Fillmore - 1968 - The Case For Case
Fillmore - 1968 - The Case For Case
Fillmore - 1968 - The Case For Case
AL 000 413
The Case for Case
Charles J. Fillmore
The Ohio State University
are theories of, and partly because some linguists are willing to
and they are: (a) what are the formal and substantive universals
what are its properties? and (c) are there any universally valid
2
John Lyons, "Towards a 'notional' theory of the 'parts of speech',"
JOURNAL OF LINGUISTICS, 11(1966) 209-236; 211, 223.
each language draws from in its own way, and he has shown what
modification. 3
6
Tesniere 5 , and others. Lyons recommends leaving for empirical
6
Lyons (1966) 227.
crganized objects.
9
Joseph Greenberg, "Language universals," in T. A. Sebeok, ed.,
CURRENT TRENDS IN LINGUISTICS, III, Mouton (1966) 61-112.
111
10
Jakobson. If such studies can be interpreted as making empirical
10
Roman Jakobson, "Typological studies and their contribution to
historical comparative linguistics," in E. Sivertsen, ed.,
PROCEEDINGS OF THE VIIITH INTERNATIONAL CONGRESS OF LINGUISTS,
Oslo University Press (1958) 17-25.
tionships are missed in all these studies, and that what is needed
11
Notational difficulties make it impossible to introduce 'case'
as a true primitive as long as the phrase-structure model deter-
mines the form of the base rules. My claim is, then, that a
designated set of case categories is provided for every language,
with more or less specific syntactic, lexical and semantic conse-
quences, and that the attempt to restrict the notion of 'case' to
the surface structure must fail.
and 'direct object' are missing. The latter are regarded as proper
languages.
Two assumptions are essential to the development of the
more and then adding random observations on how these words show
up in larger constructions. 12
12
John R. Ross pointed out, during the symposium, that there exist
some syntactic processes which seem to depend on (and therefore
'follow') particular lexical realizations of just such entities as
the comparative forms of adjectives. Compared adjectives, in short,
may be iterated, just as long as they have all been given identical
surface realizations. Witness
(i) she became friendlier and friendlier
(ii) she became sore and more friendly
but not
(iii) *she became friendlier and more friendly
The second assumption I wish to make explicit is thee,
whose name is most directly associated with the doctrine that deep-
Alin
1
3Benjamin Lee Whorf, "A linguistic consideration of thinking in
primitive communities" (c. 1936), in J. B. Carroll, ed., LANGUAGE,
THOUGHT AND REALITY: SELECTED WRITINGS OF BENJAMIN LEE WHORF, MIT
Press (1965) 65-86; 69ff.
one, one which the grammar of English does not force us to deal with.
of a speaker of English.
the verb with do to, while 'Wu, affectum object does. Thus one might
relate sentence (1), but not sentence (a), to the question given
in (3).
1
This observation is due to Paul M. Postal.
question may be seen in sentence (6) but that only in one of the
tionships.
1. Earlier approaches to the study of case
long time asking the wrong kinds of questions when they attempted
Dative and an Accusative, because that was the pattern for Old
work has been directed toward the analysis of the case systems of
syntactic relations.
'X of where 010 is the name of a particular case and 'Y' is the
name for a particular 'use' of X. The reader will recall such terms
16
as 'Dative of Separation', 'Dative of possession', and so on.
Milli=111ENW
1
For an extensive description of this type, see Charles Bennett,
SYNTAX OF EARLY LATIN, II: THE CASES, Boston (1914) Pp. 409.
Apart from the fact that such studies do not start out from
of these studies were (a) that the Nominative was largely ignored
to limit the term only to the non-nominative cases. The most impor-
explaining that "Die beiden casus recta., der Nominativ and der
Vokativ, sind bei dem Streite fiber die Kasustheorie nicht beteiligt.
Im Nominativ steht das Subjekt, von dem der Satz etwas aussagt."17
he went so far as to claim that the nominative is the only case where
of exactly the same order and exhibit the same extent if variety
why the traditional studies of case uses fail to contain such classi-
19
A. Willem de Groot, "C1assification of uses of a case illustrated
on the genitive in Latin," LINGUA, VI (1956) 8-66.
twelve of the classical 'uses' into one, which he then labels the
20
de Groot (1956) 35.
1111111MP,
He ends by reducing the thirty traditional 'uses of the genitive'
21
to eight , of which two are rare enougit to be left out of consider-
2
From de Groot (1956) 30:
I. Adjunct to a noun
A. Proper genitive, eloquentia hominis
B. Genitive of quality, homo magnae eloquentiae
II. Adjunct to a substantivalr
C. Genitive of the set of persons, ,reliqui ,editum
III. Conjunct ('complement') of a copula
D. Genitive of the type of person, Ltspientis est aperte
odisse
IV. Adjunct to a verb
E. Genitive of purpose, Aegyptum profiscitue cognoscende
antiquitatis
F. Genitive of locality, Romae consules creabantur
IVa. Adjunct to a present participle
G. Genitive with a present participle, laboris fugiens
V. Genitive of exclamation, mercimoni lepidi
is, that it occurs only with place-names having -o- and stems,
about place names, not as a fact about uses of the genitive case.
genitive, it would appear (a) that some case- uses are purely irre-
of one language from the point of view of the surface case system
2
James E. Redden, "Walapai II: morphology," INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL
OF AMERICAN LINGUISTICS, XXXII (1966), 141-163.
finds five case indices in Walapai (four suffixes and zero) and
the uses of the case-forms that may not be deducible from the
tive task is to identify the surface case forms that are distinct
selves are not taken as primary terms in the description (i.e., the
happen to be homophonous).25
phenomena.27
27
As an illustration of this last point, take Gonda's claim that
the Vedic dative is called for whenever a noun is used to refer to
the 'object in view.' The vacuity of this statement is seen in his
interpretation of
(i) vataya kaptla vidyut (Patanjali)
'a reddish lightning signifies wind'
as "the lightning has, so to say, wind in view". J. Gonda, "The
unity of the Vedic dative," LINGUA XI (1962) 141-150; 147.
28 29
The well-known studies of Hjelmslev and Jakobson are
28
Louis Hjelmslev, "La cat6gorie des cas," ACTA JUTLANDICA, Aarhus,
VII.1 (1935) i-xii, 1-184; and IX.2 (1937) i-vii, 1-78.
29
Roman Jakobson, "Beitrag zur allgemeinen Kasuslehre," TRAVAUX
DU CERCLE LINGUISTIQUE DE PRAGUE, VI (1936) 240-288; reprinted in
E. P. Hamp, F. W. Householder and R. Austerlitz, eds., READINGS
IN LINGUISTICS, II, University of Chicago Press (1966) 51-89.
the cases in a case system has led to alternative view: that all
but one of the cases can be given more or less specific meanings,
the meaning of the residual case being left open. This residual
case can either have whatever relation to the rest of the sentence
tive as "the case used for those functions not fulfilled by the
suggests that Goedicke's remark could not have been very clearly
31 32
expressed. A different approach is taken by Diver , who does
31
Bennett (1914) 195, fn. 1. At the time of writing I have not
yet had access to the Goedicke original.
but to whatever case or cases are not required for a given realiza-
-20-
verb can have one, two, or three nouns (or noun phrases) associated
accusative, the nominative being the case of the Agent, the accusa-
tive the case of the Patient, with the dative, as the 'residue' case,
33The following is from Diver (1964) 181: "In the sentence senatus
imperium mihi dedit 'the senate gave me supreme power', therm7M-
tive, with the syntactic meaning of Agent, indicates the giver;
the Accusative, with the syntactic meaning of Patient, indicates
the gift. The question is: Does the Dative itself indicate the
recipient or merely that the attached word is neither the giver
nor the gift?" Diver makes the latter choice. In particular, he
states that "knowing that mihi, in the Dative, can be neither the
Agent (the giver) nor the TaTent (the gift), we deduce that it is
the recipient."
tive here is the case of the agent, but this time the accusative
the meaning of Patient but can express any number of other meanings
sentence can express any meaning relationship with the verb. The
is the Patient is nothing more than to agree to say the word 'Patient'
of Diver's examples, his argument would have been every bit as con-
by the dative, but the role of the accusative depends on such matters
that area of syntax that deals with the effect of the choice of
language.
the table'
are inside and those which are outside the verb phrase constituent.
trast appears just in case the same verb may appear sometimes with
as (13)-(14) or (15)-(16).
accusative and nominative to the genitive, for the former two are
(genitivus objectivus).
tive with certain verbs. That is, there are verbs that 'govern'
the ablative (e.g., utor), say, rather than the accusative for
35
their 'direct objects'.
1
35 Kurylowicz (1960) 138-139; 144-147; 150. Also se, his THE
INFLECTIONAL CATEGORIES OF INDO-EUROPEAN, Heidelberg-Carl Winter
(1964) Pp. 246; 179-181. Somewhat similar interpretations of the
connections between case and diathesis are found in Klaus Heger,
"Valenz, Diathese and Kasus," ZEITSCHRIFT FUR ROMANISCHE PHILOLOGIE
(1966) 138-170; 161.
and these, too, are of various kinds. Some workers have sought
tence connective.36
rest with the latter view are those who do not require of them-
case systems traces case systems of one kind back to case systems
system as one which assigns one case (the Ergative) to the subject
system, on the other hand, is one which assigns one case to the
the Ergative (or, put differently, that the Ergative case has a
'genitive' function).
- 27 -
and the identity of the neuter ending *-m with the masculine
40
Lyons (1966) 218.
ships that are defined only in the surface structure, as when the
to account for such forms as him I like, etc.; the shift of him
42
The suggestion is of course not novel. According to Hjelmslev,
the first scholar to show a connection between prepositions and
cases was A.-F. Bernhardi, in ANFANGSGRUNDE DER SPRACHWISSENSCHAFT,
Berlin (1805); see Hjelmslev (1934) 24. I have not yet seen the
Bernhardi work.
languages which use case forms quite extensively, and the assump-
even the most elaborate case languages may also have combinations
of, say, prepositions with case forms, and that some prepositions
disappears if, after accepting the fact that the conditions for
devices are provided by the 'true' case languages, too, for example
positions.
3
The distinction would be more accurately represented by the
opposition 'relations' vs. 'categories', because when a
-30-
'direct object' can be equated with the relation that holds between
structure, then these two 'pure' relations are exactly what deter-
whether such a concept has any connection with the relation 'subject'),
the surface subject relation which are not somewhere also expressible
and the structures which contain them must be of the 'labeled' type.
the category VP, and (b) the addition to some grammars of a rule,
phenomenon.
-33-
4
Tesniere (1959) 103-105.
45
See, for example, C. E. Bazell, "Syntactic relations and ling-
uistic typology," CAHIERS FERDINAND DE SAUSSURE, VIII (1949) 5-20;
esp. p. 8 where the difference is expressed in such terms as
'degrees of cohesion', 'liaison features' found within the predi-
cate but not between subject and predicate.
tuents of sentences.
tunately, there are both good and bad reasons for asserting that
analysis.
shortly.
Bennett (1914) 3.
50
Greenberg (1966) 80, 98; the quotation is from p. 98.
-37-
many scholars a strong feeling that the term should be used only
51
Jespersen (1924) 186.
52
Jespersen (1924) 179: "However far back we go, we nowhere find
a case with only one well-defined function: in every language
every case served different purposes, and the boundaries between
these are far from being clear-cut. This, in connection with
irregularities and inconsistencies in the formal elements character-
izing the cases, serve to explain the numerous coalescences we
witness in linguistic history ("syncretism") and the chaotic rules
which even thus are to a great extent historically inexplicable.
isIIftheEnliWlmouLtaEs2n2farther than the others in grate fu
simplifying these rules, we should be devoutl
our wa to force it back into the disorder and com lexit of
centuries ago." talics added.
1111111m.
54
Lehmann (1958) 185.
syntax. 55
who suggests that the study of cases can be pursued most fruit-
56
Frank Blake, "A semantic analysis of case," in CURME VOLUME OF
LINGUISTIC STUDIES (LANGUAGE Monograph No. 7) (1930) 34-49.
3. Case grammar
571t follows that whenever more than one case form appears in the
surface structure of the same sentence (on different noun phrases),
either more than one deep-structure case is involved or the sen-
tence is complex. If, for example, German le` hren is described as
a verb which ',takes two accusatives', we have reason to believe
that in the deep structure, the two object nouns are distinct as
to case. Often enough the language will provide evidence for the
distinction, as in the occurrence of such passive sentences as
das wurde mir gelehrt.
verbs, together with the rules for forming subjects, will serve
ent explains the fact that the combined meanings of the two
is unacceptable.
which hold between cases and lexical features (e.g., between Agent
58
noun hammer is inanimate.
ence between (23) and sentences (22) and (24) becomes apparent.
option in this case: either the entire Instrument phrase may appear
ving verbs and nouns (and embedded sentences, if there are any),
59There are probably good reasons for regarding negation, tense and
modd as associated directly with the sentence as a whole, and the
perfect and progressive 'aspects' as features on the V. See for
a statement of this position Lyons (1966) 218, 223.
VIIIINIIIMMO.N1=11111Imanumme
o
In my earlier paper I suggested that sentence adverbials in
general are assigned to the modality constituent. I now believe
that many sentence adverbs are introduced from superordinate sen-
tences (by transformations of a type we may wish to call 'infra-
jections1). This possibility has long been clear for unmistakable
sentence adverbs like unfortunate a, but there are also quite con-
vIncing reasons for extending the infrajection interpretation to
adverbs like willingly, easiLE, carefully, etc.
61
The arrow notation is used throughout, but this should not be
interpreted as meaning that the proposal for a case grammar
requires an assumption of a left-to-right orientation of the
constituent symbols of the rewriting rules.
of the form (29), where at least one case category must be chosen
(29) P + V + C1 + + C
n
human beings are capable of making on the events that are going
happened to, what got changed, etc. The cases that appear to be
needed include:
2
The escape qualification 'typically' expresses my awareness that
contexts which I will say require Agents are sometimes occupied by
'inanimate' nouns like robot or 'human institution' nouns like
nation. Since I know of no way of dealing with these matters at
the moment, I shall just assume for all Agents that they are 'animate.'
1116_
- 47
store and at the store are variants of the same entitly, determined
(39) she took him to the store and left him there
the nouns and that of the verbs. Those features of nouns required
with each noun a label which identifies the case relation which
it holds with the rest of the sentence. Such a rule might
'frame features' will indicate the set of case frames into which
the given verbs may be inserted. These frame features have the
E 0 3, as in (40) ; in C 0 + A 3, as in (41) ; in [ 0 + I ] ,
Other verbs having this same feature are turn, move, rotate, bend,
-52-
frame feature for kill, in other words, will have to specify that
(45) +[ D (IA) ]
The verb murder, on the other hand, is one which requires an Agent.
Its frame feature differs from that of (44) and (45) because the
(46) +[ D (I) A ]
more than the mere array of cases in P. Since one of the cases may
IL
69
It should be pointed out that descriptions of embedded sentences
as it + 8 realizations of the category NP in 'subject/object'
grammars must somehow guarantee that this particular expansion of
NP is limited to the subjects of intransitive sentences and the
objects (direct or oblique) of transitive sentences. All such
restrictions are rendered unnecessary by the decision to limit
complement S to the case element 0.
are
VerbsAdistinguished from each other not only by specification
of the case frames into which they can be inserted, but also by
elements.
account for the use of cook in all of the sentences (48) - (50).
case frames which accept it, and that is is one of the 'deletable
The example with cook shows that the lexicon need not contain
true for verbs like like and please, to give the example that
possessed by please.
only in that the frame feature for show contains an A where that
for see does not. The verbs kill and die appear to be related
in a similar way.
fact that the frames that contain hear are E 0 + D ] and those
can be seen between see and know, on the one hand, and look and
( +E 0 + A ])
verbs with which Lakoff associates the terms 'stative' and 'non-
71
George Lakoff, "Stative adjectives and verbs in English,"
Harvard Computation Laboratory, Report No. NSF-17, Mathematical
Linguistics and Machine Translation (1966) 1.1-16.
phrases are permitted only with 'non - statives' (put the other way
particular cases.
-59-
which deep structures of the type proposed in this essay are converted
resented by the same overt form, where the determining factor may
governing word.
empty (in which case they are introduced as optional choices from
tion.73
73The verb blame, for example, chooses ('governs') for for 0 and on
for D. The 0 preposition is at for look meaning 'examine', for for
look meaning 'seek', to for listen, etc. Changes in the original
prerowtion assignment may be brought about by transformations: the
rule:, which provide surface subjects and direct objects delete
prepositions (replace them by zero), and the rules which form
deverbal (=desentential) nominals convert some of the original case
forms into 'genitive', either by replacing the assigned preposition
with of, or, in some cases, removing the original preposition and
affixing the 'geaitive' suffix.
former choice, though the grounds for making the decision one way
rewritten as K + NP.
(55)
,000101."
V
/o
oN
K NP
d N
1 I
(56)
K NP
in (57).
-62-
(57) s
.....-----i----___
m
.,...---:
N
i 1
(58)
NP P
d N V
I 1 1
(59)
NP NP
9\
past give 0 the books to my brother by John
(6o)
NP
NP K NP
I
I
(61)
NP
NP tit P
1
John past give 0 the books to my brother
- 64 -
(62) S
NP M
(63)
NP
V NP D
K NP
1 1
John gave the books to my brother
(64)
NP
NP
d N d N
I I
John gave my brother the books
(65)
7,7/`_
Ei-Pasj
K
K NP
(66)
d N
[44
V A
K NP
d
y 1
(67)
[PassV
K NP
///'N
NP
(68)
_,...),1' 1glp
d
I
I 7 I
the books were given my brother by John
(69) S
1
M
K NP
[PassV
.............0 A
.....
K I[ NP
N
I I
I I 1
to my brother past give 0 the books by John
(70)
d N
NP K NP
(71)
NP M
d N
:fq K NP NP
I d N
1
(72) S
A
+Pass
d N K NP
(73) S
NP
[Pass'
Mane.
K
given
1
the books by
T
John
my brother was
We have seen that where there is only one case category, its
shown ways of dealing with sentences containing more than one case
category where one designated case could provide the subject with-
For many of the verbs which 'take more than one case category,
by the verb
the one which contributes the subject is indicated
-68-
0 + D
itself. Of the verbs which are accepted into the frame C
represent-
714,s mentioned above, by regarding the differences here as
ing no more than idiosyncratic facts about the syntactic properties
of these verbs, we can accept historical changes like those with like,
want and think, from verbs of the type which chme 0 to verbs of the
type which choose D, to be merely a matter of detail in the subject-
selection processes in our language. In other words, we do not need
to agree with Jespersen when he describes the change in English from
the use of ekpressions of the type him like oysters to those of the
'meaning' of the
type he likes oysters as reflecting a change in the
verb like from something like "to be agreeable to" to something like
"to take pleasure in" (Jespersen 1924) 160). The change seems merely
to be a result of the inter-influencing of the two surface processes
of choosing the first word and establishing verbal concord.
77 From the fact that there may only be one case in a simple sentence,
it becomes possible to allow all subjects to be formed by a copying
NP in the same
transformation. Sentences with two copies of the same
either
case undergo one of a number of changes: the second copy is
deleted or replaced by a pro-form, or the first copy is replaced by
a pro-form.
The 'verb' true occurs in the frame [ S], i.e., in the configuration
(74).
-69-
(75).
V 0
that John likes Mary pres true that John likes Mary
S V
I
(78)
0 M
0
t
it
1\
pres be true that John likes Mary
hand, if the first copy is replaced by its pro-form (in this context,
78
it), the resulting sentence is (82).
(79)
M P
K NP
(8o)
111
(81)
NP M
(82)
K NP
may call for the introduction of the element be into the M constitu-
verbs which are adjectives as well as for verbs which have been
(83)
K NP K NP
(84)
K V L
,-----s,
K NP
d N
I I
(85) S
M L
,./...1.--NTP4**,.
d N K--------------.6ITP
d N
I
1 1 I I
gP
d N
1 I
(unstressed)
The pro-form for L in verbless sentences is expletive
the
there. The result of modifying (86) by pro-replacement of
second-copy L, as suggested
subject L is (87); extraposition of the
(87)
ct
expletive there is
Alternatively to replacing the first-copy L by
(88)
NP
d N V NP L
d . N K NP
subject is a NP which is not from the case O. The most obvious case
paraphrase relations like that between (89) and (90), and cross-
81
Jespersen (1924) 162.
When such phenomena were examined by Hall, she took one form as
objects', on the other hand, have the effect of displacing the ori-
Hall provides rules which move the locative element (the wall or his
garden of (93) and (95) respectively) into the direct object posi-
Va
direct object.
- A
7-
say that both on the wall and with paint were initially provided
2
There are semantic difficulties in treating subject and object
transformitionally, in the sense that different choices are often
accompanied by semantic differences of one sort or another. These
differences are more on tne order of 'focusing' - -to be as vague as
possible--than anything else, and do not seem to require positing
'subjects' and 'objects' in the deep structure. The 'focusing'
difference may be extremely slight, as in the pairs (i)-(ii) and
(iii)-(iv), or it may have somewhat more 'cognitive content' as in
the pairs (v)-(vi) and (vii)-(viii).
(i) Mary has the children with her
(ii) the children are with Mary
(iii) he blamed the accident on John
(iv) he blamed John for the accident
(v) bees are swarming in the garden
(vi) tht garden is swarming with bees
(vii) he sprayed paint on the wall
(viii) he sprayed the wall with paint
Sentence (vi) seems to suggest, while (v) does not, that the whole
garden has bees in it everywhere; and (viii) suggests, while (vii) does
not, that the entire wall got covered with paint.
To the extent that other grammars make use of derived subjects
and derived objects--which is the only alternative, within subject/
object grammars, to treating verbs like luma, blame open, break,
etc. as involving elaborate and unexplained examples of homonymy- -
the semantic difficulties are just as great for them as they are
for case grammar. Since the 'semantic effect' of the transforma-
tions in question is so different in kind from the semantic role of
the case relations themselves, and since the latter are not affected
by these processes, I am inclined to tolerate the re-introduction into
grammatical theory of transformations which have semantic import (of
this highly restricted kind).
themselves, would have assumed the form X has Y. The N in the modi-
tence, and the V is empty. Thus, from (98) we get (99) by deleting
the repeated noun, the tense, and the 'empty' verb, and reattaching
(98) NP
N P
7
books pres 0 0 books to John
(99) NP
to John books
(100) NP
D N
NP
I
John 's books
sentence which by itself would have the form X has Y. The fact
surface structure.
-79-
(or set of verbs), and that some of these nouns may, others must,
such words as Latin amor from its associated verb, wnat is needed
quently have the effect of converting the form of the subsidiary NPs
84 Thus the noun amor when qualified by a sentence
to the genitive.
Tr
Exactly what universal constraints there are, if any, on the
element to be converted to genitive is not at all clear. It appears
that if there is only one element that shows up in the NP, it
frequently takes the genitive form. Compare the ambiguous sentence
(i) with sentences (ii) and (iii).
(i) my instructions were impossible to carry out
(a) so I quit
(b) so he quit
(ii) my instructions to you are to go there
(iii) *my your instructions are to go there
In English it appears that if the conditions which allow the form
of the of-genitive and the s-genitive are satisfied by two different
NPs in the associated sentence, multiple genitive constructions
become possible, as in the following example borrowed from Jespersen.
(iv) Gainsborough's portrait of the duchess of Devonshire
Japanese allows conversion to genitive in true relative clauses,
as well as in the reduced relative clauses. A paraphrase of (v) is
(vi); no is the postposition most closely associated with functions
which we would call 'genitive'.
(v) boku ga yonda zasshi 1I+subject+read-past+magazine 1
sentence of the form deum amat . . . the result is again amor dei.
The D and 0 forms, in other words, are equally reduced to the geni-
affixal, etc.)
the language)
of the verb
changes on V, etc.)
B. conditions of application
etc.)
language
selection, etc.)
Lb,good reasons for believing a priori that there will be much coincidence
- 83 -
in the ways in which the different criteria sort out the world's
languages.
under I.
'subjects'
- 84 -
lines, as follows:
(101) A
0 A
0
Yana, have only one form for pronouns in all four of these
positions.
(102).
There are languages like Paiute that have a separate form for
'accusative'.
(103)
There are languages like Chinook which give one form to the A
(104)
nominative mo ergative
-85-
There are languages like Dakota which have separate forms for
(105 )
active
(106)
in these languages.
is verbal concord.
and this choice is recorded in the following way: its original case
verb meaning 'to butcher' (/sombali9/), we find that when the topic
'it is with the knife that the man butchers the carabao'
carabao188
conditions that would call for deletion in some other language may
(e.g. Chinook) has led scholars to claim that such languages lack
=1,11,..11M
9
'Andre Martinet, A FUNCTIONAL VIEW OF LANGUAGE, Oxford-Clarendon
(1962), 61-62.
lacks a subject, and hence, the argument goes, Japanese sentences lack
4.4 Topicalization
stress assignment, late word order changes, and possibly the 'cleft-
a
93McKaughan (1962) 47f.
94
of cases in Brahmanic prose as a study of secondary topicalization.
- 91 -
I would imagine that all languages possess some means of carrying out
in it
and thatAthe ergative typepas
nominative agentive
the ergative languages. This fact, plus the use of the term
96
Note that even if there is a different form for the verb in
0 ] and [ 0 A ] case frames, this cannot be interpreted
as evidence of 'passivity'. As mentioned earlier, in languages not
of the ergative type there may still be systematic variation of the
same verb root depending on whether it is used transitively or
intransitively.
these systems, the case that has been given the name 'nominative' is
tion, and the 'ergative' element in the one instance and the
.,111
9 Andre Martinet, Le sujet comme fonction linguistique et l'analyse
syntaxique du Basque," BULLETIN DE LA SOCIETE DE LINGUISTIQUE DE
PARIS (1962) 73-82; 78f.
9
Vaillant (1936) 93.
and 'dative' respectively. It looks very much as-if that is all there
is to say. For my part I would much rathar say of the ergative lang-
10
()See, e.g., Tesniere (1959) 112.
and the fact that some languages have 'invented' have-like verbs in
from expressions of the type inimicus mihi occisus est and mihi illud
known from the present state of our knowledge are really eapable of
of the cultures that have ergative languages is one which also deserves
102
to be brought into question.
102 The following seems worth quoting in full: "Nous sommes tous des
hommes, et tous nous avons deux talents: les facultes plus actives
de l'appetit et de la volontel et les facultes plus passives des
sensations et de l'apprehension; mais it est evident que les deux
sexes de l'humanite montrent sous ce rapport une difference sensible.
"Wethnologie moderne, qui a ecarte definitivement comme insuf-
fisante la doctrine du developpement uniforme, nous apprend cependant
que le progres de l'humanite a balance presque toujours entre les
cultures plus feminines ou plus masculines, dites cultures matriarcales
et patriarcales. Ce sont toujours les cultures matriarcales tries
prononcees qui, comme le basque, ont un verbe transitif de nature
passive avec comme casus rectus un patiens et comme casus obliquus un
agens; mais les cultures patriarcales, comme l'indo-europeenne ont un
verb transitif de nature active, animiste et magique, avec un sujet
au casus rectus et un object au casus obliquus. Chaque peuple a
donc le verbe qu'il merite." (van Ginneken (1939) 91Z)
- 96 -
the freedom of word order in the languages of the world are very
parts.
103
Wilhelm Havers, UNTERSUCHUNGEN ZUR KASUSSYNTAX DER INDOGERMAN-
ISCHEN SPRACHEN, Strassbourg (1911) Pp. 335; 317.
between (111) and (112) as well as between (113) and (114); but
that of the two sentences (115) and (116), the latter is ungram-
It whould be noted that Herz and Hand are the names of body parts,
5.1.2 There are cases like the above where a given language exhibits
where it appears that one language has chosen the dative expression,
Havers.
Havers (1911) 1
also used with the possessed element. Here the most readily
105
Examples are from Havers (1911) 283
106
L. Levy-Bruhl, "L'expression de la possession dans les langues
melanesiennes," BULLETIN DE LA SOCIETE LINGUISTIQUE DE PARIS,
XIX (1916) 96-104; 99.
means for kinship terms), or they may merely have a class of nouns
107
This last situation is sometimes described by saying that
nouns are 'inflected for person'. See Gabriel Manessy,
relation genitive dans quelques langues mande," PROCEEDINGS OF
THE NINTH INTERNATIONAL CONGRESS OF LINGUISTS, Mouton (1964)
467-475; 468.
The full variety of the treatment of inalienable possession
in different Amerindian languages is catalogued in Edward Sapir's
review of C. C. Uhlenbeck, "Het identificeerend karakter der
possessieve flexie in talen van Noord-Amerika," in INTERNATIONAL
JOURNAL OF AMERICAN LINGUISTICS, I (1917) 86-90.
lO8L6vy
-Bruhl (1916) 96.
109
'louse' (or 'flea') among the inalienables, a situation that
10
9Zdenik Salzmann, "Arapaho VI: noun," INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF
AMERICAN LINGUISTICS, XXXI (1965) 136-151; 139.
110
Milka Ivi6, The grammatical category of non-omissible
determiners," LINGUA, XI (1962); and "Non-omissible determiners
in Slavic languages," PROCEEDINGS OF THE NINTH INTERNATIONAL
CONGRESS OF LINGUISTS, Mouton (1964) 476-479; the example is
from p. 477.
5.1.6 Note that in sentences (124) and (127), three things are
cepts.
Using P, B and A for (a), (b) and (c) above, we mny represent
as (131).
(131) Dgen -0 B] be A
-103-
and that of (130). His example was sentence (136) (which also
112
Henri Frei, "Sylvie est jolie des yeux," MELANGES DE LINGUISTIQUE
OFFERTS A CHARLES BALLY, Geneva (1939) 185-192; 188. The express-
ions are limited to clear relational nouns, not only to body parts.
Frei notes such phrases as "des couloirs spacieux et bas de plafond"
and "fibre de moeurs." He beautifully demonstrates the distinct-
ness of the sentences involving inalienable possession from
overtly similar sentences of different grammatical structures with
the contrast between (i) and (ii) below. (p. 186)
(i) la salle est pleine de visages
(ii) la femme est pleine de visage
the order and in the choice of particles do not change the status
one finds between these and various uses of the 'middle voice'.
entity, while in (147) the word jambe can only (or, depending on
Notice that the jambe which does not have the possessive adjective
- 106 -
113
Bally (1936) 68f.
aMIMOMIIMP
assume the form 'X has Y' is embedded to NP. Since it is desir-
and (151).
(149) my dog
(151) my head
reflects the fact that the relationship between the two nouns
relationship.
For the types of inalienable possession that we have
Where further distinctions are made (as between body parts and
(153) NP
K
Nr
N
as in (155).
1177--
I am
inclined to think that they are. See my "The syntax of
English preverbs," to appear in GLOSSA, II (1967).
must make provisions for them; but if they are not, then those
115
Paul M. Postal, "On so-called 'pronouns' in English," GEORGETOWN
UNIVERSITY MONOGRAPH NO. 19, LANGUAGES AND LINGUISTICS (1966),
177-206.
its features are copied onto the determiner so that the determiner
- 109 -
5.3.Some illustrations
The D constituent often need not remain the NP: under some
in (156).
- 110-
(156)
K NP
d N
K'13
N
when the D remains inside L and A becomes the subject; when the D
moted and A becomes the subject; and when the D is promoted and
(157)
V L
K NP K NP
NP K
I
(158)
K NP V
1
K NP
D N
/%6.
NP
I I
(159)
NP
N V
D N
NP
I I
(16o)
NP
11
NP
I I
(161)
NP
I
N V NP
NP
Is
May pinched John nose
(162)
+Pass
K NP
NP N
i 1
on John 's nose past pinch by Mary
(163) S
T
xP M P
D N V
NP K
1P
N
structure is (164).
(164)
NP K P K NP
1 1 1 I 1
The possible subjects for (164) are the A or the newly promoted
(165)
NP
11 I d N
I I
(166)
xr
N .
NP
I
1
Mary pinched John on the nose
- ilk -
(167)
D M
NP
INP
// N
1 di
(168) S
1
NP M
V
Ef-Pas]
K NP K NP
1
d/ \N'
1
John was pinched on the nose by Mary
I
K NP
I
pres beautiful eyes to the girl
(170)
NP
NP K
d N
(171)
NP
1
the girl ' eyes are beautiful
(172)
NP
d N
I IN
pres beautiful to the girl 0 eyes
- 117 -
(173)
- 118 -
The reason for this decision is that this appears to reflect what
have.
NP
V N
1-----"-----'""'"---...1
the girl pres 0 0 beautiful eyes
this expression type has not yet been given; it would be something
- 119-
like (177).
oblique
(177) P be EA-0B]
type (137) and those of the type (177) is seen in the Latin
V position the function word have, a verb which takes the modi-
(181)
V NP
V N
formations which each language uses somewhat in its own way. For
- 120 -
(182) PE v E D + N
(a) PROMOTE D
body;part N and the whole 0 becomes the subject. When (b) is not
applied, the 0 becomes the subject. When (c) is not applied': the
118
time before reaching auy conclusions on these matters.
right and left are probably nouns of this type too. The reason
speaker or hearer.
of the box
the tower
- 122-
might
be a relationship between conjunction of NPs and what one
of NPs, all but the last have the postposition to. The last one
has the postposition appropriate for the case role of the whole
Redden points out that in Walapai a sentence has only one noun
boy")
NP.
(190) NP NP + C
(191) X
K NP
NP
- 124 -
(192)
V
[Pro];
NP
N K NP
d N
I
If the C remains inside the NP, the entire A becomes the subject,
(193) S
M
V------- A
[N] -. /'''*%. /*"4""
h
K NP K NP
N
1 1
'evaluative' sense--(197).
found in the fact that these nouns may accept types of modifi-
The serious problems are (a) with the use of words like
language.
I would propose that there are contexts in which the case category
taining dummy Fs. These words may have associated with them
- 128 -
is not obvious how sentences like (206) and (207) can be dealt
(203) P
V F
1
nightmare 0
(204)
nightmare nightmare
(205)
have nightmare
122
Jespersen (1924) 91
that is, that of defining phenomena which are here partly treated
chooses the cases required by that verb, then chooses the other
treatment is that NPs made subject and object may be said to have
lost their 'original' case relation to the sentence (by the rule
which 'erases' the case category whenever the case marker K has
tation.)
tree liagram.
7. Closing words
language at a time.
of the type that has been made familiar from the work of
1231 wrongly
ong y expected these remarks to have a certain shock
value at the symposium. There I was attacked for constructing
deep structure representations that were too hampered by
considerations of surface syntactic facts to get at the under-
lying semantic realities. This is a problem which, as they
say, requires further study.