EMMETT OnAestheticsofMusicVid
EMMETT OnAestheticsofMusicVid
EMMETT OnAestheticsofMusicVid
The candidate confirms that the work submitted is his own and that appropriate
credit has been given where reference has been made to the work o f others.
This copy lias been supplied on the understanding that it is copyright material
and that no quotation from the thesis may be published without proper
acknowledgement.
Contents
Acknowledgements
Abstract
Introduction
1: Fragments
2: Chora
Conclusion
Bibliography
Acknowledgements
The bulk of the many thanks owed by me goes first to the University of Leeds, for
the provision of a University Research Scholarship, without which I would have
been unable to undertake the studies presented here, and the many library and
computing facilities that have been essential to my research. A debt of gratitude is
also owed to my supervisor Dr. Barbara Engh, whose encouragem ent and
erudition, in a field of interdisciplinary research that demands a broad range of
expertise, and I have frequently demanded it, has been invaluable. Mention here
should also be made of Professor Adrian Rifkin, whose input at the earliest stage
of my research has done much to steer the course of this work in directions that
only a man of his breadth of knowledge could have imagined.
Thanks also to the administrative staff of the School of Fine Art, History of Art and
Cultural Studies, in particular Gemma Milburn, whose ever available assistance
has helped to negotiate the many bureaucratic hurdles of the last four years, and
kept me in constant touch with a department that has undergone considerable
upheaval during recent years. It is their support that has allowed my studies to
proceed with a minimum of distraction.
Finally, thanks to the other research students, especially my fellow 'noise boys’
Marcel Swiboda and David Fox, whose own fields of interest have frequently
overlapped with my own in productive ways, and who have provided direction both
away from dead ends and towards much of what is presented here. And last but in
no sense least, many, many thanks to my friends and my parents, without whose
unflagging technical and moral(e) support, or ‘nagging’ as I have occasionally
term ed it, this piece of work, for good or ill, would never have seen the light of day.
IV
Abstract
In a society which has not yet found peace, how could art cease being metaphysical,
i.e signifying, readable, representative? Fetishist? How long till music, the Text?1
My nominal topic of study, the aesthetics of music video, poses two questions: why
aesthetics, and why music video? I will return to the relevance of aesthetics later,
but with respect to music video, my response does not take the form of a simple
‘because it’s there,' after Edmund Hillary - I do not seek to ‘conquer’ music video,
bend it to my will - but rather takes the form of the confessional. Something, I
knew not what, pricked my consciousness as I encountered music video. The
punctum , of which Roland Barthes speaks in Camera Lucida,2 caught my eye and
my ear; there was, is, a quality of music video that is all its own, beyond the
marriage of music and image alone. Music videos don’t begin to resemble opera,
nor are they quite like films, nor even most television formats. This point was
brought home to me in watching the film Annihilator,3 an execrable film in most
respects, with the sole redeeming feature (at least for me) of having an entirely
unexplained and unprepared music video-like section midway through the film.
Despite being at least as badly done as the rest of the film, the disjuncture caused
by the abrupt change in register, achieved without any use of visual or aural cues,’
was a vivid demonstration of just how different music video is from film. Indeed,
the sensation of watching music video is probably closer to that of silent film,
paradoxically, than sound film, in the active engagement of the viewer to make
sense of what is presented. (Perhaps the exception to this is the musical number
of the Hollywood musical - the imitation of Busby Berkeley style choreography and
camera angles is seen relatively often in music videos - but even here the
contextual setting of the number within a broader filmic context makes for a similar,
but not identical, affective charge.) The visual effects of music video are frequently
striking, even experimental, and yet if one compares their effect to the
experimental films that Harry Partch set to his music in the 1950s and ‘60s, the
difference between these and music video could not be more apparent.
The only other medium with a comparable aesthetic is that of the
advertisement, drawing on similar visual codes, similarly abbreviated with respect
to narrative convention, and also having a similarly schizophrenic relationship to
the commodity: both advertisements and music videos are promotional tools for
commodities (music videos are known as ‘prom os’ in the music industry), and are
thus intimately tied to the fetishized commodity form, but are themselves only
rarely treated as commodities with exchange value. Music videos are explicitly
designed to perform an action upon the world rather than to take on the status of
passive object. Even with the degree of crossover seen between music video and
advertisements, however, as in the frequent employment of music video directors
to make adverts, there remains a clear distinction between the two form ats in the
prominence given to the music track.4 (There are of course exceptions - witness
the setting of Tony Kaye’s Dunlop tyre advertisement to the Velvet Underground’s
4 See Savan, L., 'Commercials Go Rock,’ Sound and Vision: The Music Video
Reader, ed. Frith, S., Goodwin, A. and Grossberg, L., (Routledge, London and
New York, 1993), pp. 85-90. Although the practice of directors moving between
these mediums has become more common since this was written, the
phenomenon of music videos as advertisements for non-music products described
here was relatively short lived, and thus presumably commercially unsuccessful.
3
‘Venus in Furs’ a few years ago, or the occasional success of the music tracks to
Levi’s adverts - but these are the exceptions that prove the existence of a rule.)
Having been ‘hooked’ by the punctum I perceived in my interaction with
m usic video, I sought to understand the phenomenon, and turned to what literature
I could find on the topic. It seemed, however, that my interest in music video was
not shared by the many writers that purported to address it: there was no shortage
of discussion, at least in the 1980s, but nobody seemed to be particularly
concerned with the music video text in itself. Most commentators were more taken
with the channel MTV than the videos p e r se,5 and music videos were an example
of this, or a proof of that, but always constituted. Rarely, if ever, was it addressed
on its own terms, and never in terms of the one thing that marked it apart from
other television forms, namely, the music. Many people seemed to be talking
about music video, but few of these seemed to be addressing what they actually
saw, instead of the ideas it represented, and fewer still were bothering to listen to
them. And then, after the initial scholarly intoxication with music video, people
stopped even talking about it. Katherine Dieckmann wrote recently:
Not so very long ago, back in the eighties, or ‘‘The Big 80s" as one short-lived video
revival show liked to call them, MTV provided fruitful ground for the pop-minded
scholar. The music video was, in fact, often considered the ideal mass cultural artifact.
...My interest in MTV is less theoretical and more pragmatic ... partly because a highly
intellectualized approach to the medium feels just about as dated now as Madonna’s
conical bustier.6
5 One of the very few book length studies, oft cited in music video research, is E.
Ann Kaplan’s Rocking Around the Clock, and yet in her introduction she explicitly
states: Let me remind readers that this book addresses itself not to rock videos in
general but to their incorporation in the institution that is MTV.’ Kaplan, E.A.,
Rocking Around the Clock: Music Television, Postmodernism, and Consum er
Culture, (Routledge, London and New York, 1987), p. 11.
6 Dieckmann, K., ‘MTV killed the music video star,’ in Kelly, K. and McDonnell, E.
(eds), Stars don’t Stand Still in the Sky, (Routledge, London, 1999), p. 89.
4
In the course of this essay, Dieckmann mentions the work of Andrew Goodwin as
an example of a ‘pop-minded scholar,’ but she neglects to mention that Goodwin
was arguing precisely against the raft of theory produced in the 1980s that treated
music video as an exemplar of postmodernism for exactly as long as it failed to
address the music. Many of the postmodern traits music video and MTV were said
to em body were entirely typical presentations of the experience of live concert
perform ance (for instance, direct address); they only became ‘postm odern’ when
erroneously viewed from the standpoint of mainstream cinema. Music video was
not only the ‘ideal mass cultural artefact,’ but an entirely idealized artefact, a
convenient peg upon which to hang theory. At the time of writing it is ten years
since Goodwin published Dancing in the Distraction Factory,7 a call for a
‘m usicology of the image,’ outlining the need to re-engage with music video as a
musical entity rather than as a branch of film theory, and in the intervening period
there has been an almost deafening silence. The most notable effort of the
handful that have addressed Goodwin is that of Nicholas Cook, as part of a wider
discussion of musical m ultimedia.8 Cook brings a welcome musicological
perspective to music video, but I would suggest that in one key respect he has
replicated the problem identified by Goodwin, and indeed Goodwin himself is also
guilty of this, for instead of understanding music video in terms of music, both
these media are understood in terms of what they mean, a difficult, and very often
not a useful concept when applied to music. Again the material qualities of the
music video are effaced in deference to an ideal category, and as I hope to
demonstrate, this is exactly what a ‘musicology of the im age’ should struggle
against. I would contend that the model in which an artefact is regarded as a
representation of something else, be that another object or an abstract concept, is
a profoundly unmusical one, and based upon a visual paradigm. Indeed, the
process of abstraction involved in the very notion of the ‘idea,’ so often unsuited to
a discussion of sound, is derived from the visual realm. As Jonathan Ree notes:
7 Goodwin, A., Dancing in the Distraction Factory: Music Television and Popular
Culture, (University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1992).
8 Cook, N., Analysing Musical Multimedia, (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1998).
5
'P lato’s use of the word “ Idea" is itself based on its root meaning of “visible form .’” 9
A genuinely musicological response to music video must hence develop a means
of addressing both image and music, and their combination without constant
recourse to the transcendent realm of the ideal: the point is to stop considering
entities as representations, and to start addressing their presence.
It is for this reason that my concern is for an aesthetics of music video: I
wish to understand the affect of a music video, and derive social critique from this,
rather than analysing the social meaning it offers up, which will of necessity simply
be a reflecting back of one’s own prejudice. It should be stressed that this is not
aesthetics understood as a contemplation of the beautiful in music video, but a
return to the original formulation of Baumgarten in his Aesthetics of 1750.
Aesthetics as ‘the business of affections and aversions, of how the world strikes
the body on its sensory surfaces, of that which takes root in the gaze and the guts
and all that arises from our most banal, biological insertion in the w orld.’10 The
original purpose of this, however, was not to provide a challenge to the realm of
reason: as Terry Eagleton points out (and this is discussed in chapter III), it was
precisely in order to separate out and harness the sensuous to Enlightenment
reason that the field of aesthetics was born. One sees here the potential risk of
ideological capitulation involved in music aesthetics, and the reason why Adorno
and modern musicology has been so keen to avoid the purely m usical’ and reveal
musical meaning, an ideological product. The aesthetic realm, however, is not so
easily ordered as it might seem. As Eagleton writes:
To lend fresh significance to bodily pleasures and drives, if only for the purpose of
colonizing them more efficiently, is always to risk foregrounding and intensifying them
beyond one’s control. The aesthetic as custom, sentiment, spontaneous impulse may
consort well enough with political domination; but these phenomena border
embarrassingly on passion, imagination, sensuality, which are not always so easily
incorporable. ... If the aesthetic is a dangerous, ambiguous affair, it is because ... there
is something in the body which can revolt against the power which inscribes it.11
Any concrete discourse (utterance) finds the object at which it was directed already as
it were overlain with qualifications, open to dispute, charged with value, already
enveloped in an obscuring mist. ... The word, directed towards its object, enters a
dialogically-agitated and tension-filled environment of alien words, value judgements
and accents, weaves in and out of complex interrelationships, merges with some,
recoils from others, intersects with yet a third group: and all this may crucially shape
discourse, may leave a trace in all its semantic layers.12
And I believe this is no less true of music than it is of language: every sound,
harmony, musical style, is intersected by all its previous instances of usage in
precisely the same way as language. An aesthetic approach to musical material
need not be a way of ignoring entirely the social dimension of music (although it
very often is, in certain analytic practices), but rather a way of approaching
meaning from a new direction, sidestepping what I termed above a visual
paradigm, predicated upon ideal concepts and a translation of the material into
11 Ibid., p. 28.
12 Bakhtin, M., ‘Discourse in the Novel,’ in The Dialogic Imagination: Four Essays,
trans. Emerson, C. and Holmquist, M., (University of Texas Press, Austin, 1981),
p. 276.
7
representation. (One sees here a possible reason for the difficulty of discussing
musical timbre in traditional analytic terms: as that element of music that is most
wedded to the material it resists translation into a representation of something
else, and is hence ignored as being non-meaning, insignificant. The value of
sonorous activity in music cannot be gauged so easily as its meaning. ) The key
to endowing aesthetics with a social dimension is to consider it as a means of
generating analysis through a connection to sensate phenomena, rather than as a
set of ideals (unity, symmetry, etc.) to which one might aspire, and for which
analysis provides a form of ‘proof.’ As Ken Hirschkop puts it: T h e points of
pleasure and tension in our musical experience should lead to questions, linked to
our social experience in general, rather than to aesthetic satisfactions which lead
nowhere.’13 Consequently, this thesis will not take the form of a ‘how to ’ of music
video analysis - analytic strategies must be developed in response to the nature of
the artefact and the context of its reception - but I do wish to set out some
fundam ents of methodology, to suggest the ways in which one might interact with
music video, and the forms that an understanding of this process might take.
II
W hat is required is a new conception of aesthetics, and this in turn demands a new
way of apprehending the object. Barthes writes: ‘Aesthetics is absorbed into an art
of living ... hence, it is less a matter of making pictures than furniture, clothes,
tablecloths, which will have distilled all the juice of the “fine” arts; the socialist
future of art will therefore not be the work (except as a productive game) but the
object of use, the site of an ambiguous flowering (half functional, half ludic) of the
13 Hirschkop, K., T h e Classical and the Popular: Musical Form and Social
Context,’ in Music and the Politics o f Culture, ed. Norris, C., (Lawrence and
W ishart, London, 1989), p. 303.
8
It is important to establish from the outset that pop music is, and always has been, a
multidiscursive cultural form, in which no one media site is privileged. The implication
of this for music video analysis is that it becomes impossible to understand the
meaning of any individual clip without considering its relation to the wider world of pop
culture.15
It may not be the case that any one medium is pushed to the fore, but what does
take place, as Goodwin notes several times, is that music video makes television
m usical,’16 The nature of the object demands, in contradistinction to the normal
hierarchy, that one understands the image according to the criteria of music rather
than vice versa, or to put it in the terms defined above, one apprehends the image
track in terms of an aural paradigm rather than applying a visual paradigm to the
sound track. In a dialogical aesthetic, the qualities of the image that are important
are not questions of what is represented or what it ‘m eans,’ so much as what are
its material, affective qualities, how does it impact upon the body; the image is
made sensuous, it is musicalized.
This model may be particularly apparent in pop music, and music videos
especially, but as Cook has pointed out dialogism can be observed in all instances
of music:
The aesthetic interaction between image and sound is possible only because music
possesses an intrinsic openness to semantic completion through the intervention of the
image. To the extent that people assimilate what they see and what they hear into a
composite experience, the every day reception of music gives the lie to the ideology of
musical autonomy, according to which the touchstone of good music is hat it is
aesthetically self sufficient.17
Both Goodwin and Cook demonstrate how both popular and classical musics are
already saturated with image, and bound up more generally with the cultures, or
‘form s of life’ to use W ittgenstein’s terminology, of which they are a part, but what I
believe to be new here is the suggestion that the criteria according to which one
perceives these images is potentially altered by their musical association. Which
is by no means to suggest that this always, or even frequently happens: the
representative, meaning-as-product model predominates in appreciation of both
the visual and the musical, but music videos enable a point of entry to the
16 Ibid., p. xvi.
17 Cook, N., T h e Domestic Gesamtkunstwerk, or Record Sleeves and Reception,’
in Composition - Performance - Reception: Studies in the Creative Process in
Music, ed. Thomas, W., (Ashgate, Aldershot etc., 1998), p. 115.
10
thing: Wittgenstein was highly critical of both the anthropologist George Frazer and
Sigmund Freud for their attempts to explain rather than clarify the nature of certain
phenom ena,20 and Adorno was not concerned with explanation, and the
implication of origin and non-contingent ‘essence’ that underpinned it. As Jay
Bernstein puts it: ‘Adorno is seeking after historical truth, not the ahistorical,
rational essence of phenomena. Historical truth is “shown” in fragmentary writing,
which does not then explicitly aim to demonstrate of to explain. Explaining and
demonstrating neutralize the phenomena in question; to explain is to explain
aw ay.'21 This echoes well with W ittgenstein’s belief that essence is expressed in
the ‘gram m ar’ of a form of life,22 and that this is not something that can be ‘said,’
but merely ‘shown.’23
Ill
Music video has scarcely begun to be adequately theorized. In part this is due to
problems in musical analysis more generally, and in the analysis of popular music
in particular. The fault lines that run through musicology, and the difficulties of
straddling sociological and musical analysis may be narrowing, but have not yet
closed, and with a genuinely interdisciplinary object such as music video these
problems are multiplied. The eclectic nature of the theories I have brought to bear
on music video in the following study has been in part necessitated by the paucity
of existing literature (with a few well-thumbed cited exceptions), and in part
inspired by the formal and disciplinary eclecticism of music video itself. I have
20 See Cioffi, F., Wittgenstein on Freud and Frazer, (Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, 1998) for details of his criticisms.
21 Bernstein, J.M., Introduction to The Culture Industry: Selected Essays on Mass
Culture, (Routledge, London and New York, 1991), p. 7.
22 Wittgenstein, L., Philosophical Investigations, trans. Anscombe, G.E.M.,
(Blackwell, Oxford, 1967), §§371 and 373.
23 Gier, N., Wittgenstein and Phenomenology, (State University of New York Press,
New York, 1981), p. 110.
12
already mentioned many of the theoretical works that betray their presence in my
own writing - Barthes, Bakhtin, Wittgenstein. Academic discourse perhaps more
than any other takes the form of a ‘collective assemblage of enunciation.’24 It is in
this spirit, and I freely admit to following Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari in this
respect, that I begin each of the three chapters with ‘the prompting of an ancestral
voice.’25 Each of these quotations is the expression of a particular historical
juncture, a moment of intensity, an activity that effects what Deleuze and Guattari
term an ‘incorporeal transform ation,’ a point in which the set of relations that
marked a specific mode of being is changed in such a way as to change the object
itself without altering its corporeal form. It is the intersection of the social and the
material, the moment in which the subject-object symbiosis is broken and reset
from within.
Music video is a varied medium, encompassing many different styles and
codes of music, word, and image, each of which, as suggested above, should be
treated according to its specific requirements. I cannot claim to have deliberately
set out to discuss as wide a range of these as possible; I have instead focussed
upon those few that caught my eye and my ear, and which time and again
prompted me to rethink what it was that so appealed to me. My interest in music
video is not that of the catalogue compiler, but of the aesthete, perhaps even the
dilettante. One might query whether this is a responsible attitude to have taken,
given both the political nature of my conclusions, and the typically uncritical and
ideologically questionable nature of the vast majority of music videos, at least in
terms of their overt content, but it is my belief that all music videos, with very few (if
any) exceptions, embody a form of relationship between sound and image that
contains an incipient critique of the sign-system itself. One can scarcely overstate
the extent to which this critique is held in abeyance, but there is nevertheless a
potency here that may occasionally be perceived, however momentary or
personalized that occasion might be. W hatever the weight of theoretical
knowledge I have brought to the artefact, however, all the conclusions I have
drawn have been drawn directly from the encounter with the artefact and the way
in which they have impacted upon me.
Much of the following takes the form of a discussion of music aesthetics
rather than explicitly addressing music video, but as I have tried to show in this
introduction, there are sound reasons (no pun intended) for this; what is true of
music is very often true of music video also. The concept of the aural paradigm:'
dialogistic, material, affective, and its distinction from the ‘visual paradigm :’
monologistic, representative, idealized, should not be read as meaning that each is
in any way bound to its corresponding medium. The point is precisely that music
video is a demonstration that these modes of apprehension can be extended
across differing media, and co-exist in the same artefact in different planes.
W hether they are of more general use to musicology as a whole I must leave for
others to decide, but it is my belief that the attempt to combine the sociological and
the ‘purely m usical’ within a single theoretical framework, as begun by Adorno, and
proposed in both the concept of ‘gesture’ and the figure of the ‘technological body’
here, would be of both theoretical and practical use. Music video as an art may
not have entirely ceased to be metaphysical, but it does, to my mind, enable
access to music, and the Text.
Fragments
Robert got up, but he was more profoundly melancholy than words can say. If I so
much as touched him, he said: “Ah! Clara, I am not worthy of your love.” He said this,
he whom I always look up to with the greatest, the most profound reverence ... ah! and
all that I could say was of no use. He made a fair copy of the variations, and as he was
at the last he suddenly left the room and went sighing into his bedroom - I had left the
room only for a few minutes, in order to say something to Dr. Hasenclever in the next
room, and had left Mariechen sitting with him (for ten days I had never left him alone
for a minute). Marie thought he would come back in a minute, but he did not come, but
ran out into the most dreadful rain, in nothing but his coat, with no boots and no
waistcoat. Bertha suddenly burst in and told me that he had gone - no words can
describe my feelings, only I knew that I felt as if my heart had ceased to beat.1
Robert’s body, on the other hand, as Barthes will point out, continued to beat
strongly, and in a variety of remarkable patterns, on its journey through the streets
of Dusseldorf. If only Clara had the benefit of Barthes’ hindsight, she might have
known: ‘the Schumannian body does not stay in place (a m ajor rhetorical
transgression). It is not a meditative body. It sometimes makes a meditative
gesture, but does not assume m editation’s bearing. ... This is a pulsional body,
one which pushes itself back and forth, turns to something else - thinks of
1 Extract from Clara Schumann’s diary, quoted in Chisell, J., Robert Schumann,
from Master Musician's series, ed. Westrup, J., (Dent, London, 1948), pp. 75-6.
15
This fusion of general and particular, in which one shares in the whole at no risk to
one’s unique specificity, resembles the very form of the aesthetic artefact. ... For the
mystery of the aesthetic object is that each of its sensuous parts, while appearing
wholly autonomous, incarnate the “law” of the totality. Each aesthetic particular, in the
3 Barthes, R., ‘Rhetoric of the Image,’ in Image Music Text, trans. Heath, S.,
(Fontana, London, 1977), p. 34.
4 Wittgenstein, L., Philosophical Investigations, trans. Anscombe, G.E.M.,
(Blackwell, Oxford, 1967), §126.
17
very act of determining itself, regulates and is regulated by all other self-determining
particulars.5
W hich is to say, it is not the 'parts’ that constitute this model, so much as the set of
relations between them, and as such, the foremost problem of the ‘aesthetic
artefact’ is also its greatest strength: the object becomes impossible to fix, its
boundaries forever fluid, since it is collapsing in on itself at the same tim e that it is
exploding outwards into the world.
Perhaps more so than any other format, the music video simultaneously
proclaims its autonomy and fails to fulfil that promise. As the supplementation of
the ‘pop’ single with an image track, it might be regarded as the ultimate fetishized
commodity, replete in itself as object, but this is far from being the case. The
presentation of spectacle in the music video is almost entirely unique, comparable
only to the television channel ‘ident’ (that is, the short segments between
programmes designed to establish the character of the channel) in the way the
image is presented. (Music videos are also unusual in that, as a collective
enterprise, subject reception is already embodied in the poietic process.) Their
com modity status, as promotional tools, is uncertain like that of advertisements;
unlike most advertisements, however, music videos reject most of the strategies of
mainstream film: in the near permanent use of direct address to camera, a
conspicuous absence of narrative, and a privileging of the striking image (what
Barthes terms a ‘pregnant m oment’6) over any commitment to continuity that might
denote a sense of self-containment. Music video is above all a parasitic medium,
constantly looking outside itself for contextualization and any sense of meaning; a
music video rarely, if ever, offers meaning - one must always make meaning from
it, or not, as will be discussed later. W hat I hope to demonstrate is that, as Andrew
Goodwin suggests, music video performs a musicalization of the image, an
5 Eagleton, T., The Ideology o f the Aesthetic, (Blackwell, Oxford, 1990), p. 25.
6 Barthes, R., 'Diderot, Brecht, Eisenstein,’ in The Responsibility o f Forms, op. cit.,
pp. 93ff.
18
extension of an aural paradigm into the visual realm (in a reversal of the usual
hierarchy), as is frequently suggested in Barthes’ discussion of ‘the text.’7
This process, however, will not take place without first examining historical
precedent; as Barthes notes: T o criticize ... is to put into crisis, something which is
not possible without evaluating the conditions of the crisis (its limits), without
considering its historical moment.’8 In order to explicate the fragmentary qualities
of the music video, it is necessary to first explore the aesthetic of the fragment as it
first appeared in the late eighteenth century. The historical proximity of the
development of the field of aesthetics, and that of the literary form of the ‘fragm ent’
in the late eighteenth century was not mere serendipity. The potency and flexibility
of thought this mode of W eltverstandnis enables generated a range of analytical
possibilities, adopted into artistic formats by the Jena circle around the likes of
Friedrich Schlegel and Jean Paul, beloved by Schumann. W hen Schlegel
famously wrote that: ‘A fragment should be like a little work of art, complete in itself
and separated from the rest of the universe like a hedgehog,’9 he clearly meant
this to say as much about the nature of the work of art as about the fragment. This
should not be taken as an argument in favour of the separation of art and world, at
least not in the sense of a straightforward autonomy - a hedgehog is no more
separate from the universe than the sun or the moon; rather it is constitutive of that
universe, in however small a way, and the same is true of the artwork, with a
similarly ill-defined boundary point. A frequently cited musical example of this is
Schum ann’s ‘lm wunderschonen Monat Mai,’ the opening song from the
Dichterliebe cycle, which in terms of functional harmony begins with the sequence:
ii74'3, V7 in F# minor, before resolving into A major on the entry of the voice, and
7 One might offer as examples, passages of S/Z, the statement that ‘listening
bears within it that metaphor best suited to the ‘textual,’ (footnote in 'The Third
M eaning,’ in Image Music Text, op. cit., p. 53), or the close of ‘Diderot. Brecht,
Eisenstein,’ op. cit., ‘How long till music, the Text?’ (p. 97).
8 Barthes, R., ‘Writers, Intellectuals, Teachers,’ in Image Music Text, op. cit., p.
208.
9 Quoted in Rosen, C., The Romantic Generation, (HarperCollins, London, 1996),
p. 48. The following reading and discussion owes much to Rosen's chapter
concludes with the same sequence, finishing on the dominant seventh chord. The
effect in performance is one of profound ambiguity, and serves to project the song
both forwards and backwards in time by implying both an unheard prologue and a
continuation of the song. Although this is a particularly impressive and beautiful
example, the same effect is produced less artfully in innumerable pop songs that
employ the familiar fade-out of a repeated chord sequence. A better example is
that of the video to Basement Jaxx’s ‘Jus’ 1 Kiss,’ which opens as if ‘cutting in’ on
a held synthesizer chord, and a black screen with a disembodied head moving
slowly around the very edge of it, moves to a muffled introduction with ‘home
video’ footage of Basement Jaxx before the song proper. (N.B. There is a
disjunction between sound and image here, the image track ‘proper’ starting
several seconds before the sound track ‘proper.’) Then to close there is more
‘home video' footage of Felix Jaxx starting up the beginning of the song again on a
portable stereo. As with ‘lm wunderschonen Monat M ai’ the music video is
projected both backward into its own pre-existence, and forwards, continuing in
another realm after its cessation in this world. This example also illustrates well a
further technique common to the Romantic fragment, that of its disjunction from
reality, or at least the problematizing of this relation. Time and again in Romantic
literature one sees either points of self-referentiality and overt situating of the
author/narrator, or else the text is consciously other-worldly, as in that most
fam ous of literary fragments, Coleridge’s Kubla Khan, subtitled as a fragm ent’ and
preceded by the story of the caller from Porlock.10 The poem is ruptured both
internally, by its constant shifting of metre, and physically by the break at line 37
(‘A damsel with a dulcimer ...’) that marks a shift in tone from story-telling to
personal (dream) recollection, and externally, ‘from the rest of the universe,’ by its
fantastical content and its conscious labelling as ‘a fragm ent.’ The artefact is
fragmented both at the level of its context and at the level of the work, and no
doubt a close reading would reveal further disjunctions amongst the words
themselves.
This multiple layering of fragmentation could be achieved musically in a
single gesture via a technique employed repeatedly by Schumann, that of musical
10 The introduction was prefixed in its 1816 publication. See Coleridge: Poetry and
Prose, ed. Garrod, H.W., (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1925), pp. 180-1 for details.
20
quotation. Of course musical quotation did not originate with Schumann - the
cantus firm i of medieval polyphony were frequently based on popular melodies;
there are dozens based upon ‘L’Homme Arm e’ alone.11 However, whereas earlier
quotation was integrated into the structure of the new piece - disguised, in effect -
Schum ann’s use of it goes to some lengths to mark it out, both by shifts of rhythm
and of texture, as in the insertion of a section of one of his own earlier works,
Papillon, into the ‘Florestan’ section of Carnaval. As Rosen states: W hat is
revolutionary here is not the introduction of a quotation from another work but the
way it is made to sound like a quotation. If Schum ann’s directions are faithfully
carried out, the phrase will appear to be an intruder from somewhere else, even to
those who have never heard another work by Schum ann.'12 Both the form of the
piece 'Florestan,' and its musical status as an autonomous work are thrown into
doubt, but the way in which Schumann introduces the quotation, first as a
momentary, hesitant, one bar fragment, then as a more completely recalled
melody, and finally absorbed into the texture of the piece, throws the relationship
between sound and world, music and listener, into an even more complex relief.
The use of this quotation, and even its labelling with a question mark in the score,
is clearly a model of musical recollection, and the way in which that memory is
then incorporated into the context of its recollection. The scraps of memory that
float into consciousness are clarified and then recontextualized in relation to
current circumstance - the dialogical relationship between past and present that is
essential to all musical appreciation is here made flesh, or rather, tone. As Rosen
dem onstrates this technique is used again on a larger scale and with greater
facility in Schum ann’s Phantasie, which works and reworks a melodic fragment
from Beethoven's An die Fem e Geliebte into a complex hierarchy of memories,
and concludes: T h e phrase of Beethoven is made to seem like an involuntary
memory, not consciously recalled, but inevitably produced by the music we have
just heard. A memory becomes a fragment when it is felt as both alien and
intimate, when we are aware that it is as much a sign of the present as of the
past.’13
Carolyn Abbate has stated that ‘Music has no past tense,’14 in that it
flattens everything out onto the level of discourse, but I would suggest that music is
nothing but past tense. Music involves a temporal displacement, like the
Bedingnis of Heidegger: T h e sounding, ringing, vibrating of language that goes on
in excess of explanation,’15 the reverberation of history from which one constructs
understanding. All experience of music is an experience of pastness, and takes
the form of recollection, in that one apprehends music as the impact of sound
waves upon the body, as vibration and resonance, as the affective trace of an
event that has already taken place. As Bjork puts it, ‘I miss you, but I haven't met
you yet, I remember, but it hasn’t happened yet.’16 Hence, listening to music is an
exercise in nostalgia, trying to hold still what has already passed, a continual
construction of what has been, that puts the subject into temporal flux, and undoes
the notion of presence. This is perhaps somewhat ironic, since it was suggested in
the Introduction that the application of an ‘aural paradigm ’ was supposed to focus
attention precisely on the issue of presence, rather than representation.
‘M usicalization’ simultaneously poses the question of presence and effaces it - it
focusses attention there only to disappoint. But in so doing, it refines the notion of
affect, which with music is inherently a communal phenomenon, transgressive of
spatial boundaries, and also inextricably bound up with the formation of memory.
Thus the memorization of the musical fragment takes on a Proustian quality, that
of the memoire involontaire, as an infolding of the sensory impact of air molecules
in motion, that is shared by all who have had the same experience. One might
compare this to a passage of Asafiev, in which he discusses the memorization of
melodic fragments by a community as a whole, such that they:
13 Ibid., p. 112.
14 Quoted in Nattiez, J.-J., ‘Can One Speak of Narrativity in M usic?’ Journal o f the
Royal Musical Association, vol. 115:2, (1990), p. 244.
15 Bruns, G.L., The Otherness of Words: Joyce, Bakhtin, Heidegger,’ in
Postm odernism - Philosophy and the Arts, ed. Silverman, H.J., (Routledge, New
York and London, 1990), p. 136.
16 Gudmundsdottir, B., ‘I miss you,’ on the Post album.
22
Enter into oral tradition as living intonations. ... Beyond the compositions themselves
lies the world of music as the activity of the mass public consciousness, from little more
than sound interjections, at times simply rhythmic intonations, and from characteristic
universally loved melodic figures, to more developed melodic shoots and harmonic
turns.17
The idea that there is a corpus of musical fragments that constitute some form of
cultural memory, one that must inevitably interact with the experience of both old
and new music, is a powerful one, and is something to which I will return in chapter
III. For now, however, it is sufficient to state that the dialectic between the
experience of music and musical experience, consciously exploited and rendered
overt by Schumann, is already bound up in the phenomenology of music, and that
the form at of this phenomenology is necessarily a fragmentary one.
An attempt to combine world and music, although to rather different ends,
is not unfamiliar to musicologists. The field of musical biography feeds upon the
presumption that connections can be drawn between the two, and in its most
disreputable form will demonstrate the precise parallels between the situation and
disposition of the composer, and the musical works that flow ineluctably from this
state of being. The intention is to provide both a narrative fram ework and unifying
creed to an often disparate corpus of work, as well as to explain the organic
genesis of each individual piece, and given the nature and type of Schum ann’s
output it is unsurprising that he has been particularly prone to such treatment. And
Schumann himself did little to dissuade anyone from trying their hand at a little
am ateur psychology; the works are peppered with biographical details, to such an
extent that the simplistic, one-to-one mapping, unidirectional (which is to say a
passage from life to work) model becomes difficult to sustain. If we return to
Carnaval for a moment, which in the words of Lawrence Kramer approaches an
ideal subject precisely through a kind of fragm entation,’ there is a superabundance
of biographical material provided freely by Schumann, insofar as all of ‘the
miniatures that make up this collection are either character sketches or dances,
17 Asafiev, B., quoted in Monelle, R., Linguistics and Semiotics in M usic, (Harwood
Academ ic Publishers, Chur etc., 1992), p. 277.
23
that is, personal or social im ages.’18 Not only do we have the divided self-image of
the composer expressed in the ‘Florestan’ and ‘Eusebius’ sections of the piece, but
the form er of these, as mentioned above, quotes from one of his own earlier
works. Sections continually run into one another, complete one another
harmonically, making a mockery of the idea of a stable and chronologically ordered
identity. The usual musicological solution to this thorny problem is to seek refuge
in the cryptic ‘Sphinxes,’ a set of three pitch motifs derived from the lettering of his
own name, and from two alternate musical ‘spellings’ of his then fiancee’s home
town, which are used to convey unity upon the Carnaval set. This conveniently
overlooks, however, both the parts of the set unrelated to the Sphinxes, and more
obviously the fact that there are three Sphinxes, which although related in pitch
content are clearly distinct. To portray this as being a unity of sorts is to wilfully
ignore a much simpler explanation; it is what Julia Kristeva terms a ‘plural
totality,’19 a multiplicity of interacting fragments, coherent but not coterminous.
It is a paradox that probably would have delighted the Jena circle, that the
idea of the fragment as an important mode of expression coincided with the
emergence of the aesthetic principles of organicism and unity. This in part
explains the unique position of Schumann in music history, at once admired and
derided, who as primary inheritor of the ideas of the Jena circle in the field of music
produced work of undeniable quality, while failing utterly to conform to the criteria
that would later become the yardstick of compositional ability, that is, the
Schenkerian ideal of large-scale compositional direction and unity. Schumann not
only appears to fail according to this standard, but at times seems almost hostile to
the idea, and yet his music has a formal brilliance all of its own, a status that
stands outside the box of the autonomous art work. Rosen writes:
The Romantic fragment is a closed structure, but its closure is a formality: it may be
separated from the rest of the universe, but it implies the existence of what is outside
itself not by reference but by its instability. The form is not fixed but is torn apart or
Narratives, without connectedness, but with associations, like dreams. Poems - just
sounding well and full of beautiful words - but also without any sense or
connectedness - at most a single strophe that is understandable - like so many
fragments of the most different kinds of things. True poetry can, at most, have an
overall allegorical sense, and make an indirect effect, like music.24
(It should be noted that the German Zusamm enhang implies a considerably more
tightly bound relationship than the English ‘connectedness;’ Rosen translates it as
‘logic.’) And it is this model of the fragment, formulated by Novalis in response to
the dreamlike qualities of fragmentation and association he perceived in music,
that is taken up by and realized in the form at of music video.
II
The recruiting of music as an art form to varying aesthetic banners has a long and
ignoble history that spans the nineteenth century, and which must act as a
fram ework of understanding for Novalis’s manifesto. There is little to choose
between Hegel’s assertion that music could not express concepts and was
therefore essentially worthless, and the stance of Hoffman et al which formed a
rather too easy connection between m usic’s indecipherability and ‘the ineffable,’
thus granting music the status of the art to which others might aspire, and all this
before one even begins to address the concept of the 'purely m usical.’ Amongst
the fog and smoke of philosophical war, in which the aim of all parties seemed to
24 Translation taken from Treitler, L , ‘Mozart and the Idea of Absolute M usic,’ in
Music and the Historical Imagination, (Harvard University Press, Cambridge,
Mass., 1989), p. 184.
25 Original German taken from Rosen, C., op. cit., p. 76.
26
be the claiming of Beethoven’s Ninth Symphony to each’s own standard, there are
any number of contradictory positions, the complexities of which would form a
lengthy book in its own right (for an overview of these issues, see Carl Dahlhaus’s
The Idea o f Absolute Music26), but a few key points do emerge. Prime among
these are the questions of meaning and music, and narrative and music.
The issue of locating meaning in music is sufficiently troublesome to have
been almost entirely avoided by traditional musicological analysis; one can’t help
but suspect that Schenkerian analysis is as much about studiously ignoring the
social complexity of music as with constructing something genuinely immanent to
its material qualities. Even the Baroque period’s interest with ‘the affections' or the
Enlightenment's ‘passions,’ while interesting in themselves, are clearly means of
substitution for the category of meaning, deliberate or not. One possible
conclusion which might be drawn from this is that the concept of meaning is simply
not a particularly useful or relevant one in relation to music, and there is a sense in
which this view has some merit, but the problem that needs to be explicated here
lies in the use of the blanket term ‘meaning.’ The concept of ‘musical m eaning’
covers a sufficiently broad range of competing arguments as to require a
distinction between different sorts of ‘m eaning:’ is the reference to denoted or
connoted meaning, semiotic or sem antic meaning, ‘extra-m usical’ meaning, or
even a Barthesian ‘third meaning’ (the obtuse, as opposed to the obvious27). The
concept of music as directly denoting meaning, as language does, is impossible to
sustain, and as such analysis of the ‘purely m usical,’ be it Schenkerian,
paradigmatic analysis, or pitch-set theory (although as Robert Snarrenberg has
suggested, in Schenker’s case this is due to a deliberate stripping down of
Schenker’s thought to its positivistic aspects alone28), has fought shy of even
addressing the question of meaning. But this is not to say that it lacks any sense
26 Dahlhaus, C., The Idea o f Absolute Music, trans. Lustig, R., (University of
Chicago Press, Chicago and London, 1989).
27 These terms are discussed and defined in Barthes’ essay T h e Third Meaning:
Research notes on some Eisenstein stills,’ Image Music Text, op. cit., pp. 52-68.
28 Snarrenberg, R., ‘Competing myths: the American abandonment of Schenker’s
organicism ,’ in Theory, analysis and meaning in music, ed. Pople, A., (Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge, 1994), pp. 29-56.
27
32 Ibid., p. 270.
33 Agawu, K., Playing with Signs: A Semiotic Interpretation o f Classic Music,
(Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey, 1991), p. 5.
34 Ibid., p. 5.
35 Cook, N., Analysing Musical Multimedia, (Oxford University Press, 1998), p. 9.
29
implicit in A gaw u’s ‘how does it m ean’ is invoked only to tie down music all the
more securely, and without reflection on what this meaning means. Understanding
meaning in music was clearly untenable and unanswerable in the form of a ‘w hat’
question, but having moved to a ‘how’ question Agawu shies away from its
ramifications.
Music ceases to be a thing, ein Ding, in Heidegger’s terms, and becomes
an event, Bedingnis, and the consequences of this for meaning are potentially dire,
or liberating, depending upon one’s standpoint. Both Cook and Chris Small effect
the change from musical object to musical event, or ‘musicking,’ as Chris Small
term s it,36 and both choose to reinstate meaning as a function of the interactions
that are set in place, rather than attempt ‘to escape the tyranny of m eaning.'37 The
tendency of meaning is always to become product rather than process, an
idealizing and fixing of something that is in flux. To make a sound event mean
something is to stop it being a sound and make it into something else, an ideal
category, stripped of its materiality and ontologized. As Adorno states in Aesthetic
Theory: T h e movement toward the negation of meaning was exactly what
meaning deserved,’38 (and I shall return to Adorno and the status of meaning in
chapter III). And in a system where musical meaning can be convincingly
com pared with the exercise of social power, as Jacques Attali has shown,39 the
resistance to fixing meaning, and of remaining en proces, is one of political
engagem ent through a form of refusal to play the game that has been set out in
advance: ‘It is a political task ... to undertake to reduce communication
theoretically to the mercantile level of human relations and to integrate it, as a
simple fluctuating level, to significance, to the text, an apparatus outside of
chronological sequence of the events’ occurrence, and the order of their unfolding
in the telling.’48 However, I believe that in distilling the complexities involved in
representing reality down to the simple matter of chronological time, Treitler has
m isrepresented the full scope of narrative. Thus when he states
The apprehension of a musical work depends, in quite similar ways, on two intertwined
processes: on the one hand the underlying patterns of conventional genres and implicit
constraints arising from the grammar of style (harmony, voice-leading, and so on), and
on the other the progressive interpretation o f these determinants through the unfolding
of the work in time. The first dimension is not exactly like the chronological sequence
of the events of a story, but it is the counterpart in being the dimension of the
determinants that are more or less fixed prior to the unfolding.49
one might be forgiven for not taking this as proof of m usic’s narrativity. Indeed, as
stated above, music’s affect confuses and complicates the linearity of the
temporal. The problem, if it might be termed so, for music is its inability to
reformulate the real, to represent, in any recognizable form, a reality outside of
itself.
48 Treitler, L., Music and the Historical Imagination, (Harvard University Press,
Cambridge, MA, and London, 1989), p. 186.
49 Ibid., p. 190.
50 Abbate, C., Unsung Voices: Opera and Musical Narrative in the Nineteenth
Century, (Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey, 1991), p. 27.
51 Ibid., p. 28.
34
Music does not lie, because of necessity the task of linking these phantoms of
characters to suggestions of action will fall to me, the listener: it is not within the
semiological possibilities of music to link a subject to a predicate. ... If, in listening to
music, I am tempted by the “narrative impulse,” it is indeed because, on the level of the
strictly musical discourse, I recognize returns, expectations and resolutions, but of what
I do not know. Thus I have a wish to complete through words what the music does not
say because it is not in its semiological nature to say it to me.54
Thus, through narrative, the word is invited in to fulfil what sound alone could, or
perhaps would, not - the formation of a product, the completion of communication,
the constitution of the subject. T h e predicate is always the bulwark with which the
subject’s imaginary protects itself from the loss which threatens it.’55 Nattiez
recognizes the misapplication of predication to music, the refusal of sound to
transfer directly the subjectivity of the composer in the poietic process, but then
52 Ibid., p. 19.
53 Nattiez, J.-J., ‘Can One Speak of Narrativity in Music?,’ op. cit., p. 249.
54 Ibid., pp. 244-5.
55 Barthes, R., T h e Grain of the Voice,’ op. cit., p. 179.
35
reinstates this in the aesthesic realm, rejecting the aural paradigm, signifiance, in
favour of the visual.
If music is so readily co-opted to a ‘visual’ model, by which I mean one
based upon secure representation, so as to enable clear meaning-product to be
communicated, it might be thought that the medium of music video would
accom plish this all the more readily. W hat I wish to argue, though, is that this is
precisely what does not happen; certainly they are an invitation to narrativize,
perhaps more so than music alone, and some are more susceptible to this than
others, but in the main it is remarkable how resistant music videos are to narrative
and any sort of secured meaning. Images, like sounds, are held en proces,
instead of being communicative of product. Music videos enable one to resist the
tem ptation of the ‘narrative im pulse.’ (It would be a mistake, however, to conclude
that pop m usic’s resistance to narrativization is in an explicitly anti-narrative
stance, as certain post-modernists would have it: the work of Kaplan,56 amongst
others, misrepresents music just as much as those that would ‘read’ a musical text
like a newspaper.) Perhaps this is less surprising if one acknowledges the type of
music that music videos are typically formed around, which is to say, the three
m inute pop song; this immediately prevents the development of any kind of
extended story. As Richard Middleton notes: ‘If pop songs are “little plays,” as has
been suggested, they are mostly sketches of situations rather than lengthy
dram atic narratives.’57
The raising of the status of music to dominant partner in the music video
com posite is prompted not only by aesthetics, but also by practicalities of music
video production, where the soundtrack precedes the image track in all but a
minute number of cases. As such, sound provides the template to which the
image must be accommodated. Furthermore, this process binds the act of music
reception into the poietic process itself, so that the making of the image takes the
form of a response to the music, and the music video is collectivized at the level of
its incipience. One might compare this to Theodor Adorno's criticism of the
56 See Kaplan, E.A., Rocking Around the Clock: Music Television, Postmodernism,
and Consum er Culture, (Routledge, London and New York, 1987).
57 Middleton, R., Studying Popular Music, (Open University Press, Milton Keynes,
1990), p. 224.
36
58 Adorno, T.W., In Search o f Wagner, trans. Livingstone, R., (Verso, London and
New York, 1991), p. 110.
59 Ibid., p. 111.
60 There are any number of examples, but a good one is Lawrence G rossberg’s
comparison of the stylistics of 1980s ‘brat-pack’ films to music video, in T h e Media
Economy of Rock Culture: Cinema, Post-modernism and Authenticity,’ in Sound
and Vision: The Music Video Reader, ed. Frith, S., Goodwin, A., and Grossberg,
L., (Routledge, London and New York, 1993), pp. 185-209.
61 Goodwin, A., Dancing in the Distraction Factory: Music Television and Popular
Culture, (University of Minneapolis Press, Minneapolis, 1992). Goodwin is
particularly critical of Kaplan and Fiske for misinterpreting video events under the
rubric of postmodernism when they can be explained straightforwardly by attention
to musical practice.
37
com plete with opening and closing credits, and made by an established film
director), eventually ‘acknowledges that there is no “plot” as such: the narrative
code that structures the story has no story to tell. Rather it creates a simulacrum
of a story, a parody of a story, in its stylistic send-up of genre conventions.’62
Notably, in his attempt to identify the narrative of this video, Mercer, in common
with Kaplan et al, almost entirely avoids any mention of the actual music, referring
only to its lyric (word) content. Conversely, if one approaches the music video as a
‘making musical of the television im age,’63 any consideration of narrative becomes
largely incidental. In Carol Vernallis’s words: T h e use of the musical section as
the fundam ental unit places an emphasis upon varied repetition of materials over
linear developm ent.’64 It is not that the idea of narrative is entirely absent from the
world of pop; just that it is not located at the level of the music video artefact.
Quoting Goodwin once more: ‘characterization, fiction, and perhaps even narrative
itself exist in popular music at the point of narration, outside the diegesis of
individual songs, live performances, or video clips, through the persona of the pop
star.’65 This phenomenon is not limited to music video - Barry King has written on
the existence of the same process at work in cinema,66 and the refocussing of
identity upon the ‘personality’ of the star constitutes what Benjamin terms false
aura.’67 However, in music video, unlike in film, it provides a mechanism by which
a visual paradigm might be reasserted, and confers a unity that is not present at
the level of music video text.
In order to understand music video analytically, then, first one must
generate and identify, both materially and relationally, a set of fragments that can
Beatles are indivisible from their films, press photographs, and record covers in the
popular imagination, let alone more recent m anufactured’ pop acts, but this is a
feature of all music in W estern culture, of the very idea of musical culture. Cook
writes:
Musical cultures are not simply cultures of sounds, nor simply cultures of
representations of sounds, but cultures of the relationship between sound and
representation. The cohabitation and confrontation of different media are inscribed
within the practice of Western classical music (and perhaps of all music), in the
relationship between sound and verbal discourse. It is in this sense that music, even
“music alone," should properly be seen as a form of multimedia in which all the
components but one have been forced to run underground, sublimated or otherwise
m arginalized.'1
This is the theoretical fram ework that one must enter into in order to develop a
practical methodology of music video analysis.
What, then, is it that I perceive in the presence of music video? W hat are
the qualities that persist in the memory after I have turned away from the screen?
The answer, at once banal and profound, is that I perceive many things in a
simultaneity, or rather, a series of simultaneities. Not the vertical disjunction of
sound, word, and image, but a syntagmatic disjunction of sound/word/image
complexes, each satiated and replete with incipient meaning, and yet
simultaneously dependent upon its connection with a broader (social) context, for
none of these complexes is received in isolation - I perceive a syntagmatic
disjunction, but as a precondition of this I perceive also the presence of syntagm, a
relationship Vernallis describes as ‘the here and now of the video, its moment-to-
moment flow.’72 To rephrase this in terms of my earlier model, as a set of
fragm ents that cohere to form something other (I hesitate to say more, though that
is undoubtedly what I mean) than the sum of their collective parts. The fragmented
address of the music video necessarily draws one’s attention to the social totality
visual material presented, the ‘sensuous image' in Benjamin’s terms, rather than
any sort of storyline.
One might theorize this as being a visual corollary to the musical concept of
the ‘hook,’ the aural signature of a pop single designed to ‘catch’ the listener, but it
is not, I think, a phenomenon entirely unique to the music video format, even if its
specific context and mode of construction are. Compare Barthes' response to the
films of Eisenstein: ‘no single image is boring, we are not forced to wait for the next
one in order to understand and be delighted: no dialectic (that interval of patience
necessary for certain pleasures), but a continuous jubilation, consisting of a
summation of perfect m oments.’74 Indeed, Eisenstein’s own conception of the
audio-visual montage approaches the techniques common to music video: ‘the
centre of gravity is no longer the element “between shots” - the shock - but the
element “inside the shot” - the accentuation within the fragm ent,’75 and it seems
there is a connection between this perceived quality of music videos, and that
quality of film that troubled Barthes, which he labelled the ‘obtuse m eaning.’
Barthes eventually drew this quality from the film still, although it should be noted
that ‘the still’ is rather different to the photograph that the term conjures in the
m ind’s eye: it is defined as ‘the fragment of a second text whose existence never
exceeds the fragment, film and still find themselves in a palimpsest relationship
without it being possible to say that one is on top of the other or that one is
extracted from the other.’76 Given this complex reciprocal relationship, it is fair to
say that there is a sense in which the music video more closely resembles a set of
stills than it does film: it resembles a set of fragments excised from a film that does
not exist. There is, however, an important difference, for whereas the primary aim
of Eisenstein’s was a representation of ari idea, ‘the historical meaning of the
represented gesture,’77 through the image, from which a third, obtuse, meaning
escaped, there is no such aim in music video. The music video fragm ent is an
the structure(s) of the artefact does not necessarily produce an analytic order, and
to do so arbitrarily would be an injustice to the material of investigation. To reduce
the play of disorder that characterizes the music video to an explicable linear order
would be a pointless exercise, and say little or nothing about the supposed object
of investigation: better to enter into that spirit of play, to map out, rather than iron
out, the complex weave of meaning and non-meaning. The Romantics, too,
struggled with the relationship between chaos and order in the artistic fragment.
Schlegel explicitly opposed the chaotic and the fragmentary, while still trying to
incorporate the idea of the chaotic, as a m etaphor for the disorder of everyday
experience, into the symmetrical order of the artistic form, writing: Rhyme must be
chaotic, and yet as chaotic with symmetry as possible. From this can be inferred
the system of Romantic m etre.’81 W hat the Romantics were unaware of was that
the chaotic is not necessarily without order, and it is on this point that my
conception of the fragment is markedly different from the Romantic fragment.
Modern mathematics has uncovered the way in which simple ordered units can
generate apparently chaotic systems, with unpredictable results, or at least results
that can be gauged only as probabilities rather than certainties. (This same
mathematics has generated the model of the fractal image, of which more
elsewhere.) The music video, then, is truly chaotic, in that although its actuality
cannot and should not be distorted into order, its mode of construction, the means
by which this actuality was arrived at, can be understood and modelled.
The model which most accurately describes the workings of the production
of meaning (and non-meaning) is that outlined by Greimas in his Structural
Sem antics,82 which although directed specifically at the structure of language can
be adapted to shed light on a range of other possibilities. His method divides
language into the basic linguistic component of the lexeme, which might be
approximated very broadly to a word or group of words, and which can be further
broken down into its constituent elements of meaning, semes. Each lexeme is a
complex of semes, a ‘stylistic constellation,’ some of which are permanent and
invariant’ forming a ‘semic nucleus,’ and others are only contextually related and
thus are ‘contextual semes.’ In any group of lexemes there must be set of semes
in common in order for them to be meaningful, but similarly there will be semes
that point in other directions outside of the intended meaning, a kind of semic
residue that appears to resemble what I have elsewhere termed an associative
Figure 183
complex. In the normal course of affairs certain isolated contextual semes will
recur and create what is termed ‘redundancy,’ while other contextual semes fall
away, remaining only as an invisible trace of language, as a necessary condition of
intelligibility. ‘Redundancy sets in at the moment when a discourse begins to
become intelligible; without redundancy language is meaningless nonsense, while
too much redundancy creates m eaningless repetition.’84 It is my contention,
however, that this process, while fundam entally the same, is somewhat altered in a
multimedia instance (using Cook’s terminology). In a music video the anchoring
semic nucleus’ is not ‘permanent and invariant’ to anything like the sam e degree,
whilst the ‘contextual sem es’ are infinitely more numerous, invoking not only the
am biguity of poetic language in the lyrics, but also the polysemy of the rhetorical
image and of music. As a result the process of redundancy is much less clear - it
is possible that there will be enough recurring semes to enable the m ultiplicity of
'senses’ that one sees emerge - and subsequently the ‘invisible trace’ of
m etonymic residue is never repressed to the same extent that it is in everyday
language. This vast array of contradictory information is not eliminated, but held in
play as a ‘m eaningless’ backdrop to the plurality of meanings available. Hence the
categories of ‘m eaning’ and ‘non-m eaning’ are hopelessly intertwined, dependent
upon one another, creating the chaotic structure of the music video outlined above:
order, such as there is, must be sought at the level of the music video equivalent of
the lexeme, the fragment, the ‘stylistic constellation,’ while understanding will be
found in the warp and the weft of their enmeshment.
Ill
What, in the meantime, has happened to Robert Schumann? W here has his flight
into the rain-soaked streets of Dusseldorf, his head filled with sound (tortured by
the music of both angels and demons), taken him? Clara’s diary cannot help - she
knows only part of the story - but perhaps Barthes can shed some light on his
situation.
Plural, lost, panicked, the Schumannian body knows (at least here) only bifurcations; it
does not construct itself, it keeps diverging according to an accumulation of interludes;
it has only that vague idea (the vague can be a phenomenon of structure) of meaning
which we call signifiance. ... Music, in short, at this level, is an image, not a language,
in that every image is radiant, from the rhythmic incisions of pre-history to the frames of
comic strips. The musical text does not follow (by contrasts or amplification), it
explodes: it is a continuous big bang.85
‘Rasch' have become the speech acts through which Robert Schumann is made
music, a set of movements (variations?) in which is expressed divergence,
accumulation, radiation, explosion: all of those qualities that are attributed to the
musical event and the music video. Schum ann’s precise line of flight through
Dusseldorf, resonating with the involuntary pre-memories of sounds unheard,
remains unspoken, however, until the point at which he arrives at the Rhine
Bridge, and it is only much later that Clara will learn, in a fragmentary and
piecemeal fashion, that the men who returned him to his home were the same
fisherm en that had dragged him from the water; and it is as this radiant image of a
man falling into the water and re-emerging plays through my mind, that it dissolves
into a video picture, and I remember (involuntarily) my object of investigation,
R.E.M .’s ‘Imitation of Life.’ Thus forms the ‘constellation of voices ... from which I
draw my voice,’87 and in the ‘jum p-cut’ I make from Schumann falling into the
Rhine, to a scene from ‘Imitation of Life,’ I at once strip the image of its obvious
meaning, making it sensuous rather than ideal, and reset meaning as activity, an
intermingling of bodies’88 en proces.
If the music video is a demonstration of fragmentary form, then 'Imitation of
Life,' incomplete, plural, vague, and radiant, is Exhibit A. The divergent quality of
the music video image track is emphasized here, as described earlier, by a spatial
separation of distinct ‘types;’ the lyrics are deliberately obtuse, peppered with non-
sequiturs, and are dispersed amongst the characters in such a way as to
problematize and pluralize the notion of ‘author;’ the music track consists of
melodic scraps which cross and recross the traditional structural divide (verse,
chorus) of the pop-song form, while superficially maintaining that structure. In
short, identity, representation, autonomy, all are called into question during these
twenty seconds of video, a fragment that is itself fragmented, reversed and
repeated some eleven times during the course of the music video composite.
Indeed, the unfolding of the video is such that alongside every moment of
congruence between sound, lyric, and image there are also several disjunctures,
which will in turn become conjunct in later repetitions, so that as Bjork suggests,
one remembers, though it hasn’t happened yet.
87 Ibid., p. 84.
88 Ibid., p. 86.
47
I have discussed the construction of the image track in very general terms
earlier in the chapter, but the effect of this is mainly to enable a focussing of
attention upon the wealth of detail present, far more than one could hope to
com prehensively address. Furthermore, there are a series of possible frameworks
for understanding these images: the ‘party scene’ totality of the video text, the
m acro-text of R.E.M. as a successful band known for their ‘folk-rock’ style of
music, as well as the lyric and soundtracks, and all or some of these frameworks
are being intuitively employed simultaneously in the activity of reception. Several
images immediately catch the eye: the burning man diving into the pool (before re-
emerging as the video reverses), that first drew me from my Schumannian reverie.
This image resembles a film image, wrenched from context, and functions
specifically as a metonym of the Hollywood action movie, belonging to the
category of ‘the stunt-man spectacle.’ It is at once somewhat at odds with the
suburban setting of the video, and with the ‘folksy’ aspect of the R.E.M. public
image (present here in the tone of the mandolin), and yet also chimes with the
repeated phrase of ‘that’s Hollywood’ that forms part of the chorus (although it is
not precisely coincident with this utterance), and the more general seme
surrounding pop and rock music of ‘American entertainm ent.’89 Thus there is an
immediate setting up of conflicting conceptual realms at play here, which are taken
up by another image spatially contiguous with the burning man, that of bass player
Mike Mills filling a champagne fountain. This is more a cultural indicator of high
living, a sign of plenitude and excess associated with (over-indulgent) rock stars
and sport stars (and I am thinking particularly of the oft shown footage of George
Best in a similar pose), but is again at odds with the axis suburban/folksy. The
image gains further poignancy from the association of R.E.M. with alcoholic excess
a relatively short time after a widely reported incident of Peter Buck’s being drunk
and disorderly on an aeroplane, a ‘classic’ rock-star moment (and no doubt the
reason for its being widely reported, despite his subsequent acquittal). A third
striking image is that of guitarist Peter Buck, the only diegetic sound source in the
video save for very brief moments of Stipe singing, playing his tradem ark
mandolin. He is focussed on only in passing, although frequently in shot, perhaps
echoing the status of his instrument, that provides near constant background
arpeggiation, but never comes to the fore of the soundtrack. W hat is remarkable is
his use of dark glasses and slightly stilted and detached deportment, the
implication seeming to be that of blindness, which when combined with the w itch’s
fam iliar he has with him (an ape) conjures the figure of the seer. Once again this
is a highly unusual personage to be present at a suburban party, and is suggestive
of a position outside the video, an ability to see a ‘truth’ that is beyond the scene
portrayed, perhaps loosely connected with the idea of recognizing the distinction
between ‘im itation’ and ‘life’ that the title sets in play. All of the images here are
resonant, rather than merely representative - they overtly point outside of
themselves, functioning as ‘texts’ rather than simple objects. It is in conjunction
with the lyric and sound tracks, however, that the sensuous qualities of these
images are put into play.
Like the image track, the lyrics consist of a series of ‘radiant’ phrases that
are without any overarching ‘sense’ - they exist as a coherence rather than as a
unity (see Appendix for complete lyric sheet). The opening stanza immediately
puts into play a set of disparate concepts, and even the opening line, ‘Charades
pop skill,’ free from any obvious meaning, sets a whole series of ideas in process.
The word ‘charades,’ referring to a similarity of gestural form, invites one both to
reconsider the ungainly backwards dancing with which the video begins, and also
to consider the question of representation put into play by the title and following
line, ‘imitation of life,’ as well as suggesting the party game of the same name that
involves guessing gestural equivalents. There are points that clearly resonate with
the image track - several water references (‘water hyacinths,’ koi in a frozen
pond’), and a ‘folksiness’ to the concise phrasing and grammar of ‘that sugar cane,
that tasted good,’ and the figure of ‘this lemonade,’ the lemonade stall being the
quintessence of suburban Americana, but there is only one brief moment of direct
connection, where the ‘teenager, cruising in the corner’ is directly represented.
Equally there are many phrases entirely at odds with the scene: a ‘Friday fashion
show,’ and the set of phrases grouped under the seme ‘natural disaster’ -
hurricane, tidal wave, avalanche, etc. - which are palpably playing against the
image track, and pointing elsewhere, i.e. outside the video scene. However, the
49
sections of the lyrics that are most clearly articulated, and of greatest interest, are
those voiced by characters in the video. Some of these are diegetic, the shouting
of ‘c’mon, c’m on;’ some take the form of, admittedly strange, conversations
between characters within the video, as with the Italianate woman at the table in
the foreground (who to my mind seems to embody the seme ‘insufferable’ with her
overt diction and habit of literally looking down her nose at people); whilst others
directly address the viewer in a ‘perform ance’ mode, expected of the ‘star’ Michael
Stipe, but more unusual when seen from some of the ‘bit’ players. This division of
lyric text makes the idea of locating a stable and unitary authorial ‘voice’ ridiculous,
especially given that there are two Michael Stipes present - as a character and as
a disembodied head on a television screen within the video fram e (a further
problematization of representation?) - and that the compressed time frame of the
image track means people are often talking across one another, the soundtrack
selecting each in turn. The question of whose words these are is left completely
ambiguous; disconnected phrases are divided amongst the party guests, although
all of them speak with Stipe’s voice.
Anyone hoping or expecting to find unity and stability at the level of the
music, however, (and this is not an uncommon move in musicology), will be
somewhat disappointed. It is precisely a musicalization of the image that has
prompted this multiplicity of analytic outcomes. Although the song superficially
resembles the typical strophic verse/chorus/middle eight format of the pop song, a
closer look will show an adaptation of this, and further analysis shows that there is
a confusion of both the identity and the structural function of the verse/chorus
relationship. The basic structure is:
V C V C Int. C C 1 C1 C C
(where V = Verse, C = Chorus, and Int. = Middle Eight, at bars 9, 264, 37, 544, 64,
764, 864, 944, 1024, 1104 respectively - see transcription in the appendix). The
interlude is a middle twelve, rather than a middle eight (in fact it is properly a
middle sixteen, but the chorus re-enters four bars before its completion). It can be
clearly seen that in the second half of the song the structural function of the verse
is replaced by that of a melodically and lyrically altered chorus. W hile verse and
chorus are given distinct tonalities, E minor and its relative major, G, respectively,
both of these are very weakly stated: there is no strong cadence in E minor, and
50
Figure 2a
t’Tnnjirb ,■
. Am
A1
m £
rhythmically syncopated, that forms the close of both A and A 1, is then used as the
basis of the chorus melody, which closes with a near identical melismatic flourish
Figure 2b
Close of A /A 1
Chorus motif
51
on the word cry’/ ’try.’ It is this close motivic interconnection, and rhythmic and
rhetorical similarity, allied to an unconventional structure that causes the confusion
between verse and chorus in this piece. The entire song is constructed from a
series of melodic fragments that are permutated in such a way as to generate both
the verse and the chorus: these repeated figures, like the Schumannian body, do
not stay in place.’ Some might see this motivic reworking as a means of
circum venting the structural ambiguity of the song so as to create a greater
consistency and unity, but, very much like the ‘Sphinxes’ of Schum ann’s Carnaval,
this rather wilfully ignores the fact that there are several motives present here,
which although undermining the distinction between verse and chorus are
nevertheless perfectly distinct with respect to one another (to say nothing of the
middle eight). There is not a unity here, but again a multiplicity, a plurality of
fragments, and the totality they produce, such as it is, is fractured but distinct in its
identity. This mode of immanent analysis demonstrates not only the literal,
repetition of motivic fragments, performed in such a way as to highlight their
material qualities, as is often seen in so-called ‘m inim alist’ works, but also
highlights the motility of this repetition en proces, its unfixed and evasive
relationship to the strictures of typical song format.
As can be seen, a brief examination of a few of the more obvious
disjunctions between and within music, word, and image, has generated a
considerable weight of analysis, and left a vast swathe of material untouched:
poetic metre, instrumental timbre, the large number of ‘background’ characters. It
is, of course, in the interaction of all these various parts that the substance of
music video is to be found, and so to conclude this analysis I will perform a brief
com parison between two similar moments with quite different affects. The two
points I refer to are both moments of ‘false’ diegesis, that is, other characters
voicing Stipe’s lyrics: the woman on the rock at the front of the pool, and the
adulterous wom an’ at the back left of the scene respectively. Both sing one of the
two adapted choruses and thus have very similar texts to sing and identical
melodies. However, whereas the form er seems to have a poignancy and quality of
regret, the latter seems far more upbeat. Since both moments have so many
sim ilarities one might think that the stem of this difference might be easy to locate,
but it is not. Does the form er’s wistfulness come from her solitariness, from
something in her face, from the fact that the film is running backwards at this point,
52
or from the qualities I draw out of the specific word ‘lemonade’ in this context? And
does the latter’s relatively upbeat quality derive from her yellow dress, her joining
with her lover, the fact that the film is now running forwards again, or more
probably from the reintroduction of the full instrumental backing, absent from the
sparse instrumentation of the first statement of the adapted chorus. The answer is
that the distinction resides in all of these facts, and a great many others besides:
for instance, ‘avalanche’ might be linked to the band T h e Avalanches,’ makers of
upbeat dance music, while ‘hurricane’ begets Hurricane no. 1,’ a rather dour rock
band, restricting reference to popular music alone. Some facts are naturally more
relevant than others, and I suspect that the m usic’s timbre is of key importance in
this instance, but none of them are irrelevant, and all contribute, in however small
a way, to the overall sense impression that the music video experience generates.
I em phasize again that this is an interactive, and not an additive process: these
senses are not a mere accumulation of associated properties but an
interconnected web. To remove one element, however small, would be to remove
its interaction with all the other elements and fundamentally alter the 'wiring' of the
object, and it is this point that will be taken up in chapter II. As fragments cohere
to form a totality, so associations cohere to form these fragments. Like the chaotic
fractal image, however deep’ one cares to travel into the structuration of the
object, the same structure will appear time and again, and as Gerald Bruns writes,
after Bakhtin, T h e point to remember is that your descent is not taking you deeper
into the inner world of preconscious grammars or, below these, into the body
where one hears the warm, undifferentiatied murmur of the mother tongue. On the
contrary, you are heading into the outer world of the “social heteroglossia." The
deeper you go, the more open things get.’90
IV
There seems to be a certain potency in the post-modernist position, which takes the
dominant system as given and proposes as method of critique the fragment:
subversion takes the form of “guerilla activity" which exploits fissures and forgotten
spaces within the hegemonic structure. An “either/or” (to the extent it existed) is
replaced by an “and/and,” a confrontation between unitary subjectivity and its
destruction by an acceptance of multiples and contradictions.91
interm ediary step against ‘mass culture,’ so as to reconstitute the totality in another
form: it is an attempt ‘to evolve structures which can admit chaos, fragmentation
and meaninglessness and which at the same time, through “critical
consciousness,” can transcend such content.’95 This fragment is a means to an
end, whereas the postmodern fragm ent has become an end in itself, a rejoinder to
the ‘grand narratives’ famously critiqued in Lyotard’s Report on Knowledge 96 Both
theories are formulated as a refusal of the status quo, but where Adorno identifies
the existing material relations of the current ‘totality’ as the problem,
postmodernism regards ‘totality’ as such to be the problem. The weakness of this
latter stance, at least in many of its subsequent formulations, is the lack of critical
leverage it enables - the fragm ent cast adrift is easily fetishized and rendered
powerless. Individualized multiplicity bears no danger for late capitalism, and is
more likely to become a new selling opportunity than a threat. W hat is required is
a reconception of the totality as an em ergent property of a set of fragments, an
unfixed and contingent collective entity, that is the resultant of a set of practices,
rather than the determinant of those practices. Such a theory is put forward by
Deleuze and Guattari in the figure of the rhizome, where T h e line no longer forms
a contour, and instead passes between things, between points. ... The multiplicity
it constitutes is no longer subordinated to the O ne.’97 The rhizome is a coherence
of fragments, which no longer need to be reified into ‘types’ for the purposes of
critical discourse; it provides an alternative rather than a challenge to the status
quo, since to challenge it directly would involve acceding to the rules of
engagem ent already set out. In this way the music video can remain musical and
not ideal, material and not transcendent, affect rather than representation.
This problem bears more than a passing similarity to that of locating a final
‘signified,’ that might act as anchor to the system of language, and I do not think
this is mere coincidence. It is essentially a question of ordering and understanding
one’s world, or better Weltanschauung, and this is necessarily connected with the
95 Ibid., p. 52.
96 Lyotard, J.-F., The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge, trans.
Bennington, D. and Massumi, B., (Manchester University Press, Manchester,
1984).
9' Deleuze, G. and Guattari, F., op. cit., p. 505.
55
issue of language. The binding of world and artefact takes place in and through
language, although this involves an expansion of the concept of 'language' beyond
the narrow one employed by Saussure. Barthes writes: T h e image is penetrated
through and through by the system of meaning, in exactly the same way as man is
articulated to the very depths of his being in distinct languages. The language of
the image is not necessarily the totality of utterances emitted ... it is also the
totality of utterances received.’98 This is not to say, however, that the image (or
music video) derives its identity from the totality of meanings centred upon it alone,
but from the very system of meaning as well, from a ‘language’ enlarged by
reception theory, the language of Heidegger, Benjamin, and Wittgenstein.
W ittgenstein in particular maps out a relation between identity and language that is
of great significance to the fragment/totality model. The idea of language as a
‘totality of utterances,’ not as a single entity, but as a connected group of things
(which he termed ‘language-gam es’), is of fundamental im portance to the later
W ittgenstein’s thought: ‘We see that what we call ‘sentence’ and ‘language’ has
not the formal unity that I imagined, but is the family of structures more or less
related to one another.’99 The connection between these things is the same as
that between different games; there is not one rule that applies to all, a unifying
law, but a range of disparate entities that are similar in some respects, different in
others, but which all overlap to a greater or lesser extent to produce the field (or
family) of ‘gam es.’
Instead of producing something common to all that we call language, I am saying that
these phenomena have no one thing in common which makes us use the same word
for all, - but that they are related to one another in many different ways. And it is
because of this relationship, or these relationships, that we call them all “language.” ...
We see a complicated network of similarities overlapping and criss-crossing:
sometimes overall similarities, sometimes similarities of detail.100
This familial relationship that characterizes language, and thus an entire culture or
‘form of life’ for Wittgenstein, a model of multiple connections which exist as a
coherence without there being any centralized unity, is precisely the kind of
relationship that exists between fragments and totality, and determines the format
and identity of any given artefact. Thus a clarification of identity and fragmentary
structure is as much an interrogation of the sign system itself as of its specific
instances.
A final coherence,’ then, is not an appeal to a singular and unified entity,
but the above does not solve the problem of its location. Barthes notes:
‘theoretically, we can never halt a sign at a final signified; the only halt we can give
a sign in its reading is a halt which comes from practice, but not from the
sem iological system itself.’101 The solution to the problem lies not in a theorization
of Weltanschauung, but in W eltanschauung itself, that is, a way of living. The
‘final’ signified, ultimate coherence, lies not in theory, but in praxis. Quoting
W ittgenstein once more: ‘Do not say: T h e re isn’t a last’ definition.' That is just as
if you choose to say T he re isn’t a last house in this road; one can always build an
additional one.” 102 Thus the ultimate arbiter is one’s own culture and language, a
form of life,’ and the ultimate coherence the community in which it is received; a
coherence in which each individual is a fragment at once constitutive of and
constituted by that community. It is worth bearing in mind, then, that the source of
this understanding is itself contingent and in no way absolute. Thus the idea of
‘sym bolic dynamism,’ the continual dialectical process in which all parts of the
system are caught up, such that yesterday’s innovation becomes today’s cliche, is
not a strain upon a transcendental absolute, but constitutive of the system itself.
This close association of model and world is not entirely benign, however,
particularly with regard to music. There is a danger that music video might
become another means by which the model of the status quo might reassert itself.
Music, as Deleuze and Guattari warn, is a powerful tool of connection/collection:
‘Since its force of deterritorialization is the strongest, it also effects the most
101 Barthes, R., 'Semiology and M edicine,’ in The Semlotic Challenge, trans.
Howard, R., (University of California Press, Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1991), p.
210 .
102 W ittgenstein, L., Philosophical Investigations, §29.
57
The pop culture text is theorized as attempting to resolve contradictions in line with the
prevailing ideology, but subcultural audiences create their own meanings, which are
necessarily resistive since they contradict the dominant discourse. ... However, this is
not necessarily a sign of progressive politics. ... The question is, does this indicate
successful local resistances or only fragmentation of capital s address to its subjects, a
series of carefully articulated “job descriptions’’?106
I am not sure, however, that I agree with T etzlaffs rather downbeat conclusion,
that in the face of late capital, as with the Daleks, resistance is futile. A resistance
to the totalizing impulse, the desire to generate fragments that cohere without
having an essential unity, like the language-games of Wittgenstein, is more than
just good post-structural practice; it is a co-optation of the techniques of capital
itself. To set up a totalized and logical system is to invite its destruction -
removing any one aspect means the collapse of the entirety - better to spread
oneself, like capital, in such a manner that there is not one target, but many, and
so the destruction of one element need not destroy the resistive power of the
artefact as a whole. And the music video artefact, as a gateway to fragmentary
aesthetics, is capable of sustaining other forms of resistance. The semic
proliferation generated by music video as described above, is in a reciprocal
relationship with the fragment, which is to say that it is both constitutive of and
amplified by, the fragment model, and can enable a form of resistance of its own,
identified by Baudrillard. T h e present argument of the system is to maximize
speech, to maximize the production of meaning, of participation. And so the
strategic resistance is that of the refusal of meaning and the refusal of speech.’107
In a system dedicated to use, to the effective transfer of information, and above all
to efficiency, the prolific generation of that without use, an excess without logic, a
kind of ‘sem ic noise,’ is a reminder of an alternative, of another way, not so very
different from the Bakhtinian carnival. Furthermore, this intense polysemy may
have the potential to rupture the sign system itself, to be the ‘specific object' of
‘sem analysis’ described by Kristeva in her essay T h e Semiotic Activity.’108
Eagleton writes: T h e representational devices of bourgeois society are those of
exchange-value; but it is precisely this signifying frame that the productive forces
must break beyond, releasing a heterogeneity of use-values whose unique
10' Baudrillard, J., T h e Masses: The Implosion of the Social in the M edia,’ in Jean
Baudrillard: Selected Writings, ed. Poster, M., (Polity, Cambridge, 1988), p. 219.
108 Kristeva, J., T h e Semiotic Activity,’ Screen, vol. 14, (1973), p. 38. Kristeva
suggests that the ‘poetic text’ will fulfil this role, but I believe the music video to be
an even better example of ‘a bearer of a surplus of signification that the system of
the sign is unable to contain.’ [ibid.]
59
My good mood made it easier for me on that evening to treat Hanslick for some time as
a casual acquaintance up to the point when he took me aside for an intimate talk and
assured me, with tears and sobs, that he could no longer bear it to see himself
misunderstood by me; the blame for anything untoward in his judgements about me,
he averred, was certainly not rooted in a malevolent intention but solely in a limitation
of the individual, and he would like nothing better than to have the boundaries of his
knowledge extended by my instruction. These declarations were made with such an
explosion of emotion that I could feel no wish other than to soothe his pain and
promised my undivided sympathy in his further pursuits.1
1 W a g n e r, R., My Life, trans. Gray, A., ed. W hittall, M., (C a m brid g e U niversity Press, 1983),
pp. 694-5.
61
hostilities between the two were resumed in earnest, and would remain
unresolved. Through a hardening of their respective positions into mutually
incom patible views of music and opera, a state that was considerably enhanced by
the willingness of their followers to either misrepresent or m isunderstand both of
their positions for polemical value, a remarkable opportunity to reform ulate the
aesthetics of music based upon the common ground of their theories seems to
have been missed.
That W agner’s aesthetics might be misunderstood is perhaps
understandable; his theoretical promiscuity and capacity for adopting entirely
contradictory stances under the rubric of a self-mythology of consistency has been
well docum ented2 and formed the basis of a vicious attack by his form er acolyte,
N ietzsche3 (and in part explains the disparate groups that labelled themselves as
‘W agnerian’ in the years following his death). W hilst W agner’s capacity for being
all things to all men has done little to alter his impact or popularity (at least outside
of Israel, where he remains taboo), the misappropriation of Hanslick as a ‘form alist’
has resulted in a persistent misreading of his theories; a situation not helped by
Gustav C ohen’s translation into English of Vom M usikalisch-Schonen that, in the
words of its recent re-translator Geoffrey Payzant ‘rarely makes contact with
Hanslick’s argument.'4 John Shepherd dismisses Hanslick as an ‘absolutist,’5
Jean-Jacques Nattiez as 'adopting a normatively form alist conception of music ...
deny[ing] that purely sonorous configurations, independent of any textual
2 See, for instance, Wagnerism in European Culture and Politics, ed Large, D., and
Weber, W , (Cornell University Press, New York, 1984), and Dahlhaus, C., The Twofold
Truth in Wagner’s Aesthetics,’ in Between Romanticism and Modernism, trans. Whittall, M.,
(University of California Press, Berkeley, 1980).
3 See both ‘Nietzsche contra Wagner,’ Collected Works, vol. Ill, trans. Common, T., (T.
Fisher Unwin, London, 1899), and The Case of Wagner,’ in The Birth of Tragedy and The
Case of Wagner, trans. Kaufmann, W., (Random House, Toronto, 1967).
4 The details of this are discussed in Payzant’s ‘Essay: Towards a Revised reading of
Hanslick,’ in Hanslick, E., On the Musically Beautiful, trans. Payzant, G., (Hackett
Publishing Company, Indianapolis, 1986).
5 Shepherd, J., 'Music Consumption and cultural self-identities: some theoretical and
methodological reflections,’ Media, Culture and Society, vol. 8, (1986), p. 310.
62
6 Nattiez, J.-J., ‘Can One Speak of Narrativity in Music,’ Journal of the Royal Musical
Association, vol. 115:2, (1990), p. 243.
7 Small, C , Musicking: The meanings of performing and listening, (Wesleyan University
Press, New Hampshire, 1998), p. 135.
8 For a discussion of the complexities of ‘feeling-theory,’ see Dahlhaus, C., Esthetics of
Music, trans. Austin, W., (Cambridge University Press, 1982), pp. 16-24
9 Hanslick selectively quotes from Wagner’s The Artwork of the Future in the section of On
the Musically Beautiful entitled ‘Some Feeling-Theorists,’ p. 91.
63
S chum ann’s aphorism that T h e aesthetics of one art is that of the others; only the
material is different.’10 In this view, taken (like so much of Schum ann’s theory)
from the aesthetics of Jean Paul (who in turn looked back to G oethe11) the defining
quality of art was not the concrete ‘feeling,’ but instead the abstract idea of ‘poetry,’
falling in line with the German Idealism of the time. In the hands of W agner the
difficult ‘poetry’ became the even more problematical ‘dram a,’ and it is at this point
that the question of how to combine differing art forms becomes embroiled in the
long running dispute over the primacy of music and word; a dispute that has
existed as long as one has been set to the other. Perhaps surprisingly, neither
W agner nor Hanslick strike a definite pose on one side of this issue: the question
is alm ost entirely incidental to the core of Hanslick's arguments (although he of
course engages with them), and is uncomfortably straddled by Wagner, as
Nietzsche pointedly exposed in his fragm ent ‘On Music and W ords,’12 but it is
worth a brief diversion to understand both the intellectual climate in which both
writers worked, and the (mis)use to which their ideas were put subsequently.
From ancient times and throughout the history of early sacred music the
primacy of the word (or, indeed, the biblical ‘W ord’) was, so to speak, taken as
read. W ith the growing complexity of W estern polyphony during the Renaissance,
however, the idea that one must be sacrificed for the glorification of the other
became more contentious, not least because of the clash between the
Reform ation’s avowed desire to strip away ornament from religion, and the
Catholic church’s awareness of the allure of musical performance to its
Colour and sound do not admit of being compared in any way, but both are referable to
a higher formula: both are derivable, though each for itself, from a higher law. They
are like two rivers that have their source in one and the same mountain, but
subsequently pursue their way, under totally different conditions, in two totally different
regions, so that throughout the course of both no two points can be compared.
music and speech had a common origin, music was now believed to be the site of
a transcendent meaning, in comparison with which words were an inferior and
incapable means of communication. This viewpoint, which has come to be
associated with the term ‘absolute m usic’ (first coined by W agner as a negative
term) form s what Dahlhaus describes as ‘the latent unity of musical aesthetics in
the nineteenth century,’15 but it continued to exist uneasily alongside an
acknowledgem ent of the importance of words to music. Music continued to be
thought of as a fundam entally vocal art, and as Nicholas Cook has noted, it is
precisely at the historical juncture where ‘absolute m usic’ emerged that there was
an explosion of words in the form of programme notes and musical analysis, as
though they were suppressed in one place only to re-emerge elsewhere.16 It is
exactly this uneasy balance that W agner attempts to strike, caught between
ancient tragedy and Schopenhauer, yet in a more profound way, and this is
som ething that Dahlhaus appears to miss, both W agner and Hanslick, in different
ways, sidestep this bugbear of music aesthetics entirely.
Regardless of what their followers might claim, or indeed what they claim of
each other, neither Hanslick nor W agner appear to be interested in establishing
the prim acy of either music or word. W agner cuts the Gordian knot by
subordinating both music and word to the properly abstract ‘dram a,’ whilst
Hanslick’s argument is based precisely on the non-commensurability of differing
art forms, at least in the terms put forward above in the Schumann quotation.17 As
Cook has suggested, the long running word/music debate has served to conceal a
far more fundamental consistency - of a model of ‘unitary conform ance’ which
begins by identifying one medium as the origin of meaning, and uses this as the
15 Dahlhaus, C., Between Romanticism and Modernism, p. 39. See also the same author’s
The Idea of Absolute Music, trans. Lustig, R., (University of Chicago Press, 1989).
16 Cook, N., The Domestic Gesamtkunstwerk, or Record sleeves and Reception,' in
Composition-Performance-Reception, pp. 105-117.
17 It must be acknowledged here that where poetry and music are joined, Hanslick states
that musical specificity predominates (The union of poetry with music and opera is a
morganatic marriage.’ On the Musically Beautiful, p. 26), insofar as he believes that bad
music can spoil a good poem in a way that the reverse can not. This seems to be a
personal prejudice, however, rather than a necessary outcome of his theoretical
framework, and is partially retracted in his comparison of music and colour.
66
m easure of other media through a series of pair-wise judgem ents of sim ilarity or
dissim ilarity.’18 Against this analysis, W agner’s model displaces all media involved
by measuring them not against each other, but against ‘dram a,’ in effect
designating all media equivalent (and thus allowing himself to appear to favour one
medium or the other at any given time without disrupting his overall aesthetic).
Hanslick deems questions regarding the relating of differing arts to be irrelevant to
their aesthetic appreciation, although not, as we shall see, to be entirely
impossible.
As mentioned above, the Schumannian concept of ‘poetry,’ the site of
Schopenhauer's ‘aesthetic pleasure’ and driving force of nineteenth-century
aesthetics (essentially derived from the Platonic Idea), is distorted by W agner’s
reading of Gluck into the concept of ‘dram a’ in the abstract, and this distortion is
not without consequences. W agner does not encounter Schopenhauer until
1854,19 and for all his attempts to reorder his earlier theories in the light of this, his
com m itm ent to Idealism remains short of being absolute, with the result that later
self-styled ‘W agnerians’ and the history of the Gesamtkunstwerk would take subtly
divergent paths. W hat is certain is that ‘dram a’ functions in a transcendent
capacity: Nietzsche makes this much clear in stating ‘It was not with his music that
W agner conquered them, it was with the “idea.”’20 If one reads on, however, it
seems that Nietzsche’s main criticism is that this transcendent idea is not ideal
enough:
It is the enigmatic character of his art, its playing hide and seek behind a hundred
symbols, its polychromy of the idea that leads and lures these youths to Wagner. ... In
the midst of Wagner’s multiplicity, abundance and arbitrariness they feel as if justified
in their own eyes - “redeemed." Trembling they hear how great symbols approach
from foggy distances to resound in his art with muted thunder.21
In Nietzsche's view, W agner should have given primacy to the musical idea
instead of tailoring the music to ‘theatrical’ symbols, and thus barring access to the
essential sanctuary of m usic.’22 To attempt to comprehend music through its
sym bolic representation is to miss the aesthetic ‘truth’ contained therein.
Perhaps, then, the answer would be to strike the category of ‘dram a’ and
even ‘poetry’ from the equation, and look directly to the sensuous possibilities
represented by the arts. Rather curiously Nietzsche is strangely quiet on the
sensuous qualities of music, so caught up is he in the musical ‘idea,’ but
paradoxically this is precisely what the symbolist movement sought to take from
Wagner. Gerald Turbow writes: Baudelaire found a similarity between W agner’s
attempt to create a synthesis of the arts and his own idea, stated in his poem
“Correspondances,” that our senses respond to forms in nature’s language that are
sym bols o f truths inherent in the world of the spirit.’23 Stripping the W agnerian
Gesam tkunstwerk of the unifying ideal of ‘dram a’ enabled the symbolist poets to
concentrate on the individual constituents and their sensuous possibilities, but this
was fatally compromised by their continued commitment to the unity of the ideal,
‘truths inherent in the world of the spirit,’ which resulted in these sensuous
possibilities being received not in their material particularity, but as ‘forms in
nature’s language.’ The irony of symbolism is that by responding directly to a
material ideal rather than dram a’ or ‘poetry,’ the symbolists lost the ability to
consider each art independently of the other: W agner’s synthesis of the arts
became synaesthesia. Nowhere is this clearer than in the Mysterium of Scriabin.
Scriabin, the ultimate sensualist, considered W agner ‘too theatrical’, and went to
extraordinary lengths to abolish the stage/theatre distinction by combining his
music with coloured lighting, dancing, sacred texts and even incense in pursuit of
22 Nietzsche, F., Those who carry away feelings as the effects of music possess in them,
as it were, a symbolic intermediate realm that can give them a foretaste of music while at
the same time it excludes them from its inmost sanctuaries,’ from 'On Music and Words,'
op. cit., p 112. It is worth noting that Nietzsche is capable of just as much contrariness as
Wagner with regard to aesthetics. Elsewhere he writes ‘there is an aesthetic of
decadence, and there is a classical aesthetics - the “beautiful in music” is a figment of the
imagination, like all of idealism,’ in ‘The Case of Wagner,’ Epilogue, op, cit., p. 190.
23 Turbow, G., ‘Wagnerism in France,’ in Wagnerism in European Culture and Politics, op.
cit., p. 162.
68
24 D eleuze, G., and G uattari, F., A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, p.
348.
25 C ook, N., Analysing Musical Multimedia, pp. 55-6.
26 Q u o te d in Butler, C., Early Modernism: Literature, Music and Painting in Europe 1900-
need not be synaesthetic, but a desire for some kind of all encompassing discrete
and unitary identity equivalent to W agner’s ‘dram a’ still hangs over his abstracted
‘form s,’ and this quickly causes problems. He continues ‘Just as music never
drags a meaning around with it, at least not in the form in which it [music]
m anifests itself, even though meaning is inherent in its nature, so too this should
simply be like sounds for the eye, and so far as I am concerned everyone is free to
think or feel something similar to what he thinks or feels while writing m usic.’2'
This final effort to offload the issue onto the site of reception fails to conceal that
Schoenberg is struggling to maintain the idea that ‘form s’ do not have meaning, so
as to allow them to act in counterpoint to one another, but his concern for unity
makes this impossible to sustain, as is clear from Cook’s reading: ‘both media,
together and in conjunction with the other elements of Schoenberg’s
Gesamtkunstwerk, converge upon a cumulative meaning which is emotional and,
in the broadest sense, dram atic.’28 A concern for the unitary identity of the work’
forces Schoenberg to conceive of the play of forms entirely in the abstract; in
suppressing the material qualities of the disparate media that make up Die
gluckliche Hand Schoenberg effectively idealizes the concept of form in the same
way as the symbolists, hence his difficulty in preventing a reterritorialization of this
upon meaning and drama.
Herein lies the greatest challenge to a unified Gesamtkunstwerk. However
much one attempts to idealize or abstract the content that makes up the work, so
as to demonstrate either its essential similarity or compatibility, a stubborn
materiality, an affective power remains, that evades any question of ‘dram a’ or of
‘m eaning.’ Cook criticizes Eisenstein’s and Hanns Eisler’s theories regarding
com posite art for being wedded to the concept of identity, and hence replicating
some of the sym bolist’s arguments, when they are attempting to form ulate a theory
opposed to the model of synaesthesia.
Like Eisenstein - like Kandinsky - Eisler has only one fundamental model for the
relationship between different media, and it is identity. ... Both Eisenstein and Eisler
assert the principle of counterpoint, but fail to theorize it; they reject the principle of
27 Ibid., p. 87.
synaesthesia, but cannot escape its language. Both Eisenstein and Eisler, in short,
end up going round in circles because they are trying to use a language predicated on
29
similarity to articulate a principle predicated on difference.
Cook's jettisoning of the concept of identity, and hence of the role played by
specific material qualities in themselves has some profound consequences,
however. He has constantly to have recourse to explanation in terms of ‘m eaning’
and ‘dram a.’ A specific timbre, a vowel sound, a striking colour, all can only be
com prehended by Cook insofar as they have meaning, that is, by discussing not
what they are but what they stand for. This is remarkably similar to one of Theodor
A dorno’s criticisms of W agner’s musical technique:
Thus one always elides the object, apprehends it by proxy; one must never
engage with it, only understand it passively.
How, then, might one begin to reconcile the material identity of differing art
forms in order to produce a composite such as a music video that coheres in any
kind of perceptible way? One can almost instinctively (that is, one perceives it to
be instinctive, although it is not necessarily a-cultural) discern that some
combinations of sound and vision are more apt than others, sometimes as a
correspondence, sometimes as a fruitful counterposition, but how does one make
29 Ibid.. p. 65.
30 Adorno, T., In Search of Wagner, trans. Livingstone, R., (Verso, London and New York,
1991), p 45.
71
If people do not acknowledge the abundance of beauty residing in the purely musical,
one may blame the undervaluation of the sensuous, which we find in the older systems
of aesthetics favouring morality and aesthetic sensitivity and in Hegel’s system
favouring the “Idea." Every art originates from and is active within the sensuous. The
feeling theory fails to recognize this; it ignores hearing entirely and goes directly to
feeling. Music creates for the heart, they say; the ear is of no consequence. ... The
auditory imagination, however, which is something entirely different from the sense of
hearing regarded as a mere funnel open to the surface of appearances, enjoys in
31 Hanslick, E., On the Musically Beautiful, p. 29. For a discussion of this phrase and the
history of its translation see Payzant’s ‘Essay’ in the same volume, op. cit., pp. 94ff. It
should be noted that Payzant’s translation is itself not unproblematic, the translation of
tOnend as 'tonally' imputing a specific musical sense that is not necessarily present in the
German original.
32
See Monelle, R., Linguistics and Semiotics in Music, p. 212.
72
conscious sensuousness the sounding shapes, the self-constructing tones, and dwells
in free and immediate conception of them.33
Thus ‘fo rm ’ is at once an expression of musical content and also of the conditions
of its own being, which is to say the nature of ‘tone;’ the actualization and potential
of musical sound in one. Remarkably, if one looks closely one can find an
acceptance of the possibility of this thesis (if not an actual endorsement) in
W agner’s own writings, even if it is described in derogatory terms, as in this
passage from The Artwork o f the Future (1850): T h e human voice had at length
com pletely taken refuge in a merely sensual and fluid tone device by means of
which alone the art of music, wholly withdrawn from poetry, continued to present
itself.’34 One sees here for a brief moment W agner’s acceptance of the idea of
m usic in and for itself, without recourse to the category of the ideal, be that dram a’
or the fully transcendent ideal of ‘absolute m usic.’ Being Wagner, however, he
regards this as being insufficient, and sets about ‘redeeming’ this state of affairs by
uniting music with the other arts, stating that Through the art of tone, the arts of
poetry and dancing understand each other.’35 The ideal site of unity that W agner
alights upon in this essay is a rather less ideal one than is seen in many of his
other writings, though; namely the motion of the human body: T h is symphony
[Beethoven's Seventh] is ... the most blissful act of bodily movement, ideally
embodied, as it were, in tone.’36 Thus W agner both acknowledges the possibility
of a non-ideal autonomous music (even if he does not like it), and suggests the
possibility of a synthesis based upon an equally non-ideal footing (which he then
rejects in favour of the ‘universal dram a’ of Beethoven’s Ninth). There is without
doubt a considerable gap between W agner’s and Hanslick’s conceptions of music,
and how music relates to the other arts, but it is not an unbridgeable one. Both
dem onstrate that the model of ‘unitary conformance’ described by Cook (see
33
Hanslick, E., op. cit., pp. 29-30.
34 Wagner, R., The Artwork of the Future, extract in Strunk’s Source Readings in Music
History, Revised Edition, vol. 6: The Nineteenth Century, ed. Solie, R., (W.W. Norton and
Co., London and New York, 1998), p 63.
35 Ibid., p. 58.
36 Ibid., p. 64.
73
above), giving primary and subordinate roles to differing media, can be subverted,
and I hope to have shown that their ideas regarding the combining of the arts are
not so implacably opposed as is usually thought. For although Hanslick is largely
silent on the topic of joining art forms, his concentration upon the ‘specifically
m usical’ need not impede the possibility of an appreciation of a composite art
work, only the idea that such a thing would have an overall ‘unity.’ In the little
com m ent he does make, Hanslick himself implies that his theory of 'content
consisting of materially moving form s’ (to paraphrase) could be extended to other
media. Indeed, when he states that ‘the formal aspects of both music and colour
rest on the same basis,’ he appears to positively encourage the same process to
be undertaken in the other arts, that is, that the visual be judged on the way in
which it works out and manipulates the qualities of images, poetry the qualities of
language, and so on. The task of the analyst of the composite art work, then, is
not sim ply to demonstrate unity, or even just to find multiple meanings (although
that may be part of it); it is to compare and contrast these differing forms, to
discover how they relate to and impact on one another, be that in the manner of
conform ance, contestation, or com plem entation.37 It is no longer a matter of
sim ilarities, but of identifying a what, how, and why of both similarity and
difference.
II
The content of an object is itself a kind of form: but this immediately requires a
great deal of clarification. Combining content and form as a single entity, when the
two have long been understood in opposition to one another, at least in music,
creates some knotty problems and is ripe for misunderstanding (hence the
designation of Hanslick as a ‘form alist’ concerned only with musical form, thus
bypassing his argument entirely). One must first define both content and form, and
show how both of these relate to the identity of an object. According to literary
theory (and since most of this theoretical territory has been mapped out there it
37 These categories are taken from Cook, N., Analysing Musical Multimedia, pp. 98-106.
74
38 H jelm slev, L., Prolegomena to a Theory o f Language, trans. W hitfield, F., (U n iversity of
W isco n sin Press, M adison, 1969).
39 W ittg e n ste in , L., On Certainty, (B lackw ell, O xford, 1969), §141.
75
40 de Saussure, F., Course in General Linguistics, ed. Bally, C., and Sechehaye, A., trans.
Baskin, W., (Peter Owen, London, 1960).
41 Ibid., p. 120.
42 Ibid., p. 120.
76
43 Ibid., p. 116.
44 See Small, C., op. cit., pp 94ff., and Magee, B., Confessions of a Philosopher,
(Wiedenfeld and Nicolson, London, 1997), especially pp 76-82.
45 De Saussure, F., op. cit., p. 126.
77
In any given system of ‘n’ points, the number of potential relations in that
system is given by the formula:
/ ( n) = 1/2 n ( n - 1 )
Therefore when two objects, ‘n’ and ‘x’ are combined, it can be seen that the
resultant is not simply the sum of the relations of n and x, but expressed as:
/(n + x ) = 1/4(n+x)((n+x) -1 ).
lost over time, such that it would sound quite unlike Bach to his contemporaries.
To paraphrase Thomas Carlyle, ‘in every object there is inexhaustible meaning;
the ear hears in it what the ear brings means of hearing.’46 Similarly, it explains
why two apparently similar objects can seem very easy to distinguish. An imitation
stone urn made from plastic will never appear quite like the genuine article,
however closely the colours and texture match, since the alteration of just one
elem ent will produce not one difference, but a whole set of different relations, a
com pletely new pattern.
One can see these principles at work in the music of Edgard Varese, based
upon the idea of crystalline structure. The crystal has no predetermined external
shape, but its internal structure, determined by the regular arrangement of one or
several ions, is a tightly defined pattern, and the manner of its growth (the form of
its expression, so to speak) is a result of the interaction of this pattern with the
medium in which it grows. The content-pattern of the crystal is the relative
positions of the ions that constitute it. One cannot point to any one of these ions
(even m etaphorically) and say ‘There it is, that is the pattern;’ the pattern is a result
of combination and arrangement. To put it in mathematical terms (which is, after
all, the language of the material) pattern is perm utational and combinatorial.
Varese writes:
The crystal is characterized by a definite external form and a definite internal structure.
The internal structure is built on the unit of crystal, the smallest grouping having the
order and composition of the substance. The extension of the unit into space forms
the whole crystal. In spite of the limited variety of internal structures, the external
forms of crystals are almost limitless. I believe this suggests, better than any
explanation I can give, the way my works are formed. One has an idea, the basis of
internal structure; it is expanded or split into different shapes or groups of sounds that
46 The actual quotation is ‘In every object there is inexhaustible meaning: the eye sees in it
what the eye brings means of seeing.’ Quoted by Raymond Briggs in response to his
critics in the paperback edition of Fungus the Bogeyman, (Hamish Hamilton, London,
1979), back cover.
79
47 Varese, E., quoted in Mellers, W., Music in a New Found Land, (Barrie and Rockliff,
London. 1964), p. 158.
48 I am indebted to Malcolm McDonald for the source of this quotation, the background to
which is discussed in the section ‘Wronski and ‘Intelligent Sounds” of his forthcoming
monograph on Var6se, currently still in manuscript at the time of writing. Varese showed
great fondness for this quotation, which he took from the nineteenth century Polish
mathematician Joseph-Maria Hoene Wronski, using it on more than one occasion.
49 Varese, E., again quoted by McDonald, op. cit., from a lecture entitled ‘Spatial Music,’
given at Sarah Lawrence College in 1959.
50 Gilbert, A., Musical Space: A Composer's View,’ in Critical Inquiry, vol. 7, (1980-1), p
605.
80
51 On this point, see Brackett, D., Interpreting Popular Music, (Cambridge University Press,
1995), although the same point is made in innumerable texts.
52 Gurney, E., The Power of Sound, (Smith, Elder & Co., London, 1880).
53 This point is discussed in detail by Bojan Bujic in his essay ‘Form and Forming: From
Victorian Aesthetics to the Mid-twentieth-century Avant-garde,’ in Composition -
Performance - Reception, pp. 118-131.
81
seem more meditative, not only seem s somewhat crass, but is also limiting in
im plying once again that music and image must conform to a unitary model. Note
Vernallis s assertion that ‘W e respond to imagery and music that work together to
reflect these spatial relationships.’55
The idea that an individual sound moment might be conceived of spatially
is seen considerably less often, although it is implicit in much music of the
twentieth century that took an increased interest in the importance of musical
timbre. The origin of this viewpoint, or certainly the first time at which it was
codified, was in the work of the physicist Hermann von Helmholtz in the mid
nineteenth century. In his book On the Sensations o f Tone,56 the analysis of
sounds in terms of the overtone series that constitute them provides a spatial
model of any given sound that is both qualitative and quantitative, noting not only
the arrangem ent of frequencies, but also their amplitudes, the relation between
them determining the identity of a sound wave. Not only did this model produce a
spatial metaphor for sound identity, but his work on acoustics also incorporated the
actual spatiality within the uniqueness of a sound, since perceived sound is also
determ ined by the space in which it resonates. These suggestions are what
Gilbert refers to as ‘the truly essential nature of the [spatial] phenom enon,’5' and is
probably what Varese had in mind when speaking of his music as spatial,’58 but
this conception of music on its own is flawed fundamentally. Varese attempted to
‘com pose out’ the implicit spatiality of an initial sound or group of sounds, but even
by attempting to do so he introduced syntagmatic spatiality, and even had he not,
the very model of the spatial is ill-suited and insufficient for a sound event
predicated upon oscillations that necessarily take place in time. The diachronic
model is similarly lacking when examined closely: it is tenable only if one overlooks
54 Vernallis, C., op. cit., pp. 158-9. Vernallis also cites Leonard Meyer’s Style and Music,
(Philadelphia, University of Pennsylvania Press, 1989), pp. 128-9, but she could as easily
have cited any number of authors.
55 Ibid., p. 159.
56 Helmholtz, H., On the Sensations of Tone as a Physiological Basis for the Theory of
Music, trans., Ellis, A.J., (London, 1885).
57 Gilbert, A., op. cit., p. 606.
58 Varese was clearly familiar with the work of Helmholtz, and would frequently cite it as an
influence upon his music.
82
the tem poral aspect of music, which might be argued to be its most im portant
quality. The balance and symmetry of an A-B-A structure exists for just as long as
one ignores that the second A section, unlike the first, is heard both as a repetition
in relation to its first airing and in relation to the B section - the experience is a
dynam ic one, unfolding not in three dimensions but in four. And here we run up
against the limits of modelling either music or the moving image as being
straightforwardly spatial, or representable by pattern alone. Any musical work is of
necessity an integration of both of these forms of spatiality, a point made explicit
by Pierre Boulez, of whom Varese may be regarded as a precursor. Boulez took
V a rese’s concept of the sound-object, but chose to superpose it with an overall
system, rather than attempt to ‘grow ’ the sound, like a crystal. As both Bojan Bujic
and A listair Williams have noted, Boulez’s notion of the relationship between static
spatiality and temporal spatiality is a dialectical one, as expressed in his essay ‘Le
system e et I'idee. ’
Boulez’s notion of musical material ... is realised by the system manifesting itself in
terms of the structural properties of the music, but relinquishing its grip sufficiently to
allow local and contingent configurations thrown up by the material to have an intrinsic
role in the musical discourse. The dialectic of system and idea is conceived in terms
commensurate with the Adornian dialectic of concept and object. The musical idea is
an object whose specificity eludes complete control by the system, yet which is in need
o f manipulation by the system. The system organises the musical object, yet
recognises its concreteness and its ability to generate local configurations.59
In placing the two aspects of musical space in a dialectical relation Boulez has
gone some way to reconcile these two strains of thought in music history, but not
quite, I believe, far enough. The connection of ‘system ’ and ‘idea’ or particle, is not
merely a dialectical one of mutual influence, but one of fused identity, certainly in
the instance of its reception, what Nattiez would call the ‘aesthesic’ realm. Any
given system is a conglomeration of its parts, an emergent property, and attempts
to control a system or distort it will be successful only insofar as one can add
things to the set of relations in order to weight the system. One can try to conceal,
or overwhelm a system, but one cannot efface any part of it; the system is an
em ergent property of the set of particles that constitute it, and each particle is
understood in relation to those with which it is connected. It is no longer a
question of space or time, or even space and time, but a fusion of the two; spaces
in m otion - Einsteinian space-time. One can see an articulation of this fusion in
the video of the Chemical Brothers’ ‘Star G uitar,’ which takes the form of a
landscape as viewed from a moving train. Musical elements or ‘sound objects’ are
made coincident with physical objects - for example, the repeated kick drum on
the first beat of each bar is accompanied by the passing of a concrete pillar, a
passing train coincides with each repetition of a high synthesizer riff - and different
landscapes, be they urban or rural, accompany different sections of the music.
Not only is the music’s ‘spatiality’ thus made visible, but the viewer positioning is
such that one can see the musical space that one has passed through receding
into the distance. Both the immediate space of the musical object and the
‘architectural’ space of the m usic’s passing through time are made available.
Even this, however, can not be regarded as a representation of music, but
only as an adjunct to it. Sound itself is not an object in space but an oscillation;
even if one inscribes a locus rather than a location, that locus must itself then be
extended in time - it is impossible to plot sound in a three dimensional pattern.
Note once more that Hanslick defined the content of music as being ‘tonend
bewegte Formen.' Even the individual ions of Varese’s crystal model are not static
but constantly vibrating; matter itself is a condensate of energy waves in motion. A
set of relations is never a fixed pattern, but a pattern that is itself in oscillation. The
principle of identity being an emergent property of a dynamic process has long
been understood in chemistry. The standard test for the identity of a metal present
in a compound is the flame test, in which the compound is held over a flame, and
the colour of the resultant flame gives the identity of the metal. The physics behind
this involves the promotion of electrons into higher energy states than they would
normally occupy by the heat of the flame, and as they fall back into their usual rest
state this energy is given up as light of a particular frequency. Thus it is the
change in energy of this process, the relation of two different states of oscillation,
that reveals the particular identity of the metal. In the words of Plato, ‘W henever
84
we see anything in a process of change, for example fire, we should speak of it not
as being a thing but as having a quality.'60 Representational pattern can either
m ap the location of an interaction, or the motion of a locale, but not both, which is
to say, the motion of an interaction - the diagram is no longer sufficient; to employ
all necessary dimensions one must move to the equation. (I am put in mind here
of the physicist’s attempt to model in two dimensions the warping of three-
dim ensional space by showing how heavy objects distort the regular grid pattern of
a taut rubber sheet. This quite literally leaves a great deal to the imagination.) To
attem pt to represent the pattern of the object is to miss the object altogether, to
encounter it only tangentially; representation of pattern-equation involves a
m athematical differentiation of its actuality, be that with respect to time or space,
with a consequent loss of information.
It is, then, perhaps unsurprising that Edmund Gurney in 1880 failed to
make the leap to an Einsteinian relativistic frame of space-time, both conceived of
as a single entity. And it is important to realize that this reconsideration of space
involves more than just adding one more dimension: the move from space to
space-tim e requires one to make one’s own status part of the equation, in that the
m ovem ent of the observer is a factor of the observed, as well as the reverse.
Relations that were a question of distance are now functions of their velocities; the
pattern is always-already motile. Henri Lefebvre writes:
Modem science suggests that rather than think of space as a container or bodies as
“things” in space, we grasp the organism as a centre for the production of space
around itself - space is not external to the body but generated by it. ... Such analysis
needs to be completed by a rhythm analysis in which time is then grasped in its spatial
form. ... Spatial practice is on this level most concretely articulated in the various
historical and cultural systems of gestuality 61
60 Plato, Timaeus, 49d, trans., Lee, H.D.P , (Penguin, Harmondsworth, 1965), p. 67.
61 Lefebvre, H., cited as an unpublished manuscript dated 1983, quoted by Berland J., in
‘Sound, Image and Social Space: Music Video and Media Reconstruction,' in Sound and
Vision: The Music Video Reader, p. 35.
85
The point is no longer just to identify where precisely something is in space, but to
understand the way the entirety of space-tim e is engineered and modulated, its
harm onies and discordances, and the way these oscillations resonate and interact.
The sim ple algebra and diagrams above clearly no longer suffice, but there is a
m athem atics and a geometry in existence designed for this task, namely the
m athem atics of quantum mechanics and non-Euclidean geometry. The very
difficult mathematics of quantum mechanics are way beyond the technical
capabilities of the writer, but the concepts and phenomena they describe and
predict enable considerable insight into notions of perception, and hence
aesthetics. The idea that an object might simultaneously be a material entity and a
set of oscillations, or rather, that these two things are one and the same, will be
fam iliar to anyone who has studied elementary particle physics and the wave
equations of Schrodinger that accompany it. The similarity between Barthes’
assertion that the idea of signifiance is theoretically locatable but not
describable’62 and Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle, which states that it is
im possible to simultaneously know the position and momentum of a quantum
particle-event, is all the more striking for the fact that they were almost certainly
developed independently. The riddle of Schrodinger’s cat was form ulated to show
the absurdity of observing quantum phenomena at the level of the object, but it told
us more about rethinking our ways of perceiving the world than it did about flaws in
quantum theory.
The model of relationality demonstrated the complexity of perception and
object comparison, but it did not go nearly far enough. Basic algebra could show
the quantitative aspect of pattern relation in simple numerative terms, but could tell
us nothing about the quality of those relations in space-time: their oscillation,
intensity, duration, in short, everything about an object that individuates it rather
than simply quantifying it. The object is not number, but matrix, and the composite
object extends in further dimensions still. Heisenberg showed that in quantum
theory the combination of 1+1 could be performed in such a way as to equal more
than two, and the complex commutation of matrix mechanics, developed to model
the behaviour of material systems, shows that this is true of the physical realm
also.
III
So far, so abstract, one might think, but this rethinking of the object inspired by
H anslick’s formulation leads to a conception of identity (and thus composite
identities) that has already been effected via a different route in the work of
Deleuze and Guattari. They write:
There is a mode of individuation very different from that of a person, subject, thing, or
substance. We reserve the name haecceity for it. A season, a winter, a summer, an
hour, a date have perfect individuality lacking nothing, even though this individuality is
different from that of a thing or a subject. They are haecceities in the sense that they
consist entirely o f relations of movement and rest between molecules or particles,
capacities to affect and be affected.63
Just as Einsteinian science demands that the relativity of the frames of reference be
included in the object studied, so the combined action of Marxism, Freudianism and
structuralism demands, in literature, the relativization of the relations of writer, reader
and observer (critic). Over against the traditional notion of the work, for long - and still
The reassignation of the object as pattern ‘dem ands’ a shift from ‘work’ to ‘text,’
and consequently a new way of approaching the object, now a subset of ‘w orld.’
The full implications of Barthes’ category of object that was ‘locatable but not
describable’ now become apparent. The question of ‘w hat’ an object is, at least in
its classical formulation of meanings, origins, causes and reasons, is not one that
can be realistically answered; to do so would be to step outside one’s own
conceptual box, an attempt to ‘use language to get outside language,’65 to borrow
W ittgenstein’s formulation of the problem. For Barthes to describe what he
perceived in the film still would require him to describe the entire culture, or form
of life’ in Wittgensteinian terms, the complete network of which that object, in all its
complexity, was part. This is of course unfeasible, but is also in a way
unnecessary, given there is likely to be considerable agreement in form of life
between ‘w riter’ and ‘reader.’ Thus one presents the space(s) occupied by the
object in the network; one can say ‘w here’ it is (or better, where it moves) rather
than ‘w hat’ it is; the linguistic trace of this idea is made clear when we talk about’
something, instead of speaking it exactly. As Barthes himself put it: textual
analysis ... is henceforth less a question of explaining or even describing, than of
entering into the play of the signifiers; of enumerating them, perhaps (if the text
allows), but not hierarchising them .’66 As with W ittgenstein’s criticism of Freud,
what is required is not (causal) explanation, but clarification of a perception, an
attem pt to ‘confer blatancy on what was immanent to it.’67 Aesthetic experience
does not prompt a search for the origin of the source of that experience, but a
relation of that event to one's own previous experience and to the ‘web of
culture. 8
68 The phrase is Gary Tomlinson’s, but is derived from his reading of the sociologist Clifford
Geertz See The Web of Culture. A Context for Musicology,’ in Nineteenth Century Music,
vol. 7, (1983-4), pp. 350-62.
69 See the essay of Montefiore, A., and Taylor, C., ‘From an analytical perspective,’ that
introduces Kortian, G., Metacritique The philosophical argument of Jurgen Habermas,
trans., Raffan, J., (Cambridge University Press, 1980), for a discussion of the relation the
ideas of Hegel and Kant to the Anglo-Saxon philosophical tradition.
70 Eagleton, T., The Ideology of the Aesthetic, pp. 122-3.
71 Kristeva, J., Revolution in Poetic Language, p. 215.
89
‘reality.’ They become different ‘language-gam es,’ different positions one might
take up within the system of one’s own form of life. Since the idea of a ‘private
language' is shown to be nonsensical by W ittgenstein, and language is the
medium in which we apprehend the world, one’s experience of the world is
necessarily intersubjective. ‘It is what human beings say that is true and false; and
they agree in the language they use. That is not agreement in opinions but in form
of life 2 Moreover, a W ittgensteinian ‘language’ is far more than the set of words
that are available, but a composite of all the possible ‘language-gam es,’ or modes
of expression, that are in use by a form of life. A language is thus a set of
practices, based upon the culture and the capabilities of the group that use it. And
as Jean-Jacques Nattiez notes, these practices may be so well ingrained as to no
longer constitute a distinct set of actions in themselves, but instead be an
unquestionable mode of being, stating ‘among the Japanese, the succession
“waiting followed by rapid and violent action” is less a literary structure than a
typical schema of behaviour, a cultural scheme and a way of being.’73 Hence,
when W ittgenstein states that If a lion could talk, we could not understand him ,’74
the point is that the activity of being a lion is so different from our own as to be
incomprehensible. As to the similarity of different human forms of life, W ittgenstein
equivocates: on the one hand he states T h e common behaviour of mankind is a
system of reference by means of which we interpret an unknown language,’75 but
on the other, ‘One human being can be a complete enigma to another. W e learn
this when we come into a strange country with entirely strange traditions; and,
what is more, even given a mastery of a country’s language. W e do not
understand the people. (And not because of not knowing what they are saying to
them selves.)’76 Thus the connection between different human ‘languages’ (in the
broad sense) is like that between different language-games, insofar as there is
overlap and familiarity, sufficient to comprehend what is going on. Unlike
language-games, though, in order to understand, one must be fam iliar with the
system as a whole, to see not only the elements but also the way in which each is
connected to the others. Understanding, and thus aesthetic appreciation, is a
com plex process of relation: one cannot properly understand either a part of the
system alone, or the whole system from the outside. One must be part of that
system. ‘Does the theme point to nothing beyond itself? Oh yes! But that means:
- The impression it makes on me is connected with things in its surroundings - e.g.
with the existence of the German language and of its intonation, but that means
with the whole field of our language gam es.’77 A distinction between subject and
object is no longer essential, for W ittgenstein, to aesthetic appreciation of an
artistic practice. One does not explain the object, and one cannot explain the
system, which constitutes one’s own frame of reference; instead one clarifies the
spatio-tem poral relations of an artistic practice to other kinds of practices, or
language-games.
This mode of W eltanschauung (world-understanding) is broadly compatible
with that of Deleuze and Guattari, who similarly see fit to dispense with the notion
of subject altogether, redesignating the systemic object and subject alike as
haecceities:
We must avoid an oversimplified connection, as though there were on the one hand
formed subjects, of the thing or person type, and on the other hand spatiotemporal co
ordinates of the haecceity type. For you will yield nothing to haecceities unless you
realize that that is what you are, and that you are nothing but that. . . . It should not be
thought that a haecceity consists simply of a decor or backdrop that situates objects, or
of appendages that hold things and people to the ground. It is the entire assemblage
in its individuated aggregate that is a haecceity.78
However, they do differ on how one regards the conditions of being for the system
as a whole itself. For Deleuze and Guattari the formation of haecceities takes
place in a defined space, the ‘plane of consistency,’ which is both 'a geometrical
plane’ and ‘a plane o f ... univocality.’79 By contrast, the form of life is precisely not
77 Wittgenstein, L., Culture and Value, revised edition, ed., von Wright, G.H., (Blackwell,
Oxford, 1998), 59e.
78 Deleuze, G, and Guattari, F., op. cit., p. 262.
79 Ibid., p. 266.
91
univocal: even though within the system one must understand the part holistically,
the system as a whole lies outside the purview of any part of that system. Even
though one understands the part holistically, the whole remains beyond
understanding since it has no exterior point of reference. ‘W hat has to be
accepted, the given, is - so one could say - forms o f life.’80 The whole is not a
unitary entity, but an emergent product of a collective energy, a ‘plural totality’ in
Kristeva’s terms. In this sense it is far closer to the Derridean reading of chora
than it is to the ‘plane of consistency.’ ‘It does not have the characteristics of an
existent, by which we mean an existent that would be receivable in the ontologic,
that is, those of an intelligible o r sensible existent. There is chora, but the chora
does not exist.’81
Derrida, of course, was addressing the idea of ‘chora’ in the light of the
work of Kristeva in Revolution in Poetic Language, and she in turn had ‘borrowed’
(her own word) it from a passage of Plato’s Timaeus.82 Kristeva describes chora
initially as being ‘not yet a position that represents something for someone (i.e., it
is not yet a sign); nor is it yet a position that represents someone for another
position (i.e., it is not yet a signifier either); it is, however, generated in order to
attain to this signifying position. Neither model nor copy, the chora precedes and
underlies figuration and thus specularization, and is analogous only to vocal or
kinetic rhythm,’ and as ‘a modality of signifiance in which the linguistic sign is not
yet articulated as the absence of an object and as the distinction between real and
sym bolic.’83 One can, however, draw a distinction between this relatively abstract
notion of chora and the specific instance of the ‘semiotic chora,’ in which ‘the
social’ ‘imprints its constraint in a mediated form which organizes the chora not
according to a law but through an ordering,'84 (although it should be noted that
80
Wittgenstein, L., Philosophical Investigations, p. 226.
81 Derrida, J , ‘Khora’ (rewritten throughout as ‘chora’ for reasons of consistency), in The
Derrida Reader: Writing Performances, ed. Wolfreys, J., (Edinburgh University Press,
1998), p. 237.
82 Plato, ibid., 48d-53, pp. 67-72.
83 Kristeva, J., Revolution in Poetic Language, p. 26.
84 Ibid., p. 27. It is also worth noting that Deleuze and Guattari briefly touch on (and reject)
the idea of a 'semiotic chora’ (ibid., p. 65), but do not mention chora again, despite its
similarity to their notion of the ‘plane of consistency.’
92
Kristeva herself does not make this distinction explicit). In this process chora is
m ade geometric, in as much as this ordering ‘fixes the chora in place and reduces
it.’85 The idea of form of life seems to fall somewhere between this transition from
the Platonic idea of chora, to an instance of the chora, through its h a b ita tio n into a
Freudian system of drives, being neither so abstract as the former, nor as
determ ined as the latter. As suggested above, the reading of chora that most
readily approximates to the social and biological character of a form of life is that of
Derrida, as when he writes:
Chora “means " place occupied by someone, country, habited place, marked place,
rank, post, assigned position, territory, or region. And in fact, chora will always already
be occupied, invested, even as a general place, and even when it is distinguished from
everything that takes place in it Whence the difficulty . . . of treating it as an empty or
geometric, or even, and this is what Heidegger will say of it, as that which prepares the
Cartesian space.86
It is this fusion of the abstract and the concrete achieved in the fam iliar Derridean
‘always already’ that makes this so similar to the ‘form of life.’ The positing of a
capacity is coexistent with its realization, neither preceding the other. The social
field does not expand into space; instead the expansion of the social generates a
new space. There is a potential dynamism of the social in Derrida and
W ittgenstein that Kristeva seems to close off, if not disavow entirely, in semiotizing
chora through the body of the mother, and hence the Lacanian phallus.8' It would
be unfair to compare Kristeva to a dishonest taxi driver, as Cioffi does Freud,88 that
takes one on a gratuitously long journey to a destination that was round the corner,
but there is a degree of this in Revolution in Poetic Language. Having suggested
that the semiotic chora is no more than the plane where the subject is both
generated and negated, the place where his unity succumbs before the process of
charges and stases that produce him ,’89 and then dem onstrated how this subject is
then undone in and through language in the very act of his production, we are left
in the end with linguistic and artistic practice.90 The subject is offered only to be
withdrawn, and what remains seems very much like the elements of a form of life,
having been put through a psychoanalytic mill. However, although Kristeva has
taken us a great distance only to arrive very close to where we started, she has
furnished us with a range of analytic tools along the way. W ittgenstein (after
Hegel) had already reconceived the object as a set of dynamic relations, as
khoros, above all as practise: Kristeva performs this move all over again (in a more
explicit way), but she also introduces the idea of the social in the form of the
‘sym bolic,’ which brings a critical potential to the form of life that is often thought to
be missing. Montefiore and Taylor note that T o the Wittgensteinian, critical
theorists may appear as just another band of fools rushing about over the ground
which has just been so carefully cleared by the assembled reminders about the
ways in which our language works; conversely, to critical theorists the
W ittgensteinian may come across as preaching an obscurantist acceptance of the
status quo.'9' Kristeva shows that it is possible after all to understand chora or
form of life critically through the theory of text (although this is only a partial
understanding), without stepping outside one’s own conceptual box (even if the
Oedipal model of the social she deploys would have been an anathema to
W ittgenstein in its determinism). If we return to an earlier analogy for a moment, it
m ight be said that in the same way that gravity is a warping of space-time, such
that bodies are not directly aware of this except so far as their motion is weighted
towards a massive body, so the form of life/system distorts, but does not
predetermine, the limits of one's horizon. And it is through an interrogation of the
social that one can become aware of this process of distortion.
89
Kristeva, J., Revolution in Poetic Language, p. 28.
90
Ibid., pt. IV, sec. 5, The Second Overturning of the Dialectic: After Political Economy,
Aesthetics,’ pp. 214-6.
91 Montefiore, A., and Taylor, C., op. cit., p. 21.
94
IV
Let us prepare to grapple with the ineffable, and see if we may not eff it after all.92
G iven that the object has been superseded (at least theoretically) by a set of
dynam ic relations, it is worth asking how one begins to perceive anything from the
m ass of information the senses receive. How does one cut through the holism of
the system so as to apprehend apparently discrete units, and what is the mode of
that apprehension? W hether one turns to Hanslick or Wagner, W ittgenstein or
Kristeva, there is a truly remarkable convergence of opinion on this topic; a
reiteration of Hanslick’s wish to reinstate the role of the sensuous in perception,
grounded in the capacities of the human body. As Terry Eagleton notes, Thought,
to be sure, is more than just a biological reflex: it is a specialized function of our
drives which can refine and spiritualize them over time. But it remains the case
that everything we think, feel and do moves within a frame of interests rooted in
our “species being,” and can have no reality independently of this.’93 As discussed
earlier, we need to understand our relationships to the Lebenswelt not only
quantitatively, identifying connection, but also qualitatively, in identifying the
properties of those relations, and one’s means of doing this lie in the realm of the
senses, of affect. This is a return to the original project of aesthetics as formulated
by the eighteenth-century philosopher Alexander Baumgarten: an attempt to
cognize the world of sensation that lay outside of Kantian reason. Although the
discipline of aesthetics grew increasingly distant from its initial raison d ’etre over
tim e, a strain of it remains in the thought of Schelling, of Nietzsche and
W ittgenstein, and has become a fam iliar trope of Cultural Studies over the past
twenty years, to the extent that ‘few literary texts are likely to make it nowadays
into the new historicist canon unless they contain at least one mutilated body.’94 A
m odel based upon the idea that ‘the physical and sensuous experience of human
92 Adams, D,, Dirk Gently 's Holistic Detective Agency, (Pan Books, London, 1988), p 150.
93 Eagleton, T., The Ideology of the Aesthetic, p. 235.
94 Ibid , p. 7.
95
beings and our bodily experience of the world '15 is a prerequisite of understanding,
will necessarily privilege the biological facts of the sense organs in our relation to
the material. This is not to say, however, that different materials impacting on
different sensory modes are irredeemably distinct to the extent that they are
unrelatable: the semiotic chora is a ‘continuum ,’90 and although each mode may
have a specific type of pattern, it is pattern nonetheless. Acknowledging the
m aterial specificity, the ‘untranslatability’ of an object need not make a comparison
of their affective qualities impossible, once they are grounded in ‘the bottom of all
purely human art - that of plastic bodily m ovem ent.'97 W ittgenstein wrestled with
this process of comparison for many years, particularly as it related to music, and
finally concluded that 'there just is no paradigm there other than the theme. And
yet again there is a paradigm other than the theme: namely the rhythm of our
language, of our thinking and feeling And furtherm ore the theme is a new part of
our language, it becomes incorporated in it; we learn a new gesture.'98 This
adoption of the concept of gesture as a human equivalent (and not a
representation) of a specific affective entity late in his career (the above was
written just five years before his death), is an important step in his last writings,
w ith wide-ranging ramifications.
It should be stressed that gesture as a term here encompasses a great
deal more than gesticulation alone. Gesture is the resultant of the interaction of
the material and the social, the negotiation of object and world; it is a spatio-
tem poral actualization or corporealization of what Idealists would term essence; it
is the space-time of affect, where material becomes sensuous and intermingles
with the social body in a specific pattern-event, two modes of oscillation combining
to produce a movement, khoros. Here is the beating of the body in Barthes
‘R asch,’ the music affecting the body and the body inside the m usic.99 W hen
Barthes asks ‘W hat does my body know ?’100 the answer is gesture. Thus gesture
is the subject and the object in combination; not a translation, not a representation,
but thing and apprehension in one. As Paul Johnson puts it, in writing of music:
The phrase says something, but something which cannot be paraphrased - it says
itself It makes a unique gesture, but the significance of that gesture can be explored
by relating it to the network of possibilities against which it has meaning. ... What is at
stake is not the substitution of one general sign for another; rather it involves finding a
link between two incommensurate realms, both of which get their importance from their
connection to human life and feeling.101
101 Barthes, R , Camera Lucida: Reflections on Photography, trans. Howard, R., (Vintage,
London, 2000), p. 9
101
Johnson, P., Wittgenstein: Rethinking the Inner, (Routledge, London and New York,
1993), p. 110.
1L‘ Wittgenstein, L., Philosophical Investigations, pp. 181-3.
103 Johnson, P., op. cit., p. 116.
97
language, rather than a transcendence of the social. Indeed, the very idea of an
encounter with the ineffable is rather odd, since if one encounters it, it must have
been expressed: in W ittgenstein’s words, 'if only you do not try to utter what is
unutterable then nothing gets lost. On the contrary, the unutterable will be -
unutterably - contained in what has been uttered.’104 And this same point is
repeated time and again in Barthes’ writing on the experience of signifiance, those
m oments where meaning is temporarily obliterated to reveal - the grain of the
voice, that part of the cinematic image ‘that does not represent anything, '05 the
phonism of speech (in ‘Writers, Intellectuals, Teachers’)106 - much as the
obliteration of the sun in an eclipse reveals its own, normally invisible, corona. In
any moment where one ceases to pursue what Hanslick termed ‘the chimera of
m eaning,’10, the fullness of gesture, which is to say the undoing of one’s own
subjecthood in a dialectic of the social and the material, may be glimpsed.
Perhaps the most immediate aesthetic ramification of gesture, however, is
its dynamism. The world of gesture is no longer a world of beings, but of doings,
processes rather than products. Small writes: ‘Music is not a thing at all but an
activity, something that people do. The apparent thing “m usic” is a figment, an
abstraction of the action, whose reality vanishes as soon as we examine it at all
closely. '08 This reconceptualization of the abstract ‘m usic’ as the act of
‘m usicking’ is the touchstone of Christopher Sm all’s attempt to reinscribe the social
character of music at the heart of the discipline, and indeed at the heart of all the
arts, so as to render all artistic endeavour ‘perform ative.’ Furthermore, he states
that the process of social inscription undertaken in musicking is such that T h e act
of musicking establishes in the place where it is happening a set of relationships,
and it is in those relationships that the meaning of the act lies.’109 Sm all’s
em phasis upon locating meaning is perhaps the reason for his repetition of the
now familiar pursuit of unity, this time in the concept of ritual, which he terms ‘the
104 Wittgenstein, L., in a letter to Paul Englemann, quoted in Johnson, P, ibid., p. 115.
105 Barthes, R , The Third Meaning: Research notes on some Eisenstein stills,’ in Image-
Music-Text, p. 61.
106 Ibid., p. 207.
10 Hanslick, E., op. cit., p. 44
10c Small, C., op. cit., p. 2.
109 Ibid.. p. 13.
98
great unitary art in which all of what we today call the arts ... have their origin.’110
He is correct, however, it seems to me, in dem onstrating that the idea of gesture,
as a set of dynamic relations, is a means of successfully comparing (although not
necessarily uniting) differing art forms.
The experience of a particularly striking aesthetic impression will almost
always elicit a desire for knowledge and discussion of that experience, and the
form that this takes is often the search for an explanation of the phenomenon. ‘I
should like to say: “These notes say something glorious, but I do not know what."
These notes are a powerful gesture, but I cannot put anything side by side with it
that will serve as an explanation.'111 But as W ittgenstein suggests, to seek an
explanation is to miss the point of the phenomenon. To ‘explain’ it, and find its
‘m eaning,’ is to translate it into something else, to step away from the phenomenon
that inspired one in the first place. Instead, what is required is an elucidation of the
event, a clarification of the relationships involved: ‘Understanding a sentence lies
nearer than one thinks to what is ordinarily called understanding a musical theme.
... In order to ‘explain’ I could only compare it with something else which has the
sam e rhythm (I mean the same pattern).’112 And as Cioffi notes, ‘W hat this
am ounts to is an attempt to provide an equivalent in a different modality for the
experience we wish to characterize or elucidate.’113 The particular gesture that
expresses an aesthetic experience is specific and untranslatable: one cannot
explain it. One can, however, compare it to other gestures, relate it to previous
experiences, both those with the same material component and without, in
different modes. Velvet, double cream, the descending Ch arpeggio played on the
lower middle register of an old Moog synthesizer that opens the Kid A album by
Radiohead: clearly these are entirely distinct phenomena, and yet there are
underlying similarities that most people would recognize - their patterns of identity,
gestures, overlap. As Barthes notes:
Rhetorics inevitably vary by their substance (here articulated sound, there image,
gesture, or whatever) but not necessarily by their form. ... Thus the rhetoric o f the
image (that is to say, the classification of its connotators) is specific to the extent that it
is subject to the physical constraints of vision (different, for example, from phonatory
constraints) but general to the extent that the ‘figures’ are never more than formal
relations of elements.1'''
There is no overarching identity to unify and explain these similarities, but there
are resemblances nevertheless, like those of a family, or the overlapping concepts
that constitute the word ‘gam e’ for Wittgenstein. It follows that any response to an
aesthetic phenomenon conceived of as gesture is always already a composite
experience, cutting across different modes in such a way as to bring out
resem blances without ever compromising specificity or identity. 'It is through
gesture (i.e. rhythm of movement) that the spatial and temporal arts are linked.
The two share a common temporal-spatial universe, albeit working within it to
different ends.'115 The distinction between different musical objects is perceived as
readily as that between objects of similar gesture presented in different modes of
perception. An apparent attempt to explore this notion can be observed in Michel
G ondry's video to Daft Punk's Around the W orld.’ The five musical instruments
that make up the piece each have a commensurate group of four dancers, and
their movement in musical space is echoed by the choreography of the dancers
around a small circular set. Thus the rising and falling of the bass line coincides
w ith the ascending and descending of a set of steps of the ‘bass’ dancers, and as
each instrument comes to the fore the choreography determines that the
com m ensurate group of dancers is either foregrounded or highlighted by the
selection of camera shot, until all move in unison at the end. The mirroring is not
absolutely precise, and the characterization of each instrument (the drums as
bandaged mummies, the synthesizer as women in sequinned bathing suits and
caps) is clearly an invention, increasing points of relation, rather than a replication,
1 ~ Barthes, R., 'The Rhetoric of the Image,' in Image-Music-Text, p. 49. N.B. Barthes’ use
of gesture’ here is different to my own usage.
115 Kershaw, D , Music and Image on Film and Video: An Absolute Alternative,’ in The
Companion to Contemporary Musical Thought, ed. Paynter, J., et al, (Routledge, London
and New York, 199?), p 497.
100
116 Hawkins, S., ‘Perspectives in Popular Musicology,’ in Popular Music 15, (1996), p. 32.
101
landscapes. At no point does the rhythm of his running equate to the underlying
rhythm of the music, but for a short time (approximately twenty seconds) while he
runs across a shining sea at a slightly higher rate, there is a relation between his
running rate (around 233 beats per minute) and the beat of the music (exactly 89
beats per minute) that has an almost magical effect. To ask whether this is due
solely to their relative proportions (which is incidentally that of a doubled Golden
Section proportion, insofar as both are Fibonacci numbers and have a Golden
Section relation to the intermediate Fibonacci number 144),11/ or to its relation to
w hat has gone before, or the way the celebratory brassy fanfares of the chorus
echo the glinting of light on the water, is to ask the wrong question. It is of course
due to all of these things in part, some more than others, and many more besides,
but suffice to say it is not because they are ‘the sam e.’ Plato describes a similar
process, noting ‘the various bodies part or come together in the course of mutual
interchanges of position and what seems like magic is due to the complication of
th e ir effects on each other.’118
And where there are similarities, or isomorphisms, these need not mean an
equivalence of identity. One might compare the phenomenon of sympathetic
resonance in strings, where the upper partials of a sound will provoke a response
on strings of a certain proportional relation, with a different pitch to the original, and
given sufficient strength of input this would in turn produce its own upper partials,
so that a system of great complexity can be generated from simple rules. This
tendency of simple inputs to generate complex outcomes, such that similarities
m ight be observed across the system in differing registers, without compromising
the specificity of the part or the diversity of the system as a whole, is described by
the mathematics of chaos theory, and based upon the idea of the fractal. Fractal
mathematics can be observed in a range of apparently random phenomena: cloud
form ation, air turbulence, or crystal growth, to pick up Varese’s analogy. It can
117 For a detailed discussion of Golden Section proportions as they might be related to
music, see Lendvai, E., B6la Bartdk: An Analysis of his Music, (Kahn & Averill, London,
1971).
118 Plato, ibid., 80, pp 107-8.
102
also be seen in music analysis,119 and in the technology used to com press and
store digital images. In terms of analysis, this m eans that two very different
gestures may have an underlying similarity that is difficult to discern, and also that
com bining even two very simple gestures can produce a chain that resembles
neither. To say that the world is a complex place is not to say much, but it does
dem onstrate that any attempt to analyse a music video would barely touch the
surface of what it might offer, and also that to concentrate on identifying the
sim ila r’ would be likely to miss even that limited target.
W here meaning seeks to reduce the object, to translate it, represent it, and efface
its m ateriality in favour of the ideal, gesture is its antithesis, pluralizing, opening the
object out onto the world. Meaning fixes the khoros of gesture, geometricizes its
oscillations: ‘here would be instituted against music (against the text),
representation.’121 In an essay on Bertolt Brecht, Barthes writes, ‘One of the tasks
of a critical age is precisely to pluralize the object, to separate pleasure from the
sign; we must de-semanticize the object (which does not mean de-symbolize it),
119 See Madden, C., Fractals in Music: Introductory Mathematics for Musical Analysis,
(High Art Press, Salt Lake City, 1999), and also a rather more poetic account in Adams, D.,
op. cit., pp. 144-7.
120
Hanslick, E., op. cit., p. xxii.
121 Barthes, R , ‘Diderot, Brecht, Eisenstein,’ in The Responsibility of Forms, p. 89.
103
give the sign a shock: let the sign fall, like a shed skin.’122 And it is Brecht that
seeks to make a synthesis of these opposites, in the concept of the social gestus.
‘a gesture, or set of gestures, in which can be read a whole social situation.’123
Brecht resisted the totalized meaning - his plays are not constructed with a final,
single moral in mind, to be reified and taken home. His plays are active, the
gesture is given to be taken up and used, but he remains committed to meanings,
an engagement with the social order made on the terms of that society. The
Brechtian gesture, gestus, is extracted from its aesthetic bodily origin, and
‘prom oted’ to the standing of reason by virtue of its capacity for meaning. The
gesture, insofar as it is an entity of perception, is always already socialized, but it
m aintains a certain stubborn materiality, signifiance, at work on the social, undoing
it. The gestus has already abandoned this process in favour of meaning, and no
sooner has it done this than it has become re-presentation, divorced from its
materiality. In Kristevan terms, it has privileged phenotext at the expense of
genotext.
And this process will recur every time there is a search for meaning: Small
notes that ‘the convention of the concert hall denies them [musicians] any
expressive use of bodily gesture, confining them to gestures in sound that are
m ade through their instruments. The art of representation has alienated itself
com pletely from the human body and its gestures.’124 Small has partially
recognized the problem; what he describes is in large part the phenotext of a
performance, but he seems so intent on uncovering the m eanings of the
relationships a performance sets up, the non-meaning aspects of sound that have
a more directly somatic appeal, the genotext, in short, (although this rather
oversim plifies Kristeva’s categories), has been overlooked. He is by no means
alone in this intent: Adorno is not only concerned with eliciting meaning, but is
positively hostile to anything that might cloud this. ‘Many of the cultural products
bearing the anti-commercial trademark “art for art’s sake” show traces of
122 Barthes, R., ‘Brecht and Discourse: A Contribution to the Study of Discursivity,’ in The
Rustle of Language, trans. Howard, R., (University of California Press, Berkeley and Los
Angeles, 1989), p. 222.
12‘ Barthes, R., ‘Diderot, Brecht, Eisenstein,’ op. cit., p. 93.
12* Small, C., op. cit., p. 155.
104
125 Adorno, T W , 'How to Look at Television,’ in The Culture Industry: Selected Essays on
Mass Culture, ed. Bernstein, J.M., (Routledge, London, 1991), p. 137.
126 Benjamin, W., 'Surrealism: The Last Snapshot of the European Intelligentsia,' in
Reflections, trans. Jephcott, E., (Schocken, New York, 1986), pp. 183-4.
127 Barthes, R., ‘Kristeva’s Semieotike,' in The Rustle of Language, trans. Howard, R.,
(University of California Press, Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1989), p. 170.
128 Barthes, R., The Grain of the Voice,’ in Image-Music-Text, p. 185.
129 Barthes, R , The Greek Theatre,’ in The Responsibility of Forms, p. 82.
105
stubbornly material, the music video allows for the possibility of seeing beyond the
social and enabling ‘the very transcendence of egotism .’133 The aim of an
aesthetics of music video ‘is no longer the platitudinous one of Beauty: it is
festivity.’134
133 Barthes, R., ‘One Always Fails in Speaking of What One loves,’ in The Rustle of
Language, p. 305.
134 Ibid., p. 304.
The Technological Body
This is the kind of lawlessness that easily insinuates itself unobserved [through music]
... because it is supposed to be only a form of play and to work no harm. Nor does it
work any, except that by gradual infiltration it softly overflows upon the characters and
pursuits of men and from these issues forth grown greater to attack their business
dealings, and from these relations it proceeds against the laws and the constitution
with wanton license until it finally overthrows all things public and private. ... For the
modes of music are never disturbed without unsettling of the most fundamental political
and social conventions.1
1 Plato, The Republic, trans. Shores, P., Loeb Classical Library, (Putnam’s, New York,
1930), quoted in Attali, J., Noise: The Political Economy of Music, trans. Massumi, B ,
(Manchester University Press, Manchester, 1985), pp. 33-4.
2 Eagleton, T., The Ideology of the Aesthetic, p. 9.
108
3 Frith, S., Performing Rites: On the Value of Popular Music, (Oxford University Press,
Oxford, 1996), p. 272.
4 Scruton, R , The Aesthetics of Music, (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1997), p. 390.
5 Abrahams, G., The Concise Oxford History of Music, (Oxford University Press, Oxford,
1979), p. 32, although Abrahams is closely paraphrasing a passage from Plato’s Republic,
see Strunk, O. (ed), Source Readings in Music History: Antiquity and The Middle Ages,
(W W. Norton & Company, New York and London, 1950), p. 12.
6 Adorno, T.W., ‘On the fetish character in music and the regression of listening,’ in The
Culture Industry, ed. Bernstein, J.M., (Routledge, London, 1991), p 26.
109
What music does (all music) is put into play a sense of identity that may or may not fit
the way we are placed by other social forces. Music certainly puts us in our place, but
it can also suggest that our social circumstances are not immutable. . .. It may be that,
in the end, I want to value most highly that music, popular and serious, which has
some sort of disruptive cultural effect, but my argument is that music only does this
through its impact on individuals, and that this impact is obdurately social.7
The idea that music can both be form ed by society and actively construct collective
identity in the same instant is what makes its social status such a thorny problem,
or a revolutionary potential, depending upon one’s approach. The complexity of
the problem is doubled in relation to music video, not least because it involves a
combination of music, seen as a collectivizing force, and television, which is
typically regarded as a dividing, individuating medium. However, as with Frith's
good’ music, the primary impulse upon seeing a particularly striking and enigmatic
music video is a social one; as with Frith’s aesthetic response to hearing a
favourite track on the radio in a hotel room, ‘I wish there were someone to play this
to .’8 My desire to discuss the music video with others, to clarify its status, to make
meaning, is perhaps evidence of Andrew G oodwin’s premise that music video is
‘the m aking m usical of the television im age,’ such that Television is m usiced.’9
(Or one might say, after Chris Small, television is ‘m usicked.’) In return, music
video may lay bare certain aspects of popular music, either directly, or indirectly by
deliberate omission of the expected, making explicit the social qualities implicit in
music. One might cite the instance of The W iseguys’ ‘Start the Com m otion’ as a
particularly clear example of this reciprocity. Like much modern dance music it is
constructed through the principle of ‘sam pling’ older records, and this track is
made almost entirely from scraps of preexisting musical material that are cut up,
looped and repeated. The video is similarly constructed from a set of fourteen
fragm ents of performance footage (one for each auditory source plus footage of a
DJ, one of The Wiseguys), all filmed separately on the same set and then intercut
to match the music, or to preempt and cue a sam ple’s ‘entrance,’ but always paced
7 Frith, S., Performing Rites: On the Value of Popular Music, pp. 276-7.
8 Ibid., p. 278.
9 Goodwin, A., Dancing in the Distraction Factory: Music Television and Popular Music, p.
70.
110
in such a way as to reinforce the rhythm of the track. Although each of these
fragm entary perform ances’ take place against the same sparse backdrop, all are
costum ed appropriately, with the dress, hairstyles, and gestural m annerisms that
one might expect of the tim e period and genre of the musical samples. Thus the
folk-style flute sample is ‘played’ by a long-haired, corduroy-clad ‘folkie,’ perched
on a high stool, whilst the rock guitar and drum sound that underpins the track is
perform ed’ by a Rolling Stones-style four piece band, complete with a strutting,
pouting singer. The only two performers in contemporary apparel are the rapper
that presents the bulk of what are presumably new (with the track) lyrics, although
his performance is visually ‘sam pled’ in the same way as the other musical
elements, and the DJ, seen leafing through records before a single Dansette-type
turntable. Although the DJ-creator of the track does not produce any of the sonic
material himself, his role as composer (literally) of the track is being deliberately
presented in the image track, despite the fact that there is no ‘perform ance’ as
such to show. (This Hitchcock-like presence of non- performing' DJ composers is
quite common in dance tracks; witness the peripheral presence of both the
Chemical Brothers and Fat Boy Slim, on T-shirts, paintings, or as ‘extras' in many
o f their videos.)
The video to ‘Start the Com m otion’ makes overt the latent (social) content
of the music track, its historical points of reference and its means of production, but
one performs this connection of music to its so-called ‘extra-m usical’ meaning at a
subconscious (if not unconscious) level every time one listens to any piece of
music. An educated listener (and by educated I simply mean socially practised, a
form of life, rather than trained) is capable of making these associations, Peircean
indexical relationships, almost instantaneously. The principle is illustrated in an
obvious way in this music video by doubling up the ‘social content’ of the music in
the image to a large extent, (although not completely: there are subtle
connotations to the setting, facial expressions, and a myriad of others not
immediately present in the sound, and vice versa - as Cook puts it, neither
exhausts the signification of the other). But the same forces are at work, in either
a complementary or dialectical relationship, in every music video. And the binding
of image, a much more clearly socialized medium insofar as it is based upon the
notion of representation, with the potentially socially disruptive music is to raise the
stakes somewhat, perhaps even to demand a Kristevan sem analysis’ that would
111
mean the interrogation of the fundam ental matrix of our civilization grasped in its
ideological, neuralgic locus.’10 Certainly when she writes ‘sem analysis needs to
provide itself with a specific object which the traditional modes of analysis are
incapable of grasping in all its specificity,’11 she might as easily be talking of music
videos rather than the poetic texts to which she devotes her attention. Indeed,
Kristeva identifies the im portance of the ‘poetic musicality found in “sym bolist’’
poetry and in M allarm e,’12 and also suggests that through ‘m usicality’ ‘Logical
syntheses and all ideologies are ... displaced toward something that is no longer
within the realm of the idea, sign, syntax, and thus Logos, but is instead simply
sem iotic functioning.’13 Kristeva does not follow up these suggestive statements
with specific reference to music, but I believe it would be fair to state that music
video does involve a calling into question of the Stoic sign, which is Kristeva’s
stated aim for ‘sem analysis.’
Before continuing, it is worth outlining a few distinctions that are required in
a discussion of ‘the social’ so as to prevent confusion, namely distinguishing
precisely what is meant by the concepts of ‘the individual’ and 'the social,’ and
differentiating between ‘the social’ and ‘the collective,’ a distinction which Frith
(amongst others) fails to make, or at least make explicit. The category of the
social’ is a difficult one either to embrace or reject entirely, particularly for those of
a le ftis t’ persuasion (so far as this is still a useful positional term). For while on the
one hand there are those who would wish to rescue ‘society’ from the wastebasket
of history that it was thrown towards by Margaret Thatcher’s now infamous
proclamation that ‘There is no such thing as society,’ it is difficult at the same time
to argue in favour of the heavy handed wielding of state power that is implied in the
term ‘social order.’ The valorization of the individual in modern W estern thought,
often under the rubric of democracy, has been driven in recent times from two
independent sources almost simultaneously, both in opposition to these differing
conceptions of ‘society:’ namely in a ‘freeing’ of the self from an oppressive social
order’ as a strain of the 1960s counterculture, and also in the withdrawal of the
14 These ideas were explored in much greater depth in the BBC television series ‘Century
of the Self,’ broadcast in the Winter and Spring of 2002. The following discussion draws in
part on these programmes.
15 Benjamin, W., The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction,’ in Illuminations,
ed. Arendt, H., trans. Zohn, H., (Fontana, London, 1973), p. 243n.21.
113
in music becomes available. Thus the individualism of the 1960s opposed social
ordering,’ whereas Thatcherite individualism was set against ‘the collective.’
Freudian theory suggested that social ordering was both necessary and
desirable, repressing the base motives of the collective ‘id,’ or ‘the m ob’ as it could
equally be termed, in order to function in any kind of society (hence, Civilization
and its Discontents). (It is interesting to note that the word ‘m ob’ is derived from the
Latin m obile, and semantically close to the Greek khoros.) Followers of Wilhelm
Reich, a student of Freud’s who rejected this idea, including A dorno’s
contem porary Herbert Marcuse, fam ously pronounced T he re is a policeman in our
heads; he must be destroyed.’ However, the atomized individuals produced by
this form of psychoanalysis lacked any kind of coherent political agency; as the
Black Panther group realized when they were invited to participate at this school,
as soon as one renounced collective identity, one lost the political power that the
collective could call upon. Since the collective is not an object but a set of
relations between individuals, it has a far greater resistive capacity to social control
than any one individual, no matter how liberated. Conversely, however, a
communal identity is difficult to direct, and thus liable to favour the status quo, but
it does at least have the potential to challenge. The answer was not to destroy the
policeman in our heads,’ but collectively to take control of it and restrict and
redirect the power it held over the individual.
In this bifurcated vision of society, 'social reality,’ that is, the everyday
circumstances of people, occurs at the interface of collective will, such as it is, and
state power/social ordering (and by ‘state’ I shorthand both government, nominally
itself an expression of collective will in a democracy, and also a range of non
governmental corporate interests - what was once known as the ‘military-industrial
com plex’), so that in the absence of any collective will expressed in the notion of
‘the public’ there is only state power, and a utopia would be a destruction of the
state, leaving only collective will in genuine and total consensus. Thus any attempt
to produce an effect upon social reality must involve a stimulation of collective
conscience, and here can be seen why Plato credited music, rather than any other
art form, with the power to either support or destroy the social order. Music has
the capacity to short circuit the officially sanctioned practices of aesthetic
understanding, to bypass representation and translation into an ideal. As Frith
puts it, ‘Music can stand for, symbolize and offer the immediate experience of
114
16 Frith, S., Towards an aesthetic of popular music,’ in Leppert, R. and McClary, S. (eds),
Music and Society the politics of composition, performance and reception, (Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge, 1987), p. 140.
17 Nietzsche, F., ‘Nietzsche contra Wagner: The Brief of a Psychologist,’ in The Works of
Friedrich Nietzsche: vol. Ill, trans. Common, T., (T. Fisher Unwin, London, 1899), p. 69.
115
com merce (represented by the ‘superclubs’ that form ed in the wake of this) was
not something the state was prepared to sanction.
If music and music video then have this charge, this social power, can
anyone explain why 'Top of the Pops’ doesn’t bring people out onto the streets, or
why one’s local branch of HMV isn’t a hotbed of revolutionary fervour? The
absurdity of the question is ample proof that one can easily overestimate the
oppositional power of the collective, inclined as it is to reflect the status quo rather
than rise up against it in a politically engaged way, but it is also a reminder that
m usic is in no sense independent of social reality even while it may articulate an
alternative to that reality. ‘Short-circuiting’ the straightforwardly representative
artistic model of social reality does not necessarily evade the influence of the
social entirely. This is of course the birthplace of critical musicology, and more
particularly of the dialectical approach of Theodor Adorno. In A dorno’s aesthetic
theory it is the very capacity of music to speak outside of the social that enables its
relation to the social to be stated: ‘W orks of art - like all precipitates of the
objective spirit - are the object itself. They are the concealed social essence
quoted as the phenomenon. ... While works of art hardly ever attempt to imitate
society and their creators need know nothing of it, the gestures of the works of art
are objective answers to objective questions.’18 It is not the case that one simply
recognizes a replication of the social order in music, but a question of absence, of
what the music is not, and can not be, that enables critical reception and Adorno’s
‘negative dialectics.’ As Max Paddison puts it: T h e relationship between the social
totality and the “autonomous” realm of art is thus misrepresented if reduced to any
crude form of reflectionist theory, or to functionalism. The emphasis is rather on
m ediation,’19 The intensely dialectical nature of Adorno’s method of argument
frequently resembles the actions of a tightrope walker, constantly checking himself
and often giving the impression of self-contradiction: his attitude towards the
relation of the individual to the collective is especially contorted, as when he writes
In music, too, collective powers are liquidating an individuality past saving, but
18 Adorno, T.W., Philosophy of Modern Music, trans. Mitchell, A.G. and Blomster, W.V.,
(Sheed & Ward, London, 1973), pp 131-2.
19 Paddison, M., Adorno, Modernism and Mass Culture: Essays on Critical Theory and
Music, (Kahn & Averill, London, 1996), p. 49.
116
against them only individuals are capable of consciously representing the aims of
the collectivity.’20 At other times, as in his writing on Stravinsky, the collective is at
once an attack upon 'comfortable conformity with individualistic society,’21 and also
akin to a Freudian mob. W hat remains constant, however, is his com mitm ent to a
form of aesthetic engagement dependent upon the location and critique of musical
m eaning,’ to which end was developed his technique of ‘immanent analysis.’ The
problem atic character of Adorno’s ‘musical m aterial,’ as identified by Carl
Dahlhaus, is discussed by Paddison elsewhere,22 and there is little point in
replicating his arguments here, but the very real achievement of Adorno here is to
transpose the straightforward ‘w hat’ question of meaning into a ‘how’ question, an
analysis of productive forces, a dialectical process that marks the dissolution of the
distinction between ‘m usical’ and ‘extra-m usical.’ ‘The rudiments of external
meanings are the irreducibly non-artistic elements in art. Its formal principle lies
not in them, but in the dialectic of both moments - which accomplishes the
transform ation of meanings within it.’23 Despite his many disagreements with
popular musicologists, it is this insight, which underpins his critical project, that has
been fundamental to a large part of recent musicology, and provided it with a
critical edge that might otherwise have been lacking. Artistic endeavour is not
merely a resultant of social order, but is also formative in one’s experience of that
order, in an ongoing dialectic with the consumer of that art. As Adorno wrote in a
criticism of Benjamin’s work on Baudelaire, T h e fetish character of the commodity
is not a fact of consciousness; rather it is dialectical, in the eminent sense that it
produces consciousness.’24
20 Adorno, T.W., ‘On the fetish character in music and the regression in listening,' op. cit.,
p. 52.
21 Adorno, T.W., Philosophy of Modern Music, p. 159. See the entire section Identification
with the Collective.’
22 Paddison, M., Adorno, Modernism and Mass Culture, pp 117-24, and also in the same
author’s Adorno's Aesthetics of Music, (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1993).
23 Adorno, T.W., ‘Commitment,’ trans. McDonagh, F., in Aesthetics and Politics, (Verso,
London and New York, 1980), p. 178.
24 Adorno, T.W., ‘Letters to Walter Benjamin,’ trans. Zohn , H., in Aesthetics and Politics, p.
111 .
117
Given all of this, it becomes difficult to reconcile this analytic technique with
his repeated insistence upon the complete and finished work of art’ as product
rather than continuing process, the very idea that there might be such a thing as a
separating out of the ‘message in a bottle’ and its instance of reception. The
objectivity of art lies in the fixation of such moments. W orks of art are sim ilar to
those childish grim aces which the striking of the clock causes to become
permanently fixed.’25 A dorno’s dialectic only works in one direction - all work is
done in artistic production, what Nattiez terms poiesis. The object may be
form ative of the subject, but only the social com poser-artist as subject is involved
in the production of art-as-product. It is this belief in the fundamental passivity of
the audience at the moment of reception that is the greatest flaw in Adorno’s
thought (at least with regard to popular m usic26), most evident in his undervaluing
of the impact of sensory perception and the difficulty of relating his theory to the
som atic realm. His critique of Stravinsky in the Philosophy o f Modern Music27 is
based almost entirely on the charge of a reification of sound material and its
withdrawal from the dialectic, which is based in turn upon a questionable notion of
the body in music (a notion which is by no means restricted to Adorno).
One can detect two rather different approaches to the issue of the body in
m usic in Adorno's writings, in his earlier discussions of mass culture, and in his
approach to Stravinsky respectively. The writings on mass culture are potentially
more optimistic, insofar as this can ever be said of Adorno, for although he seems
to repress the issue of the body, to avoid discussing it at all, when it does briefly
appear it resembles the physiological site of resistance one encounters relatively
frequently in writing on popular music. In his essay ‘On the fetish character in
music and the regression in listening’ he pointedly distinguishes between the
‘m endacity’ of aesthetic pleasure, and physical response (which is theoretically
25 Adorno, T.W., Philosophy of Modern Music, p. 132. Adorno was so fond of this analogy
that he reused it in The Schema of Mass Culture,’ op. cit., p. 82.
26 For more detail on this point, and on the connection of this to Adorno’s reaction to
fascism see Middleton, R., Studying Popular Music, (Open University Press, Milton Keynes
and Philadelphia, 1990), pp. 34-63.
27 A better translation would be Philosophy of New Music, as Paddison chooses to call it,
but I have retained the title as translated in the English edition throughout for the sake of
consistency.
118
It is a matter of the chimerical rebellion of culture against its own essence as culture.
Stravinsky undertakes such a rebellion not only in the familiar aesthetic game with
barbarism [in Le Sacre du Printemps], but furthermore in the fierce suspension of that
element in music which is called culture — the suspension, that is, of the humanly
eloquent work of art. ... He is attracted to that sphere in which meaning has become so
ritualized that it cannot be experienced as the specific meaning of the musical act.30
Adorno’s analysis of Stravinsky’s music is very often highly accurate - his relation
to the history of W estern art music, his treatment of musical material and harmony,
the ‘spatialization’ of time, all of which infuriate Adorno - but his conclusions are
flawed, because of the way in which he regards the body, and disregards Nattiez’s
‘aesthesic realm.’ Adorno recognizes that there is little to be gained from the
'immediate bodily presence’ of ‘On the fetish character,’ but fails to see that the
28 Adorno, T.W., ‘On the fetish character in music and the regression in listening,’ op. cit.,
p. 29.
29 Adorno, T.W., The schema of mass culture,’ in The Culture Industry, p. 82.
30
Adorno, T.W., Philosophy of Modern Music, p. 140.
119
31 Ibid , p. 173.
32 Ibid., pp 173-4.
33 Ibid., p. 173.
34 Ibid., p. 140.
120
II
A d o rn o ’s theories are both a challenge and a store of great promise: much of his
despair with regard to mass culture and its reception is entirely understandable
w hen viewed in the context of rising fascism in which it was written (even if his
refusal to readdress these issues in the 1960s is less so), yet the toolkit he has
furnished the critical musicologist with is invaluable. Perhaps the greatest
disappointm ent, however, is the fact that he failed to apply his own principles with
sufficient rigour to the concept of the human body - one can only assume that this
w as an oversight caused by Adorno s own circumstances of production rather than
lacking the courage of his own convictions - but the idea that the body’s relation to
m usic is immediate, somehow immune to the processes of mediation that take
place all around it, is endemic (if not universal) in musicology, and has
consequently mistaken the actuality of music reception’s means of resistance.
Tim e and again one sees recourse to the idea of the body as some form of
‘transcendental ground,’ absolutized as a guarantor of authenticity, but rarely does
one see the full acknowledgement that a ‘form of life’ is in every sense a
contingent entity, and functions as an absolute only in a particular context. Indeed,
I have already quoted authors in chapter two, such as Christopher Small, who are
guilty of this, and even Simon Frith repeatedly draws on a somewhat romanticized
and idealized notion of the body in music, as when he writes:
Music making and music listening, that is to say, are bodily matters; they involve what
one might call social movements. In this respect, musical pleasure is not derived from
fantasy - it is not mediated by daydreams - but is experienced directly: music gives us
a real experience of what the ideal could be.35
Adorno (indeed he was one of the first writers on popular music to do so, although
with some obvious provisos with respect to popular culture), regarding the
presence of productive forces and social mediation of the musical text, and if
anything he applies these ideas more rigorously to the notion of the body than
does Adorno. Frith counters A dorno’s passive and unengaged body-object, an
object that reacts precisely,’ with the idea of the body as an active and productive
entity, dialectically engaged with and formative of ‘the social.’ And yet at the same
time he seems to be drawing on the same uncritical notion of an ‘immediate body,’
invoking the 'essentially hum an’ via its autonomic functions; he has his socially
dialectical cake and eats it in positing the simultaneous existence of an ideal’
bodily location. As Brian Massumi puts it in discussing the related notion of
‘intensity,’ this ‘inevitably raises the objection that such a notion involves an appeal
to a pre-reflexive, romantically raw domain of primitive experiential richness - the
nature in our culture.’36
I will return to the question of autonomic response presently, but the
problem with Frith’s model is not in its internal logic, but in the paradigm of both the
body and music that it employs. Frith disassembles Adorno’s body-as-site-of-
reception only to reconstitute it as a site of reception and production, when the
problem was not the absence of product in itself, but the setting up of the body as
a site, a location which serves as the origin of sound, or upon which sound acts.
This becomes clearer in Frith’s discussion of voice, of which he writes: ‘The voice
seems particularly expressive of the body: it gives the listener unmediated access
to it.’37 As the astute reader will by now probably be aware, the key word here is
‘unm ediated.’ In order to maintain this idea Frith replicates one fundamental
mistake in two ways: first the definition of the body as a discrete object-product
(which retains this status regardless of whether it is fixed or unfixed) that might act
as a source of sound, rather than as a medium that is itself en proces (to borrow
Kristeva’s term), and second the misunderstanding of sound itself, reifying it as a
concrete thing, product, rather than as the performing of an action, a modulation of
atmospheric pressure, process.
36 Massumi, B., The Autonomy of Affect,’ in Deleuze: A Critical Reader, ed. Patton, P.,
(Oxford, Blackwell, 1996), p. 223.
37 Frith, S., ‘The Body Electric,’ Critical Quarterly, 37:2, (1995), p. 1.
122
The point at which both music and the body are objectified is the point at
which they lose whatever resistive potency their intersection might have had. As
Terry Eagleton notes in The Ideology o f the Aesthetic, the aesthetic project first
outlined by Baumgarten was devised as a means of ideologizing that which lay
outside the purview of the category of reason, such that T h e aesthetic springs into
being as a kind of cognitive underlabourer, to know in its uniqueness all that to
which higher reason is necessarily blind.’38 The aesthetic is a socialization and
subjectification of affect in order to create meaning in the form of emotion, which in
turn serves as a tacit explanation and justification of the social order: A t the very
root of social relations lies the aesthetic, source of all human relations.’39 Thus any
attempt to deterritorialize musical sensation in the guise of object-product, via the
body as object-product, serves only to effect a massive reterritorialization40 onto
the same old category of the ideal; there is no point in a movement to process if it
is only done in order to restore meaning in a new site. To paraphrase an old
cliche, it is not just that the travelling is important, rather than the arriving - there is
no arrival, nowhere at which to arrive. The body adopts the function of site, while
retaining a status other than that of the unitary location. As Brian Massumi writes,
T h e body doesn’t just absorb pulses or discrete stimulations; it infolds contexts, it
infolds volitions and cognitions that are nothing if not situated. Intensity is asocial
but not presocial - it includes social elements, but mixes them with elements
belonging to other levels of functioning, and combines them according to different
logic.’41 And in order to access the resistive power of the body in music this new
paradigm is required, one in which the parameters of the body are altered and
extended, an opening up of m eaning-product in order to remain en proces, in
jouissance.
Frith’s discussion of voice referred to above was formulated in response to
the renowned essay by Roland Barthes, T h e Grain of the Voice,’ a text cited
repeatedly in musicological approaches to the body. The definition of grain’ that is
most often taken away is that of ‘the body in the voice as it sings,’42 but the
subtleties of Barthes’ argument are frequently overlooked in the desire to claim this
as a support for the straightforward expression of physicality in the voice, which is
then tied to an ‘organic’ and ‘natural’ web of (Romantic) metaphor. A close
reading, however, will reveal that this is almost exactly what Barthes is arguing
against, as, for instance, in his stating: ‘Opera is a genre in which the voice has
gone over in its entirety to dram atic expressivity, a voice with a grain which little
signifies. ... The voice is not personal: it expresses nothing of the cantor, of his
soul.’43 Indeed, given that Frith opens by describing Barthes’ T h e Grain of the
Voice’ as ‘his argument that different timbral qualities have different bodily
im plications,’44 when Barthes explicitly states T h e “grain” of the voice is not - or
not merely - its tim bre,’45 one begins to suspect that there has been a systematic
misreading of Barthes’ intentions. As Frith correctly notes, T h is point is usually
taken up in music criticism as a celebration of “the materiality of the body,”’46 but
the nature of ‘the body’ that is being celebrated here is not an issue that is in
question, despite the fact that this is arguably the key concept of the essay. There
is a powerful element of critics taking from Barthes what they want to hear, or
rather read, regardless of what he has to say, and in doing so they have missed
the formulation of an entirely new paradigm of the body in music that frees critique
from the situated body of the aesthetic project.
Barthes begins T h e Grain of the Voice’ with a discussion of the problems
faced in the translation of music into language through the form of the predicate,
and the limitations that this places upon perception by situating the subject and
tying him or her into an ethical (which is at once an aesthetical) system.
The man who provides himself or is provided with an adjective is now hurt, now
pleased, but always constituted. .. . A historical dossier ought to be assembled here, for
adjectival criticism (or predicative interpretation) has taken on over the centuries
certain institutional aspects. The musical adjective becomes legal whenever an ethos
of music is postulated, each time, that is, that music is attributed a regular - natural or
magical - mode of signification.47
If one wishes to disrupt the system of exchange set in place by this mode of
musical ‘understanding,’ the answer is not to be found in ‘struggling against the
adjective,’48 as Adorno might be said to do, but instead by attempting ‘to change
the musical object itself, as it presents itself to discourse, better to alter its level of
perception of intellection, to displace the fringe of contact between music and
language.'49 If the rules of the game are stacked against you, the answer is not to
try to change the rules of the gam e in the teeth of opposition, but to play a different
game. The nature of this displacement is not simply a change of location, but the
opening up of an entirely new space, or more correctly space-time, 'where melody
explores how the language works and identifies with that work. It is, in a very
simple word but which must be taken seriously, the diction of the language.’50
Diction, the m anner of enunciation, the way in which something is done, action,
process. ‘The grain is ... almost certainly signifiance,’51 and as such is concerned
with the undoing of subjecthood rather than a constitution or expression of
corporeal essence. Indeed, in T h e Third M eaning’ (which might be regarded as a
com panion piece to ‘The Grain of the V oice’ insofar as it addresses signifiance in
the image, as opposed to sound) Barthes quite bluntly states of the obtuse (which
is to say, signifiance): ‘Something in the two faces [on film] exceeds psychology,
anecdote, function, exceeds meaning without, however, coming down to the
obstinacy in presence shown by any human body.’52 There is little point in
dissolving the art object and the subject into process, only to reinscribe them both
in an objectified corporeality.
47 Barthes, R., The Grain of the Voice,’ op, cit., pp. 179-80.
48 Ibid., p. 180.
49 Ibid., pp. 180-1.
50 Ibid., pp. 182-3.
51 Ibid., p. 182.
52 Barthes, R., The Third Meaning: Research notes on some Eisenstein stills,’ in Image
Music Text, p. 54.
125
If I perceive the “grain” in a piece of music and accord this “grain" a theoretical value
(the emergence of the text in the work), I inevitably set up a new scheme of evaluation
which will certainly be individual ... but in no way “subjective" (it is not the
psychological “subject" in me who is listening; the climactic pleasure hoped for is not
going to reinforce - to express - that subject but, on the contrary, to lose it).62
62 Ibid., p. 188.
63 Frith, S., ‘Art versus technology: the strange case of popular music,’ Media, Culture and
Society, 8, (1986), pp. 266-7.
64 Ibid., p. 270.
128
both the relationship between putative sound production and sound receiver, which
is to say the subject and the collective, and also blurs the boundaries between the
singer and his or her technologization - there is an interpenetration of the body of
the singer and its mediation. Frith wrote this essay in 1986, but subsequent
developments have only increased the extent to which the two have become
confluent: witness the band Daft Punk, pioneers of the ‘filtered disco’ sound, who
only appear in public in the form of two robots, conducting interviews through a
Steven Hawking-style computerized voice processor.
These ideas are clearly of great interest to the Icelandic singer-com poser
Bjork, and one can see a repeated referral to these ideas in her music videos and
the literature surrounding her work, particularly in the enigmatically titled Post, a
companion book to her album of the same name. Sjon Sigurdsson tells the story
of NovaBjork,’ a girl found buried in the forest and ‘m ended’ through a process of
amalgamation. He writes:
The composer gathered together instruments from the 01’ World and the Nu. With
sure hands he placed harp strings, microchips, pieces of brass, tiny transistors and
other Energies inside the girl’s body.65
W e have here the clearest possible articulation of the notion of the ‘technological
body,’ or as Steve Sweeney-Turner describes it in this context, a cybjork. The
technologization or mediation of the organic is played out both in her lyrics, and in
the computer modulation of ‘found sounds’ in her music, as well as an illustration
of the cybjork in the video to ‘All is Full of Love.’ It is in the video to 'Hyperballad,’
however, that one sees a reflection-echo of the part played by the video itself in
the further technologization of the musician.
The track opens with an ethereal tone cluster (Bb, C, Eb, F - the tonality of
the verse section hovers between C minor and Bb major throughout) played on
synthesized strings, under which enters an electronically generated sound lacking
65 Sigurdsson, S., ‘The Birth of NovaBjork: a tale in the old style of Science Fiction,’ in
Sigurdsson et at, Post, (Bloomsbury, London, 1995), quoted by Steve Sweeney-Turner in
an unpublished paper Bjork and the Figure of the Machine.’
129
any sort of attack, that slowly descends through a repeated Et>, D, C two octaves
below middle C, mapping a wide sonic space. The image that accom panies this is
of a modelled landscape of a plain and distant mountains, over which move
com puterized clouds, instantly picking up the motif of mediated organicism. As the
scattershot drum break enters with a statement-echo pattern driving through each
bar, sim ilar in rhythm to the clatter of a railway, the camera pulls round to show an
apparently lifeless Bjork lying amongst leaf litter, but with an electronic ‘haze’
crackling across her in time to the drum rhythm, in a parallel, superposed plane.
With the entry of the vocal line a second, ghostly imprint of a singing Bjork
appears, again superimposed upon ‘organic’ Bjork and the ‘electric’ plane. Not
only does this serve to confound authorial presence, but it also illustrates the
technologized, mediated voice, and the mediation of the Bjork-image in the video.
A third, ‘com puter-gam e’ Bjork appears with the chorus, running across the model
landscape which is now also superposed with computer graphics, before enacting
the line ‘I imagine what my body would sound like, slamming against those rocks’
(see Appendix), and returning to the dead Bjork/ singing Bjork composite, until all
three are superposed in a sim ultaneously static and moving landscape. (It is
difficult to describe the full com plexity of the series of superimposed levels
compressed into a single plane that form the image track to this video, but it
involves at least three pieces of footage that are combined using motion tracking
techniques.) In this problematization of movement in space-time, the combining of
‘organic’ and ‘machinic’ sounds technologically with the singer-com poser’s unique
Icelandic inflected diction, and then routing all of this through a set of ‘bodies’ that
are all moving in unison and all identifiably Bjork, any notion of a distinct, originary
singing body as sound-source, opposed to its technological status, is com pletely
overrun. W hat might at first appear to be the corporeal alienation of Bjork’s voice,
instead becomes the means of reinscribing Bjorkness’ across a series of
technologized corporealizations. To paraphrase Deleuze and Guattari, Bjork and
Michel Gondry, the director, make audio-visual the sound-image process, the
production of that process, in a music-video machine.
130
III
Could a machine think? - Could it be in pain? - Well, is the human body to be called
such a machine? It surely comes as close as possible to being such a machine.66
The material or machinic aspect of assemblage relates not to the production of goods
but rather to a precise state of intermingling of bodies in a society, including all the
attractions and repulsions, sympathies and antipathies, alterations, amalgamations,
penetrations, and expansions that affect bodies of all kinds in their relations to one
another. ... Even technology makes the mistake of considering tools in isolation: tools
exist only in relation to the interminglings they make possible or that make them
possible. The stirrup entails a new man-horse symbiosis that at the same time entails
new weapons and new instruments. Tools are inseparable from symbioses or
amalgamations defining a Nature-Society machinic assemblage. They presuppose a
social machine that selects them and takes them into its “phylum:” a society is defined
by its amalgamations, not by its tools.70
This goes some way to clarifying the nature of the individual in theory - the
Barthesian singing voice is a fine example of a Nature-Society machinic
assem blage' - but still leaves open the question of the precise mechanism by
which material bodies perceive, or at least interiorize, their own ‘state of
interm ingling.’
A clue as to how one might apprehend individuation without denying the
continuity of individual and context is given by Ernst Bloch:
We do not possess it, that which all this around us ... is or signifies, because we are it
itself and are standing too close to it. ... But the sound burns out of us, the heard note,
not the sound itself or its forms. This, however, shows us our path without alien
means, our historically inward path, as a fire in which not the vibrating air but we
ourselves begin to quiver and cast off our cloaks.71
71 Bloch, E., The philosophy of music,’ in Essays on the Philosophy of Music, trans
Palmer, P., (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1985), p. 1.
72 Massumi, B., The Autonomy of Affect,’ op. cit., p. 222.
73 Ibid., p. 223.
74 Massumi, B., The Bleed: Where Body Meets Image,’ in Welchman, J (ed.), Rethinking
Borders, (Macmillan, London, 1996), p. 30.
75 Ibid., p 31.
133
traces have established an infrastructure for such centring.’76 Massumi has simply
displaced the social construction of the memory trace from the conscious brain to
the w ider nervous system in a way that is not unrelated to subjectivity, but neither
is it dependent upon it.
Proprioception effects a double translation of the subject and the object into the body,
at a medium depth where the body is only body, having nothing of the profundity of the
self nor of the superficiality o f external encounter. This asubjective and non-objective
medium depth is one of the strata proper to the corporeal; it is a dimension of the flesh.
The memory it constitutes could be diagrammed as a superposition of vectorial fields
composed of multiple points in varying relations of movement and rest, pressure and
resistance, each field corresponding to an action.77
The collective is a body, too. And the physis that is being organised for it in technology
can, through all its political and factual reality, only be produced in that image sphere to
which profane illumination initiates us. Only when in technology body and image so
interpenetrate that all revolutionary tension becomes bodily collective innervation, and
76 Mowitt, J., The sound of music in the era of its electronic reproducibility,’ in Leppert, R
and McClary, S. (eds), Music and Society: the politics of composition, performance and
reception, (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1987), p. 183. As Mowitt discusses,
this particular point is made by Derrida.
77 Massumi, B., The Bleed: Where Body Meets Image,’ op. cit., p. 31
78 Lefebvre, H., see chapter 2, n. 61.
134
all the bodily innervations of the collective become revolutionary discharge, has reality
transcended itself to the extent demanded by the Communist Manifesto.79
79
Benjamin, W., 'Surrealism: The Last Snapshot of the European Intelligentsia,’ in
Reflections, trans. Jephcott, E., (Schocken, New York, 1986), p 192. Also quoted in
Eagleton, T., The Ideology of the Aesthetic, p. 336.
80 Mowitt, J., op. cit., p. 193.
81 Eagleton, T., The Ideology of the Aesthetic, p. 336.
Conclusion
M usic videos are neither intended, nor very often received as attacks on the notion
o f capital, monologistic aesthetics, or anything else for that matter; more often they
are precisely the opposite, calculated by corporations to maximize return on a
cultural commodity. Anyone hoping to inspire revolution by subjecting the
populace to large doses of boy bands and ‘nu-m etal’ videos will be a long time
waiting. It would be foolish to ignore the fact that both the denoted and connoted
m essages of the great majority of music videos (the Barthesian ‘obvious’
m eaning), are supportive of the capitalist system almost to the point of
propaganda. W hether one looks at the level of the individual video’s ‘pseudo-
narrative,’ or the ‘star-text’ of the meta-narrative, the same set of ideals based
around the notion of the ‘pop-star,’ and in particular his or her conspicuous
consumption, predominate. Much of the foregoing argument has attempted to
show how, despite this fact, the nature of the intertwining of music and image in
m usic video simultaneously undoes the ideology represented, not by countering it,
but by problematizing the very notion of representation. This refusal of meaning,
obvious’ or otherwise, derived from the experience of music, only a short time
after ‘new’ musicologists have worked so hard to bring it into the equation might be
regarded as a controversial move, but it is borne of the belief that a critical project
founded upon direct opposition to the status quo, although by no means worthless,
is in the end unlikely ever to fulfil its aims. Its inevitable consequence is the
reduction of music analysis to ‘the dilemma of either the predicable or the
1 Exchange between Lisa and Marge Simpson, The Simpsons, episode reference
unknown.
136
o ne of Deleuze and Guattari’s own exam ples,4 the action of a hijacker brandishing
a w eapon transforms the plane into a prison, the passengers into hostages, and
yet the material conditions remain unaltered. T h e transformation applies to bodies
but is itself incorporeal, internal to enunciation.’5 Similarly, in reformulating the
m ode of interaction between sound and image, based upon aesthetic criteria
derived from a consideration of music, one’s understanding of the world is
instantaneously relativized. As with W ittgenstein s ‘duck-rabbit,’6 one is suddenly
confronted with an alternative mode of cognition, in such a way as to require a
reappraisal of one’s relationship to the entity in question, and generate a
previously unimagined social reality and praxis.
One sees both of these possibilities explored (that is, conventional
oppositional critique and incorporeal transformation), in the video to ‘Remind M e’
by the Norwegian ambient dance group Royksopp. Taking off from the title and
repeated intonation of the chorus lyric ‘remind m e,’ the video demythologizes
aspects of everyday working life, by appropriating the form at of the technical
diagram and animating it - a train journey is seen in terms of the relative statistics
on modes of travel, as it passes through a cross-sectional image of tunnel
construction, and via a diagram of the shifting patterns of signals and points.
Similarly, a young wom an’s lunchtime burger is transformed into a part of a cow,
w hich is in turn part of a herd, and the industrial processing of the milk involved in
th e production of her milkshake is passed through. Although the video’s
avoidance of naturalistic representation and appropriation of the imagistic tools’ of
industrialization to the form of animation, as well as its highlighting of industrial
processing itself, might be regarded as straightforwardly resistive, it is when these
im ages are conjoined with music that they have a genuinely subversive potential.
T he stock market graphs and production charts that are presented as part of the
office environment are m usicked here, made to ‘dance’ and move to the rhythm of
the music. The imagery of international finance is transformed at an affective
level; it ceases to be representative and is made sensuous.
This strategy is not without risk: affect in itself is entirely lacking in critical
capacity, and as Deleuze and Guattari note of sound, ‘since its force of
deterritorialization is the strongest, it also effects the most massive of
reterritorializations.'' There remains the possibility that the demythologizing
rhetoric of the images in the ‘Remind M e’ video are neither reinforced nor
superseded by their relation to the sound track, but are instead recommodified in a
w a y that the music serves to conceal. There is a danger in overstressing the
‘redem ptive’ capacities of music, and of tying it too firmly to the idea of an ‘aural
parad igm ’ suggested above, for which an aesthetics of sound alone was only a
prom pt. One sees, on occasion, a favouring of the affective, the sensuous, in the
realm of the image also, particularly in the films of directors such as Scorsese and
Tarantino (often in association with prominent sound tracks), and in much
photographic art. Aesthetic appreciation is predicated on the simultaneous
presence of both ‘visual’ and ‘aural’ paradigms, their intermingling, not in an
either/or relationship, but in their shifting patterns of emphasis.
There are times at which the ‘aural paradigm ’ comes uncomfortably close
to the nineteenth-century category of the transcendent, with a shiny new
postm odern veneer. Reinscribing ‘the unsayable’ in signifiance, and then showing
how ‘the aural’ has privileged access to this realm, may appear to reinstate m usic’s
connection to ‘the ineffable,’ but this would be to misunderstand the profoundly
socialized, if not entirely effable, character of signifiance, which Kristeva
dem onstrates is based precisely in the space of interaction between subject and
society.8 My use of terms such as ‘m usicalization’ may obfuscate instead of
illum inating this point, but this is due to the difficulty of the problem faced, rather
than a simple matter of terminology. ‘G esture,’ as defined in chapter 2 above, is
an attempt to bind the material and the social in a single entity, so as to facilitate
m aterial analysis that is at once a form of social critique - the ‘holy grail’ of critical
musicology. Although theoretically sound, again concrete examples of its
application have proved frustratingly difficult to produce, and the fear must be that
it becomes a means of endlessly delaying a genuine social analysis rather than
enabling it. W hether ‘gesture’ is a useful model of musical, or any other material,
has still to be proven, but I remain hopeful that it may have avoided many of the
problem s encountered by musicologists on this issue.
An attack on what Barthes terms the ‘Organon of Representation’ that
addressed it directly would involve addressing it on its own terms: in the realm of
the ideal, where objects and music are only ever ciphers of something else, never
sensuous and motile. Music video instead sidesteps this, musicks the image in
such a way as to open it up to collectivization, rather than giving the autonomous
individualized subject the palliative of the ideal. It is not so much what music
videos do, as what they allow. It does not attempt to destroy the status quo, but to
undercut it and set it adrift of its moorings, facilitating its undoing.
If at times I have seemed hostile to the psychoanalytic subject, it is
because of the emphasis it places upon the individual at the expense of the
collective, the private rather than the public. Atomizing the social poses no threat
to hegem onic forces; it only weakens the capacity for resistance. Music video
enables one to recognize, via affective charge, what Deleuze and Guattari refer to
in stating:
9 Ibid., pp. 79-80. It is worth noting that they absolve Mikhail Bakhtin of any failings
on this score.
10 Barthes, R., Sade/Fourier/Loyola, trans. Miller, R., (Johns Hopkins University
Press, Baltimore, 1976), p. 37.
140
harm ony, totality, appearance),’" and burrows within the form of the object in order
to und o it, and to extract those m eans of resistance that are still available, but it will
not d o this unaided Like the Brechtian gestus, the critical potential that inheres in
m usic video is given in order to be taken up, and it is only in its being taken up that
its aesthetic might become manifest.
Song Lyrics
R .E .M . - Imitation of Life
W e live on a mountain
Right at the top.
T h e re ’s a beautiful view
From the top of the mountain.
Every morning I walk towards the edge
And throw little things off
Like:
Car-parts, bottles and cutlery
O r whatever I find lying around.
W hen it lands
W ill my eyes
Be closed, or open?
Transcription
A<« .i t *
* ___
— v — — F: r
:2 P
com t, t W t oeJi f tivA.'t' ciV\r\*-m art } - w»eAy c 'm o O , n o oiy
*\€>»
Am C-orrt—i— __ D
&
: E
■ » ' 4--
Cfcfi 3 it t^ou tr*^.
p ^ , n Em Km E> Lxn
5
-y ^ = JS -
p i
\
------- N
r
' s ..--■ v V 1
■^
■7*------->A-
v ^ - a r r *
JL------ # - • • i M' • 1
V= Z _ f — , - 4—i J- C : >J-,
ik — 1L -# ♦
#
—r- 1 # » ------- ^ -
--------- » ♦ > »
^»u •OfcW' t*VjL jrtttfc^sfc tVw. tVui«-j Sfntt b rejJ l ca»<. . 'foi/vTyt it *ll
tm hrf\
FJ-+- Gr. . . -D
f t fc
*■ # £
r— „
Cfi/\S\V-J |V> tM. tor-r\£-»', f r ^ fa (oo^c Ukt ^ ,0 eW'f t«"
145
Am Cm
-
±
f » ♦
. »VK. -------
Ca <U-, CK«-t t(x3fc£*l^*«t, tK C t
rr* * * 1
LI + -0 -
*?
D
- 4l X — MH O P * f MHn O
3
i= ^ r^H 0
...»
,
(3^rttv»ti\t^t( iti- p,*ft,0
D J i c
(.So-fro voc.t') N s - c M c in
JU JJU LTO
i|eii c«^.
•?£- — Or tJ________ _ Cm Am
Si 3 * *
B r H-f H f in ».
u
*
» *-0
i- 4 . -
c‘ " '4,l 1 nocx'X. can s«- i^oo cn-y
8fc | Q" 1 tM Am
m i>j i i nj
*m . ___ ■' m • m 7 *
T R i'3 ju ^ a r c P*-L, tV u .3
-0- 0— •
oAt., t W '5
f!
h u rri tA ^ t ( V r» ^ A o fc n - |V w A , t*
____ r-^*'__________ —
__fq_| r r n jL ' i Qri
CetOX, T"''-^t'
THf inE ^»o4| imK»ljo®aft, fkfci'J
r p r » # <L p
P r r— PH' n p— 0— I
# ^
f ♦- p- — * *
...- -
J _
r > \ f •iM
wVlt^buji/v (jv l4 , t 'r r it n , rtoa»vi c a n truj.
146
fc.rv\ An* J - l __ L t
' FT-
T Z
f -'r f rr pf r -fr :^ =
j \ .. jw | | f 7 l ~ tp ft
ckfv-t, tVuvA" • > * ' » ( - 1 ‘tVuut'S ioUt± i^oo tfiv/tA, c'rwon , t'rA an r\° e»\i.
^ - _
pynb# A"' .__________ - ____ _ D £V>
ilX
=£
Books
Abbate, C. (1991), Unsung Voices: Opera and Musical Narrative in the Nineteenth
Century, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Abraham , G. (1979), The Concise O xford History o f M usic, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Adam s, D. (1988), Dirk Gently's Holistic Detective Agency, London: Pan.
Adorno, T.W. (1973), The Jargon o f Authenticity, trans. Tarnowski, K. and Will, F.,
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Adorno, T.W., Benjamin, W. et al (1980), Aesthetics and Politics, trans. editor
Taylor, R., London and New York: Verso.
Adorno, T.W. (1987), Philosophy o f Modern Music, trans. Mitchell, A.G. and
Blomster, W.V., London: Sheed & Ward.
Adorno, T.W. (1991), In Search o f Wagner, trans. Livingstone, R., London and
New York: Verso.
Adorno, T.W. (1991), The Culture Industry: Selected essays on mass culture, ed.
Bernstein, J.M., London: Routledge.
Agawu, K. (1991), Playing with Signs: A Semiotic Interpretation o f Classic Music,
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Allanbrook, W.J. (1983), Rhythm ic Gesture in Mozart, Chicago and London:
University of Chicago Press.
Apel, K.-O. (1996), ‘W ittgenstein and Heidegger: language games and life form s,’
in McCann, C. (ed.), Critical Heidegger, London and New York: Routledge, pp.
241-274.
Attali, J. (1985), Noise: The Political Econom y o f Music, trans. Massumi, B ,
Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Bakhtin, M.M. (1981), The Dialogic Imagination: Four Essays, ed. Holmquist, M.,
trans. Emerson, C , and Holmquist, M., Austin: University of Texas Press.
148
Barthes, R. (1967), Elements o f Semiology, trans. Lavers, A. and Smith, C., New
York: Hill and Wang.
Barthes, R. (1976), Sade/Fourier/Loyola, trans. Miller, R., Baltimore: Johns
Hopkins University Press.
Barthes, R. (1977), Image-Music-Text, trans. Heath, S., London: Fontana.
Barthes, R. (1981), Theory of the Text,’ trans. McLeod, I., in Young, R., Untying
the Text: A Post-Structuralist Reader, London and New York: Routledge, pp.
31-47.
Barthes, R. (1989), The Rustle o f Language, trans. Howard, R., Berkeley and Los
Angeles: University of California Press.
Barthes, R. (1990), S/Z, trans. Miller, R., Oxford: Blackwell.
Barthes, R. (1991), The Responsibility o f Forms, trans. Howard, R., Berkeley and
Los Angeles: University of California Press.
Barthes, R. (1991), The Semiotic Challenge, trans. Howard, R., Berkeley and Los
Angeles: University of California Press.
Barthes, R. (1993), Mythologies, selected and trans. Lavers, A., London: Vintage.
Barthes, R. (2000), Camera Lucida: Reflections on Photography, trans. Howard,
R., London: Vintage.
Baudrillard, J. (1988), Selected Writings, ed. Poster, M., Cambridge: Polity.
Benjamin, W. (1968), Theses on the Philosophy of History,’ in Illuminations, trans.
Zohn, H., New York: Schocken, pp. 253-265.
Benjamin, W. (1973), T h e W ork of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction,’ in
Illuminations, ed. Arendt, H., trans. Zohn, H., London: Fontana, pp. 211-243.
Benjamin, W. (1979), 'On Language as Such and on the Language of M an,’ in One
Way Street, trans. Jephcott, E. and Shorter, K., London and New York: Verso,
pp. 107-123.
Benjamin, W. (1986), ‘Surrealism: The Last Snapshot of the European
Intelligentsia,’ in Reflections, trans. Jephcott, E., New York: Schocken, pp.
177-192.
Berland, J. (1993), ‘Sound, Image and Social Space: Music Video and Media
Reconstruction,’ in Frith, S., Goodwin, A., and Grossberg, L. (eds), Sound and
Vision: The Music Video Reader, London and New York: Routledge, pp.25-43.
Bianconi, L. (1987), Music in the Seventeenth Century, trans. Bryant, D.,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
149
Dieckmann, K. (1999), ‘MTV Killed the Music Video Star,’ in Kelly, K. and
McDonnell, E., Stars D on’t Stand Still in the Sky: Music and Myth, London and
New York: Routledge, pp. 88-97.
Dyer, R. (1991), 'A Star is Born and the construction of Authenticity,’ in Stardom:
Industry o f Desire, ed. Gledhill, C., London and New York: Routledge, pp. 132-
139.
Eagleton, T. (1986), ‘W ittgenstein’s Friends,’ in Against the Grain: Essays 1976-
1985, London: Verso, pp. 99-130.
Eagleton, T. (1990), The Ideology o f the Aesthetic, Oxford: Blackwell.
Eagleton, T. (1996), Literary Theory: An Introduction (second edition), Oxford:
Blackwell.
Eagleton, T. (2000), The Idea o f Culture, Oxford: Blackwell.
Eco, U. (1979), A Theory o f Semiotics, Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Edmonds, D. and Eidinow, J. (2001), W ittgenstein’s Poker: The story of a ten-
m inute argument between two great philosophers, London: Faber and Faber.
Ferrneyhough, B. (1995), 'Concerning the Functional Role of Timbre in the early
works of Anton W ebern,’ in Ferneyhough: Collected Writings, ed. Boros, J. and
Toop, R., Amsterdam: Harwood Academ ic Publishers.
Feuer, J. (1993), The Flollywood M usical (second edition), London: British Film
Institute Publishing.
Forster, E.M. (1941), Howards End, Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Foucault, M. (1978), A History of Sexuality: vol. 1, trans. Hurley, R.,
Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Foucault, M. (1985), Discipline and Punish, trans. Sheridan, A., Harmondsworth:
Penguin.
Frith, S. (1987), Tow ards an aesthetic of popular m usic,’ in Leppert, R., and
McClary, S. (eds), Music and Society: the politics o f composition, perform ance
and reception, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 133-149.
Frith, S. (1996), Performing Rites: On the Value o f Popular Music, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Galilei, V. (1950), ‘Dialogo della musica antica e della m oderna’ (extract), in
Strunk, O. (ed.), Source Readings in Music History: The Renaissance, New
York and London: W.W. Norton & Company, pp. 112-132.
Gallop, J. (1985), Reading Lacan, Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press.
152
G arrod, H.W. (1925), Coleridge: Poetry and Prose, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
G enova, J. (1995), Wittgenstein: A W ay o f Seeing, London and New York:
Routledge.
Gier, N. (1981), Wittgenstein and Phenomenology, New York: State University of
New York Press.
G oodwin, A. (1992), Dancing in the Distraction Factory: Music Television and
Popular Culture, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Greimas, A.J. (1983), Structural Semantics: an attempt at a method, trans.
McDowell, D., Schleifer, R. and Velie, A., Lincoln: University of Nebraska
Press.
Gurney, E. (1880), The Pow er o f Sound, London: Smith, Elder & Company.
Hanslick, E. (1986), On the M usically Beautiful, ed. and trans. Payzant, G.,
Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
Hayward, S. (1996), Key Concepts in Cinema Studies, London and New York:
Routledge.
Heidegger, M. (1978), T h e Question Concerning Technology,’ in Krell, D.F. (ed.),
Heidegger: Basic Writings, trans. Verlag, M.N., London and Henley: Routledge
and Kegan Paul, pp. 284-317.
Helmholtz, Hermann von (1954), On the Sensations o f Tone as a Physiological
Basis for the Theory o f Music, trans. Ellis, A.J., New York: Dover Publications.
Hinton, S. (1993), 'Germany, 1918-45,’ in ed. Morgan, R.P., Modern Times: From
W orld War I to the present, Man and Music series, London: Macmillan, pp. 83-
110 .
Hirschkop, K. (1989), T h e Classical and the Popular: Musical Form and Social
Context,’ in Norris, C. (ed.), Music and the Politics o f Culture, London:
Lawrence Wishart, pp. 283-304.
Hjelmslev, L. (1969), Prolegomena to a Theory o f Language, trans. W hitfield, F.,
Madison: University of W isconsin Press.
Hodeir, A. (1975), Since Debussy: A View o f Contemporary Music, trans. Burch,
N., New York: Da Capo Press.
Ilson, R., Crystal, D., Wells, J.C. and Long, T.H. (eds) (1998), R eader’s Digest
Universal Dictionary, London etc.: Reader’s Digest Association Limited.
Johnson, P. (1993), Wittgenstein: Rethinking the Inner, London and New York:
Routledge.
153
Kaplan, E.A. (1987), Rocking A round the Clock: Music Television, Postmodernism,
a nd Consum er Culture, London and New York: Routledge.
Kershaw, D. (1992), 'Music and Image on Film and Video: An Absolute
A lternative,’ in Paynter, J. et al (eds), The Companion to Contem porary
M usical Thought, vol. 7, London and New York: Routledge, pp. 466-499.
King, B. (1991), 'Articulating Stardom ,’ in Stardom: Industry o f Desire, ed. Gledhill,
C., London and New York: Routledge, pp. 167-182.
Kramer, L. (1990), Music as Cultural Practice 1800-1900, Berkeley and Los
Angeles: University of California Press.
Kristeva, J. (1984), Revolution in Poetic Language, trans. Waller, M., New York:
Columbia University Press.
Lendvai, E. (1971), Bela Bartok: An Analysis o f his Music, London: Kahn & Averill.
Lyotard, J.-F. (1984), The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge, trans.
Bennington, D. and Massumi, B., Manchester: Manchester University Press.
MacCabe, C. (1981), ‘Realism and the Cinema: Notes on some Brechtian Theses,’
in Bennett, T. (ed.), Popular Music and Film, London: British Film Institute
Publishing.
McDonald, M. (forthcoming), Varese, (unpublished manuscript).
Madden, C. (1999), Fractals in Music: Introductory Mathematics for M usical
Analysis, Salt Lake City: High Art Press.
Magee, B. (1997), Confessions o f a Philosopher, London: W iedenfeld and
Nicolson.
Massumi, B. (1996), T h e Bleed: W here Body Meets Image,’ in W elchman, J.,
Rethinking Borders, London: Macmillan, pp. 18-40.
Massumi, B. (1996), T h e Autonomy of A ffect,’ in Patton, P. (ed ), Deleuze: A
Critical Reader, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 217-239.
Mellers, W. (1964), Music in a New Found Land, London: Barrie and Rockliff.
Mercer, K. (1993), ‘Monster Metaphors: Notes on Michael Jackson’s Thriller,’ in
Frith, S., Goodwin, A., and Grossberg, L. (eds), Sound and Vision: The Music
Video Reader, London and New York: Routledge, pp. 93-108.
Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964), T h e Primacy of Perception and its Philosophical
Consequences,’ trans. Edie, J.M., in Edie, J.M. (ed.), The Prim acy of
Perception and other essays on Phenom enological Psychology, the
Philosophy o f Art, History and Politics, Northwestern University Press.
154
Metz, C. (1974), Film Language: A Semiotics o f the Cinema, trans. Taylor, M.,
Chicago and London: The University of Chicago University Press.
Metz, C. (1981), ‘Story/Discourse (A Note on Two Kinds of Voyeurism ),’ in The
Im aginary Signifier, trans. Guzzetti, A., Bloomington: Indiana University Press,
pp. 91-97.
Meyer, L. (1989), Style and Music: Theory, History and Ideology, Philadelphia:
University of Pennsylvania Press.
Middleton, R. (1990), Studying P opular M usic, Milton Keynes: Open University
Press.
Mitchell, W.J.T. (ed.) (1981), On Narrative, Chicago and London: The University of
Chicago University Press.
Monelle, R. (1992), Linguistics and Semiotics in Music, Chur, etc.: Harwood
Academ ic Publishers.
Montefiore, A. and Taylor, C. (1980), ‘From an analytical perspective,’ in Kortian,
G., Metacritique: The Philosophical Argum ent o f Jurgen Habermas, trans.
Raffan, J., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mowitt, J. (1987), T h e sound of music in the era of its electronic reproducibility,’ in
Leppert, R. and McClary, S. (eds), Music and Society: the politics o f
composition, perform ance and reception, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, pp. 173-197.
Nattiez, J.-J. (1977), T h e contribution of musical semiotics to the sem iotic
discussion in general,’ in Sebeok, T.A. (ed.), A Perfusion of Signs,
Bloomington: Indiana University Press, pp. 121-142.
Nattiez, J.-J. (1990), Music and Discourse: Toward a Semiology o f Music, trans.
Abbate, C., Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Nietzsche, F. (1899), ‘Nietzsche contra Wagner: The Brief of a Psychologist,’ in
The Works o f Friedrich Nietzsche, vol. Ill, trans. Common, T., London: T.
Fisher Unwin, pp. 61-93.
Nietzsche, F. (1967), T h e Case of W agner,’ in The Birth o f Tragedy and The Case
o f Wagner, trans. Kaufmann, W., Toronto: Random House.
Nietzsche, F. (1979), ‘On Truth and Lies in a Non-moral Sense,’ in Breazeale, D.
(ed.), Philosophy and Truth, Humanities Press, pp. 79-97.
155
Nietzsche, F. (1980), ‘On Music and W ords,’ trans. Kaufmann, W., in Between
Romanticism and M odernism , trans. Whittall, M., Berkeley and Los Angeles:
University of California Press, pp. 103-119.
Paddison, M. (1993), A dorno’s Aesthetics o f M usic, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Paddison, M. (1996), Adorno, M odernism and Mass Culture: Essays on Critical
Theory and M usic, London: Kahn & Averill.
Plato (1950), T h e Republic’ (extract), in Strunk, O. (ed.), Source Readings in
M usic History: Antiquity and The Middle A ges, New York and London: W.W.
Norton & Company, pp. 3-12.
Plato (1965), Timaeus, trans. Lee, H.D.P., Harmondsworth, Penguin.
Ree, J. (1987), Philosophical Tales: An Essay on Philosophy and Literature,
London and New York: Methuen.
Rosen, C. (1976), Schoenberg, London: Marion Boyars.
Rosen, C. (1996), The Rom antic Generation, London: HarperCollins.
Rosenthal, B.G. (1984), ‘W agner and W agnerian Ideas in Russia,’ in Wagnerism in
European Culture and Politics, Large, D C. and Weber, W. (eds), Ithaca and
London: Cornell University Press, pp. 198-245.
Sadie, S. (ed.) (2001), The New Grove Dictionary o f Music and Musicians, second
edition, London: Macmillan.
Samuels, R. (1994), ‘Music as Text: Mahler, Schumann and issues in analysis,’ in
Pople, A. (ed.), Theory, analysis and meaning in music, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, pp. 152-163.
de Saussure, F. (1960), Course in General Linguistics, ed. Bally, C. and
Sechehaye, A., trans. Baskin, W., London: Peter Owen.
Schonberg, A. (1975), Style and Idea: Selected Writings o f Arnold Schdnberg, ed.
Stein, L., trans. Black, L., London.
Schonberg, A. (1978), Theory o f Harmony, trans. Carter, R.E., London: Faber and
Faber.
Scruton, R. (1997), The Aesthetics o f Music, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Sebeok, T.A. (1977), ‘Ecumenicalism in Sem iotics,’ in Sebeok, T.A. (ed ), A
Perfusion o f Signs, Bloomington: Indiana University Press, pp. 180-206.
Sebeok, T.A. (1994), An Introduction to Semiotics, London: Pinter Publishers.
Shepherd, J. (1991), Music as Social Text, Cambridge: Polity.
156
Small, C. (1998), Musicking: The M eanings o f Perform ing and Listening, Hanover,
NH: W esleyan University Press/University Press of New England.
Strohm, R. (1995), ‘Musical Analysis as Part of Musical History,’ in (ed.) Pozzi, R..
Tendenze e m etodi nella ricerca musicologica, Florence, pp. 61-81.
Tarasti, E. (1994), A Theory o f M usical Semiotics, Bloomington: Indiana University
Press.
Tetzlaff, D. (1992), ‘Popular Culture and Social Control,’ in Scannell, P.,
Schlesinger, P. and Sparks, C. (eds), Culture and Power, London. Sage, pp.
48-72.
Toolan, M. (1988), Narrative: a critical linguistic introduction, London and New
York: Routledge.
Treitler, L. (1989), Music and the Historical Imagination, Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press.
Turbow, G.D. (1984), ‘Art and Politics: W agnerism in France,' in Wagnerism in
European Culture and Politics, Large, D C. and Weber, W. (eds), Ithaca and
London: Cornell University Press, pp. 134-166.
Wagner, R. (1850), T h e Artwork of the Future’ (extract), in Solie, R.A. (ed.) (1998)
Strunk’s Source Readings in Music History, vol. 6, revised edition, New York
and London: W.W. Norton & Company, pp.52-70.
Wagner, R. (1983), My Life, trans. Gray, A., ed. Whittall, M., Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Weber, W. (1984), ‘Wagner, W agnerism, and Musical Idealism ,’ in Wagnerism in
European Culture and Politics, Large, D C. and Weber, W. (eds), Ithaca and
London: Cornell University Press, pp. 28-71.
W en-Chung, C. (1979), ‘Ionisation: The Function of Timbre in its Formal and
Temporal Organization,’ in The New Worlds o f Edgard Varese: A Symposium,
New York: Institute for Studies in American Music.
Whiteley, S. (1997), 'Seduced by the Sign: An analysis of the textual links between
sound and image in pop videos,’ in Whiteley, S. (ed.), Sexing the Groove:
Popular Music and Gender, London and New York: Routledge.
Williams, A. (1994), ‘’Repons’: phantasmagoria or the articulation of space?’ in
Pople, A. (ed.), Theory, analysis and meaning in music, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, pp. 195-210.
157
Biddle, I. (2000), Kraftwerk and the electronic sublime: synthesis and the politics
of representation at the end of the “analogue era,’” delivered to conference,
‘Popular Music and National Identities,’ at the University of Newcastle upon
Tyne.
Bjornberg, A. (1994), ‘Structural relationships of music and images in music video,’
Popular Music, 14, pp. 51-74.
Brackett, D. (1995), T h e Electro-acoustic mirror: voices in American pop,’ Critical
Quarterly, 37:2, pp. 11-27.
Clarke, E.F. (1993), ‘Generativity, Mimesis and the Human Body in Music
Performance,’ Contemporary Music Review, 7, pp. 207-221.
Frangois, A.-L. (1995), ‘Fakin’ it/M akin’ it: Falsetto’s Bid for Transcendence in
1970s Disco Highs,’ Perspectives o f New Music, 33:2, pp. 442-456.
Frith, S. (1986), ‘Art versus technology: the strange case of popular m usic,’ Media,
Culture and Society, 8, pp. 263-279.
Frith, S. (1995), T h e Body Electric,’ Critical Quarterly, 37:2, pp. 1-10.
Gilbert, A. (1981), ‘Musical Space: A Com poser’s View,’ Critical Inquiry, 7, pp. 605-
611.
Hawkins, S. (1996), ‘Perspectives in Popular Musicology,’ Popular Music, 15, pp.
1-36.
Hawkins, S. (2000), ‘Fixity and Indifference in Norwegian Club M usic,’ delivered to
conference, ‘Popular Music and National Identities,’ at the University of
Newcastle upon Tyne.
Jameson, F. (1984), ’Postmodernism, or the cultural logic of late capitalism ,’ New
Left Review, 146, pp. 53-92.
Kerman, J. (1980), ‘How we got into analysis, and how to get out,’ Critical Inquiry,
7, pp. 311-331.
Kristeva, J. (1973), T h e Semiotic Activity,’ Screen, 14, pp. 25-39.
Lockwood, L. (1974), ‘Aspects of the ‘L’Homme Arm e’ tradition,’ Proceedings o f
the Royal Musical Association, vol. 100, pp. 97-122.
159
Cigarettes, J., ‘Pre-Millennium Pretension: The New Prog,’ New M usical Express,
(7th February 1998), pp. 22-24.
G udm undsdottir, B., ‘Compose yourself: Bjork meets Karlheinz Stockhausen,’
Dazed, (October 1997), pp. 42-46.
Harris, J., T h e Video G eneration,’ The Independent on Sunday: Real Life, (5th
December 1999), pp. 1-2.
Hoskyns, B., ‘Stardust Memories: Glam is making a com eback,’ The Observer
Review, (5th October 1998), p. 2.
McCrone, J., ‘Network Culture: a review of Capra, F., Hidden Connections: A
Science for Sustainable Living, HarperCollins,’ The Guardian Review, (3rd
August 2002), p. 12.
O ’Hagan, S., Beat G eneration,’ The Guardian Weekend, (12th June 1999), pp. 20-
25.
O ’Reilly, J., ‘Face the M usic,’ The Guardian: Friday Review, (5th March 1999), pp.
16-17.
Paz, O., ‘Journeys into the abyss,’ The Guardian Review, (10th August 2002), pp.
28-29.
Sutherland, S. and Cigarettes, J., ‘From Teds to Mods to Hippies to Skins to Punks
to Goths to This: The Death of Tribalism ,’ New M usical Express, (5th
December 1998), pp. 20-22.
Videography