Global Health and Scientific Research (Flory, 2004)
Global Health and Scientific Research (Flory, 2004)
Global Health and Scientific Research (Flory, 2004)
I
In , million people died. Violence killed fewer than one million of
them; famine contributed to about six million deaths; more than
million died of some form of disease.1 Many of these illnesses were the
result primarily of old age and may have been unpreventable. That is
unlikely to be true, however, of over a million deaths from malaria, nearly
two million deaths from tuberculosis, nearly three million deaths from
AIDS, and over four million deaths from respiratory disease.2
To suggest that many of these deaths could have been prevented
might be to make one of two distinct claims. First, in the current state of
our knowledge, available techniques exist for responding to the diseases
mentioned above and for saving those who suffered from them. Second,
these are scourges that we might hope to overcome in the course of
future biomedical research. Part of the worlds burden of disease could
have been alleviated if those who died had had access to drugs or treat-
ments routinely available to others in different places. Another part
could have been lightened if there had been more thoroughgoing efforts
to discover methods of combating disease, methods that the actual
course of biomedical research has so far not yet found.
Our aim is to understand the relation between the ways that people
die and the kinds of weapons against disease that medicine has acquired
and that it seeks to extend. We shall try to give substance to the familiar
view that the diseases that contribute to the global burden of death are
not well-aligned with the dominant directions in biomedical research.
This misalignment, we claim, underwrites an obligation for individual
researchers to reorient their inquiries and for the institutions that
support research to alter their priorities. We begin with some facts about
the worldwide distribution of disease and the strategies for treating
those afflicted.
II
In the poorest nations, many people die prematurely from the diseases
we have mentioned. Before we think about possibilities for new tech-
nologies, it is worth asking if we could make better use of the knowledge
already available. Many nations use existing biomedical techniques to
provide effective control of tuberculosis and similar diseases. But most
of the countries where malaria, tuberculosis, respiratory infections, diar-
rhea, parasitic infestations, and so forth are rampant owe their trouble
not to the lack of twenty-first century medical technology but to the
absence of late nineteenth century sanitation. For example, one of the
most historically successful strategies for malaria control is to eliminate
stagnant water sources where mosquitoes breed. Even with emerging
malarial resistance to drugs, it is certain that the burden of the disease
could be greatly reduced by drainage projects combined with a more
pervasive and effective system of public health in the affected countries.
Tuberculosis is a similar case. Inconsistent use of antibiotics has
contributed to the spread of drug-resistant tuberculosis, but even most
resistant strains can be beaten by a public health system that applies
existing therapies quickly and thoroughly. As matters stand, millions of
tuberculosis (TB) patients receive incomplete courses of drugs, bringing
temporary respite at the cost of giving the TB bacillus an opportunity to
evolve antibiotic resistance.3 If well-funded, trained clinicians reached
. The classic example is Russia after the collapse of the Soviet system, where
overcrowded prisons provided the tuberculosis bacillus with extraordinary new ecological
possibilities. See Laurie Garrett, Betrayal of Trust (New York: Oxford University Press, ),
p. .
38 Philosophy & Public Affairs
all these patients, the emergence of resistance could be slowed and the
vast majority of tuberculosis deaths prevented without a single new
technological idea.
It is immediately obvious, however, that making existing technologies
more broadly accessible is far from simple. In malaria, Africa has a pro-
found source of suffering that could be greatly relieved with clinical care
that employs only procedures that are routine elsewhere (the courses of
antibiotics that are administered in affluent countries); in tuberculosis,
the Russian federation faces the same situation. But the infrastructure
needed to supply that care no longer exists in the regions in question;
neither does the funding nor political will to build it.4 For outsiders to
replace this infrastructurebuilding clinics, training physicians and
nurses, supplying policy, and doing all of this for an indefinite period of
timeamounts to taking responsibility for the public health of the
nations involved. Such intervention may be an enormously valuable
undertaking, but it is also very expensive and politically delicate. Devel-
oping new ways to fight tuberculosis is a difficult scientific problem, but
rebuilding the former USSRs tuberculosis control programs may be an
even harder political one.
It would thus be an error to think that, simply because a strategy for
combating a disease is available in a particular, privileged, region of the
world, medical research on alternative strategies is pointless. When the
task of exporting the technology to other contexts is beset with large
socio-political obstacles, the best means of bringing relief may be to find
treatment better adapted to those contexts. Thus, when we consider
biomedical research, well want to consider two sorts of goals: most obvi-
ously, ways of addressing diseases for which no treatment is available
anywhere, but also new methods for fighting diseases for which the only
available therapies cannot be exported to the contexts in which many of
the afflicted find themselves. In other words, one cant simply declare that
. Ibid. These causes of death may not rate the most intense research attention either
because they already have good low-tech solutions (e.g., oral rehydration therapy works
for some diarrheas) or because they cluster many different diseases, each taking a rela-
tively small toll. Thus the marginal rate of return for them may not be as high as it is for a
single major killer, such as malaria or tuberculosis. Interestingly, the second objection
applies to cancer research.
. Full Report: World Health Report .
. Christopher Dye et al., Global Burden of Tuberculosis, Journal of the American
Medical Association (): .
. Report of the Ad Hoc Committee on Health Research Relating to Future Inter-
vention Options (Geneva: World Health Organization).
41 Global Health and the Scientific
Research Agenda
. If our conjecture here is incorrect, then the right strategy might be to increase the
total amount of support given to biomedical research to allow both for the retention of the
advantages of present approaches to affluent-world diseases, and for the additional ben-
efits of attention to the diseases that afflict poor nations. We would also note that some
fundingand its hard to estimate just how muchgoes to develop lifestyle drugs, sub-
stances meant to alter the users body in ways not intended to cure disease. Attempts to
overcome impotence, halt hair loss, reduce obesity, and remove wrinkles attract hundreds
of millions of research dollars each year. These problems are trivial in comparison with the
suffering wreaked by the deadly diseases of the poor world. (See Ken Silverstein, Millions
for Viagra, Pennies for the Poor, The Nation, July , , pp. .) Since our primary
concern in this article will be with public funding of science, rather than with biophar-
maceutical research, we shall not press this point.
42 Philosophy & Public Affairs
. See Philip Kitcher, The Lives to Come: The Genetic Revolution and Human Possibil-
ities (New York: Simon & Schuster, ). Our view is that the chances are actually signifi-
cantly higher from the pathogen sequencing/vaccine development project than from the
standard ways of applying information from the Human Genome Project.
44 Philosophy & Public Affairs
ten years away.17 This is probably optimistic. Without more funding, its
likely that promising leads wont be explored, so that the ten years will
balloon into twenty or more. In the case of tuberculosis, vaccine research
is hardly off the ground. Because of the high expense of treating the
disease, and its propensity to become drug resistant, a tuberculosis
vaccine is particularly desirable. But tuberculosis vaccine research
receives even less funding than malaria vaccine research, and vaccine
development has lagged accordingly. No new tuberculosis vaccines are
in clinical trials today.18 Thanks largely to the recent sequencing of the
TB bacillus genome, promising new avenues for research are open, but
the research is only in the earliest stages, and the funding needed to
carry it out with a serious chance of success isnt yet available. Indeed,
at current levels of funding, a vaccine may never be developed.
Weve tried to defuse one line of objection, one that stresses the need
to take research promise into account in the apportionment of funding.
We now turn to the second, which charges that weve operated with too
crude a measure of suffering by concentrating on numbers of deaths. It
would be correct to note the possibility that some diseases inflict more
suffering for a given mortality rate than do others: a disease that kills
some number of people late in life may cause much less suffering than
one that kills the same number of people but strikes earlier and inflicts
long periods of disability in many nonfatal cases. Extensive work has
been done, largely by the World Health Organization, so that these con-
siderations can figure in a more nuanced calculation of the burden of
disease.
Instead of simply assuming that mortality rates correspond directly to
the amount of suffering, the most common practice has been to intro-
duce a unit known as the DALY (Disability-Adjusted-Life-Year). The fun-
damental idea is that we should look for the number of years of life lost
because of the disease. Life is lost not simply through early mortality but
also through the discounted value of years of life lived with disability,
where the discounting is based on widely shared views about the value
one would attribute to a future year of ones life in the diseased state as
. Quest for Malaria Vaccine Revs Up, But Much Work Remains, Bulletin of the WHO
(): .
. Theres an old vaccine, BCG, that has been in use for over seventy years. It can
provide children with some protection against some strains. For the most prevalent form
of tuberculosis, adult pulmonary tuberculosis, its quite useless.
45 Global Health and the Scientific
Research Agenda
the total burden may be higher in that nations with endemic malaria
have economic growth slowed by . percent per year, suggesting that the
economy of Africa might be larger by a third had malaria been wiped out
two decades ago.23 Effective technology for eliminating malaria in Africa
might thus serve as a basis for ameliorating other forms of suffering.
Plainly, if such socio-economic considerations were incorporated into a
refined conception of a diseases fair share, they would only increase the
gap that divides fair share from actual expenditure.
Before we consider the possibility that the misalignment grounds an
obligation to change the ways that research is funded in the affluent
world (which is, after all, where research happens), well close this
section with a quick look at the ways that resources are actually divided.
The funding for science that comes out of biopharmaceutical business
roughly matches the funding provided by government. Each of the ten
largest drug companies has, in theory, the capacity to direct in excess of
a billion dollars a year to any biomedical research problem.24 In total, the
annual research and development expenditure of the international
pharmaceutical community is estimated at $ billion. Each year, the
lions share of drug companies resources is directed toward the most
profitable projects they can find, and the resulting research agenda is
dramatically imbalanced. Drug companies aspire to revenues of around
a billion dollars a year for a single drug. In the case of tuberculosis, for
example, theres no wealthy market for any new drug, so the profits are
unavailable, and its hardly surprising that there are no such drugs in the
pipeline of any major company. Over twelve hundred new drugs were
developed between and , but only thirteen were aimed specifi-
cally at tropical diseases.25
Plainly, the market imposes constraints on drug research; even in a
merciless market, however, some corporate idealism is possible. Merck
maintains a vaccine division (the only one in the major drug companies)
despite its lower profitability relative to other projects. In response to
political pressure, Merck also has also invested modest resources in
adapting a veterinary drug, Ivermectin, for combating a form of river
blindnesswhich infects million people in the world today and has
. It should also be noted that the NIHs budget is currently growing at a rate enor-
mously in advance of inflation; in it will have doubled in five years, from $ to $
billion. Thus an increase to a half-billion dollars each in the annual funding for the malar-
ial and tuberculosis vaccine projects would do no more than slightly slow the rate of growth
of research into chronic diseases.
. Ruth E. Brown, Bess Miller, William R. Taylor, Cynthia Palmer, Lynn Bosco, Ray M.
Nicola, Jerry Zelinger, and Kit Simpson, Health Care Expenditures for Tuberculosis in the
United States, Archive for Internal Medicine (): .
. Garrett, Betrayal of Trust, p. .
. See Garrett, The Coming Plague.
50 Philosophy & Public Affairs
III
There are familiar arguments to the effect that we should do something
about the situation just reviewed, arguments that make the imperative
moral rather than merely a counsel of prudence. From a straightforward
utilitarian perspective its not hard to argue that frivolous expenditure by
affluent people should be redirected toward the alleviation of human
misery, and, in the same way, one can indict the investment in research
into new lifestyle drugs or the current neglect of many diseases.33 Even
without commitment to utilitarianism, or any form of consequentialism,
its hard to resist the conclusion that the imbalance of effort represented
by the / gap imposes some form of obligation to change how global
health is pursued.34 The amount of suffering that lies behind the recita-
tion of facts in Section IIcondensed and sparse though our review is
calls out for a response, and one cannot simply dismiss the burden of
disease as distant or no concern of ours.35 If pleas for attention to global
health (or global hunger) are met with apathy, that is surely the result of
a sense that the case is hopeless; that no matter what we might do, the
problem wouldnt be solved or even significantly alleviated.36
In our judgment, the sense of hopelessness arises from the conclu-
sions that are typically drawn from the moral exhortations: although
its correct to think that the skewed distribution of the worlds disease
burden requires somebody to do something, we think its important to
think broadly about what which individuals (or institutions) should do.
The standard arguments focus on ordinary citizens of affluent nations
and on possibilities for giving aid to distant people who are afflicted with
. The arguments are made with great force by Peter Singer, Famine, Affluence, and
Morality, Philosophy & Public Affairs, (): ; Peter Unger, Living High and
Letting Die (New York: Oxford University Press, ).
. Thus we wont try to offer a moral theory to buttress the claim that we have a prima
facie obligation to respond to the plight of afflicted people in poor countries, because we
dont see any plausible moral theory that fails to endorse any such obligation. The real
issue, we maintain, is whether the size and severity of the challenge undercuts the view
that what appears to be obligatory is genuinely demanded of us.
. Unger, Living High, makes the case against evasion on such grounds, and does so
with enormous thoroughness and clarity.
. Unger, Living High, refers to this as futility thinking, and we agree with him both
that such thinking lies behind the evasion of moral responsibility and that it is fallacious.
As well explain in the text, we think that the fallacy is a bit more complicated than Unger
takes it to be.
51 Global Health and the Scientific
Research Agenda
. See Unger, Living High; Singer, Famine, Affluence, and Morality, uses similar
examples.
. This might be called the Malthusian Response, after the author of the Essay on
Population, with its attempt to vindicate the gospel dictum that the poor will always be
with us. The name is useful, because the standard diagnosis of Malthuss mistake views
him as overlooking the possibility that technological developments can disrupt his alge-
braic assumptions, but it also has misleading connotations, and so weve used the less spe-
cific skeptical response.
52 Philosophy & Public Affairs
rehydration today because she has had diarrhea from drinking contam-
inated water, but she will continue to live in a place where the water
supply is always untrustworthy, where the chances for many forms of
parasitic infestation are high, where malaria and tuberculosis are
endemic, where there is no chance for education, where women are
treated like commodities, where there are interminable tribal squabbles
that flare into hostility, and so on and so forth. Oral rehydration today
is a band-aid in that it fails to remove any of the many causes of her
continuing distress. Thus, it isnt the case that, all by itself, the action of
giving will genuinely reclaim the lives of those toward whom the aid is
directed.
One might dispute the point, arguing that the assessment that the
child saved today will be vulnerable tomorrow is unduly pessimistic.39
Yet the skeptic will remind us of the full range of the suffering reviewed
briefly in Section II. Every month, a million children suffer and die of the
same conditions we have attempted to alleviate, and for this vast major-
ity the world remains unchanged. To all appearances, when we and the
few children we have saved are gone, this tide of mortality will still roll
in unabated. Anybody studying it will see our efforts as a gesture, a tiny
island of generosity, not a solution.
Once we are aware of this point, we can appreciate a second skepti-
cal concern. To recognize the obligation to give now would produce a
situation so little different from the initial state that we would have an
equally pressing obligation to go on giving. The skeptic invites us to con-
sider two possible futures, the Status Quo and the Bleak World. In the
Status Quo, children in poor nations suffer and die somewhat earlier
than they do in the Bleak World; in the Bleak World their lives are pro-
longed, thanks to generous responses from affluent people. In the Bleak
World the entire population of the affluent world does what is viewed as
their obligationthey give and they keep givingbut the scale is so large
that the donors find themselves committed to a policy that withdraws
funds from many, indeed most, of the enterprises that give pleasure to
people in the affluent world: opera houses and theaters close, sports
tournaments are cancelled, ancient monuments are allowed to decay,
. Unger (Living High, pp. ) suggests that affordable contributions would give
a child in a poor country a percent chance of reaching the age of , so he would
presumably make the charge of pessimism. The skeptic might respond that the success
criterion that Unger uses is still too weak.
53 Global Health and the Scientific
Research Agenda
. Here the skeptic appeals to the kinds of considerations that lead Derek Parfit to
identify the claim that a world in which billions live lives that are just worth living is prefer-
able to a world in which a much smaller population enjoys lives that are full and rich as
the Repugnant Conclusion (Reasons and Persons, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ,
part IV). One of us has argued elsewhere that the problem posed by Parfit is insoluble; see
Philip Kitcher, Parfits Puzzle, Nos, (): . The upshot of that analysis is that
we ought to adopt a multidimensional approach to human well-being.
. Perhaps they would not be as dire as the skeptic believes. Surely (one might think)
if everyone in the affluent world gives to help the afflicted, the costs will be spread suffi-
ciently thinly that much of the quality of life can be sustained. We wont try to resolve this
issue because we believe that a purely reactive approach, even if effective, is not the best
way to address the problem.
54 Philosophy & Public Affairs
. We wont try to set this up formally, but there are obvious similarities with both the
Prisoners Dilemma and the Tragedy of the Commons. A principal difference, of course, is
that the payoffs represent the values that a reflective, altruistic, moral agent would assign:
according to these payoffs, Dont Contribute is superior to Contribute no matter which
course of action the others pursue.
55 Global Health and the Scientific
Research Agenda
IV
The skeptical trap is to frame debate by envisaging a line of worlds
ranging from the Status Quo to the Bleak World: the worlds are distin-
guished by the amount of money affluent people send to provide such
things as food, oral rehydration therapy, the drugs made available by past
research, and what we can expect by continuing with the same research
agenda. Well leave it to others to combat skepticism by claiming that the
scale along the line is wrong, or that even if its right, we have some oblig-
ation to head along the line that the skeptic draws. Our strategy is to get
off the line. As we noted in Section II, the creation and maintenance of
public health infrastructure could substitute efficient preventative mea-
sures for recurrent reactive treatments. Further, if the scientific research
agenda were modified (specifically, if far more resources were commit-
ted to studying the diseases that afflict people in poor nations) then we
might obtain systematic ways of eliminating major causes of suffering,
or at least diminishing their power.43 The social change we need to see
is the extension of successful public health infrastructure and practices
to parts of the world that lack them; the technological change is the cre-
ation of effective drugs and vaccines that can stop third world diseases
in third world conditions.
In our judgment, people in affluent countries have at least three dif-
ferent types of obligations. First, were obliged to provide relief for those
. In effect, were responding to skepticism in just the way that the historical Malthus
has been answered: we propose that seemingly inevitable human suffering can be evaded
by social and technological change.
56 Philosophy & Public Affairs
V
There is a tendency to think of the obligations of scientists as very
simple; to view science as a private pursuit, driven by the love of truth.
To be sure, virtually everyone would concede that in seeking the truth
about aspects of nature, there are certain kinds of things that cant
be done: human subjects shouldnt be treated as mere means to the
58 Philosophy & Public Affairs
. Two well-known examples of cases in which this moral requirement was violated
are the Tuskegee study of syphilis (in which Black patients were left untreated and igno-
rant of their condition) and the grotesque experiments of some Nazi doctors.
. Of course, the line between the university research laboratory and the marketplace
is becoming increasingly blurry. For reasons that will become obvious from our discussion,
we take this to be a matter of considerable concern; see also Philip Kitcher, Science, Truth,
and Democracy (New York: Oxford University Press, ).
. Here, and in what follows, weve been influenced by Michael Hardimons revival of
role obligations; see his Role Obligations, Journal of Philosophy (): .
59 Global Health and the Scientific
Research Agenda
Our defense of the claim that a narrower conception of the set of view-
points represented is morally mistaken will be relatively brief. Its a
matter of historical accident that some people live in societies with the
resources to commit to scientific research, and, we suggest, no ideal for
the direction of scientific inquiry should reflect such accidents. Its easy
to extend a familiar Rawlsian thought experiment and to imagine our-
selves choosing an ideal for the conduct of science without yet knowing
whether we shall find ourselves in one of the societies lucky enough
to support research; as we understand that thought experiment, the
obvious decision is to include the perspectives of all in the framing of
well-ordered science. Further, if, as we believe, the principal opposition
to responding to human needs, even when they are distant, is that such
responses are inevitably futile, then no such counterargument is avail-
able when the envisaged responses feature the development of the
sciences. The institution of science fulfills a valuable social function
because scientific knowledge brings us both intellectual and practical
goods, and societies invest in and support the institution largely because
they believe in the efficacy of research to address practical problems.51
Neither the claim that scientific inquiry is futile nor that it can only
address the needs of a restricted group of people has the least plausibil-
ity. Any narrowing of the class of viewpoints represented in well-ordered
science thus reflects not hard-headed realism but a callous neglect of
those who are poor and distant.
Having outlined and briefly defended an ideal, we now consider what
obligations flow from it. Taking on the role of a scientist brings with it
the responsibility of contributing to well-ordered science. That respon-
sibility doesnt necessarily preclude the possibility of addressing issues
that have purely theoretical significance, of attempting to satisfy human
curiosity. Yet it would be a travesty of well-ordered science to propose
that only two kinds of inquiries be pursued: those that attempt to satisfy
disinterested curiosity and those that seek to meet the practical needs of
citizens of affluent nations. Hence, in the presence of the / gap,
theres ample reason to think that scientific research is not promoting its
proper goal. In consequence, scientists have an obligation to do what
they can to remedy the situation.
. For further development of this theme about the function of scientific research, see
Philip Kitcher, The Scientists Role (John Wesley Powell Lecture, ).
61 Global Health and the Scientific
Research Agenda
For some scientists, of course, theres little that can be done directly;
they work in fields that are too remote from those that bear on the
neglected issues. Biomedical researchers, however, can often do much
more. Some have the option of pursuing inquiries that might have
value in relieving arthritic symptoms or of working on some model
organism that might be useful in studying infectious disease. By taking
the latter course, they can move the research community closer to a state
of well-ordered science. In our judgment, they have the obligation to
do so.
Further, all scientists have an obligation to engage in political
activism, to campaign publicly for greater investment in research that
would address the disease burden of the poorer regions of the world. But
the capacity of ordinary scientists to bring about much change is prob-
ably limited; they are typically inclined and trained to discover facts, not
influence political opinion. The administrators who control the flow of
cash to science play on a more public stage. We turn next to their
responsibilities.
Several different types of organizations fund enough research sub-
stantially to affect science policy. Governments of rich nations are obvi-
ously important, although we think it more useful to consider these as a
few different, semiautonomous institutionsin the United States, for
example, we might list the NIH, the NSF, and the complex of national
laboratories. A second type consists of the biopharmaceutical industry,
considered either as a bloc or as individual companies. Independent
foundations like the Wellcome Trust and the Gates Foundation make up
a third. The university research system is a fourth, although once one
considers the sources of funding it becomes clear that university labo-
ratories cant operate independently of the government institutions and
a few foundations. Were going to concentrate on the American research
effort, and well reduce the four categories to two: the first is the gov-
ernment, primarily in the form of the NIH and the university labs it
funds; the second is the biopharmaceutical industry.
If, as weve claimed, the / gap represents a departure from
well-ordered science, then while we may view scientists as having been
insufficiently vocal in protesting, the root of the trouble seems to be the
research priorities set by the NIH and the biopharmaceutical companies.
Well deal with the two sources of funding separately, beginning with the
case of publicly funded science.
62 Philosophy & Public Affairs
As noted in Section II, the priorities of the NIH budget are badly
misaligned with the global burden of disease. In light of the promise
of technological solutions to problems that cause massive human
sufferingsuch as pathogen sequencing, with consequent attempts to
construct vaccinesNIH administrators have a moral obligation to do
what they can, within the budgetary constraints imposed, to modify the
current grossly skewed distribution; since the constraints make it impos-
sible even to approximate a distribution that would make research on a
disease comparable to the toll exacted by that disease, they have the
broader responsibility to protest the legislative guidelines. By the same
token, legislators ought to repeal the existing constraints in ways that
would make it possible to move much closer to well-ordered science.
Citizens have the obligation not only to write their individual checks,
but also to support these legislative changes.
How might these claims about moral responsibility be evaded? If we
are right in claiming that the principal source of resistance to the origi-
nal arguments enjoining individual contributions to disease relief lies in
the sense that such contributions are futile, then the crucial issue is
whether our revised moral imperative faces a similar skeptical response.
Skeptics can certainly point out that changing the research agenda isnt
guaranteed to bring success, either in addressing any particular disease
or in creating a climate in which public health interventions would be
welcomed. But, of course, we typically lack guarantees when we invest
in biomedical research, and, as we noted in Section II, theres good
reason to anticipate results from an ambitious vaccine development
project. If the calculated risk of investing in research pays off, the scale
of the potential reward is inspiring. For example, AIDS, tuberculosis, and
malaria are each single causes of a million or more deaths a year, along
with considerable related suffering. If we can develop and distribute an
effective vaccine for just one of these diseases, the gain to human well-
being is hard to express adequately. Since our hope here is to eradicate
or completely control the disease, the skeptics worry that were com-
mitted to an indefinite sequence of draining contributions is no longer
germane. Since the costs of such vaccine research are low on a global
scale, and returns to world security and the world economy great, we
need not worry that it will drive us toward the Bleak World or make us
do poorly by our commitments. Continued AIDS vaccine research and
credible attempts at malaria and tuberculosis vaccines are the least futile
of enterprises.
63 Global Health and the Scientific
Research Agenda
. For a more detailed account of how levels of funding might be set under well-
ordered science, see Kitcher, Science, Truth, and Democracy, ch. . We note that the level
we envisage here seems not to be vulnerable to the skeptical concerns about the sacrifice
of many things that are valued in the affluent world.
. Given our account of the roles of citizens, of legislators, and of NIH administrators,
its relatively easy to see that any worries about the potential collective action problem are
forestalled; in effect, were envisaging a classical solution to the difficulties of coordina-
tionto wit, the use of government as a coordinating mechanism.
64 Philosophy & Public Affairs
. See Wealth of Nations, books and . The cluster of issues about the proper sphere
of governmental provision continues to occupy political economy after Smith; see, for
example, J. S. Mills Principles of Political Economy.
. One intriguing possibility, suggested to us by the Editors of Philosophy & Public
Affairs, is that scientists form nonprofit organizations in which to pursue biomedical
research. This seems to us an option well worth exploring.
65 Global Health and the Scientific
Research Agenda