The Executive Power To Pardon: Discourse Dilemmas of The Constitutional
The Executive Power To Pardon: Discourse Dilemmas of The Constitutional
The Executive Power To Pardon: Discourse Dilemmas of The Constitutional
The discretionary power to pardon finds recognition in the Indian Constitution, which
confers this power on the President of India and the Governors of States. This article traces
the boundaries of the power stipulated under the Indian Constitution, as well as the
jurisprudence developed by the Supreme Court of India.
It commences with an enquiry into the rationale underlying the power to pardon and goes on
to engage with a number of issues that the power to pardon has given rise to. One of the
issues examined in the article is the doctrine of separation of powers in the context of the
prerogative to grant pardon. The constant tussle between the executive and judicial branches
of the State is discussed with special reference to the dilemmas posed by the issue of defining
the extent of this executive power.
I. INTRODUCTION
An important function of the President and the Governors of States under the Constitution is
the power to pardon. This paper seeks to delve into a study of this power by examining some
of the problematic issues that it poses. For the purpose of convenience, the paper has been
divided into seven parts. Section I of the paper deals with the background of the power to
pardon, by discussing the historical origins of the power and the various purposes sought to
be achieved through an exercise of the power. Section II analyzes the manner in which the
Constitution of India provides for this power. Section III pertains to the importance of the
advice of the Council of Ministers with regard to the pardoning power and suggests that such
advice should not be considered binding on the President or Governor. Section IV examines
the areas where the executive power to pardon could potentially interfere with the legislative
and judicial branches of the government, thereby upsetting the theory of separation of
powers. Section V attempts to ascertain the extent of the discretionary power to pardon.
Section VI highlights the importance of a review mechanism of the pardoning power. Lastly,
Section VII discusses the power to pardon in the practical context by providing a critique of
the Mohammad Afzal Guru case.
II. EXAMINING THE BACKGROUND OF THE POWER TO PARDON
The power to pardon, as it exists in the Constitution, must be examined in light of the
historical evolution of the concept of pardon, and the purpose sought to be achieved by
vesting such a power in the executive branch of the State. This section of the paper seeks to
delve into a conceptual understanding of the notion of pardon, or clemency, as it is very often
referred to.
Another ancient practice analogous to the power of pardon existed in ancient Rome, where
instead of executing an entire army of transgressors, the Romans would execute every tenth
condemned troop member.2 The reasons for carrying out such a practice appear to be largely
political, and hence, it is more difficult to draw parallels from this practice to the
contemporary practice since it is not clear whether mercy was the intended motive. However,
the effect of such an act seems to be similar to the effect of pardoning accused individuals in
present times: although an individual is found guilty and sentenced to a punishment, the
actual execution of the punishment does not take place.
Notwithstanding the possible analogies that may be drawn to the aforementioned ancient
practices of pardoning accused individuals, the concept of pardon as enshrined in the Indian
Constitution can most realistically be said to be derived from the British tradition of granting
mercy. Granting mercy has historically been the personal prerogative of the Crown, exercised
by the monarch on the basis of advice from the Secretary of State for the Home Department.3
This practice is based on the understanding that the sovereign possesses the divine right and
hence, can exercise this prerogative on the ground of divine benevolence.4 While under the
1 R. Nida and R. L. Spiro, The President as His Own Judge and Jury: A Legal Analysis of the
Presidents Self-Pardon Power, 52 OKLA. L. REV. 197 (1999).
2 Id.
3 B. V. Harris, Judicial Review of the Prerogative of Mercy, PUBLIC LAW 386 (1991).
4 G. B. Wolfe, I Beg Your Pardon: A Call for Renewal of Executive Clemency and Accountability
in Massachusetts, 27 B.C. THIRD WORLD L.J. 417 (2007).
British system, the monarch is the Head of the State, under the Indian Constitution, it is the
President who is deemed to be the Head of the State, which would explain the reason why the
power to grant pardon has been vested in him, along with the Governors of States, who act in
a manner similar to the President at the level of the states.
The English concept of pardon was also borrowed by the U.S. Constitution which, under
Section 2, Clause 1, placed the power to pardon in the President of the United States.5 The
United States Supreme Court has clarified on more than one occasion that the term pardon
should be given the same meaning under the United States Constitution as was given to it in
England.6
There are many views regarding the rationale behind granting pardon to accused individuals.
The Hegelian view advocates that pardons are justified only when they are justice-
enhancing, that is, in certain cases justice may not be served without the grant of pardon due
to the unduly harsh nature of the sentence or due to an individual being sentenced wrongly.7
As per this view, the grant of pardon in cases where a larger goal of justice is not sought to be
achieved would be unwarranted. The Hegelian view may be linked to the larger philosophy
of retribution: the retributivist school of thought believes that pardon is only justifie as an
extra-judicial corrective measure to remedy any failure of the system, such that the ultimate
aim of the accused receiving just deserts may be secured. The philosophy of retributivism
only concerns itself with the goal of enhancing justice and no further.8
In contrast to the retributivist view is the school of thought based on rehabilitation and
redemption, which believes that pardons may be justified even when the goal is justice-
neutral, that is, not necessarily concerned with the aim of securing remedial justice.9 For
example, the redemptive philosophy gives importance to the post-conviction achievements of
the accused, which the retributivists refuse to consider relevant. The redemptive school of
thought justifies pardon on the grounds of public welfare and compassion.10 It is argued that
the modern practice of granting pardons reflects a combination of both the abovementioned
13 Id.
14 Professor Upendra Baxis critique of the expression reasons of state would be discussed at a
later stage in the context of the extent of the pardoning power of the President and
Governor, in Section VI of this paper.
15 Satpal & Anr. v. State of Haryana, (2000) 5 SCC 170.
16 Supra note 1.
the state, this principle could translate into upholding the widespread views of the public
which has, directly or indirectly, chosen the head of the state as its representative.
The power of the executive wing of the State to grant pardons finds mention in the
Constitution of India in two forms: first, the power of the President to grant pardon under
Article 72 of the Constitution and second, the power of the Governor to grant pardon under
Article 161 of the Constitution. Before delving into a discussion of the myriad legal issues
that the exercise of the power to pardon presents, it would be useful to study the nature of this
power, as conveyed by a bare reading of the text of the Constitution of India. The power to
pardon covers the power to suspend, remit, and commute sentences. In the course of this
paper, the term pardon would be used as a general term, which would cover these modes of
reducing the sentence passed by the court.
Under Article 72(1) of the Constitution, the President is empowered to grant pardons,
reprieves, respites or remissions of punishment, or to suspend, remit or commute the sentence
of any individual who has been convicted of offences that are covered within the ambit of
clauses (a) to (c) of Article 72(1). The instances enumerated under Article 72(1) are: first,
cases where the punishment or sentence has been given by a Court Martial17 ; second, cases
where the punishment or sentence relates to an offence against any law concerning matters
that the power of the Union extends to18 ; and third, all cases where the sentence in question
is a sentence of death19 .
Article 72(1)(a) is qualified by Article 72(2), which states that the power conferred by law on
any officer of the Armed Forces for the purpose of suspending, remitting or commuting a
sentence passed by a Court Martial would not be affected by the power of the President
contained in Article 72(1)(a).20 Further, Article 72(3) expressly provides that the power of the
President to suspend, remit or commute sentence of death under Article 72(1)(c) would not
In addition to vesting the power of pardon in the President of India, the Constitution also
provides the Governor of a State the power to grant pardons; however, this power of the
Governor, dealt with under Article 161 of the Constitution, is narrower in scope than the
power of the President to grant pardons under Article 72. Article 161 of the Constitution
empowers the Governor to grant pardons, reprieves, respites or remissions of punishment, or
to suspend, remit or commute the sentence of any person who has been convicted of an
offence against any law that relates to a matter covered by the executive power of the State.22
A plain reading of the Constitution of India would, by itself, reveal that the nature of the
power of pardon granted to the President under Article 72 is far superior to the power of
pardon granted to the Governor under Article 161. Two points of comparison that may be
gauged from the explicit wording of Articles 72 and 161 might be stated in this regard: first,
the power of the President to grant pardon extends to the power of pardon to sentences
granted by a Court Martial, whereas there is no comparable power vested in the Governor of
any state; and second, the President is expressly granted the power to consider all cases
where the sentence of death has been granted.
At this juncture, it is important to observe that a combined reading of Articles 72 and 161
reveals that an area of overlap between the pardoning powers of the President and the
Governor that is, cases concerning matters to which the executive power of the Governor
extends and which have resulted in the sentence of death has been contemplated by the
framers of the Constitution. However, the Constitution ensures that the President is superior
to the Governor while granting pardons to individuals convicted for such cases. Article 72(3)
has the effect of allowing the Governor of a State to seize the mercy petition in respect of a
death sentence, but there is no bar to such a petition being presented to the President at
a later stage.
Hence, it merits mention that, although the power of the President to grant pardon extends
only to those cases that concern matters for which the Union Government has the power to
make laws, the practical effect of Article 72(1)(c) read with Article 72(3) is that the
pardoning power of the President has a much wider ambit and extends even to matters that
the State Government has the power to make laws in relation to, provided that cases
concerning such matters have resulted in the sentence of death.
It is not impossible to conceive of situations where a mercy petition against a sentence of
death, once rejected by the Governor of a State, finds its way to the President, and indeed the
Constitution does not express any intention to create a bar against such a situation. It follows
that the Constitution seeks to treat situations involving a death sentence on a higher pedestal
than all other kinds of sentences, such as life imprisonment or rigorous imprisonment. By
providing those condemned to death a recourse against the rejection of their mercy petition
by the Governor of their respective State, the Constitution places the President at the very top
of the constitutional scheme of pardons, indicating that the exercise of the discretion of the
President would be deemed to be more superior than that of the Governors of various States.
While the Constitutions implicit recognition of the importance of the right to life is
commendable, the creation of such a hierarchy has the obvious drawback of increasing the
time taken for the death sentence of a petitioner to achieve the utmost finality.
B. JUDICIAL PRECEDENT
Although a textual interpretation of the Constitution fails to convince that the framers of the
Constitution intended for the advice of the Council of Ministers to be binding on the
President and Governors while exercising their pardoning powers, the judicial interpretation
of the Constitution suggests an entirely different proposition. In Samsher Singh v. State of
Punjab,28 a seven-judge bench of the Supreme Court held that the satisfaction of the
President or the Governo required by the Constitution is not their personal satisfaction, but
As per the established practice, the power to grant pardon in Britain is exercised by the
reigning monarch in consultation with the Secretary of State for the Home Department.30 The
Supreme Court, in Maru Ram, laid emphasis on the British practice while arriving at its
conclusions regarding the Indian position. Krishna Iyer, J. stated: it is fundamental to the
Westminster system that the Cabinet rules and the Queen reigns.31 The British practice
appears to have been incorporated in India as well, where a Section Officer in the Ministry of
Home Affairs prepares a note, which moves up the hierarchy with varying degrees of
indifference or interest.32
An interpretation of the Constitution to the effect that the President and Governors are bound
to act as per the advice of the Council of Ministers while exercising their pardoning powers
may lead to situations of absurdity. For example, in the case of Kehar Singh,33 the accused in
relation to whom pardon was sought was the assassin of Ms. Indira Gandhi, a former Prime
Minister of India. In such a situation, the possibility of the advice of the Council of Ministers,
which comprised ministers from the same political party as the former Prime Minister,
suffering from bias or a lack of objectivity cannot be precluded. Further, in the era of
coalition governments, there is a chance that the advice given to the Council of Ministers
would not reflect a true, just, reasonable and impartial opinion,34 and would instead be
based wholly on political motivations.
In light of such possibilities, it is submitted that some leeway for the President to exercise the
power to pardon without being bound by the advice of the Council of Ministers, and without
bowing to political pressures, is absolutely necessary. Hence, I am of the opinion that the
decisions of the Supreme Court in this regard have been far from prudent.
E. THE SOLUTION
A study of the prevailing situation indicates that there is a need to find a reasonable solution
such that the exercise of the pardoning power is based on equitable, logically sound reasons,
and that the advice of the Council of Ministers is given effect to, wherever appropriate.
It has been recommended that there should be a constitutional amendment which expressly
vests the power to pardon in the President, such that he is under no obligation to act on the
aid and advice of the Council of Ministers.35 I find that such a view is flawed on two counts:
first, such an amendment to the Constitution would be virtually impossible to pass, since the
reigning party in the Parliament or State Legislature would be absolutely unwilling to divest
themselves of the power of aiding and advising the President or the Governor, respectively;
and second, regardless of the possibility of absurdity in certain cases, the reigning party is the
representative of the will of the people, and its advice must be given effect to as far as
possible, to uphold the public confidence. I submit that the solution to the foreseeable
problem described above may be found by way of the President or Governor exercising
his/her discretion in a self-determined manner. That is, the President/Governor should be
allowed to use his/her discretion to distinguish between situations where the advice of the
Council of Ministers is extremely important in light of the context of the case and the need to
give effect to certain policy decisions of the ruling party (for example, a strong stand against
terrorism), and those situations where giving effect to the advice tendered by the Council of
Ministers would be most obviously problematic and raise doubts as to the correctness of the
decision to grant or deny pardon.
In my opinion, there are two ways in which the Parliament and State Legislatures in India can
interfere with the President or Governor exercising their pardoning power: first, under Article
61 of the Constitution, the President may be impeached by the Parliament; and second, by
carrying out the function of enacting legislations, which may have a direct or incidental
impact on the carrying out of the discretionary power of granting pardons. The first measure
acts as a direct check on the President, and will be discussed subsequently in Section VI of
this paper.
As regards the second aspect, namely interference with the pardoning power by enacting
legislations, it was held in the United States decision of Ex parte Grossman36 that the
executive can reprieve or pardon all offences after their commission, either before trial,
during trial or after trial, by individuals, or by classes, conditionally or absolutely, and this
without modification or regulation by Congress. This indicates that the Legislature is not at
liberty to modify the decision of the President in relation to a pardon. In the Indian context, it
may be noted that the vesting of this power in the President and Governors, as opposed to
the Prime Minister or Legislatures, may have been deliberate, so as to prevent the grant of
pardon being made open to any sort of legislative debate. In addition to directly modifying
the decision of the President or Governor, the Legislature can also enact legislations, which
may be directly relevant to issues such as sentencing. The decision of the Constitution Bench
in Maru Ram v. Union of India,37 while discussing Section 433A of the Code of Criminal
In the context of the power to pardon, the possibility of conflict between the executive and
the judiciary is more apparent than that of the conflict between the executive and legislature.
This stems from the fact that the power of the President/ Governor to grant or deny pardon
may overlap, to some degree, with the power of the judiciary while pronouncing its
sentences. However, this friction has been sought to be minimized by those who argue that
the power of the executive and the judiciary exist in entirely different realms.
1. The exercise of investigative and adjudicative powers by the President/
Governor
The decision in Kehar Singh was extremely significant for expressly pronouncing that while
exercising the pardoning power, the President/Governor would have liberty to enter into the
merits of the decision passed by the court: it is open to the President in the exercise of the
power vested in him by Article 72 of the Constitution to scrutinise the evidence on the record
of the criminal case and come to a different conclusion from that recorded by the Court in
regard to the guilt of, and sentence imposed on the accused.40 It is not difficult to see why
such a ruling tests the concept of separation of powers, by allowing the executive to perform
the same function as the judiciary. As per one view, vesting investigative and adjudicative
powers in the President threatens the rule of law, particularly since the limits of exercising
these functions are determined by the President himself/herself.41
The Supreme Court in Kehar Singh qualified the pronouncement discussed above in Section
V(B)(1) by stating: The President does not amend or modify or supersede the judicial
record. The judicial record remains intact, and undisturbed. The President acts on a wholly
different plane from that on which the Court acted. He acts under a constitutional power, the
nature of which is entirely different from the judicial power and cannot be regarded as an
extension of it. And this is so notwithstanding that the practical effect of the Presidential act
is to remove the stigma of guilt from the accused or to remit the sentence imposed on him.42
A similar proposition was made in Sarat Chandra Rabha v. Khagendranath Nath,43 where
the Supreme Court distinguished between the practical effect and the legal effect of an order
of remission by the President/ Governor:
An order of remission thus does not in any way interfere with the order of the court; it
affects only the execution of the sentence passed by the court and frees the convicted person
from his liability to undergo the full term of imprisonment inflicted by the court, though the
order of conviction and sentence passed by the court still stands as it wasin law, the order
of remission merely means that the rest of the sentence need not be undergone, leaving the
order of conviction by the court and the sentence passed by it untouched. 44
44 Id.
45 K. M. Nanavati v. State of Bombay, AIR 1961 SC 112.
46 H. M. SEERVAI, CONSTITUTIONAL LAW OF INDIA: A CRITICAL COMMENTARY, VOLUME II 2104 (2004).
In the opinion of Seervai, the Supreme Courts decision in Sarat Chandra Rabha deprived
the decision of the Court in K. M. Nanavati,45 a case decided by the Court earlier in the same
year, of its binding value.46 In the case of Nanavati, the Supreme Court had stated that the
judicial power of the Supreme Court under Article 142 of the Constitution, whereby it can
make orders for doing complete justice and the executive power contained in Article 161
could be exercised in the same field within certain narrow limits. The Court had suggested a
harmonious interpretation of the two provisions of the Constitution.47 Seervai cautions
against the misapplication of the principle of harmonious construction, such that disharmony
is created between two constitutional provisions where such disharmony does not exist in the
first place.48
Another argument that is made to distinguish between the powers of courts and the executive
power to grant pardon is that while the former is concerned with the legal rights of an
individual, the latter is concerned with compassionate grounds for relieving the individual of
the punishment imposed on him/her. In the words of Lord Diplock: Mercy is not the subject
of legal rights. It begins wher legal rights end.49 While making decisions, the judiciary
considers the legal grounds for imposing punishments and is not at liberty to make
pronouncement on the basis of compassion. It is said that through its exercise of the power to
pardon, the executive performs the function of neutralising the insufficiently compassionate
judgments of the judiciary.50 This principle has been recognized in India in Mohinder Singh
v. State of Punjab.51
It is submitted that the power of the judiciary to make decisions regarding the guilt of an
accused and the appropriate sentence in each case may be said to be more limited than the
power to decide the acceptance or rejection of a mercy petition for two reasons. First, it may
not be possible for the judiciary to take into account certain factors that can be considered
only after the sentence of the convict has begun, such as the post conviction behaviour and
contributions made by the convict. The Supreme Court has recognised that this is an
important consideration and should be given due importance by the President/Governor
while making a decision on whether pardon should be granted.52 Second, the decision to grant
pardon may be based on certain reasons that may not be appropriate for the court to consider
while sentencing an individual. It has come to be accepted that decisions granting or
declining pardon contain a certain policy element. Courts may not be the most appropriate
forum for giving effect to such policy decisions, since they are concerned only with
ascertaining the guilt or innocence of the accused. Further, it is pointed out that courts may be
logistically handicapped to decide cases on the basis of policy considerations: policy
decisions often require access to empirical information and the benefit of the views of a wide
range of people, neither of which may be available through the judicial process.53
It must be noted that the executive and judiciary give due regard to the principle of comity
between the branches of government. That is, both branches have been willing to recognise
the limits of their realms of functioning and behave in a manner deferential to the other
branch of government, or assist the other branch of government in carrying out its functions.
In certain instances, the Supreme Court has declined to adjudicate on a petition brought
before it on the ground that the same matter has been seized by the President under his
pardoning power.54 The principle of comity has also been extended to cases where, for
example, two out of the three individuals who were accomplices in the same crime have been
granted commutation, whereas the third has been unsuccessful in this regard the Supreme
Court may recommend to the President that in the interests of equity, the punishment of the
third accomplice be commuted as well.55
53 Supra note 3.
54 Mohinder Singh v. State of Punjab, (1977) 3 SCC 346.
55 Harbans Singh v. State of Uttar Pradesh, AIR 1982 SC 849.
6. The issue of deterrence and the need for executive self-restraint
Lastly, it must be said if the power to pardon is exercised in an indiscriminate manner, then it
may undermine the precedental value of judicial decisions and upset the equilibrium that
should ideally exist between executive and judicial action. Unless the President and
Governors exercise a certain degree of self-restraint while making decisions under the pardon
to power, the use of this power could potentially destabilise the authoritativeness of decisions
made bythe judiciary, and have a negative impact on the deterrent effect sought through
such judgments. It is important that the President and Governors provide cogent
and convincing reasons while exercising their pardoning power.
That the nature of the power envisaged under Articles 72 and 161 of the Constitution is a
discretionary power may be established through a textual interpretation of these Articles. A
plain reading of these provisions shows that there is complete silence regarding the factors
which must be taken into account by the President and the Governor while exercising the
power to pardon. It is reasonable to assume that this silence was deliberate, since the power to
pardon has historically been in the nature of a prerogative.
The view that it is not desirable to fetter the power to pardon by imposing guidelines has been
endorsed in a number of decisions. The judiciary has been reluctant to impose guidelines on
the executive for exercising the power to pardon in most cases, with a few exceptions.56 In
Kuljit Singh v. Lt. Governor of Delhi,57 the Supreme Court expressed the view that the
56 See supra note 38, where the Supreme Court expressed the view that the executive should formulate its own guidelines for exercising the
power to pardon.
57 Kuljit Singh v. Lt. Governor of Delhi, (1982) 1 SCC 417.
58 Supra note 11.
59 Supra note 14, 504.
pardoning power of the President is a wholesome power that should be exercised as the
justice of a case may require, and that it would be undesirable to limit it by way of judicially
evolved constraints. In Kehar Singh,58 the Supreme Court stated that the power under Article
72 should be construed in the widest possible manner without the Court interfering to lay
down guidelines of any sort. However, the Court went on to state that the power to pardon
may be exercised to correct judicial errors, and for reasons of state. Even though such a
proposition appears to be extremely broad, providing ample scope to the President to exercise
his discretion, it has come under attack from Upendra Baxi, who is of the opinion that such a
statement would fetter the scope of the power in a manner not contemplated by the
Constitution: To extend to clemency power the logic of the doctrine of the reasons of state is
constitutionally perverse in the face of the fundamental right to life and liberty in Article 21.
The Constitution does not authorise a policy of death to traitors, insurgents, naxalites,
dacoits, terrorists in the exercise of the discretion inherently entailed in the clemency
power. Nor can the Constitution authorise such a pattern of exercise of that power. It has to
be exercised case by case, and under the discipline of Article 21.59
It is submitted that the view that fundamental rights act as sufficient guidelines for the
exercise of pardoning powers under the Indian Constitution is correct. To go beyond the most
fundamental prescriptions in the Constitution for circumscribing the power to pardon may
have the dangerous effect of unjustly curtailing the power of the President and the Governor,
which is not intended by the Constitution. Hence, the examination of the circumstances and
context of each case on its own merits represents the most appropriate approach while
exercising the pardoning power.
B. THE REPERCUSSIONS OF THE WIDE DISCRETION OF THE
PRESIDENT AND GOVERNOR
Having discussed the merits of an approach where pardoning power is decided in light of the
facts and circumstances of each case, and the undesirability of fettering the power by
prescribing guidelines, it must be said that certain exceptional instances may warrant a
mechanism of review of the exercise of power.
As stated above, the fundamental rights prescribed by the Constitution of India comprise the
basic minimum guidelines that the President and Governor must defer to, while exercising
their pardoning power. It follows that in instances where there is a failure to do this, the
aggrieved individual should have some remedy, whereby a violation of his fundamental
rights is recognised. To my mind, the situations where the fundamental rights of an individual
may be violated in the course of the President/Governor exercising the power to pardon may
be classified into two broad categories: first, the discretion of the President/Governor may be
exercised in an arbitrary manner at the time of decision-making, whether in terms of the
procedure employed or the substantive reasons given for accepting or rejecting the mercy
petition; and second, in the event that the pardon granted is conditional that is, the person
seeking pardon must fulfil certain conditions before the pardon becomes effective and the
condition imposed by the President/Governor is violative of fundamental rights.
In the absence of any well-defined guidelines for the exercise of the pardoning power, the
possibility of the President/Governor granting pardon to himself/herself cannot be precluded.
Undoubtedly, such a situation would be rare, and it is argued that any individual worthy of
holding a position as important as the position of a President should be vested with the power
to pardon.60 Although it is expected that the position of the President and those of Governors
of States, being such privileged positions, would be occupied by individuals who do not
possess a criminal record, there are two important facts that require to be noted: first, the
Constitution of India does not prescribe a bar on convicted or under-trial individuals
contesting the position of President/Governor; and second, neither Article 72 nor Article 161
prescribe a bar on the power of pardon being exercised in relation to the person exercising the
power. Although not expected in the ordinary course, the possibility of such a situation
arising cannot be excluded completely, and in such instances, it would be necessary for the
propriety of the decision of the President/Governor to be reviewed.
As discussed in Section VI above, there is a possibility that in certain instances, the decision
of the President/Governor under Articles 72 and 161 would require to be subjected to a
mechanism of review, in the interests of justice. This section of the paper discusses the
viability of various methods of checking the power of the executive, such that it is not
exercised in a capricious manner, and arrives at a conclusion regarding the most appropriate
mechanism.
A. PUBLIC ACCOUNTABILITY
There is a widespread belief that the political or electoral process acts as the perfect check on
the President while exercising the power to pardon.61 This view is based on the assumption
60 Supra note 1.
61 Supra note 41.
62 Id.
that the electorate keeps a check on the President by voting the President out of power when
the prerogative of pardon is exercised in an arbitrary manner. While this may be relevant for
holding the President accountable in countries such as the United States, where the President
is elected directly, in countries such as India, where the common masses directly elect the
members of Parliament and State Legislatures, and not the President/Governor, the relevance
of this measure for the purpose of holding the President and the Governor accountable is
significantly diminished. The political process can act as a check only as far as voting out
political parties who exercise an influence on the President in relation to the power to pardon
is concerned. Moreover, it has come to be accepted that allowing judicial review to
accompany existing political checks might yield more favourable results by facilitating
greater accountability.62
As per one school of thought, the impeachment of the President acts as a sufficient check
against the misuse of the pardoning power.63 The Constitution of India provides for the
impeachment of the President under Article 61 of the Constitution. It is submitted that in the
Indian context, impeachment cannot be said to exist as a sufficient check against the
pardoning power being exercised in an arbitrary manner. Three reasons may be furnished in
support of this argument.
First, the Constitution of India only provides for the impeachment of the President and does
not contain any provisions for dealing with the impeachment of Governors of States. Hence,
the process of impeachment is of limited value in relation to the power to pardon, which may
be exercised by the President and also by the Governors of States.
Second, the process of impeachment, as provided for under Article 61, is carried out by the
Members of Parliament. In the event that the Council of Ministers have advised the President
to render the unsatisfactory decision of granting or declining pardon, it would be unlikely that
the ruling party or coalition would be in favour of undertaking the measure of impeachment
against the President, since the Presidents decision would, in such an instance, be a
reflection of the decision of the Council of Ministers. Indeed, if in the situation envisaged
here, the Council of Ministers were to actively attempt to impeach the President, it would be
an utterly irresponsible act.
Third, in the event that there is a general dissatisfaction with the manner in which the
President has exercised his power under Article 72, one of the reasons for which could be that
the advice tendered by the Council of Ministers was rejected by the President, the Members
of Parliament can commence proceeding for impeaching the President. However, due to the
inherent nature of the requirements of Article 61, it may be extremely difficult for the
63 Id. See also M. Strasser, Some Reflections on the Presidents Pardon Power, 31 CAP. U. L. REV. (2003).
impeachment process to be successful. Since the President occupies such an important
position, stringent conditions have been imposed for his/her removal. As per Article 61(2),
the first step in the process of impeachment is the submission of a resolution to impeach
the President that must be signed by at least one-fourth of the total number of members of
the House seeking to impeach the President. It is to be noted that the resolution must be
signed by one-fourth of the total number of members of the House, as opposed to the number
of members present and voting in the House, which is the term used in relation to passing
Bills in a joint sitting of both Houses of Parliament. Similarly, after the charge(s) against the
President have been examined,64 and after the President has had an opportunity to appear
before such investigation, it is required that a resolution is passed by at least two-thirds of the
total membership of the House for the impeachment to be successful.65 Hence, the
impeachment of the President is not likely to be successful in the ordinary course, unless
there is a substantial degree of agreement between the members of the House of Parliament
initiating impeaching proceedings that the President should be impeached.
After discussing the limited viability of the political process and impeachment as potential
measures to prevent the arbitrary exercise of pardoning power by the President and Governor,
I would like to propose a model of judicial review wherein the judiciary would act in a
disciplined manner to lay down limits for itself, such that the principle of comity between the
judiciary and executive remains intact, but the exercise of the pardoning power in blatant
violation of the fundamental rights and principles of natural justice does not go unchecked.
1. Justiciability of the subject matter of pardon decisions of the President/ Governor The
appropriateness of judicial review of a particular subject matter is measured on the basis of
justiciability. Courts are said to have a constitutional obligation to uphold the rule of law by
enforcing the procedural rights in relation to executive decision-making.66 Being in the nature
of an executive power, the power to pardon may be said to be justiciable insofar as examining
the procedural propriety of decisions of pardon is concerned. The view that this executive
power should not be subject to judicial review merely since its in the nature of a prerogative
has been criticised by some as being merely a bald assertion.67 The model of judicial review
sought to be proposed by me is one that would operate on the basis of self-regulation by the
judiciary. It is a well-recognised principle of administrative law that judicial review may vary
in intensity based on the subject matter sought to be reviewed. It has been observed: It is
increasingly becoming common for courts to adopt a variable standard of review, the
intensity of which alters depending upon the subject matter of the action. Terms such as
irrationality and proportionality can be applied with differing degrees of rigour or intensity.
67 Supra note 3.
68 P. P. CRAIG, ADMINISTRATIVE LAW 552 (2003).
This feature has become more marked as the courts have shown a greater willingness to
protect individual rights, employing more intensive review in such instances.68
Hence, in cases involving judicial review, courts may choose to enter the domain of review
only insofar as procedural impropriety and the rights of individuals are concerned, and not on
the substantive merits of the decision made by the President/Governor. In the event that
courts were divested of the power to exercise this qualified power of review, individuals
suffering due to the arbitrary action of the President/Governor would have no remedy to
correct procedural wrongs and the injustice of their fundamental rights being violated.
As mentioned above, I seek to propose a model of judicial review whereby the judiciary
would act in a mature, disciplined manner by setting its own limits and respecting the
exercise of discretion by the President and Governors insofar as it does not border on
71 Id.
72 Supra note 11.
73 G. Krishta Goud v. State of Andhra Pradesh, (1976) 1 SCC 157.
74 Supra note 15.
One of the pending mercy petitions, which has been in the news in recent times is that of
Mohammed Afzal Guru, who was found guilty in the Parliament Attack case and sentenced
to death.75 He has been on the death row for three years, and the UPA Government has been
repeatedly delaying its decision on the petition.76 The Government has hinted that the reason
it has chosen not to take a decision yet is because the execution of Mohammad Afzal Guru
may lead to his attaining the status of a martyr, which may have an adverse impact on the
situation in Jammu and Kashmir.77 Such inaction on the part of the Government has been
criticized by the Bharatiya Janata Party, which feels that strong action must be taken against
acts of terrorism.78 The reluctance to take action may also be reflective of an intention to not
antagonize the Muslim electorate before the elections in 2009.
It is submitted that regardless of the manner in which the practice to grant pardons has
developed, whereby the political parties in power play a primary role in granting or rejecting
the mercy petition, the Constitution recognizes the President and Governor as the repositories
of the power to pardon. In the case of Mohammed Afzal Guru, it is the responsibility of the
President to act in a proactive manner, such that the prerogative of pardon is not allowed to
be made hostage to political pressures. Although the President is at liberty to base her opinion
for granting or rejecting the petition on the advice of the Council of Ministers, as has been
demonstrated through this paper, she should not be seen as being obliged to defer to the
advice of the Council of Ministers. Hence, in such a case, where there has been unreasonable
delay on the part of the Council of Ministers in arriving at a decision, the President should
make prudent use of her power to pardon and dispose of the petition in an expeditious
manner. In the event that the adverse impact on the public anticipated due to the execution of
Mohammed Afzal Guru outweighs the merits of executing him, the petition must be rejected
and reasons of public interest must be furnished for the same. However, the indefinite
deferral of a decision in the mercy petition has the undesirable impact of casting the
constitutional power to pardon in bad light.
IX.CONCLUSION
75 No Urgency to Dispose of Afzals Clemency Petition, Economic Times, June 11, 2008, available at
http://economictimes.indiatimes.com/News/PoliticsNation/No_urgency _to _dispose_
of_Afzals_clemency_petition/articleshow/3121228.cms (Last visited on June 29, 2008).
76 Government Doesnt Want Another Martyr, Hindustan Times, June 10, 2008, available at
http://www.hindustantimes.com/StoryPage/StoryPage.aspx?id=4cfa1ba0-536e-417e-acfb-
8ccc2b80c1be (Last visited on Sep 21, 2015).
A study of the power to pardon under the Constitution of India reveals that this power is
intended to be in the nature of a discretionary power, or a prerogative, a theme that runs
through the course of this paper. I have attempted to demonstrate reasons why the President
and Governors of State may need to exercise this power without being bound by the advice of
the Council of Ministers, as well as the undesirability of putting in place guidelines that
would fetter the discretion that should ideally be exercised upon an examination of the facts
and circumstances of each case. In a mature democracy, it is expected that the various
branches of the government would be reasonably capable of laying down limits for their own
jurisdiction. It is precisely this premise that my conclusions have been based on. I seek to
propose a model wherein the executive and judiciary operate through self-regulation, by
being deferential to the realms of each others powers. Through such a disciplined exercise of
their respective powers, justice would be ensured in the best possible manner. Any undue
interference by one branch in the functioning of the other would erode the authority of both
the branches. Both the executive and the judiciary must also aim at dealing with cases
pertaining to pardon in an expeditious manner, since the detrimental effects of an inordinate
delay in decision-making is clear from cases such as that of Mohammed Afzal Guru, which
have caused much controversy in recent times.