”
(Postone 1993, 195). It is, in Postone’s interpretation, "a form of wealth whose
59
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Capital as read by Moishe Postone: Alchemy or Astrology?
Marxists have obviously not failed to voice objections to Postone’s view. For them it is
surprising to see notions of class, state, the struggle of the working class and other
social forces disappear, only to be replaced by a purely structural dynamic, a
“structure” reduced to value and which abandons any “socialist” project. Despite all
this, however, Postone has become the representative of an emancipated Marxism,
rising like a phoenix. His discourse has appealed to militant expectations, while
academic commentaries have credited him with a mysterious ability to shed light on
60
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Capital as read by Moishe Postone: Alchemy or Astrology?
the “times” we are living in. In fact, those confusions that are concentrated in his work
can be found, to different degrees, in the various problematics referring to
“reification,” “alienation,” “loss of meaning,” “general intellect,” “cognitive capitalism,”
“productive capitalism,” and “the commons” – so familiar and rich in many
respects. This accounts for why critique of Postone is frequently so indecisive. It is
thus not perhaps without interest to try to read him more closely.
Postone uses a curious interpretative method: explaining the text actually
published by Marx, Capital, on the basis of its first draft, Grundrisse. In between this
and Capital were fifteen years of corrective elaborations, inventions, and re-
workings. By ignoring all this – setting Marx up as a tutelary figure, always identical
to himself – Postone believes he is able to situate his remarks within the
philosophical paradigm of the “great self-moving Subject” driven by value. Crucial
concepts like exploitation, reproduction, inter-capitalist competition, and
accumulation are completely overlooked. Of course, in principle Postone does not
forget exploitation, etc. He just adds – tirelessly – that one cannot “confine oneself” to
these concepts: “value” has to be analysed more deeply. Using the same trick
throughout his work, he ostentatiously acquiesces to statements found within
Capital. He supposedly takes over Marx’s entire “chemistry”. But he does so in the
manner of an alchemist who possesses its deeper truth, or in the manner of an
astrologer who knows a bit of astronomy. He is not wrong for wanting to take things
from a higher perspective: but the problem becomes how to do so.
In fact, Postone’s discourse only fits into the Marxian framework – that is
supposedly so important to him (linked to his invention, “traditional Marxists”) –under
cover of a number of confusions that are hidden within pseudo-concepts generally
attributed to Marx. These can only be cleared up – and it seems to me that this is
only very partially considered by Postone’s critics – if one keeps in mind the rigorous
Marxian distinction (unfortunately, rather overlooked) among the three levels of
abstraction which govern the whole project of Capital :
(L1): Labour (and social labour) in general. Here, Marx ultimately gave up
dealing with this topic in an introduction – like the one found at the beginning of the
Grundrisse. However, it nevertheless does appear at different moments, as in the
famous text on the “production of use values” in chapter five of volume one, in
contrast to “the production of surplus value”.
(L2): The logic of commodity production (or market production), discussed in
section one of volume one, which is not reducible to a problem of “circulation,” as
61
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Capital as read by Moishe Postone: Alchemy or Astrology?
philosophers who comment on this work tend to believe. It is at this level that value is
conceptualised and this concept is never modified throughout the rest of the work.
(L3): The logic of the capitalist commodity discussed in section three of
volume one, in which labour force the role of a commodity. It is at this level, that of
the “production of surplus-value,” that capital is defined, and that is what the rest of
the work is about.
With this in mind we will now engage in an epistemological exercise: let’s
wager that clearing up Postone’s confusions will allow us to better understand the
nature of Marx’s approach, its own rationality within its limits. And let’s also bet that
we’ll be in a better position to discern what it is possible, or not, to do with the body of
concepts and the theoretical constructions that it/Marx leaves as a legacy to all
those who come after him.
On the one hand, Postone considers he can understand the particularity of capitalist
society (L3) without referring, by contrast, to generalities, to traits that we encounter
in every society (L1). We know that for Marx, the labour which produces commodities
(L2) has two “sides,” Seiten. As “concrete labour” it produces use values. As “abstract
labour,” that is, “expenditure of labour power” (or labour force, the other translation of
Arbeitskraft) whatever the form of the object may be, it creates the value of the
commodity, which is actualized in the exchanges on the market. But, to his way of
thinking, concrete labour and abstract labour are, in themselves, the two constitutive
traits of labour in general (L1). What is proper to commodity production (L2) is that
the relation between the two “sides” is actualizing itself in the market form, that is in
terms of “value”. This value is not a function of their utility, but of the socially
necessary time for producing them under the conditions of commodity production:
competition and variations in the relationship between supply and demand.
Socially necessary time, Marx said, is one that involves a physiological
expenditure. This is indeed a general trait (L1), but it is one that takes on particular
characteristics in commodity production (L2). “Physiology” does not only refer here to
the fatigue common to human beings when they are working. Marx analyses this
question first, at level L2, in terms of the social constraints (intensity, productivity) that
the market as such exercises on bodies at work; and further, at level L3, he considers
the psycho-physiology of the salaried workers of the capitalist factory, and the
biopolitics present within it. Postone, taking up Rubin’s (economistic) view, thinks that
62
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Capital as read by Moishe Postone: Alchemy or Astrology?
the “physiological” does not have a place in political economy. He relegates it the
field of anthropological generality, without any concern for what it becomes in
capitalism. In fact, he represses it. Significantly, he surreptitiously modifies Marx’s
terminology: he replaces regularly “expenditure of labor force” with “labor time
expenditure” (Postone 1993, 26, 34, 190, 194). He prefers “labor power” to labor force”.
He displaces the biopolitical body entailed here out of play – that is, the daily
biopolitics of the class struggle: between those who “spend” their labour force and
those who “consume” it, as Marx says.
On the other hand, he makes “labour” (elsewhere: “value” which is not
however the same thing…) into “the general social mediation” (Postone 1993, 227). In
modern society, “labour mediates itself” (Postone 1993, 225) and it assures
“mediation,” the social relation between all people as well as between all elements of
social networks. This would not have been the case before. Marx poses the question
of “mediation” entirely differently in Grundrisse. Labour, he explains, is not a
mediation: it needs “mediations”. In order for it to exist as social labour, “there must
naturally be mediation,” Vermittlung muss natürlich stattfinden. And, he adds, there
are two rational mediations: the market and organization, die Organisation. These
are, in fact, two very old configurations of mediation that over the course of time take
on historically particular forms. When these mediations are taken in consideration we
pass from L1 to L2. Capital begins with the study of the market mediation (section
one). He then arrives at organizational mediation when he analyses the division of
labour in manufacture and in society, chapter 14. In contrary to Marx, Postone, by
defining the market as “external to labour” and labour as the universal “mediation”
under capitalism, goes down an obscure path. He prevents himself from considering
the two inter-individual “mediations” of the market and organization, on whose basis
alone an analysis of the class structure proper to modern society (which is based on
the instrumentalization of these two mediations) can begin.
Ultimately, this relation of labour to time, this “temporal determination” of
labour that Postone claims he would like to abolish is, in reality, not at all proper to
capitalism (L3), to the market, or to value, as he puts it (L2). It defines quite simply
“labour in general” (L1) as a specific activity: labour aims to produce its result, a use
value, in the least amount of time, or by spending as little labour force as possible. All
economy is an “economy of time,” as Marx says. This is unlike artistic, romantic,
religious, or playful activities. Of course, this time constraint can only exist as a
socially determined constraint – as an “economy”. Postone would like to deliver us
63
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Capital as read by Moishe Postone: Alchemy or Astrology?
from them. One can certainly be liberated from labour by working less, and
differently. But one cannot save labour, make it “free”, by delivering it from time.
Postone does not take into consideration the rationality of the market. Marx presents
the relation between use value and value as a “unity,” Einheit, of “contrary” elements,
Gegenteile, that are “counterparts” of each other (MEW 23/221 and 70, CAP I/197 and
70). “Commodity production” (L2) is, as is well known, a “mode of rational
coordination of labour on a social scale”. It is in this respect that it plays a “mediating”
role, as one sees in chapter one of volume one. The commodity (or market) form of
production based on competition among private producers, is one of the ways,
necessarily constraining, to deal with the constraint of cooperation inherent to
“social” labour. This is the market way (L2) of producing use values (L1). It pre-exists
capitalism, in different degrees and different places. And it is what forms the rational
background of capitalism – a limited rationality that Marx attributes to competitive
market relations.
This is certainly how economists understand it (beginning with Sweezy who is
criticized by Postone) when they consider this “abstract” level where the market is not
yet specified in its capitalist determination. They obviously do not see this as a simple
problem of “circulation” or “distribution,” as Postone would have it. They see, at the
heart of Marx’s theoretical discussion an analysis of the logic of commodity
production taken in “abstraction” (L2): Marx, in this sense, claims to be going “from
the abstract to the concrete,” when he passes from L2 to L3, from the market to
capital, within the theoretical exposition.
Marx insists on this point as pivoting his discussion in the conclusion of
chapter five. Marx insists on this point in the conclusion of chapter five, which is the
pivot of his discussion. He expressly distinguishes, on the one hand (L2) the “process
of the formation of value,” Wertbildungprozess, or the “process of commodity
production” (Productionsprozess von Waren), which is the object of section one,
from, on the other hand (L3), the “valorization process” Verwertungsprozess, or the
“process of capitalist production,” kapitalischer Produktionsprozess (MEW 23/211,
CAP 1/197), the object of section three (which is the kernel of the rest of the work).
Concrete, or useful, labour, he explains, gets connected in very different ways to
“value” in L2 and to “surplus value” in L3. This distinction is extremely important.
Postone neutralizes this approach “from abstract to concrete,” from L2 to L3, with the
64
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Capital as read by Moishe Postone: Alchemy or Astrology?
dialectical idea that L2 can only be understood on the basis of L3. Certainly, capital
L3 “posits” (produces, universalizes) the market L2 as its presupposition. But it does
not define its terms. It can only “transform” them: capital can use the logic of the
market in a “determinate” (capitalist) context because labour force appears therein
as a commodity. But, in order to understand the relation between the market and
capital, they first have to be distinguished, and additionally, the market, the market
logic of production, needs to be understood on its own terms.
By not dwelling on this rational moment of the market (which, as Marx shows,
becomes a fetishistic madness once it is transformed into a “natural order”), Postone
understands the composition of the “opposed” elements that constitute commodity,
use value and value, immediately as a contradiction. It is here that we get to the
heart of the confusion that dominates Postone’s entire work: the confusion of the
market with capitalism.
65
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Capital as read by Moishe Postone: Alchemy or Astrology?
The “contradictions” that Marx attributes to capital, Postone assigns to value, which,
as we have seen, he erroneously turns into the essence of capitalism; because, for
him, everything is already contained in value whose nature is to enhance itself. To his
way of thinking “exploitation and domination are integral moments of commodity-
determined labor” (Postone 1993, 160). For him, the “abstract” logic of capitalism,
which Marx attributes to the relation of exploitation, follows from a primary logic,
which would be that of “value,” which thus “structures” society under the heading of
an “abstract time” – that of abstract labour. This way, he confuses the abstraction L1
(present in L2), which is that of abstract labour, as correlative to concrete labour,
productive of use value, and the abstraction L3, which is that of surplus value,
abstract wealth and indifferent to use value. "The abstraction of “abstract labour”
belongs to the logic of the market: various products of any (concrete) kind can be
exchanged with various others. Abstraction of the concreteness, the concrete nature
of the different commodities. Postone is not the only philosophical commentator to
be confused about this; and this is why critiques of his work are often so faltering.
One cannot, however, make a greater error regarding Marx’s theory.
66
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Capital as read by Moishe Postone: Alchemy or Astrology?
67
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Capital as read by Moishe Postone: Alchemy or Astrology?
as such that is the production of surplus value. Of course, modern production has
not exclusively a form of capitalist market production. It is, in part, “administered”
(state managed). This does not entail, however, that it escapes the “logic of
abstraction” entirely, nor any class logic. But there is no sense in conflating the three
senses of the word “productive,” which is what happens when one speaks of
“production for production”. The analytic work that leads to the political and
economic investigations begins with the distinction among these three terms, L1, L2,
and L3.
68
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Capital as read by Moishe Postone: Alchemy or Astrology?
“The market, competition, class relations” do not explain everything, Postone likes to
repeat. The explanation for the frantic course of our destiny is to be found in a “law of
value” which is of a “dynamic” nature (Postone 1993, 290-291). The “temporal
dimension of value” realizes itself in capital, which exhausts us by making us
produce more in the same amount of time. Marx’s explanation is the inverse of this:
capitalists are in competition with each other for the maximum amount of profit, in a
war of all against all (here we can add that the “competent managers” are also in
competition and also pushed to grandeur and excess). This leads to not only a
maximum of exploitation but also to an incessant search for higher productivity –
Postone sees this as an effect of an “ceaseless motion,” “intrinsically connected to
the temporal dimension of value” (Postone 1993, 270), to its inner drive, to what
makes it “the core” of an “intrinsically dynamic” social form (Postone 1993, 269). Marx
attributes the modern historical “dynamic” to the form of “surplus-value-form, that is,
to capital, and not to the market, nor to the category of value as specific to it. From
Marx’s perspective, hundreds of generations of artisans and peasants both produced
for a market (one part of their production) and experienced the necessity of
producing “according to value” without this “dynamic” that is, in fact, a proper effect
of capitalism. The treadmill is an effect of capital, not of value and it is an effect of
capital on “abstract labour,” as an expenditure of labour force. Not the inverse.
69
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Capital as read by Moishe Postone: Alchemy or Astrology?
One: with the concentration of production within large modern firms, the industrial
workers will get more and more numerous, educated and united by the very process
of production, so more able to conceive and achieve the overthrow of capitalism.
Both more conscious and more powerful. That was, as known, the hypothesis. And it
is this which contemporary Marxists try to translate into post-industrial terms.
It is surprising that Postone does not refer to the famous page of the Critique of
the Gotha Program where Marx evokes, beyond a first communism that mobilizes
and pays equally all the labour powers, a “second phase,” a virtual one, in which,
thanks to the progress of productive science, one would see the end of coerced
labour and the rise of free time. This is really the horizon towards which Postone
turns: labour would in this sense disappear. “Although an economy of time would
remain important, this time presumably would be descriptive.” (Postone 1993, 379).
Marx certainly does not say how one gets to such a “second phase”. But he holds
that one can only work towards the first through a process of class struggle.
However, no such thing for Postone: he invites his reader to rely on a historical
dynamic inherent to a “law of value” increasing in power and nuisance up to the
point where it abolishes itself thanks to critical consciousness. Nothing more is said
of the relations of force that could lead to this result, or to hinder it. And it is this which
prevents him from dealing with an emancipatory strategy.
Translated by Ed Pluth
References
Arthur, Ch. 2004. “Subject and Countersubject.” Historical Materialism 12(3): pp.93-102.
Backhaus, H.-G. 1997. Dialektik der Wertform. Untersuchungen zur Marxschen Ökonomiekritik,
Freiburg i. Br.: ça-ira-Verlag. [1970].
Bidet, J. 2007. Explication et Reconstruction du Capital. Paris: PUF.
—. 2001. L’État-monde/ Paris: P.U.F.
—. 2014a. Foucault avec Marx. Paris: La Fabrique.
—. 2014b. “Misère de la philosophie marxiste, Moishe Postone lecteur du Capital.”
Période, http://revueperiode.net/misere-dans-la-philosophie-marxiste-moishe-postone-lecteurdu-
capital.
—. 2016. Marx et la Loi Travail, Le corps biopolitique du Capital. Paris: Les Éditions sociales.
Bonefeld, W. 2004. “On Postone’s Courageous but Unsuccessful Attempt to Banish the Class
Antagonism from the Critique of Political Economy.” Historical Materialism 12(3): pp.103–124.
70
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Capital as read by Moishe Postone: Alchemy or Astrology?
Marx, K. 1867. Das Kapital, Hamburg, Otto Meissner, 1867. Reedition: Hildesheim, Gerstenberg Verlag,
1980.
— Le Capital, vol. 1. Paris: Les Éditions sociales.
—. 1968. Marx-Engels-Werke. Berlin: Dietz Verlag.
—. 1974. Grundrisse, I/27. Berlin: Dietz Verlag.
—. 1980. Manuscrits de 1957-1858. Paris: Les Éditions sociales.
Miller, K. 2004. “The Question of Time in Postone's Time, Labor and Social Domination.” Historical
Materialism 12(3): pp.209–237.
Osborne, P. 2008. “Marx and the Philosophy of Time.” Radical Philosophy 107: pp.55–72.
Postone, M. 1993. Time, Work and Social Domination. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
—. 2009. Temps, travail et domination sociale. [Time, Work and Social Domination] Trans. by O. Galtier
and L. Mercier, Fayard-Mille Publishing.
—. 2009. History and Heteronomy, ed. by V. Murthy. Tokyo: UTCP.
—. 2011. “Le sujet de l’histoire. Repenser la critique de Hegel dans l’œuvre marxienne de la maturité.”
[The Subject of History: Rethinking Hegel’s Criticism in the Marxian work of Maturity]. Actuel Marx 50:
61–79.
Reichelt, H. 1970. Zur logischen Struktur des Kapitalbegriffs bei Karl Marx. [On the Logic of the
Structure of the Concept of Capital in Karl Marx] Frankfurt: Europäische Verlagsanstalt.
71