The Bad Man Law Theory

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 21

Yale Law School

Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository


Faculty Scholarship Series Yale Law School Faculty Scholarship

1-1-1998

The "Bad Man," the Good, and the Self-Reliant


Jack M. Balkin
Yale Law School

Sanford Levinson

Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/fss_papers

Recommended Citation
Balkin, Jack M. and Levinson, Sanford, "The "Bad Man," the Good, and the Self-Reliant" (1998). Faculty Scholarship Series. Paper 261.
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/fss_papers/261

This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Yale Law School Faculty Scholarship at Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository. It
has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship Series by an authorized administrator of Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository. For
more information, please contact [email protected].
1998 THE BAD, THE GOOD, AND THE SELF-RELIANT 1

Originally published at 78 B.U. L. Rev. 885 (1998).


Copyright 1998 by Sanford Levinson and Jack M. Balkin. All rights reserved.

THE "BAD MAN," THE GOOD, AND THE SELF-RELIANTd1

Sanford Levinsona1
J.M. Balkinaa1

*885 When we think of the many famous ideas associated with Justice
Oliver Wendell Holmesand with The Path of the Law in particularone of the
first that comes to mind is his famous image of the "bad man."1 Although this
metaphor has been one of Holmes's most lasting legacies, it has also been one of
his most troubling as well, for it suggests that the deepest truths about the law can
be found by adopting the perspective of someone who is "bad." It is one thing to
say that wisdom comes from the mouths of babes or even from fools; it is quite
another to say that we should look to the worst among us for insight.

Indeed, the metaphor of the "bad man" has haunted Holmes's legacy.
Although it seems to mesh well with his unsentimental, positivist approach to law,

d1 Prepared for presentation at a conference on The Path of the Law after


100 years at Boston University School of Law, September 17, 1997. Although we
thank everyone who participated in that conference, we offer special thanks to
Jack Beermann, Robin West, Ruth Gavison, and Bob Ellickson, all of whom
offered especially probing questions or comments about the arguments.

a1 W. St. John and W. St. John, Jr. Regents Chair in Law, University of
Texas School of Law.

aa1
Knight Professor of Constitutional Law and the First Amendment,
Yale Law School.

1 See Oliver Wendell Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev.
457, 459, reprinted in 78 B.U. L. Rev. 699, 701 (1998). We ordinarily try to
avoid sexist language in our writing whenever possible. However, two of the
central concepts of this Article are expressions used by Holmes in the 19th
centurythe "bad man" and the "good man." Rather than avoid these expressions
entirely, we have placed them in quotes whenever they are invoked.

1
2 THE BAD, THE GOOD, AND THE SELF-RELIANT 1998

it has also probably contributed to the recurrent image of Holmes as nothing more
than an insensitive moral skeptic, who regarded law purely instrumentally, and for
whom the only real truth was the truth of raw power.2 It is this image of Holmes
that has been dragged out again and again whenever people have tried to dismiss
his ideas by defaming his character.3 In *886 fact, we agree with Holmes's critics
that the "bad man" is a bad metaphor. It is bad not only because it conveys a
misleading attitude toward law, but becauseas it has normally been
understoodit may also well be inconsistent with Holmes's larger views about
law, morality, and the place of the individual in society. Revealing those more
implicit ideasand showing how they are obscured by the unfortunate metaphor
of the "bad man"is the goal of the present Essay.

One of the central influences in Holmes's thought was Ralph Waldo


Emerson, and behind many of Holmes's most important pronouncements can be
found traces of Emerson's thought. We think that this is as true of The Path of the
Law as any of Holmes's other writings. Our goal in this Essay is to convince you
that a better way to understand law, and indeed, perhaps a better way to
understand Holmes's own view of the law, is not from the perspective of the "bad
man," but, rather, from the perspective of a more Emersonian, "self-reliant,"
person.

I. The "Bad Man" and the "Good Man"

The entire reference to the "bad man" in The Path of the Law is quite
brief. It comes near the beginning of the address, when Holmes is "lay[ing] down
some first principles for the study of this body of dogma or systematized
prediction which we call the law . . . ."4 He immediately states that understanding
law depends on a sharp analytical separation between law and morals. As a way

2 This is not to say, though, that the image is wholly undeserved. It was
Holmes, after all, who asked "What proximate text of excellence can be found
except correspondence to the actual equilibrium of force in the communitythat
is, conformity to the wishes of the dominant power." Oliver Wendell Holmes,
Montesquieu, in Collected Legal Papers 250, 258 (1920).

3 See, e.g., Ben Palmer, Holmes, Hobbes, and Hitler, 31 A.B.A. J. 261
(1945), for the most notable example of this genre. A far more recent example is
Albert W. Alschuler, The Descending Trail: Holmes' Path of the Law One
Hundred Years Later, 49 Fla. L. Rev. 353 (1997). An alternative strategy has
been to deny Holmes's influence and importance. See Louise Weinberg, Holmes's
Failure, 96 Mich. L. Rev. 691, 692 (1997) (decrying Holmes's "littleness" and
arguing that Holmes is greatly overrated as a thinker and as an influence on the
shaping of American Law).

4 Holmes supra note 1, at 458, 78 B.U. L. Rev. at 700.

2
1998 THE BAD, THE GOOD, AND THE SELF-RELIANT 3

of making this point, Holmes notes, altogether correctly, "that a bad man has as
much reason as a good one for wishing to avoid an encounter with the public
force."5 This "bad man" is defined as one who "cares nothing for an ethical
rulewhich is believed and practised by his neighbors," yet he "is likely
nonetheless to care a good deal to avoid being made to pay money" or go to jail.6
"Thus, if you want to know the law and nothing else," Holmes tells us, "you must
look at it as a bad man, who cares only for the material consequences which such
knowledge enables him to predict, not as a good one, who finds his reasons for
conduct, whether inside the law or outside of it, in the vaguer sanctions of
conscience."7

At first glance, the image of the "bad man" seems perfectly clear. He is
a version of the ideal-type of homo economicus interested only in maximizing his
own individual preferences, indifferent to others except insofar as they *887 serve
as material obstacles to fulfilling egoistic desires. The "bad man" appears to have
no notion of moral obligation; he seems to be asocial in the most profound sense.8
Yet it is important to note that Holmes does not offer us the "bad man" in
isolation. Instead, Holmes contrasts him to the "good man," even if the point,
ironically or not, is that the "good man" has little to tell us about the nature of law.
One is reminded of Mae West's famous response when someone exclaimed
"Goodness!" upon seeing her character's impressive diamond ring: "Goodness,"
she drawled, "had nothing to do with it."9 Like Mae West, Holmes seems to

5 Id.

6 Id.

7 Id, 78 B.U. L. Rev. at 701.

8 Robert Ellickson, a fellow participant at the Boston University


symposium, suggested this account of the "bad man." As will become clear
momentarily, this interpretation, whether or not faithful to Holmes's actual views,
overstates the case. A bad person may be neither amoral nor egoistic: he or she
may desire to protect friends and familyconsider the example of a mafia
chieftanand so may be quite a social creature. Such a "bad man" is not utterly
without mores, he is merely one whose mores differ radically from those of the
larger society around him. In an essay published after the present essay was
initially drafted, David Luban offers an account of the "bad man" that is
considerably closer to Ellickson's. See David Luban, The Bad Man and the Good
Lawyer: A Centennial Essay on Holmes's The Path of the Law, 72 N.Y.U. L.
REV. 1547, 1564 (1997) ("In short, Holmes's 'good man' is the man of
conscience, and Holmes's 'bad man' is not.").

9Night After Night (Paramount 1932), quoted in Bartlett's Familiar


Quotations 685 (16th ed., Justin Kaplan ed., 1992). Indeed, she made this the title
of her autobiography; see Mae West, Goodness Had Nothing to Do With It

3
4 THE BAD, THE GOOD, AND THE SELF-RELIANT 1998

suggest that the good person is, as a practical matter, useless in helping us to
understand the operational meaning of law10 even if Holmes might resist any
suggestion that "goodness" is irrelevant to assessing the worth of particular lives.

But are things really so clear cut? If Holmes really thought the good
person irrelevant to the understanding of law, why did he bother to mention him at
all? One need not be a full-blown (post-)structuralist to recognize that things are
sometimes best understood in terms of their opposites, and that goodness and
badness form a pretty basic binary oppositition in our culture. There is a reason,
after all, that parents tell their children that Santa Claus spends the months leading
up to Christmas determining who has been good *888 and bad in the previous
year; they hope their present-hungry children will attempt to figure out the
difference. So to understand what Holmes means by the "bad man," perhaps we
had better look at what he means by the "good man" and the good person's view
of the law.

The "good man," Holmes tells us, is motivated by conscience.


Adherence to conscience, rather than fear of some predicted misfortune, offers the
good person a "reason[ ] for conduct."11 Presumably, the good person would not
violate a just or morally binding law even if public authorities stopped punishing
its violation or the courts were closed. Hence Holmes's definition also seems to
imply that for the good person, law is something other than predictions of official
behavior; instead, law is a norm that generates a feeling of obligation to obey it,
regardless of the probability of state- enforced sanctions resulting from
disobedience. This, we take it, is the point of Holmes's statement that the good
person "finds his reasons for conduct, whether inside the law or outside of it, in
the vaguer sanctions of conscience."12

(1957). Or, as Ms. West put it on another occasion, "I used to be Snow White, but
I drifted." Joseph Weintraub, Peel Me a Grape 47 (1975).

10 We purposely use the term "operational meaning" rather than, say,


"nature of," in order to emphasize the basic pragmatism of Holmes's approach. He
is not, we think, offering what might be termed a legal "ontology." He does not
think it important to offer a philosophical definition of law good for all purposes,
much less insight into the "essence" of law or a theory of the conceptual
preconditions of law being law. The latter issues might be addressed by an
academic legal philosopher. However, there is no reason to believe that The Path
of the Law or the "bad man" test was directed at that audience. Holmes's argument
was offered as a heuristic account of law for ordinary lawyers interested in
determining, as a practical matter, what they should say to clients who ask if "the
law" will be a hindrance or a help to them in achieving their purposes, and who
are prepared to spend good money to find out the answer.

11 Holmes, supra note 1, at 459, 78 B.U. L. Rev. at 701.

12 Id.

4
1998 THE BAD, THE GOOD, AND THE SELF-RELIANT 5

As soon as we begin to unpack this formula, however, something very


puzzling begins to happen. Holmes's "good man" starts to look increasingly like
his "bad man," and his "bad man" increasingly resembles his formulation of the
"good man." Consider, for example, that Holmes uses the "sanctions of
conscience" to explain why the "good man" obeys the law. These "sanctions"
presumably range from feelings of guilt to the fear of hellfire; and the "good man"
can surely predict that they will descend upon him if he misbehaves. Thus, both
Holmes's "good man" and his "bad man" seem to be defined in terms of responses
to sanctions. Of course, we are not claiming that Holmes has accurately described
the motivations of good and bad persons; rather, we are pointing out how
impoverished his psychological model seems to be. Holmes's picture of the "good
man" more resembles a person driven by a dominating superego than a mature
individual whose ego can exercise at least some measure of autonomous reflection
and judgment. In short, if a "bad man" is defined as one driven by the fear of
punishment, the Holmesian "good man" is just a special case of his "bad man"
he is a "bad man" driven by the fear of sanctions existing outside the law. This
may seem to be a play on words, but if so, it is one generated by Holmes's
peculiar choice of language.

Conversely, if a "good man" is defined as a person driven by the


sanctions of his conscience, Holmes's "bad man" becomes a special case of his
"good man." Most "bad men" who break or manipulate the lawparticularly the
civil laware not sociopaths, totally devoid of conscience and moral purpose.
Rather, their conscience is simply directed in different (and perhaps to us morally
reprehensible) ways. Nor are they purely egoists; often they seek to benefit their
friends, their relatives, their associatesor even their clientsat the expense of
strangers or other people to whom they *889 feel they owe a reduced duty. For
example, Mafia members and other criminals may have well-developed codes of
conduct and honor, yet they may regard the law as an obstacle to work around or
to ignore when conditions permit.

There are still deeper problems with Holmes's formulation: Holmes's


contrast of the "good man" and the "bad man" assumes that only the latter is
important to understanding the law. The "bad man" is important because he is
always threatening to disobey law if it is to his advantage and if he can get away
with it.13 By contrast, Holmes suggests that the "good man" is less important to

13 This formulation suggests that the "bad man" may be more interested
in whether his misconduct will be detected and prosecuted by others than in the
particular content of court decisions. David Luban has suggested that the
Holmesian bad man is in fact "pretty tame," because he does not "consider
enforcement possibilities as well as enforcement outcomes." See Luban, supra
note 8, at 1571. Even if Luban offers a tenable reading of The Path of the Law,
because of Holmes's insistence on courts as the focus of attention, his criticism
could hardly apply to Holmes's Legal Realist disciples whom his essay influenced.
They correctly emphasized that law is the province of many, many officials, and

5
6 THE BAD, THE GOOD, AND THE SELF-RELIANT 1998

understanding the practical meaning of the law. But if so, it must be because he
lacks those qualities associated with the "bad man"; that is, because he is more
likely to obey the law rather than strategize around it or break it on the sly.

Yet this distinction raises two important questions: First, does Holmes
really believe that a "good man" is likely to obey the law when the "bad man" will
not? Second, if so, why does Holmes believe that the "good man" is more likely
to obey the law? Is it because the law is usually good or because it is usually good
to obey the law?14

Consider the first of these questions. Does Holmes really believe that
the "bad man" disobeys more often than the good person? Perhaps the point of
his contrast between the good and the bad person is merely that the sanctions of
the good person's conscience are "vague[ ]." Thus, although good and bad people
disobey the law in equal numbers and with equal frequency, the *890 behavior of
the "bad man," being egoistical, is relatively predictable, while the behavior of the
"good man," being driven by private conscience, is relatively uncertain.

However, this will not do. Once we see that the "bad man" is also
driven by conscience, albeit one different from that of many of his fellows, we
cannot necessarily assume that his actions are more predictable. We may not
know his idiosyncratic private preferences anymore than we can know the
particular pangs of conscience that drive the good person to disobey the law. Put
another way, we can say only that bad people violate the law when it serves their
preferences, however those are defined, while good people violate the law when
the law seems unjust to them, however their vision of justice is defined.

In any case, the whole point of Holmes's theory is to understand the


practical operations of law. It is not clear that viewing the law from the
perspective of the "bad man" gives us a proper understanding of law if people

any understanding of "the law in action," rather than the mere "law on the books,"
had to take account of the likely behavior of these officials.

14 These ambiguities are implicit in his definition of the "good man,"


"who finds his reasons for conduct, whether inside the law or outside of it, in the
vaguer sanctions of conscience." Id. One could read this sentence to suggest that
sometimes the good person "finds his reasons for conduct [[ ]... inside the law."
Id. That is, sometimes conscience demands that the good person obey the law
because it is the law. If so, then the reason why the good person usually obeys the
law is because it is usually good to obey the law. On the other hand, one might
more plausibly read Holmes as saying that whether or not good people's conduct
is within or without the law, their reasons for action must be found in the
sanctions of their own individual consciences. Under this reading, the good
person usually obeys the law because the law is usually good, and the good person
obeying his conscience will rarely stray from it. Nevertheless, as we shall shortly
discover, both of these accounts are unsatisfactory, albeit for different reasons.

6
1998 THE BAD, THE GOOD, AND THE SELF-RELIANT 7

break the law as much from the "vaguer sanctions" of conscience as from self-
interested calculation. So Holmes must be assuming that most examples of law
breaking stem from "bad men," and not good citizens. And this leads us to the
second questionwhether the reason why good persons usually obey the law is
because it is usually good to obey the law or because the law is usually good. 15

We begin by noting that Holmes could hardly have believed that the
good person will usually obey law because it is usually good to obey the law.
Imagine someone who says: "Whenever I feel torn between two potential
possibilities of action, I always ask what the legally-constituted authorities ask of
me, and then I behave accordingly." This speech may in fact be consistent with
some accounts of how law gains its authority.16 But would any of *891 us say that
a person who routinely thinks and acts this way is a "good person," even if he or
she is (by definition) law-abiding? As Holmes himself tried to emphasize in The
Path of the Law and elsewhere, law and morality are two separate things. Holmes
was a determined opponent of that version of classical natural law that makes the
notion of "unjust" or "immoral" law a contradiction in terms. For Holmes, as for
later positivists, what made law "law" was precisely the possibility that it could be

15 There is a final possibility. Perhaps Holmes believed that the "bad


man" was more important than the good one because most law breaking occurs by
"bad men," not because "bad men" are more predictable, but simply because there
are so few good ones who disobey out of conscience. According to this picture,
one which we think is not at all uncharacteristic of the pessimistic Holmes, the
vast majority of people are neither good nor bad. They are simply sheep, obeying
the law out of habit. "Bad men" and good alike disobey law, but so few good
people exist who disobey law for reasons of conscience that they can be safely
ignored in understanding law.
This is, of course, an empirical assumption, and Holmes gives us no
reason to think that it is true. It depends on the nature of the legal regime and
equally importantly on the nature of the specific law whose operation one wishes
to understand. In very unjust regimes, for example, one might find considerable
civil disobedience based on conscience. Even in otherwise relatively just societies
one might expect considerable civil disobedience against particular laws that
people think are unjust. Hence, if Holmes is assuming relatively little lawbreaking
by a relatively small number of good persons, his assumption seems question
begging.

16 See Joseph Raz, Authority and Justification, in Authority 115-41


(Joseph Raz ed., 1990). Raz argues that the authority of law consists in its
providing people with reasons for action that displace the reasons they already
have. See id. at 124. Law has authority over people if people are more likely "to
comply with reasons which apply to [them] (other than the alleged authoritative
directives)" if they accept the law "as authoritatively binding and tr[y] to follow
[it], rather than by trying to follow the reasons which apply to [them] directly." Id.
at 129 (emphasis omitted).

7
8 THE BAD, THE GOOD, AND THE SELF-RELIANT 1998

unjust and immoral. Given his rejection of natural law premises, Holmes could
not possibly have believed that a person who routinely obeys the will of the
authorities because it is their will was a "good person."

Both Holmes and his audience clearly recognized that sometimes the
law mandates the performance of an immoral act, or forbids performance of a
moral act. After all, Holmes was speaking in Massachusetts, which had been
famous for its opposition to chattel slavery and to the return of escaped slaves
under the fugitive slave laws. Anyone listening to Holmes who was of the same
age (56 years old in 1897), would have been thirteen on June 2, 1854, when
Anthony Burns and other fugitives were returned to slavery in the name of fidelity
to the iniquitous Fugitive Slave Act of 1850.17 None of them would have had to
be reminded that law and morality often diverge.

A more contemporary example might be the dilemmas surrounding


assisted suicide. Does compliance with the law automatically make our decision
justifiable, insulated from criticism as "immoral" ? Faced with a loved one racked
with interminable pain and suffering, is it a sufficient reason to refuse to assist
suicide that all but one state currently outlaws the practice and that the United
States Supreme Court upheld the constitutionality of such prohibitions?18 Is the
"good man" the one who argues that "I personally believe that my patient ought to
receive a prescription for a potentially fatal drug, but I refrain from prescibing or
delivering it because the law prohibits *892 it" or, perhaps even more to the point,
"I personally believe that my brother ought to be allowed his wish to be spared
further suffering, but since the law prohibits my placing the fatal dosage on his
tongue, I will not do so" ? Conversely, if one is a doctor living in Oregonwhich
permits narrowly defined forms of assisted suicideis it completely
unproblematic, as a moral matter, to honor a patient's request for a potentially
fatal prescription?

At most we might allow the "good person" to say that there is a prima
facie obligation to obey the law. But this means only that anyone who would

17 The story of the Burns case is superbly told in Paul Finkelman, Legal
Ethics and Fugitive Slaves: The Anthony Burns Case, Judge Loring, and
Abolitionist Attorneys, 17 Cardozo L. Rev. 1793, 1793-1858 (1996). For months
previous, Boston had been the scene of civil disturbances and protests. On the day
of Burns's extradition to the South, Finkelman notes, Boston was "an occupied
city," as "[s]oldiers and policemen lined the streets" and "soldiers, policeman, and
one hundred and twenty recently deputized federal marshals" guarded the
courthouse. Id. at 1794. "The moral quality of these newly created guardians of
the law seemed to mock justice." Id. See also generally Albert J. Von Frank, The
Trials of Anthony Burns: Freedom and Slavery in Emerson's Boston (1998).

18 See Washington v. Glucksberg, 117 S. Ct. 2258 (1997) (upholding


Washington state's ban on physician assisted suicide against a facial due process
challenge).

8
1998 THE BAD, THE GOOD, AND THE SELF-RELIANT 9

violate the law has the burden of persuasion of demonstrating good grounds for
doing so. Only a particular (and not, to our minds, very successful) version of
natural law theory could claim that obedience to law was always mandated of
good persons. And Holmes, as we know, was not a devotee of any form of natural
law.

The remaining possibility is that Holmes believed that the good person
is less important to understanding law breaking than the bad person because the
laws are generally good and so good persons will usually obey them for reasons
of conscience. But this seems unfounded as an empirical matter; it certainly could
not be true of all legal systems, including the legal system existing in the United
States in 1897. As we have seenand as Holmes himself well understood
systems of law are rarely wholly just, and the more unjust the law appears to the
good person, the less likely that person is to obey it.

Indeed, the ubiquity of unjust laws and unjust legal systems threatens to
reverse once again the stereotype of the good person who obeys law and the bad
one who cares for nothing other than the extent to which it is the proxy for
predictions of official force. There may be many occasions when the "bad man" is
delighted to discover that playing by the rules means that official force will be
brought to bear against his adversaries. Even as good persons may avoid obeying
unjust laws when they can, the wicked will often insist on enforcing the letter of
even the most iniquitous laws when it suits their interests, and they may gladly
take advantage of loopholes in otherwise good laws.

Conversely, when good people obey the law, they may not do so simply
because it is the law. Rather, they may obey because the law is a good one, or
because they judge that it would be better to obey the law than to incur the bad (in
the moral sense) consequences that might flow from disobedience. The law is not
in and of itself a sufficient reason for obedience; rather it is one feature in a larger
moral environment that the good person must consider. To paraphrase (and
reverse) Holmes's famous phrase, the good person has as much reason as a bad
one for wishing to avoid an encounter with the public force. Taking the interests
of others and the legal environment into account, the good individual weighs up
the moral advantages and disadvantages of various courses of action.

We seem to have arrived at a curious reversal. One who usually obeys


the law may be a very bad, or at least morally obtuse, person, while the so-called
"bad man"initially conceptualized as one who stands ready to disobey *893 the
law whenever "the price is right," hence his interest in prediction of the incidence
of public forcemay actually be a good person disobeying an unjust law. The
good person takes the existence of the legal system and the various consequences
that flow from disobedience into account in deciding whether or not to violate the
law, but he or she does not obey it simply because it is the law. Rather, good
people obey the law because it is right, or because, given the balance of
consequences, more good will flow from obedience than disobedience. And
implicit in this formulation is the possibility that if the law strays too far from
what conscience demands, the good person will have no hesitation in breaking or

9
10 THE BAD, THE GOOD, AND THE SELF-RELIANT 1998

evading it. One of Holmes's major purposes in offering the figure of the "bad
man" was to insist in the separation between law and morals. But it has become
increasingly clear that the "good man" is just as important to this demarcation as
his "bad man."

One might object at this point that Holmes's metaphor has an equally
important purpose: the "bad man" stands as a symbol of his "predictive theory of
law"that the real law, the law in practice, consists in how people use it and
respond to it. Hence to understand law we should approach it from the perspective
of a "bad man" because bad people, malsocialized in the norms that we ordinarily
identify with acceptable conduct, will respond to incentives to break or evade the
lawunless, of course, the law suits their interests, in which case they will gladly
obey it.

Yet what if the law itself is bad? Might a good person not also want to
break it or evade a bad law? Might an opponent of slavery not want to avoid
returning a fugitive slave? Might not a conscientious objector wish to evade
fighting in an unjust war? Surely to understand how a law will be applied in
practice, whether and how often it will be complied with, and how many
individuals will seek to evade it, one must take into account the possibility of civil
disobedience or morally inspired evasion.19

Thus, the "bad man" does not seem to have a monopoly even when it
comes to the predictive theory of the law. Rather, to understand how the law
works in practice, we must take into consideration both the "bad" people who
evade it because it conflicts with their private agendas, and the "good" people
who evade it because it conflicts with their sense of justice. For if we assume that
good people usually do not disobey law, or that people who disobey law usually
are not good, we assume an equation between law and justice that Holmes himself
would never have accepted.

II. The Self-Reliant Individual

We seem to have reached an impasse. The famous passage that almost


everyone has regarded as a definitive statement both of Holmes's positivism and
his predictive theory of law turns out to undermine itself. The distinction *894
between "good" and "bad" people does not do the work that Holmes intended.

It is time to discard the confused metaphor of the "bad man" and


exchange it for one more relevant, anddare we say itmore authentic to
Holmes's life and thought. Almost thirty years ago, one of us (Levinson)
completed a dissertation on Holmes that argued, among other things, that he could

19And we must not forget that the line between moral objection to law
and personal self-interest is often difficult to draw. Human motives are often
untidy mixtures of conviction and opportunism.

10
1998 THE BAD, THE GOOD, AND THE SELF-RELIANT 11

be understood as an Emersonian.20 Much of the argument was biographical,


focusing, for example, on the fact that Emerson was well known to the Holmes
household and that Holmes indeed acknowledged the influence. Thus, Holmes in
1876 sent the Concord philosopher a note to accompany one of his first legal
essays: "Accept this little piece as . . . a slight mark of the gratitude and respect I
feel for you who more than anyone else first started the philosophical ferment in
my mind."21 Lest one think this is mere flattery written for the occasion, note
Holmes's 1930 comment to Sir Frederick Pollock, one of his oldest friends, that
"[t]he only firebrand of my youth that burns to me as brightly as ever is
Emerson."22 If Emerson was Holmes's "firebrand," burning brightly in both youth
and old age, perhaps it is time to offer an Emersonian reading of The Path of the
Law. Indeed, many arguments, images, and turns of phrases in Emerson's most
famous essay, Self-Reliance,23 could with little effort find a home in The Path of
the Law.

An Emersonian reading is consistent with the larger themes of Holmes's


life and work. Nevertheless, we cannot establish a definitive and direct influence
from Self-Reliance to The Path of the Law, much less argue that Holmes
"intended" the reading that we are about to offer, though we believe that our
reading does no violence to the text. What we do insist, though, is that we can
understand Holmes better if we read him through Emerson, and if we look at law
through the eyes of the "self-reliant individual" rather than the "bad man." Why
Holmes chose the "bad man" rather than "the self-reliant man" as his provocative
metaphor is beyond our abilities to answer. David Seipp has suggested in an
interesting and highly provocative essay that The *895 Path of the Law is
basically a sport.24 It was the product of numerous factors, including Holmes's

20 SeeSanford Levinson, Skepticism, Democracy, and Judicial Restraint:


An Essay on the Thought of Oliver Wendell Holmes and Felix Frankfurter (1969)
(unpublished Ph.D. dissertation, Harvard University) (on file with author).

21Mark DeWolfe Howe, Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes: The Shaping


Years, 1841-1870, at 203 (1957).

22 Holmes-Pollock Letters: The Correspondence of Mr. Justice Holmes


and Sir Frederick Pollock, 1874-1932, at 264 (Mark DeWolfe Howe ed., 2d ed.
1961). Holmes also reproached Harold Laski for criticizing Emerson: "Emerson, I
think, had the gift of imparting a ferment.... To my ear some of Emerson's
sentences sing, or did when I read them, enchantingly." Holmes-Laski Letters:
The Correspondence of Mr. Justice Holmes and Harold J. Laski, 1916-1935, at
474 (Mark DeWolfe Howe ed., 1953).

23Ralph Waldo Emerson, Self-Reliance, in Essays and Essays: Second


Series 35-73 (Morse Peckham ed., 1969).

24 See David J. Seipp, Holmes's Path, 77 B.U. L. Rev. 515, 516 (1997).

11
12 THE BAD, THE GOOD, AND THE SELF-RELIANT 1998

general desire to shock his tender-hearted listeners,25 his joie de vivre sparked by
an affair of the heart with Lady Clare Castletown,26 and possibly even Holmes's
acquaintance with Melville Davisson Post's The Strange Schemes of Randolph
Mason, a book "contain [[ing] seven stories about a mysterious New York lawyer
who advised clients how to commit murder and other crimes without legal
consequences."27 The ultimate validity of Seipp's arguments is for historians and
biographers to determine. Nevertheless, we think the terminology of
"self-reliance" not only works better analytically, it also makes Holmes's
argument more attractive, anddare we say itmore Holmesian.

"Every law which the state enacts, indicates a fact in human nature; that
is all."28 This Emersonian dictum, with its heavily inflected "every" and "all" (try
speaking the sentence aloud), suggests a positivized notion of law that deprives it
of any necessary majesty (or legitimacy) to supplement its brute existence. To be
sure, Emerson, like Holmes, would not have questioned the premise that many
laws do have moral grandeur, but this is a completely contingent fact. The
"essence" of law, as it were, is its amorality, its facticity.29

25 See id. at 537.

26 See id.

27 Id. at 542.

28 Ralph Waldo Emerson, History, in Essays and Essays: Second Series,


supra note 23, at 9.

29 Perhaps the best example of this point is the Fugitive Slave Act, which
Emerson openly despised. See Robert D. Richardson, Emerson: The Mind on Fire
495-99 (1995). Indeed, so fervent was his opposition that in an 1854 speech on
the Act he sounded almost like a natural lawyer. Pronouncing it an "immoral
law," Emerson suggested that "an immoral law cannot be valid." See Ralph
Waldo Emerson, The Fugitive Slave Act, in The Selected Writings of Ralph
Waldo Emerson 866 (Brooks Atkinson ed., 1950). Nevertheless, Emerson had no
illusions that the Fugitive Slave Act was not valid law from the standpoint of the
legal system, and he denounced "[t]his filthy enactment" as "the most detestable
law that was ever enacted by a civilized state" and announced that "I will not obey
it by God." Richardson, supra, at 498. Emerson scathingly attacked Massachusetts
judges for their willingness to collaborate with slavery by enforcing the Fugitive
Slave Law: "What avails their learning or veneration? At a pinch, they are no
more use than idiots." Id. at 881. And he delivered a strong speech on November
18, 1859, on behalf of John Brown, even as Brown stood condemned to death for
his raid on Harper's Ferry. See Ralph Waldo Emerson, John Brown, in Selected
Writings of Ralph Waldo Emerson, supra, at 879-882.

12
1998 THE BAD, THE GOOD, AND THE SELF-RELIANT 13

If moral grandeur is not a product of the sheer fact of enactment,


neither is it the product of mere age. There is an obvious affinity between
Holmes's and Emerson's views of history. Whatever Holmes's fame as an historian
of the common law, he accorded the past no intrinsic moral authority. In The
*896 Path of the Law itself, Holmes "look[s] forward to a time when the part
played by history in the explanation of dogma shall be very small,"30 and of
course the same essay includes his famous and flamboyant pronouncement that
"[i]t is revolting to have no better reason for a rule of law than that so it was laid
down in the time of Henry IV."31 One has little doubt that Emerson would have
applauded these sentiments. "Whence then this worship of the past?"32 Emerson
wrote. "The centuries are conspirators against the sanity and majesty of the
soul."33

And consider what is almost certainly the most famous single passage
from Self-Reliance: "Whoso would be a man must be a nonconformist. He who
would gather immortal palms must not be hindered by the name of goodness, but
must explore if it be goodness. Nothing is at last sacred but the integrity of our
own mind."34 These words are so famous that we must struggle to avoid thinking
of them as cliches. In one sense this is ironic given that Emerson, like Holmes, is
attacking the power of cliches. But reading these words afresh, it is not too much
of a stretch to interpret Emerson, in Self-Reliance, as arguing that the standard
beliefs and notions of one's society (including, of course, any naive joinder of law
and morality) should be washed in what his disciple Holmes called "cynical
acid."35 Above all, Emerson thought, the self-reliant individual must avoid
confusing what society calls good with what really is good.

In this passage Emerson offers his own "hermeneutics of suspicion"


about the ordinary language of morality. "Good and bad," he tells us, "are but
names very readily transferable to that or this; the only right is what is after my
constitution, the only wrong what is against it. . . . I am ashamed to think how
easily we capitulate to badges and names, to large societies and dead

30 Holmes, supra note 1, at 474, 78 B.U. L. Rev. at 712.

31 Id. at 469, 78 B.U. L. Rev. at 708.

32 Emerson, supra note 23, at 54.

33 Id.

34 Id. at 41.

35 Oliver Wendell Holmes, Address Delivered at the Dedication of the


New Hall of the Boston University School of Law (Jan. 8, 1897), quoted in Seipp,
supra note 24, at 551.

13
14 THE BAD, THE GOOD, AND THE SELF-RELIANT 1998

institutions."36 Ultimately, "[w]hat I [and presumably you, the implied reader]


must do, is all that concerns me [and all that should concern you], not what people
think . . . ."37 The world is full of busybodies "who think they know what is your
duty better than you do."38 Undoubtedly, they also enact laws that purport to
announce our duties. Emerson tells us "[i]t is easy in the world to live after the
world's opinion; but the great man is he who in the midst of the crowd keeps with
perfect sweetness the independence of *897 solitude."39

To be sure, what Emerson finds "sweet" others might denounce as a


kind of radical egoism. At times Emerson's "great man" seems to be a sort of
Nietzschean Ubermensch, ready to attack social pieties and work for the
"transvaluation" of values too easily taken for granted. (Indeed, Nietzsche's
admiration for Emerson is by now well-established, and both Richard Posner and
David Luban, among others, have noted the similarities between Holmes and
Nietzsche.40 ) We ought to recognize that the Emersonian "great man" who
discards society's values is not necessarily a more admirable figure than the
"conformist" who clings to conventional values. That obviously depends on the
values themselves. Under some circumstances, the "great man" might be a very
"bad man" indeed, while we would all express relief for the presence of
conformists among us even if their "goodness" is simply due to the fact that they
blindly follow a law that is basically just. Yet the transvaluing great person might
also be genuinely great, and later generations might honor such great people
precisely because they possessed sufficient resources of "self- reliance" to avoid
callow submission to banal notions of duty, including those congealed in the law
of their time.

Today people might object to Emerson's views on very different


grounds: They might contend that the Emersonian conception of self-reliance is
unrealistic in the late twentieth century, in which the social construction of the
individual is so well-accepted as to become a cliche. How can we believe in
Emerson's principle of self-reliance, foreswearing the opinions of the community,
when our very forms of understandingincluding the very notion of the "self"
that ostensibly understandsare shaped by the community? Whatever else might

36 Emerson, supra note 23, at 42.

37 Id. at 469, 78 B.U. L. Rev. at 708.

38 Id.

39 Id.

40 See, e.g., Richard A. Posner, Introduction to The Essential Holmes at


xviii-ix (Richard A. Posner ed., University of Chicago Press 1992); David Luban,
Justice Holmes and the Metaphysics of Judicial Restraint, 44 Duke L.J. 449, 478
n.96 (1994).

14
1998 THE BAD, THE GOOD, AND THE SELF-RELIANT 15

be said about our attempt to wed Holmes and Emerson, isn't the very notion of
self-reliance implausible in our jaded age of social constructionism and
post-modernism?

In fact, we think that Emerson makes as much sense in our age as in his
own. What Emerson meant by self-reliance was naturalness and spontaneity: the
ability and the will to follow one's nature, regardless of how that nature came to
be. That nature has power over us regardless of our attempts to evade it.41 This is
the real meaning of his often quoted and often misunderstood *898 expression
that "[a] foolish consistency is the hobgoblin of little minds."42 Emerson's point
was that we should not strain to act consistently with what we thought was right in
the past. Rather, our moral imagination should be forward-looking, without fear
of contradicting some past self of ours that had, perhaps, decided an issue
differently. Indeed, fears of contradiction are illusory, for the consistency of our
moral character will shine through:

I suppose no man can violate his nature. All the sallies of his will are
rounded in by the law of his being as the inequalities of Andes and
Himmaleh are insignificant in the curve of the sphere. Nor does it matter
how you gauge and try him. A character is like an acrostic or
Alexandrian stanza; read it forward, backward, or across, it still spells
the same thing. 43

Emerson did not deny that one's nature is shaped by the influence of
society; he merely insisted that each of us has a specific nature, that itis unique
and that it makes of each of us a unique individual. Indeed, he insisted that we
will return to our natureswhether socially constructed or otherwiseas
inevitably as the point of a compass returns to the magnetic north. For Emerson,
nature was not in contradiction to human freedom, but its source. Our natures may
be shaped by living in society, but the exercise of our moral judgment, and the
application of our sense of decency, are our own and no one else's. Some people

41 Indeed, the problem that social constructivism seems to pose for


Emerson's notion of self-reliance is already produced by his recurrent emphasis
on the trope of "nature" and "the natural." Emerson often suggests that the Self is
a manifestation of Nature, and that each individual is compelled to follow his or
her own nature. If the Self is so dependent on Nature, what can it mean to be
"self-reliant" ? This is neither the time nor the place for a detailed exegesis of the
concepts of Self and Nature in Emerson's thought. What we do wish to emphasize,
however, is that the language of social construction does not fundamentally alter a
problem that already appears in Emerson's writings.

42 Emerson, supra note 23, at 47.

43 Id. at 48.

15
16 THE BAD, THE GOOD, AND THE SELF-RELIANT 1998

are cowards and others are courageous, some are conformists and others rebels,
and this is true regardless of the fact that the nature of all is socially constructed.

Emerson's self-reliant individual rejects the rule of others and stands as


the model figure of the independent self. It takes relatively little effort to see
Holmes's own idealized self-portrait as just such an autonomous, relentlessly
independent, thinker. Consider, for example, Holmes's remarks about the Arctic
explorer Nansen, offered to Brown students at their 1897 commencement (the
same year as Holmes's talk at Boston University).44 As he speaks of Nansen, one
can easily imagine him speaking of himself. "In the first stage" of exploration,
Holmes remarks, "one has companions."45 "But if he is a man of high
ambitions"46 and who can doubt from even the barest acquaintance with
Holmes's life that his own ambitions were the highest?"he must leave even his
fellow-adventurers and go forth into a deeper solitude and greater trials. He must
start for the pole. In plain words he must face the loneliness of original work. No
one can cut out new paths in company. He *899 does that alone."47 This is
self-reliance indeed. Even if we find this language somewhat hyperbolic, and even
if we accept the communitarian criticisms of the "self as autonomous chooser,"48
we suspect that very few Americans can resist entirely the power of Holmes's
imagery and its Emersonian call to question authority and decide for oneself how
to live one's life. (Perhaps, a communitarian might respond, the resonance of these
words in the American soul shows how much we are constituted by our identity as
Americans.)

Yet choices always are made within a context, including the brute facts
that effectively structure the options open to oneself. For most of us these facts
certainly include law and institutions of law enforcement. Because there are laws
and because there is law enforcement, there may come occasions when, as
Thoreau suggested to his friend Emerson, the only place for the genuinely "good
man" is in jail, or fighting alongside a vigilante like John Brown. The self-reliant
man may have to surrender his liberty or his life to rid the world of an evil like
slavery. Presumably, Emerson's failure to join Thoreau behind bars in opposition

44 See Oliver Wendell Holmes, Address at Brown University


Commencement, in 3 Collected Works of Justice Holmes 518 (Sheldon Novick
ed., 1995).

45 Id.

46 Id.

47 Id.

48See Michael J. Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice 1-183


(1982); Michael J. Sandel, The Procedural Republic and the Unencumbered Self,
12 Pol. Theory 81, 81-97 (1984).

16
1998 THE BAD, THE GOOD, AND THE SELF-RELIANT 17

to the Mexican War and to the expansionist slavocracy behind the War is
evidence that he did not think the benefits of civil disobedience worth the price. It
is impossible, though, to believe that this prophet of self-reliance would have
castigated Thoreau for daring to question the authority of the state. In any case,
"self-reliant" individuals those who choose (and take genuine responsibility for)
their own values and actionswould have every incentive to ask about the
consequences of their contemplated actions (including the legal consequences)
and then to decide accordingly.

III. The Self-Reliant Individual and Legal Governance

In this essay we have argued that one can easily replace the Holmesian
"bad man" with the the self-reliant individual without loss. Indeed, the
substitution comes with considerable gain. Self-reliant individuals include not
only criminals and egoists, but also people like Thoreau, or John Brown, who
decide to violate the law in the interest of what they believe is a higher good. To
understand the law, we must take into account not only people who violate law
because of wicked motives or callous self-interest, but people who violate it
because they have the courage to stand up to what the rest of us know is unjust,
and people who violate it because they judge it inconsistent with their values,
whether these values seem right or wrong in our eyes.

Our rejection of the metaphor of the "bad man" is based on our


conviction that to understand law we must also understand the different varieties
of human character and motivation. We do not think that our emphasis on these
matters is at all inconsistent with the sort of tough-minded positivism that *900
Holmes attempted to offer us in The Path of the Law. Quite the contrary, we think
that it has always been implicit in the positivist vision. Consider as an example
H.L.A. Hart's eloquent argument on behalf of the rigorous separation of law and
morality:
So long as human beings can gain sufficient co-operation from some
to enable them to dominate others, they will use the forms of law as one of their
instruments. Wicked men will enact wicked rules which others will enforce. What
surely is most needed in order to make men clear-sighted in confronting the
official abuse of power, is that they should preserve the sense that the certification
of something as legally valid is not conclusive of the question of obedience, and
that, however great the aura of majesty or authority which the official system may
have, its demands must in the end be submitted to a moral scrutiny.49

Moreover, a shift to the "self-reliant" individual is valuable because it


emphasizes the multiplicity of perspectives about the law. As lawyers we are often
trained to think of the law in terms of governance; that is, we understand the law
from the perspective of the state, which wants to know what set of rules will
create the right incentives for behavior leading to the effects the state desires to

49 H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law 210 (2d ed. 1994).

17
18 THE BAD, THE GOOD, AND THE SELF-RELIANT 1998

produce. This instrumental conception of law views law essentially as the servant
of public policy goals; it stands in marked contrast to a conception of law as the
protector of individual rights (or a private sphere of individual liberty) on the one
hand, and a vision of law as the working out of the inherent logic of existing
doctrinal categories on the other. This instrumental conception is entirely familiar
to American legal scholars, especially those living in the generations after Legal
Realism. It is the conception that Holmes promoted and announced as the wave of
the future in The Path of the Law. Indeed, The Path of the Law stands as one of
the first programmatic statements of the instrumental conception.

But in opposing the instrumental conception of law to other


conceptionssuch as the protection of rights or the elaboration of doctrine, we
tend to forget another important aspect of this visionthat it is a conception of
law that views matters from the perspective of the state and its agents. It is a
conception in which individuals and groups are objects of governance by the
state. They are collected, organized, selected, rejected, coerced, bribed, taxed,
subsidized, punished, and rewarded in order to achieve particular ends. The "bad
man" fits well into this perspective, because the "bad man" is simply another of
the conceptual tools that the state uses to determine the appropriate mix of
incentivesbe they inducements or punishments, carrots or sticksto push,
cajole, and direct subjects into appropriate forms of behavior. If the "bad man"
regards the law as little more than a pricing system, the law can happily respond
by setting the appropriate prices.

Focusing on the self-reliant individual, however, requires us to look at


law *901 from the perspective of an individual, living within a matrix of legal
regulation, and subject to its punishments, who regards it with no particular sense
of moral awe or legitimation, and even as a potential obstacle to the achievement
of the good and the just. One could, of course, say this is exactly what Holmes
meant by the "bad man," and we do not deny the potential truth of this. What we
do deny is that "bad man" is a felicitious way of evoking someone committed to
the moral life and concerned that a life lived entirely within the law may lead in
fact to immorality and injustice.

From the state's perspective, the "best" citizen is precisely the one who
believes that law is self-justifying and who will, sheep-like, do whatever the law
requires. The second best citizen is a certain kind of "bad man," who simply
wants to avoid pain and discomfort and hence can be made an object of
governance by providing the optimal mixture of rewards and punishments,
subsidies and taxes, carrots and sticks necessary to achieve the state's goals. In
Emersonian terms, the state may well be happiest with people who either do not
know their own minds, because they are mired in conventional ways of thinking
and behaving, or people who can safely be treated as unproblematically
predictable objects of impersonal incentive structures. The self-reliant individual,
on the other hand, is the most dangerous to the state, for this individual denies the
state its accustomed moral legitimacy, and resists being treated as an mere object
of prediction and structuring. The greatest threats to the state, in other words, are
those people who have the courage to think for themselves.

18
1998 THE BAD, THE GOOD, AND THE SELF-RELIANT 19

Both the Holmesian "bad man" and the Emersonian "self-reliant"


individual understand that the law does not legitimate itself. Each is determined to
go his or her own way. But the self-reliant citizen is more dangerous in this sense:
The self-reliant individual understands that ovine acceptance of the legal status
quo may threaten not only one's personal safety (like complacent sheep on the
way to slaughter), but, far more importantly, one's integrity, because one ends up
collaborating with what is in fact an evil regime. We should teach our students
that there is nothing "bad" about accepting Holmes's basic structure of analysis,
though it may well be "bad" to be the kind of radical egoist that Holmes's
language suggests. But we should also remind them that the alternative to radical
selfishness is not giving over one's conscience to the legal sovereign. It is, instead,
to adopt a genuine responsibility for one's own thoughts and deeds.

We think that this Emersonian interpretation puts Holmes's theory of


law in a much more admirable light. At the same time, we recognize that it is
possible that these conclusions are not Holmesian at all.50 Holmes was a complex
character whose personality displayed many seemingly contradictory sides.51
Perhaps the true Holmes was the one who suggested that his *902 epitaph should
be "Here lies a supple tool of power."52 Perhaps Holmes really meant it when he
followed his reference to the "bad man" by avowing that "[t]he law is the witness
and external deposit of our moral life" and that "[t]he practice of it, in spite of
popular jests, tends to make good citizens and good men."53 After all, we know
that Holmes was a statist, and the state, of course, is always worried about the
presence of too many self-reliant citizens who question its authority.54 Perhaps for
all of Holmes's iconoclasm and desire to shockwhich David Seipp offers as the

50 This would certainly be the conclusion of David Luban. See Luban,


supra note 8, at 1563-64.

51 Indeed, Posner noted that Holmes's thinking demonstrated a wide


variety of often contradictory philosophical strains. See Posner, supra note 40, at
xix-xx (detailing that one could find pragmatism, altruism, liberalism,
materialism, aestheticism, utilitarianism, militarism, and other strains in Holmes's
work).

52 Yosal Rogat, The Judge as Spectator, 31 U. Chi. L. Rev. 213, 249- 50


(1964) (quoting Holmes).

53 Holmes, supra note 1, at 459, 78 B.U. L. Rev. at 700.

54 Indeed, one might argue that he was a statist of a particularly


unattractive kind. David Luban claims that while H.L.A. Hart insisted that the
state had to be more than a "gunman writ large," Luban, supra note 8, at 1566
(quoting H.L.A. Hart, Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals, 71 Harv.
L. Rev. 593, 603 (1958), Holmes "did think of the state as a gunman writ large,"
id., and that the state was no less admirable for that.

19
20 THE BAD, THE GOOD, AND THE SELF-RELIANT 1998

best way to understand The Path of the LawHolmes remained at root an utterly
conventional conformist.

If so, that is not a Holmes that we think it worthy to commemorate a


century later. We much prefer the Holmes who was true to his Emersonian roots.
We much prefer the Holmes who preached the gospel of self-reliance, both in his
words and through his deeds. That is the Holmes worth remembering. That is the
Holmes we celebrate today.

20

You might also like