Social Meaning and Philosophical Method: Citation

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 25

Social Meaning and Philosophical Method

The MIT Faculty has made this article openly available. Please share
how this access benefits you. Your story matters.

Citation Haslanger, Sally. "Social Meaning and Philosophical Method."


American Philosophical Association 110th Eastern Division
Annual Meeting (December 2013).
As Published http://c.ymcdn.com/sites/www.apaonline.org/resource/resmgr/ea
stern2013/e2013_meeting_program.pdf
Publisher American Philosophical Association

Version Author's final manuscript


Accessed Sun Oct 16 19:42:24 EDT 2016
Citable Link http://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/97049
Terms of Use Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-Share Alike
Detailed Terms http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/4.0/
Social Meaning and Philosophical Method

...political subversion presupposes cognitive


subversion, a conversion of the vision of the world.
(Bourdieu 1982, 127-8)
1. Preamble

There are special challenges in writing a Presidential Address: you want to address a very broad

group of philosophers with knowledge and abilities that far exceed your own, and you want to say

something that will be as engaging as possible. Philosophers have addressed a great many issues,

with different methods, and I want there to be space in our discipline for all of them. I myself

love arcane philosophical topics put me in a world where I could spend my time pouring over

Aristotles Metaphysics and Id be happy and I believe that philosophy yields knowledge and

that is intrinsically valuable. I also love kinds of philosophy that many would not regard as

philosophy at all: philosophy as it emerges in thinking about personal and family issues,

philosophy in the context of political activism, and philosophy that is inextricable from empirical

research.

However, I am also critical of philosophy as a discipline. The way I would like to frame

my critique, at least today, is not in terms of what is included in philosophy, but in terms of what

is often left out or devalued. The spirit behind my talk is one of invitation: an invitation to think

about more issues, to explore different histories, topics, and methods deserving of philosophical

attention. There are many philosophers who are already engaged in the project that I will

describe, so Im not just sketching my research agenda. Rather, I will be attempting to frame

research that some are already doing in a new light. I hope this will encourage others to

appreciate it in ways they havent before, and potentially inspire them to contribute.

2. Social Justice

Feminist philosophers and critical race theorists have complained that contemporary Anglophone

philosophy, although sometimes useful, is not as valuable as it might be for our projects. A

primary concern is that analytic philosophy is overly individualistic. Another is that it is

1
insufficiently sensitive to the context of theorizing, e.g., the social and political facts that give rise

to the questions we ask (and dont ask), the methods we endorse (and dont), and the implications

of our theories for living together. A theme in both of these concerns is that there is a lack of

attention to the social domain, both as a subject for our theorizing and its influence on us as

theorizers. Today I would like to explore these concerns and to consider how analytic philosophy

might contribute more fruitfully to efforts to achieve social justice.

Where should we look for a theory of social justice? On the one hand, mainstream

analytic political philosophers spend a lot of time thinking about the State and institutions that

form the basic structure of society, but (perhaps due to the influence of political liberalism) do

not consider the micro-politics embedded in the practices of everyday life. Ethicists, on the other

hand, tend to focus on individual action (character, will) and often dont even consider that an

agent, in acting, is engaged in a social practice. This may be a serious misrepresentation of recent

history of philosophy. However, even if it is a distortion, I think it is worth making a case for

more systematic attention to the domain of social justice, i.e., the domain that we have reason to

think is outside the states purview, but where we are talking about structures and practices and

not just individual thoughts and actions.

Although the Womens Movement and the Civil Rights Movement achieved great gains

in the 20th century, and the LGBT Rights Movement and Disability Rights Movement are doing

so in the 21st, our societies remain unjustly stratified. Racial and ethnic minorities, women,

LGBTQ communities, non-citizens, the disabled, the poor, and others, are categorically

disadvantaged; and this disadvantage is systematic and durable (Tilly 1999). There is no doubt

that both individuals and social institutions play a role in causing this stratification. But persistent

inequality is not simply a result of the bad or unjust actions of individuals or badly structured

institutions.

2
Individuals obviously play a role in causing injustice, but a set of good or morally

responsible individuals doesnt necessarily make a just society. Good people can behave in ways

that are individually permissible, but nevertheless their actions result in outcomes that are unjust:

The cumulative effects of a series of transactions, each of which satisfies the local criteria

of justice, and which begins from a just starting point, may be disastrous. Asset markets

can suffer from speculative booms and busts that throw millions of innocent people out of

work and into poverty. (Anderson 2012, 164)

One source of this problem is that good individuals can suffer from blameless ignorance about the

context and the consequences of their actions.

Moreover, morally responsible individuals sometimes live in badly organized societies,

so given their feasible options, they cannot avoid contributing to injustice. No matter how

morally scrupulous, a poor person may have no choice but to purchase food and clothing that are

produced unjustly; a wealthy person may pay taxes that are used for corrupt or unjust purposes.

Under conditions of oppression, groups are systematically positioned in relations that are morally

problematic, e.g., a group may be exploited or culturally marginalized (Young 1990). Such

positioning is typically the result of broad social forces that are not under any individuals control.

As Charles Tilly puts it:

whatever else we have learned about inequality, social scientists have made clear that a

great deal of social inequality results from indirect, unintended, collective, and

environmentally mediated effects.... (Tilly 2002, 28)

It is important to recognize that the wrongfulness of a structure goes beyond individual

wrongdoing. Oppressive structures organize social life so there are entrenched roles that require

whoever occupies them to wrong or harm others.1 We may grant that individuals who occupy

such roles do wrong, but to point only to the individual actions is to miss the fact that the

1
Thanks very much to Tom Dougherty for making this point in conversation and pushing me to develop it.
My point here draws on Haslanger 2014.

3
structure will find ways to position someone or other in that role. For example, in oppressive

work conditions, a manager will be responsible for many unjust hardships the employees face.

But even if a particular manager quits, there will be others who replace him or her, since the

broader social structure may offer few options for those who reasonably seek to avoid poverty or

to develop their talents. Even if we suppose that each of the individual managers acts badly, there

is a further bad or wrong in the structure of the workplace and the broader society. (Note also that

good structures likewise provide roles for people to do good; structures can facilitate, by the roles

they make available, vision, creativity, generosity, leadership, and other good things.)

Unfortunately, justice is not simply a matter of well-structured institutions either. Let us

assume for the purposes of argument that Rawlss theory of justice is a good example of a theory

that applies to the basic structure of society. G. A. Cohen has argued that a just structure is not

enough to achieve justice, for legitimate choices and preferences within a just structure can tilt it

towards injustice:

A society that is just within the terms of the difference principle, so we may conclude,

requires not simply just coercive rules, but also an ethos of justice that informs individual

choices. In the absence of such an ethos, inequalities will obtain that are not necessary to

enhance the condition of the worst off: the required ethos promotes a distribution more

just than what the rules of the economic game by themselves can secure. (Cohen 1997,

10; also Cohen 2000, 119-123)

Cohen frames his critique of Rawls by echoing the feminist slogan the personal is political.

But note that Cohens observation is that the additional condition necessary for justice lies in the

social ethos. The idea seems to be that culture matters, and further, culture is not just a matter of

individual psychology or political institutions. Even if Cohens critique of Rawls is not wholly

persuasive, he is right to draw attention to culture as a further site of moral concern.

Is there really a separate domain of social justice? One might object from two sides, the

individual and the political. On the individual side, the claim would be that good people arrange

4
themselves in ways that prevent injustice, so if there is injustice, some people must not really be

doing the right thing. On the political side the claim is that if you have justice in the basic

institutions of society usually understood these days in Rawlsian terms then thats all justice

requires. Under such conditions things might not be perfect, but thats due to moral wrongdoing.

It isnt injustice.

I find both of these arguments startling. If the Civil Rights Movement and Womens

Movement of the late 20th century taught us anything, they taught us that state action cannot reach

many sources of bias that are responsible for persistent inequality, and this persistent inequality is

unjust. The state cant tell us whom to love, trust, or admire; it cant tell us what to aspire to,

where to live, what to care about. But these issues arent just a matter of individual psychology

and individual agency either, for who we are and how we live is conditioned by the social

practices and social meanings that structure our lives. As individuals, we arent responsible for

social meanings (though we must constantly navigate them) or social practices (though we can act

to resist or sustain them). Good people enact problematic practices: they may enact them

unintentionally or without awareness; they may even think that the behavior in question is

entirely natural and they have no choice; or they may not be in a position to have any idea they

are problematic. Many of the practices in question cannot be ruled out by state intervention and

so could occur even within a politically just society. (See also Cohen 1997, 2000.)

Maybe the suggestion that, Good people arrange themselves in ways that prevent

injustice, is exactly the problem. Good people are, by the time they are socialized, already

arranged. We are embedded in social meanings. We live in a social world structured by practices.

It is true, of course, that these meanings and practices can change. But the change must be social

change, collective change, cultural change.

These broad considerations introduce several aspects of social justice worth considering.

5
Collective responsibility. Because we together constitute the social world, we are responsible

for the injustices it embodies. But it may be that none of us is individually (or the State,

given the limits of its purview) is responsible for the injustice.

Collective action. Society depends on social coordination, and the terms of that coordination

may be unjust. My being morally perfect may do nothing to change the terms of coordination

that dominate the social context. (In order to make a difference, we must organize.) And

many forms of social coordination are not apt for State management.

Socially embedded agency: the terms of our action and interaction are not up to us as

individuals. What is valuable, what is acceptable, even what we do, and want, and think,

depend on cultural frameworks of meaning.

In this essay, I will focus on the third aspect. Given that all action by individuals or the state

occurs within a cultural context that gives it meaning, one might argue that individual and

institutional injustice are just the tip of the iceberg. These injustices are the manifestation of

deeper and less tractable sources of inequality in culture, or social meaning. But what exactly is

social meaning?

3. Social Structures

The concepts of social structure, social practices, and social relations are not common sense

concepts. As I use them, anyway, they are theoretical notions. They enable us to identify and

explain certain persistent patterns and dependencies in human interaction. Social structures, on

the view I endorse, are networks of social relations. For example, domestic life is structured by

family and kinship relations (between spouses, children, pets, extended family, other sorts of

chosen family and friends), relations to property (a home, a car, food), and, in some cases,

employees who contribute to caregiving and upkeep. These relations take different forms

depending on the cultural context and family history.

6
On the account I favor, social relations need not be intentional or conscious. For example,

a sequence of individual owners of a car, or employees sequentially holding a position in a

company, may constitute a vacancy chain, without knowing each other (Martin 2009, 9);

individuals within these chains stand in a social relation, and such chains may (or may not) come

to have significance for an insurance company or a corporate manager. One may stand in

complex kinship relations to others one has never heard of (having never heard of the kinds of

kinship relations in question, or the individual others). We each stand in multiple civic

relationships to members of city, state and federal government without knowledge or intention.

Social relations need not be transparent either: I may not understand the nature of my

relations with others and may actually misunderstand our relationship. For example, I may think

of the group I am part of to be united by virtue of being Gods chosen people. But there may be

no God, and even if there is, God may not have established a special covenant with any group.

Nevertheless, the social group could exist in spite of such false beliefs. In fact, an explanatory

social theory may explicitly debunk social self-understandings by redescribing our social

relations in terms we, the participants, would reject.

In core cases, social relations are constituted through practices.2 There are many different

accounts of what it is to be a practice, and they seem to fall on continuum between thin and

thick conceptions. On the thinnest conception, practices are simply patterns of interaction,

regularities in our behavior. One kind of thick conception focuses on a subset of these patterns,

in particular, those that emerge because the participants understand their normative

responsibility to act in a certain way (Martin 2009, 7). Different thick conceptions vary, e.g.,

with respect to whether only intentional actions count as performances of a practice (and how

intentional), the degree of common knowledge of the norms or of other participants is required,

the kind of normativity at issue, etc. If one adopts a thick conception of practices according to

2
I am not aiming to provide necessary and sufficient conditions for social relations, social practices, social
structures, and the like. I favor a focal approach to most concepts and the first step is to identify the cases
that are central for the theoretical purposes at hand. (Haslanger 2012, 7, 21, 228)

7
which the existence of a practice depends on shared expectations, and if one builds social

relations and social structure from this base, then, social structure is ultimately a matter of shared

expectations, leaving no gap between the subjective conceptions of actors and the action patterns

that an analysis might uncover (Martin 2009, 6).3 If we want to allow the theoretical possibility

that agents can be confused or misled about the social structures that they enact, then we must

either adopt a conception of practice on the thinner end of the spectrum, or deny that structures

are built up from practices.

I take it as a broadly shared background assumption that social structures dont exist apart

from our collective behavior. Their existence depends on our actions and interactions. However,

because the notions of social structure and social relations are introduced to be explanatory, we

should not take them to be just any regularities in behavior. Certain regularities, especially

certain robust regularities, are what we want explained. Moreover, as suggested above, we also

want to allow that we participate in structures and, in doing so partly constitute them, without an

awareness of what we are doing, and without intending to.4 Structures that we constitute in and

through our behavior can be revealed to us. So the thicker conceptions of practice are not apt for

our purposes. It seems promising, then, to develop a notion of practice falling somewhere

between the thickest and thinnest according to which they give rise to social relations and

structures, but need not be intentionally loaded.5

Let us consider some examples. Our practices relate us to each other and to the material

world; they situate us at nodes in the structure. Consider cooking:

3
Bicchieri (2006, 11) defines social norms in terms of shared expectations. If one also holds that practices
are patterns of behavior guided by social norms, then one seems to assume transparency.
4
It is also significant that nonhuman animals seem to live in social structures without a capacity for
sophisticated intentional agency.
5
It is not part of my project to insist that we use the term practice for the notion I am developing. Within
the practice tradition in social science, I believe that this thinner notion is common, but some
philosophers clearly use the term in a thicker sense.

8
Cooking rice is an instance of a more general practice of cooking, and regular

engagement in the practice is constitutive of a social role: cook. Being a cook relates one

in specific ways to other persons (not only the customer or family, but also the farmer,

grocer, garbage collector, sources of recipes, including traditions, cookbooks, etc.), and

also relates one in specific ways to things (foodstuffs, sources of heat, water, utensils).

Cooking is only possible within a social structure that provides the ingredients, skills,

tools; the norms for taste, texture and ingredients; the distribution of labor of cooks and

consumers, etc.

Keeping examples such as these in mind, how should we characterize a practice? Social

practices are, in the central cases, ways of organizing ourselves either towards some end or goal,

or in response to a coordination or access problem. To say that our responses are organized is

not to say that anyone organized them. The practice may have evolved through trials and errors.

But practices will typically be, to some degree, self-sustaining. As a result, over time a practice

may become congealed and dissociated from the interests and functions that were their original

impetus.

Another example is traffic management. Traffic management is poses a coordination

problem. The road is a resource that provides passable public access to destinations. Many

people have an interest in access to the road. If we dont organize access, we have destructive

chaos. So there are practices that enable us to share the road effectively: in the United States we

drive on the right; we stop and go in response to traffic lights. Local regions develop their own

micro-practices, e.g., in Boston, if you stop at a yellow light, you are likely to be rear-ended.

Although driving on the right is a convention, practices are not always conventional. For

example, on Lewiss classic view, conventions are arbitrary solutions to coordination problems

that are mutually beneficial (this explains their stability) and are common knowledge among the

participants. However, practices may not be arbitrary: cooking is a practice, but it is not arbitrary

how or what we cook. Moreover, there may not be, in any meaningful sense, common

9
knowledge among participants what the coordination problem is or how it is being solved. It may

be that the participants cant properly be said even to know what to do in order to follow the

practice, for they may do so habitually or guided by sub-personal systems. (Burge 1975, Millikan

2008)

Further, although practices are stable patterns of behavior, a practice may not be rational

or mutually advantageous. Practices of food distribution that require women to wait until men

have taken what they want is not mutually advantageous and may be practically irrational

depending on the circumstances, e.g., during womens childbearing years, if fertility and healthy

offspring are desired. There are many (and better) ways to explain the origin and stability of

practices other than rational choice theory. And it is implausible that the mutual satisfaction of

preferences is adequate to explain the origin of a practice, for a meaningful sense of preference

with respect to the resource in question may be constituted only through the practices that

organize our responses. For example, what sort of practice will best organize our access to food?

Our relationship to food is already mediated by cultural practices that shape our preferences; there

is no culturally unmediated position from which we can judge what is tasty or disgusting, filling

or taboo.

But even returning to the conventional practices of traffic management, it is important to

note that in organizing ourselves to make effective use of the road, we dont simply agree upon

public rules that users of the road are expected learn, but also create an infrastructure that guides

our use: we create laws, signs, traffic lights, cross-walks and bike lanes, maps, cars with turn

signals and brake lights, a licensing and ticketing system for drivers, and such. In engaging in a

practice we interact, often spontaneously, with parts of the world that have been molded to be

used by the practice. Practices are materially realized.

These observations support a conception of practice that is common in contemporary

anthropology (and social science more broadly),

10
Practices consist of interdependent schemas and resources when they mutually imply

and sustain each other over time. (Sewell 1992, 13)

Roughly, schemas consist in clusters of culturally shared concepts, beliefs, and other attitudes that

enable us to interpret and organize information and coordinate action, thought, and affect. Both

concepts and beliefs, in the sense intended, store information and are the basis for various

behavioral and emotional dispositions. Although schemas are variable and evolve across time

and context, their elements are sticky and resist updating.

Resources are things of all sorts human, nonhuman, animate, or not that are taken to

have some (including negative) value (practical, moral, aesthetic, religious, etc.). In social reality,

schemas and resources are both causally and constitutively interdependent. Consider food, e.g.,

corn:

An ear of corn can be viewed as something to eat, as a commodity to be sold, as a

religious symbol. In other words, we can apply different schemas to the object, and the

schemas frame our consciousness and evaluation of the object. The different schemas not

only offer modes of interpretation, but license different ways of interacting with the corn.

Actions based on these different schemas have an effect on the ear of corn qua resource,

e.g., it might be cooked for food, or the kernels removed to be shipped, or it might be

dried and hung in a prominent place to be worshipped. The effects of our actions then

influence the schema. If the corn sells for a good price, its value is enhanced and the

farmer may seek ways to grow it more efficiently, possibly investing in new and different

varieties.

On this model:

Social practices establish patterns in our interaction with a part of the world by tuning our

collective responses to it and molding it to our responses.

Social relations are established by entrenched and repeated practices.

Systems of interdependent practices/relations are structures.

11
A social group, e.g., a gender, a race, but also farmers, nurses, the unemployed, is a set of

people who function at a node (or set of nodes) in a structure.

Schemas are the basis for social meaning.

5. Social Meaning

What is social meaning?6 Lawrence Lessig has done important work to clarify the notion:

Any society or social context has what I call here social meanings the semiotic content

attached to various actions, or inactions, or statuses, within a particular context[the

point is to] find a way to speak of the frameworks of understanding within which

individuals live; a way to describe what they take or understand various actions, or

inactions, or statuses to be; and a way to understand how the understandings change.

(Lessig 1995, pp. 951-2)

The point of saying that an action has a social meaning is to understand it as having a significance

by virtue of collective understandings, not just the personal meaning given to it by the agent (or

patient).7 Extending Lessigs suggestion, we should allow that not only actions/inactions and

statuses have social meanings, but also include things such as corn, traffic signals, money,

jewelry. After all, pink means girl and blue means boy, right? Importantly, Lessig points out,

[Social meanings] change, they are contested, and they differ across communities and

individuals. But we can speak of social meaning, and meaning management, I suggest,

without believing that there is a single, agreed upon point for any social actEven if

there is no single meaning, there is a range or distribution of meanings, and the question

we ask here is how that range gets made, and, more importantly, changed. (954-55)

6
In this section I draw on Haslanger 2014.
7
The emphasis on the social collective rather than the individual, and on the background symbolic
resources rather than speech events, also distinguishes a semiotic approach from a speech act approach to
social meaning. The speech act approach can be extremely helpful in analyzing the social import of action,
and has been developed in brilliant ways by Langton (2009), Hornsby (2000), McGowan (2004, 2009), and
others. I dont see these two approaches as competing, but as complementary.

12
Semiotics, at least on one understanding, is the study of such social meanings, what they are, how

they are created, reproduced, disrupted. On the picture I am developing, social meanings are

embedded in our practices: they included in the schemas by which we interpret resources and

which guide our interaction with each other and with the material world.8

How are social meanings relevant to social justice? In spite of the possibility of change

and contestation, the effects of social meaning are in an important way, non-optional. They

empower or constrain individuals, whether or not the individual choses the power or constraints.

(Lessig 1995, 955; see also 1000) They are the cultural backdrop for action. Although both

individual actions and institutions are sources of injustice, injustice is learned and lived through

culture. Insofar as social meanings partly constitute our social practices, and internalized

meanings guide our interactions, social justice requires attention to and changes to social

meanings.

Let me offer two sorts of examples: (a) social stigma and (b) social ideals.

a) Elizabeth Anderson characterizes racial stigmatization during Jim Crow:

The condition of racial stigmatization consists of public, dishonorable, practically

engaged representations of a racial group with the following contents: (1) racial

stereotypes, (2) racial attributions or explanations of why members of the racial group

tend to fit their stereotypes, that rationalized and motivate (3) derogatory evaluations of

and (4) demeaning or antipathetic attitudes (such as hatred contempt, pity, condescension,

disgust, aversion, envy, distrust, and willful indifference) towards the target group and its

members. (Anderson 2010, 48)

8
At this point it is unclear to me exactly how to understand the relationship between schemas, ideology,
and social meaning. In my recent work I have suggested that a groups ideology in the relevant sense of
ideology consists in its shared cultural schemas (allowing that groups much smaller than a society have
a culture). Here I suggest that social meanings are included in the schemas/ideology. Because I dont
yet have a firm grasp on the best account of social meanings, I cannot explicate further what I mean by
included in, though I want to allow that there are components of schemas/ideology that are not social
meanings.

13
Stigma, like other social meanings, and like linguistic meanings, are collective and public.

Although Anderson emphasizes the representational aspect of stigmatization, racial stigma

depends on schemas to focus attention, coordinate expectations, sift evidence, and rationalize

behavioral and emotional dispositions. Such meanings affect us and our interactions even if we

reject their content: Claude Steele gives an example of a friend, Brent Staples, whistling Vivaldi

while walking down the street in Chicago in order to counter racial stereotypes of black men and

to reassure white folks who may encounter him (Steele 2011). By choosing what music to

whistle or listen to, what to wear, how to cut or style our hair, what we eat and, in cases where we

have options, how we decorate our home and spend our free time, we are navigating social

meaning. Although stigmatization involves ascribing to and imposing on group a negative

meaning, not all social meaning is negative or oppressive. Social meanings give shape to our

lives and negotiating them is an inevitable part of living in a culture.

b) Social meanings offer resources to idealize groups as well. George Lakoff offers an

analysis of our ideal of mother in terms of five overlapping cognitive models based on birth,

genetics, nurturance, marriage, and genealogy. (Lakoff 1999, 395) He says,

more than one of these models contributes to the characterization of a real mother, and

any one of them may be absent from such a characterization. Still, the very idea that

there is such a thing as a real mother seems to require a choice among models where they

diverge. (395)

When the situation is such that the models for mother do not pick out a single individual,

we get compound expressions like stepmother, surrogate mother, adoptive mother, foster

mother, biological mother, donor mother and so on. Such compounds, of course, do not

represent simple subcategories, that is, kinds of ordinary mothers. (396)

The central case [is] where all the models converge. This includes a mother who is and

has always been female, and who gave birth to the child, supplied her half of childs

14
genes, nurtured the child, is married to the father, is one generation older than the child,

and is the childs legal guardian. (400)

Lakoff argues that further complexity is added by metonymy: the housewife-mother is, in a

particular socio-cultural context, taken to stand for the category as a whole. Thus we get further

categories: unwed mother, working mother, etc. and a representativeness structure encoding a

central ideal and norms explicable in terms of variation from the core.9

As Lakoff goes on to note, the sub-categories of mother are historically and culturally

specific. But we should also note that even the core models depend on the availability of

knowledge (genetics) and social practices (marriage). There is no general rule for generating

kinds of mothers. They are culturally defined and have to be learned. They are by no means the

same in all cultures. (401)

6. Schemas and Language

By structuring the perception which social agents


have of the social world, the act of naming helps to
establish the structure of this world...
Bourdieu (1982, 105)

Ive suggested that social meanings can be understood as schemas that are culturally assigned to

actions, objects, events, and such. Internalized schemas provide recognitional capacities, store

information, and are the basis for various behavioral and emotional dispositions. Importantly,

schemas are learned and triggered by language, especially (but not only) the language of

classification. Consider the effects of describing someone, say, Chris, as a woman, or a mother,

or a slut. Language is a social resource. It encodes the schemas that govern social life, and does

so in a way that establishes them as common sense, seemingly inevitable.10

9
See also Charlotte Witt, The Metaphysics of Gender (2011) for an account of how the fundamental
schemas for gender interact with other schemas.
10
Im not saying that the meaning of the term, say, mother is the mother-schema or that social meaning
just is linguistic meaning. The relationship between linguistic meaning and social meaning is more
complex and deserves theoretical attention.

15
As we have seen, schemas can be problematic in a variety of ways. They may

incorporate false normative or descriptive beliefs; they may be the basis for dispositions that are

morally questionable. However, they may also fail because they rely on inapt concepts.

Concepts are neither true nor false, but they can be evaluated: do we have reason to track the

distinction drawn by the concept? Should we have this or that concept in our repertoire at all? If

so, how we should construe it? What alternative concepts might we deploy instead? (See also

Fricker 2007.)

Consider, for example: slut, mother, woman. Such terms are used to carve out an

extension, to invoke a schema that attributes features to the members of the extension, to establish

links to other concepts, and guide our responses.11 Suppose that through normative inquiry we

determine that a particular social practice is misguided or unjust. One question we should ask is

how our discursive practices are implicated: how does our language support the categorization

that the social practice relies on? Does it prime us to respond in ways that are problematic, e.g.,

to stigmatize or idealize?

There is an obvious cultural stigmatization of sexually promiscuous women (sluts) in

contrast to the glorification of sexually promiscuous men (and the related blaming of rape on

women). A standard response to such shaming, of course, is to reject the term slut because it is

demeaning and serves to create a distinction that we have no good reason to mark. Recently,

however, some feminist activists have organized slut walks to challenge the evaluative content

of the slut-schema: even sexually active and provocatively clad women are not asking to be

raped. According to the Toronto Observer, the organizers of the original walk wanted to

reclaim the definition of slut as someone who is in control of their own sexuality.12 One

11
One way of thinking about the relationship between language and the various schemas or cognitive
models associated with them is in terms of mental files (Recanati 2012, Schroeter & Schroeter 2014).
12
http://torontoobserver.ca/2011/03/30/slutwalk-set-to-strut-past-queens-park-to-police-hq-on-april-3/

16
might not agree with this tactic, but it would miss the point entirely to claim that the effort is

misguided because thats just not what slut means.

What is going on here? I tentatively propose that in a particular social context the norms

governing default inferences and apt (affective, behavioral) responses depend substantively on the

schemas that are dominant in the context. The schemas license what cognitive, behavioral and

emotional responses are appropriate, given a conceptualization of something as an F. Slut walks

target our schemas, the social meanings.13

Putnam (1975) makes a related point: that in order to acquire a word, one must learn a

stereotype associated with its extension. The content of the stereotype is determined by the

linguistic community:

The nature of the required minimum level of competence depends heavily upon both the

culture and the topic, however. In our culture speakers are required to know what tigers

look like (if they acquire the word 'tiger', and this is virtually obligatory); they are not

required to know the fine details (such as leaf shape) of what an elm tree looks like.

English speakers are required by their linguistic community to be able to tell tigers from

leopards; they are not required to be able to tell elm trees from beech trees. (249)

The theoretical account of what it is to be a stereotype proceeds in terms of the notion of

linguistic obligation; a notion which we believe to be fundamental to linguistics and

which we shall not attempt to explicate here. What it means to say that being striped is

part of the (linguistic) stereotype of 'tiger' is that it is obligatory to acquire the

13
Note that I am not suggesting that the schemas are part of the linguistic meaning of the terms in
question. Rather, the schemas are (in a loose sense) conventionally linked to the terms [and other socially
meaningful stuff]. How might we develop this? We can think of conversations as guided by
conversational norms, some quite general, some specific to a social milieu, and others to a particular
conversational context. The norms, among other things, determine the permissible next steps in the
conversation (whose turn, what tone, speech act, content), permissible inferences, and default additions to
the common ground. The permissible inferences include not only what is entailed by what has been said
thus far, but also material inferences that cannot plausibly be captured on the model of explicit reasoning.
(See, e.g., Stalnaker (1999), Brandom (2001), Williamson (2003); Thanks to Jack Marley-Payne for
helping me see this possibility.)

17
information that stereotypical tigers are striped if one acquires 'tiger'... (251)

In short, to learn a language is not just a matter of learning what terms refer to what. We also

internalize associated schemas that guide perception, cognition, and behavior. In speaking of

social meaning, I am suggesting something similar, but extending it in two ways: the

stereotype is not just a set of beliefs about the extension of the term, but can include a broader

range of cognitive/affective/behavioral elements. And Im not just concerned with terms, i.e.,

linguistic or specifically communicative items, but also social items more generally (as Lessig

suggests, various actions, or inactions, or statuses, within a particular context, and, as we saw

before, objects, properties, and potentially, it seems, virtually everything).

The act of defining, of assigning a stereotype or schema to an expression, of deciding

which words to include (or not) in our vocabulary are political acts. This is not just true of terms

such as slut. Consider mother. Womens lives are substantially organized around practices of

mothering in anticipation, in avoidance, in enactment, in resistance. But why do we employ the

concept(s) of mother? What is a mother? The Lakoff discussion in the previous section shows

that there isnt a simple answer to that question. For example, why do we persist in thinking that

ones sex is relevant to ones parental nurturing? How we define mother and whether we

continue to categorize people as mothers are political choices. There is more than one way to

refuse to be a mother: one is to avoid becoming a parent. Another is to embrace parenting

rather than mothering as the apt description of ones activities.14

The schemas assigned to expressions are subject to moral and political evaluation, and

controversy over the schemas often yields controversy over the associated language, e.g., what do

we really mean by the term in question? What are we trying to capture, and why? In some cases

social critique will require a change of schema, but will leave the terms extension intact. This

may be the strategy behind the slut walks: You call me/us a slut? Well yes, Im a slut and Im

14
As Monique Wittig (1981, 49) claims in a different, but related, context: To refuse to be a woman,
however, does not mean that one has to become a man. Also quoted in Haslanger (2012, 63).

18
proud. In other cases social critique demands a rethinking of the extension: You call me a

slut? Well youre wrong, because no woman is a slut. Or: Yes, we are both his (real) mother.

He has two mothers. In yet other cases, social critique renders the extension irrelevant: You

could call me his mother, but what difference does that make? I am his parent. Or Im happy

to become a parent, but I refuse to be a mother.

A different, perhaps more Quinean, way of putting the point Im driving at would be to

say that there isnt a sharp line between linguistic meaning and social meaning, even between

descriptive terms and slurs. Words mean what we use them to mean. Language is a social

practice that requires coordination in order to take advantage of the resource of signs to

communicate.

If there is no clear line between linguistic/conceptual meaning and social meaning, then it

isnt entirely clear what we are doing when we attempt philosophical analysis, especially of

concepts that have social implications for action and affect. This is a remix of Quines point

about the web of belief. We rely on a web of schemas to communicate and coordinate. Instead

of observation statements at the periphery, this webs periphery consists of schemas that guide

action directly. Revision is permissible throughout the web, and is called for when the social

practices constituted by the schemas are problematic. (We might call this: social meaning

holism.) How we revise schemas whether we discard or modify the concepts, core beliefs,

evaluations, emotive scripts must be justified holistically and in terms of the impact on social

practices.

The elucidation and evaluation of a schema that constitutes a practice is not feasible

without close attention to the particular social contexts in which the schema is deployed. The

particular configuration of concepts, beliefs, evaluations, and dispositions that make up the

schematic element of our practices is historically specific. And any improvement on this

particular configuration will have to take into account the ways in which our social world has

19
already been constituted by these practices and the social/political/rhetorical options available.

This cant happen from the armchair.

7. Philosophical Analysis

Even the most strictly constative scientific


description is always open to the possibility of
functioning in a prescriptive way, capable of
contributing to its own verification by exercising a
theory-effect through which it helps to bring
about that which it declares.
(Bourdieu 1982, 134)

So far I have suggested that an action is meaningful in relation to a social practice. This

challenges an individualism that, e.g., treats actions simply as outputs from an agents beliefs and

desires. Ive also suggested that our conceptual repertoire is embedded in cultural schemas that

organize our life together. Because many of the social practices/structures within which action is

meaningful are unjust, we should subject the schemas to a form of critique that depends on rich

empirical investigation. Note, however, that our theorizing itself a social practice, so should also

be subjected to critique.

Analytic philosophy, at least in some forms, aims to provide analyses of our concepts and

the relations between them. But it should be clear by now that from the point of view of those

working on social justice, this is woefully inadequate. We can do so much more. For example,

(i) We need more in the way of a social philosophy of language/mind, epistemology,

ontology. We need a systematic account of social meaning and meaning change; a more detailed

account of how individual thought and action both depend on collective understandings and also

constitute collective understandings; a theory of aptness. We need more attention to the ontology

and epistemology of social structures and the structural explanation of human action.

(ii) We need critique, critique of ordinary schemas, but also philosophical schemas.

Philosophical concepts dont exist in a vacuum. They not only organize our thinking, but are also

enacted in our social world; they are embedded in our social practices; they structure our lives.

20
So we need to critique the very philosophical concepts we study, and not just take them as given.

Consider, e.g., knowledge, mind, body(!), person, nature, objectivity, justice, responsibility,

freedom, agency, autonomy, morality in addition to the thicker concepts we use in everyday life:

family, mother/father, abortion.15

Without critique of the schemas that constitute our social practices, philosophy takes the

status quo as given. For those of us who find the status quo intolerable, philosophy is implicated

in the injustices we face. We do need to understand the schemas that structure our lives both

the concepts and the core beliefs so explication is valuable. But without critique, our efforts are

dogmatic. Even if a concept is valuable and worth preserving, philosophy needs to explain why.

It may be tempting to suggest that in the case of philosophical inquiry we are just

concerned with truth. Does a bare concern with truth provide a basis for our inquiry? The simple

answer is no. Truths can be expressed with inapt concepts (grue?). But inapt concepts dont

make good theory (or even knowledge?). Moreover, in the social domain, discourse structures

reality; simply describing that reality is insufficient. Dogmatism is not the only danger: our

inquiry may, in fact, undergird schemas that we should reject. An uncritical acceptance of truths

and the concepts they depend on may actually cause systematic harm.

But how should we judge the aptness of our philosophical concepts and the schemas that

embed them? Undoubtedly, many philosophical schemas lie close to the core of the web and

there are ways to preserve them, even in the face of critique. However, as in any inquiry, aptness

of concepts should be evaluated relative to the purposes of the theorizing (medicine: pathogen).

Philosophy is many things, answers many different questions, has multiple purposes. But in

central cases, philosophical inquiry is an inquiry into the concepts we (collectively) ought to use.

It differs from scientific inquiry in that it aims to provide us with the basic tools we need to live

together, tools that are transposable across different domains. So we should be asking not simply

15
Of course, there are many examples of such critique, not only in the contemporary context, but
throughout the history of philosophy. Recall that to critique a concept is not necessarily to reject it
(Anderson 2001, 21-22), as much feminist work demonstrates, e.g., (Mackenzie & Stoljar, 2000).

21
what concepts track truth, even fundamental truth, but rather: What distinctions and

classifications should we use to organize ourselves collectively? What social meanings should we

endorse? Determining what is required for knowledge, or virtue, or autonomy, is not just a matter

of describing reality for, as noted before, definition is a political act. And it is so whether we

acknowledge it or not. Philosophy has the power to create culture; we are not just bystanders but

producers. I urge you to attend to social meaning in your philosophical work, recognize its

import for philosophy, and help us understand it better in the hope that this will serve the cause of

social justice.

Works Cited

Anderson, Elizabeth S. 2001. "Unstrapping the Straitjacket of 'Preference': on Amartya Sen's

Contributions to Philosophy and Economics," Economics and Philosophy 17: 21-38.

______. 2010. The Imperative of Integration. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

______. 2012. Epistemic justice as a virtue of social institutions. Social Epistemology 26(2): 163-

173.

Bicchieri, Christina. 2006. The Grammar of Society: The Nature and Dynamics of Social Norms.

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Bourdieu, Pierre. 1982. Language and Symbolic Power. Edited by John B. Thompson. Translated

by Gino Raymond and Matthew Adamson. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Brandom, Robert B. 2001. Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism. Cambridge,

MA: Harvard University Press.

Burge, Tyler. 1975. On Knowledge and Convention. Philosophical Review 84(2): 249-255.

Cohen, G. A. 1997. Where the action is: On the site of distributive justice. Philosophy and Public

Affairs 26(1): 3-30.

______. 2000. If You Are an Egalitarian, How Come Youre So Rich? Cambridge, MA: Harvard

University Press.

22
Fricker, M. 2007. Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. New York: Oxford

University Press.

Haslanger, Sally. 2012. Resisting Reality: Social Construction and Social Critique. Oxford:

Oxford University Press.

______. 2014. Studying While Black: Trust, Opportunity and Disrespect. DuBois Review

11(1): 109-136.

Lakoff, George. 1999. Cognitive Models and Prototype Theory. In Eric Margolis and Stephen

Laurence, eds. Concepts: Core Readings. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 391-423.

Lessig, Lawrence. 1995. The Regulation of Social Meaning. University of Chicago Law Review

62(3): 943-1045.

Mackenzie, Catriona & Natalie Stoljar, eds. 2000. Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives

on Autonomy, Agency and the Social Self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Martin, John Levi. 2009. Social Structures. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Putnam, Hilary. 1975. The Meaning of Meaning, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of

Science 7: 131-193.

Recanati, Francois. 2012. Mental Files. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Schroeter, Laura & Franois Schroeter. 2014. Normative Concepts: A Connectedness Model.

Philosophers Imprint 14(25): 1-26.

Sewell, William. 1992. A theory of structure: Duality, agency, and transformation. Amer. Journal

of Sociology 98 (1): 1-29.

Stalnaker, Robert. 1999. Context and Content: Essays on Intentionality in Speech and Thought.

Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Steele, Claude. 2010. Whistling Vivaldi: How Stereotypes Affect Us and What We Can Do. New

York: W.W. Norton.

Tilly, Charles. 1999. Durable Inequality. Berkeley: University of California Press.

______. 2002. Stories, Identities and Political Change. New York: Rowman and Littlefield.

23
Williamson, Timothy. 2003. Blind Reasoning. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 77

(1): 249-293.

Witt, Charlotte. 2011. The Metaphysics of Gender. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Wittig, Monique. 1981. One Is Not Born a Woman, Feminist Issues 1: 4754.

24

You might also like