Ipshita Sengupta
Ipshita Sengupta
Ipshita Sengupta
I. I ntroduction
India has the second largest legal profession in the world with approx-
imately one million lawyers1 with more than 80,000 lawyers graduating
each year from around 900 government and private law schools.2 Despite an
increasing demand for admission into law schools, the legal profession contin-
ues to be the subject of public misunderstanding and mistrust.
*
B.A. LL.B. (Hons.), The WB National University of Juridical Sciences, LL.M., International
Development Law and Human Rights, Warwick University. The author works on legal and
policy issues at the United Nations High Commissioner for Refugees (UNHCR). The author
would like to thank the anonymous editors and peer reviewers for their comments on the
paper.
1
The Indian Legal Profession, Harvard Program on the Legal Profession (2011), available
at http://www.law.harvard.edu/programs/plp/pdf/Indian_Legal_Profession.pdf.
2
Id.
14 JOURNAL OF INDIAN LAW AND SOCIETY [Vol. 5 : Winter]
As concerns about the falling ethical standards of the legal profession are
growing, both the Bar and the legal academy have undermined the importance
of instilling normative values in lawyers. The exaggerated importance placed
on rules, claims and defences and analytical reasoning in traditional legal
education has insulated students from learning about the relevance of social
context and processes, moral reasoning, and care and connection between law-
yers and clients.3 The preoccupation with legal procedure in teaching and legal
practice has lost sight of the fact that procedural guarantees are a means to the
end of truth of justice and not an end in itself.4
3
Barbara Bezdek, Reconstructing a Pedagogy of Responsibility, 43 Hastings L.J. 1159,
1160 (1991-92), available at http://digitalcommons.law.umaryland.edu/cgi/viewcontent.
cgi?article=1651&context=fac_pubs.
4
Dallin H. Oaks, Ethics, Morality and Professional Responsibility, 3 BYU L. Rev.
591, 596 (1975), available at http://digitalcommons.law.byu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.
cgi?article=1039&context=lawreview.
5
Stephen Ellman, The Ethic of Care as an Ethic for Lawyers, 81 The Geo. L.J. 2665, 2667
(1992-1993).
6
Chandra Krishnamurthy, Legal Education and Legal Profession in India, 36(2) Intl. J.
Legal Info. 245, 260 (2008), available at http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/cgi/viewcontent.
cgi?article=1136&context=ijli.
7
Ann Juergens, Practicing what we Teach: The Importance of Emotion and Community
Connection in Law Work and Law Teaching, 11 Clinical L. Rev. 901 (2005), available at
http://open.wmitchell.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1191&context=facsch.
8
Susan Daicoff, Lawyer Know Thyself: A Review of Empirical Research on Attorney Attributes
Bearing on Professionalism, 46 The Amer. U. L. Rev. 1337, 1338 (1997), available at http://digi-
talcommons.wcl.american.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1406&context=aulr.
NURTURING CARING LAWYERS 15
lawyers themselves complain about their disillusionment and cynicism with the
profession.
If indeed, law is a noble profession, meant to help and heal, then why is
it that the legal system is becoming increasingly inaccessible to the poor and
more and more lawyers are turning away from ideals of justice and public ser-
vice, choosing financial gain over professional ethics and obligations?9
Increasingly, we find that law students graduating from the elite law
schools in India are attracted to careers that disconnect them from their
intrinsic values and motivations like integrity, care, help etc. and they drift
towards extrinsic orientations like winning, high salaries, social status etc. As
a result, they begin to understand and practice professionalism as separate
from job/personal satisfaction when, in reality; they are inseparable as ones
quality of life and professional reputation manifest from ones choice of opti-
mal goals, values and motives.19
17
Utkarsh Anand, 93% Lawyers fail paper on Ethics, Advocacy, Indian Express (April 10, 2013),
http://www.indianexpress.com/news/93lawyers-fail-paper-on-ethics-advocacy/1099986/.
18
Id.
19
See Lawrence S. Krieger, The Inseparability of Professionalism and Personal Satisfaction:
Perspectives on Values, Integrity and Happiness, 11 Clinical L. Rev. 425 (2005), available at
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=549361.
20
Susan Daicoff, supra note 8, at 1422.
21
Susan Daicoff, supra note 8, at 1424.
22
Susan Daicoff, supra note 8, at 1423.
23
Theodore Eisenberg, Sital Kalantry & Nick Robinson, Litigation as a Measure of Well-being,
Cornell Law Faculty Working Papers, Paper 99 (2012), available at http://scholarship.law.
cornell.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1102&context=clsops_papers.
24
Id, at 34. (The study recorded higher litigation rates in those Indian states with higher human
development indices (HDI) which suggest that people are more likely to use the courts when
they are economically, socially and physically better off. The HDI has both an economic
NURTURING CARING LAWYERS 17
Robinsons analysis has also shown that it takes the Supreme Court of
India, four years, on average, to decide a matter28 and everyone cannot access
it equally as most of the admitted appeals are company, tax, service and land
acquisition matters from Delhi and other wealthy states.29 Contrary to pop-
ular belief, only two per cent of the Supreme Courts cases are writ petitions
and social action litigation (SAL) comprises only one per cent.30 A 2009
World Bank analysis of Supreme Court data showed that on average, 260 out
of 60,000 cases per year are SALs (0.4 per cent), a large majority of which
are brought through formal channels and not through letters and handwritten
petitions received from ordinary, public spirited citizens.31
On average, it takes more than ten years for a litigant to get a final ver-
dict on their case.32 The Indian litigation experience demonstrates that too
many cases are filed but too few are timely adjudicated33 and potential litigants
are slowly turning away from courts.34
component, reflected in higher income per capita and a non-economic component, such as
health, education, etc.).
25
See Vivek Kanwar et al., Justice without Delay: Recommendations for Legal and Institutional
Reforms in the Indian Courts, 2(1) Jindal Global L. Rev. 9 (2010), available at http://papers.
ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1679350; see also Kannan Kasturi, Civil Litigation? No,
Thanks, India Together (July 12, 2009), available at http://www.indiatogether.org/2009/jul/
gov-civil.htm.
26
For details, see Jayanth K. Krishnan et al, Grappling at the Grassroots: Access to Justice in
Indias Lower Tier, 27 Harv. Hum. Rts. J. (2014), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/
papers.cfm?abstract_id=2297152.
27
Theodore Eisenberg, supra note 23, at 15. (Table 2. India States Civil Filings & GDP, 2005-
2010, HDI, Literacy, Population Density, Backlog).
28
Nick Robinson, A Court Adrift, Frontline (3-5-2013), available at http://www.frontline.in/
cover-story/a-court-adrift/article4613892.ece.
29
Robinsons study shows that in the last five years, the Supreme Court has adjudicated mainly
criminal matters (21%), service matters concerning government employees (16%), direct and
indirect tax matters (13%) and land acquisition matters (9%).
30
Id.
31
Varun Gauri, Public Interest Litigation in India: Overreaching or Underachieving?, World
Bank, Policy Research Working Paper 5109, 10 (2009), http://elibrary.worldbank.org/doi/
pdf/10.1596/1813-9450-5109.
32
Nick Robinson, supra note 28.
33
Theodore Eisenberg, supra note 23.
34
Theodore Eisenberg, supra note 23.
18 JOURNAL OF INDIAN LAW AND SOCIETY [Vol. 5 : Winter]
In one of the early treatises on the modern Indian legal profession, Marc
Galanter asked whether Indian lawyers can adapt outside the adversarial set-
ting of courtrooms to collaborate with others to find solutions for substantive
problems of their clients, and whether they can think beyond their rule-mind-
edness to develop creative and practical problem-solving approaches.35 He sug-
gested that legal education should develop the capacity to impart these new
skills and attitudes.
The increasing court backlogs and judicial delays are giving rise to alter-
native forms of dispute resolution such as mediation, which demands creative
and collaborative approaches to lawyering. Yet, law schools continue to teach
students to think like lawyers practicing in an adversarial setting and stress
on doctrinal learning methods focusing on legal analysis of legislation and case
law.
35
Marc Galanter, Introduction: The Study of the Indian Legal Profession, 3 L. & Soc. Rev. 201,
217 (1969), http://marcgalanter.net/Documents/papers/scannedpdf/studyoftheindianlegalprof.
pdf.
36
Colin G. James, Lawyers Wellbeing and Professional Legal Education, 42(1) The Law Teacher:
The Intl. J. Legal Edu. 85, 92 (2008), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.
cfm?abstract_id=2322339.
37
Id, at 93.
38
Id.
39
Marc Galanter, supra note 35, at 208.
NURTURING CARING LAWYERS 19
Upendra Baxi has long recognised the need for a socially relevant legal
education which requires legal pedagogy to move beyond the lecture method
of instruction and be embedded in the socio-legal context and legal curriculum
to acknowledge and address the contemporary problems of society and the cor-
responding tasks before law and lawyers.40
What has also been ignored by the legal profession is the subject of
obligations. Law schools and legal professionals have emerged as gladiators,
guarantors and enforcers in relation to rights41 but have remained uncharacter-
istically silent on the subject of responsibilities.
It has been argued by some legal educators that law students cannot be
taught ethics and morality in law school because these notions are developed
before they enrol42 and the blame is often shifted to the Bar which is accused
of lowering standards of professional discipline and failing to provide the kind
of moral and legal leadership expected from officers of the court.43 It is com-
monly believed that lawyers will learn to grapple with complex intellectual and
emotional issues with their experience of practice.44
The dominant legal pedagogy offers lawyers an excused status, i.e. law-
yers are seen as merely facilitating transactions, solving problems and working
within the legal system.45 Lawyers are generally absolved as long as they use
clean means, no matter what the end pursued by their clients.46 Flynn argues
that greater harm is caused when lawyers engage in amoral conduct and have
no standard of right and wrong by which to judge their conduct.47
Studies in American law schools have found that law schools de-empha-
sise the role of human relationships and connections in lawyering by teaching
40
Upendra Baxi, Notes Towards a Socially Relevant Legal Education: A Working Paper for the
UGC Regional Workshops in Law 43 (1975-77), http://www.ugc.ac.in/oldpdf/pub/report/1.pdf.
41
Dallin H. Oaks, supra note 4, at 597 See also Elliot Richardson, On Behalf of Obligations, 8
Lincoln L. Rev. 109 (1973).
42
Id, at 593 See also Murray L. Schwartz, Legal ethics v. Common Notions of Morality, Learning
& the Law 40, 47-48 (Spring 1975).
43
Id. at 594 See also Bayless Manning, If Lawyers were Angels: A Sermon in One Cannon, 60(7)
Amer. Bar Asso. J. 821 (1975).
44
Andrew S. Watson, Lawyers and Professionalism: A Further Psychiatric Perspective on Legal
Education, 8 Mich. J. Legal Ref. 248, 252 (1974-1975).
45
Barbara Bezdek, supra note 3, at 1162.
46
Barbara Bezdek, supra note 3, at 1162.
47
See John J. Flynn, Professional Ethics and the Lawyers Duty to Self, 1976(3) Wash. U. L. Q.
429 (1976), http://digitalcommons.law.wustl.edu/lawreview/vol1976/iss3/3.
20 JOURNAL OF INDIAN LAW AND SOCIETY [Vol. 5 : Winter]
law students to think like a lawyer and remain emotionally neutral which
may cause psychological discomfort among those students who are forced to
deny their care orientation in favour of an analytical, rule-based, rights orienta-
tion.48 When law schools refrain from identifying and clarifying ethical issues
associated with legal practice, they fail in their duty to train future legal prac-
titioners to understand that value judgments are a significant part of his/her
function as a lawyer.49
The present legal curriculum does not engage in such critical conver-
sations as lawyers are socialised as pragmatic problem solvers who get things
done, not poets who wallow in angst or therapists whose expertise is empa-
thy.50 Law schools must realise that such conversations are not merely ques-
tions of private morality but constitute an important part of a lawyers
professional training.
48
Sandra Janoff, The Influence of Legal Education on Moral Reasoning, 76 Minn. L. Rev. 193, 234
(1991).
49
Murray L. Schwartz, Legal ethics v. Common Notions of Morality, Learning & the Law 40,
47-48, 50 (Spring 1975).
50
Barbara Bezdek, Reconstructing a Pedagogy of Responsibility, 43 Hastings L.J. 1159, 1172
(1991-92).
51
Theresa Glennon, Lawyers and Caring: Building an Ethic of Care into Professional
Responsibility, 43 Hastings L. J. 1176 (1992).
52
Andrew S. Watson, supra note 44, at 250.
53
Colin G. James, supra note 36, at 95.
NURTURING CARING LAWYERS 21
More than two decades ago, law professors, David Wexler and Bruce
Winick studied the therapeutic or anti-therapeutic impact of mental health law
on patients, their families and other relevant stakeholders. Subsequently, they
developed the idea of therapeutic jurisprudence as a perspective that focuses
on the impact of the law on emotional life and psychological well-being.62 It
examines how the law, which consists of legal rules, legal procedures, and the
behaviour and roles of legal actors, often produces therapeutic or anti-thera-
peutic outcomes.
54
Theresa Glennon, supra note 51, at 1179.
55
Id.
56
Theresa Glennon, supra note 51, at 1180.
57
Theresa Glennon, supra note 51, at 1181.
58
Theresa Glennon, supra note 51, at 1184.
59
Theresa Glennon, supra note 51, at 1186.
60
Michael Hunter Schwartz, Humanising Legal Education: An Introduction to a Symposium whose
time came, 47 Washburn L.J. 235, 241 (2007-2008).
61
See Michael S. King, Restorative Justice, Therapeutic Jurisprudence and the Rise of Emotionally
Intelligent Justice, 34 Melb. U. L. Rev., (2008) http://www.austlii.edu.au/au/journals/
MULR/2008/34.html.
62
David B. Wexler., Therapeutic Jurisprudence: Issues, Analysis and Applications, 27 Seattle U.
L. Rev. 217, 217-222 (2000-01).
22 JOURNAL OF INDIAN LAW AND SOCIETY [Vol. 5 : Winter]
The adversarial legal system teaches law students from the very first year
of law school to argue against someone for the purpose of establishing that
they are right and others are wrong, thus, dangerously emphasising binary
thinking.65 Traditional legal education justifies a variety of practices focused on
the self and to the detriment of others.66
63
Susan Daicoff, Law as a Healing Profession: The Comprehensive Law Movement, Bepress
Legal Series, Paper 1331 (2005), available at http://law.cwru.edu/lectures/files/2008-
2009/20090410_Daicoff_excerpt.pdf.
64
Colin G. James, supra note 36, at 96.
65
Carrie Menkel-Meadow, Is Altruism Possible in Lawyering?, 8(2) Geor. State U. L. Rev. 385,
387 (1991), http://scholarworks.gsu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1363&context=gsulr.
66
Id, at 386.
67
See John J. Flynn, Supra note 47, at 441.
NURTURING CARING LAWYERS 23
Rand and Dana Jacks research has shown three common responses to
the conflict faced by caring lawyers-denial of their care orientation and rejec-
tion of their emotional side; using ones emotional side in ones personal and
family life and ones logical, analytical side at work; attempting to incorporate
a care orientation into lawyering.68 Although a focus on care orientation is a
potentially good response to this conflict, it is rarely invoked by lawyers.
68
See Rand Jack & Dana Crowley Jack, Moral Visions and Professional Decisions: The
Changing Values Of Women And Men Lawyers 130-155 (1988).
69
See, Lawrence Kohlberg, The Philosophy Of Moral Development: Moral Stages
And The Idea Of Justice, Essays On Moral Development I (1981) (Kohlbergs six stage
theory has three levels- The pre-conventional in which behaviour is based on obedience and
punishment, the conventional in which maintenance of good relations is paramount and the
post-conventional in which individual conscience is paramount).
70
Id.
71
Carol Gilligan, In A Different Voice 35 (1982).
72
Narnia Bohler-Muller, Developing a new jurisprudence of gender equality in South Africa,
Doctoral Thesis, Faculty of Law, University of Pretoria, South Africa 47 (Nov.
2005), available at http://upetd.up.ac.za/thesis/available/etd-06152006-123856/unrestrict-
ed/01thesis.pdf.
73
Id, at 90.
74
Carol Gilligan, Moral orientation and moral development; in Women And Moral Theory 10
(Eva Fedder Kittay & Diana T. Meyers eds., 1987).
24 JOURNAL OF INDIAN LAW AND SOCIETY [Vol. 5 : Winter]
Theoretically, the distinction between justice and care cuts across the
familiar divisions between thinking and feeling, egoism and altruism,
theoretical and practical reasoning. It calls attention to the fact that
all human relationships, both public and private, can be characterised
both in terms of attachment, and that both inequality and detachment
constitute grounds for moral concern. Since everyone is vulnerable both
to oppression and to abandonment, two moral visions- one of justice,
and one of care- recur in human experience. The moral injunctions,
not to act unfairly toward others, and not to turn away from someone
in need, capture these different concerns.
Is it possible for legal actors (lawyers, judges, clients, law students, law
professors) to acknowledge the centrality of care and if yes, how and with what
consequences will they employ it?79 Gilligans contribution is of significant
value in the field of legal and moral theory as she has attempted to deconstruct
the modern legal subject- rational, abstract, autonomous Man80 by articulating
a plural, non-hierarchical and relational subject.81
75
Stephen Ellman, supra note 5, at 2668.
76
See Carol Gilligan, Reply by Carol Gilligan, 11 Signs 326 (1984).
77
Carol Gilligan, supra note 74.
78
Sandra Janoff, supra note 48, at 228-29.
79
Carrie Menkel-Meadow, supra note 65.
80
Susan Hekman, Moral Voices, Moral Selves: Carol Gilligan And Feminist Moral
Theory 2 (1995). See generally Grace Clement, Care, Autonomy And Justice: Feminism
And The Ethic Of Care (1993).
81
Narnia Bohler-Muller, supra note 72, at 50.
82
Carrie Menkel-Meadow, supra note 65, at 401.
83
Id.
84
Carrie Menkel-Meadow, supra note 65, at 407.
NURTURING CARING LAWYERS 25
in care terms will show that lawyers who believe in the centrality of care in
defining their professional responsibility will care for all parties involved in a
legal situation.85 In Gilligans words, an ethic of care rests on the premise of
non-violence- that no one should be hurt.86
85
Stephen Ellman, supra note 5, at 2679.
86
Carol Gilligan, supra note 71, at 174.
87
Carrie Menkel-Meadow, supra note 65.
88
For a more detailed discussion on this, see E. Wayne Thode, The Ethical Standard For the
Advocate, 39 Texas L. Rev. 575 (1961).
89
Carrie Menkel-Meadow, supra note 65, at.
90
Carrie Menkel-Meadow, supra note 65, at 411-12.
91
See Carrie Menkel-Meadow, Portia in a different voice: Speculations on womens lawyering pro-
cess, 1 Berkly. Womens L.J. 39 (1985), available at http://scholarship.law.berkeley.edu/cgi/
viewcontent.cgi?article=1001&context=bglj.
92
Stephen Ellman, supra note 5, at 2675.
93
Stephen Ellman, supra note 5, at 2704 (Ellman argues that caring lawyers may make paternal-
istic interventions if there is a demonstrated need for action based on his/her deep knowledge
of the clients situation, such as in the case of a victim of domestic violence who is unable
to take action against her partner/spouse and allows him/her to move back into the family
home. If a caring lawyer is convinced that his/her client will face harm as a result of her
26 JOURNAL OF INDIAN LAW AND SOCIETY [Vol. 5 : Winter]
Many might question the notion that lawyers should have such freedom
of choice of clients as this will allow lawyers to reject cases by always prior-
itising their own interests over others. Charles Fried advocates that a lawyers
personal autonomy justifies his/her selection of any client that he/she wishes
for any reason, as long as he/she can faithfully represent the client within the
choices if he does not intervene, he would rather make a paternalistic intervention rather than
remain silent and be indifferent).
94
Stephen Ellman, supra note 5, at 2674.
95
Stephen Ellman, supra note 5, at 2699.
96
Kimberley E. OLeary, Creating Partnerships: Using Feminist Techniques to Enhance the
Attorney-Client Relationships, 16 Legal Study F. 217, 217 (1992).
97
Kimberley E. OLeary, Creating Partnerships: Using Feminist Techniques to Enhance the
Attorney-Client Relationships, 16 Legal Study F. 217, 217 (1992).
98
Nel Noddings, Caring: A Feminine Approach To Ethics And Moral Education 47,
86, 112 (1982) (Unlike Gilligan, Noddings rejects the possibility of caring for everyone and
argues that the caring person will dread the arrival of the stranger needing her care, because
true care is very demanding for the person caring and the notion of equal care for all is
implausible).
99
Stephen Ellman, supra note 5, at 2681.
100
Stephen Ellman, supra note 5, at 2674.
NURTURING CARING LAWYERS 27
limits of the law.101 William Simon, on the other hand, asks lawyers to exercise
their ethical discretion by taking up those cases that seem most likely to pro-
mote justice.102
101
See, Charles Fried, The Lawyer as Friend: The Moral Foundations of the Lawyer-Client
Relations, 85 Yale L.J. 1060 (1976).
102
See, William H. Simon, Ethical Discretion in Lawyering, 101(6) Harv. L. Rev. 1083 (1988).
103
Upendra Baxi, The Pathology of the Indian Legal Professions, 13(3, 4) Ind. Bar Rev. 455 (1986).
104
Donald Nicolson, supra note 10, at 604.
105
Upendra Baxi, supra note 103, at 480.
106
Id.
28 JOURNAL OF INDIAN LAW AND SOCIETY [Vol. 5 : Winter]
The BCI Rules framed under the Advocates Act 1961 prohibits advocates
from refusing client representation108 and encourages them to represent their
clients irrespective of moral considerations. Yet, in practice, we find that advo-
cates exercise absolute discretion in refusing clients as the existing code does
not provide any guidance on how to exercise this discretion.
The rules also allow lawyers to maintain a close nexus with the econ-
omy. Although they cannot engage in business, the rules permit them to serve
as sleeping partners, directors of companies, inheritors of family businesses,
investors and lobbyists110 to supplement their earnings. In addition, there is no
regulation of legal fees charged by lawyers.
107
Donald Nicolson, supra note 10, at 604.
108
Part VI, Chapter II, Standards of Professional Conduct and Etiquette, Bar Council of
India Rules (under The Advocates Act 1961), http://www.barcouncilofindia.org/wp-content/
uploads/2010/05/BCIRulesPartVonwards.pdf.
109
Part VI, Chapter II, Standards of Professional Conduct and Etiquette, Bar Council of
India Rules (under The Advocates Act 1961), http://www.barcouncilofindia.org/wp-content/
uploads/2010/05/BCIRulesPartVonwards.pdf. (S. II, Duty to the Client).
110
Upendra Baxi, supra note 103, at 458.
111
Upendra Baxi, supra note 103, at 459.
112
Upendra Baxi, supra note 103.
NURTURING CARING LAWYERS 29
restriction on the market for legal services. The existing dichotomy between
prohibition of solicitation or advertising by lawyers, on one hand and the
wholesale buying of legal services, at unregulated legal fees113 on the other,
invariably benefits the prominent lawyers and the resourceful clients,114 thus,
promoting unfair competition and creating an unequal Bar.
Yet, to a limited extent, the current rules that regulate the legal profes-
sion in India seem to be informed by care considerations. The conflict of inter-
est rules prevents a lawyer from appearing in a case in which he is a witness
and obligates a lawyer to fully disclose to his client, at the time of engagement,
all information relating to his connection with the parties and/or any interests
which is likely to affect the clients decision in engaging him.115
However, the rules do not recognise the heterogeneity of the legal pro-
fession. For example, a lawyer owes a duty to the court to restrain himself
and his client from engaging in unfair practices, including use of inappro-
priate language and aggressive tactics and arguments, in relation to the court
and opposing parties and counsels and should refuse to represent a client who
engages in such improper conduct.117 The rules also stipulate that a lawyer
should not be a mere mouthpiece for the client. However, in reality, some law-
yers, particularly law officers in government service, are rarely in a position to
question the means adopted by their client-the government, and in fact, have
to justify the actions of the government, no matter how unfair,118 in court
and in public.
The cornerstone of a good justice system is the right of all persons, irre-
spective or their socio-economic status to full and effective legal representation.
Yet, two standards of justice for the haves and the have-nots, continues and
those most in need of legal assistance must overcome great barriers to obtain
it. Quality legal representation is an expensive commodity in the legal market
and the poor are not able to choose the lawyer, nor the lawyer to choose the
113
Upendra Baxi, supra note 103.
114
Upendra Baxi, supra note 103 (The Code does not differentiate between different types of cli-
ents. The capacity and resources available to government, corporations, banks, financial insti-
tutions, registered societies, etc. vary greatly from that of an individual client).
115
Supra note 108. (S. II, Duty to the client, BCI Rules).
116
Supra note 108.
117
Supra note 108.
118
Upendra Baxi, supra note 103, at 461.
30 JOURNAL OF INDIAN LAW AND SOCIETY [Vol. 5 : Winter]
poor.119 The quality of legal representation available for the poor reflects their
value within our legal system and whether they are seen as worthy of receiving
the same quality of legal counsel as the wealthy.120
A World Bank study has also shown that SAL has not benefited the poor
and other marginalised individuals and groups. The failure of SAL to realise
its original objectives has manifested itself in two ways- beneficiary inequality,
i.e. the middle class with greater organisational and financial resources than
the poor have gained better access to the courts and reaped benefits of SAL
and policy area inequality, i.e., the judiciary comprising of judges representing a
certain social class and ideological disposition, have been more sympathetic to
the cause of the middle class and the wealthy, as witnessed in rulings involv-
ing WTO accession, Union Carbides liability in the Bhopal gas leak case and
the construction of the Narmada Dam.122 The analysis of SALs in this study
brings forth real concerns about equality of access to justice.
119
Kaleeswaram Raj, Fair Advocacy as a Right, The Hindu, (March 27, 2014), http://www.the-
hindu.com/opinion/lead/fair-advocacy-as-a-right/article5836221.ece.
120
Michelle S. Jacobs, Full Legal Representation for the Poor: The Clash Between Lawyer Values
and Client Worthiness, 44 Howard L.J. 257, 258 (2001), available at http://scholarship.law.ufl.
edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1147&context=facultypub.
121
Marc Galanter & Jayanth K. Krishnan, Bread for the Poor: Access to Justice and Rights of the
Needy in India, 55 Hastings L.J. 789, 796-97 (2003-2004).
122
Varun Gauri, Public Interest Litigation in India: Overreaching or Underachieving?, World
Bank, Policy Research Working Paper 5109, 8 (Nov. 2009), available at http://elibrary.
worldbank.org/doi/pdf/10.1596/1813-9450-5109.
NURTURING CARING LAWYERS 31
If indeed lawyers have a duty to render legal aid, then why do the most
successful and affluent lawyers routinely refuse to take up cases of poor per-
sons in need of legal assistance?123 Senior advocates routinely charge exorbitant
fees under different heads like retainer fee, settlement of brief charges, con-
ference charges, appearance charges, reading fees, opinion/consultation fees
etc.124 Galanter and Robinson, in a recent study, observed that elite litigators
or Grand Advocates of India charged 500,000-600,000 INR per appearance
($10,000-12,000) at the Supreme Court.125
123
Upendra Baxi, supra note 103, at 457.
124
Kaleeswaram Raj, supra note 119.
125
Marc Galanter & Nick Robinson, Indias Grand Advocates: A Legal Elite Flourishing in the Era
of Globalisation, 5 Harvard Law School Program on the Legal Profession Research
Paper Series 2013 11, available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2348699.
126
Id.
127
S. 16(1) of the Advocates Act. (It provides, An advocate may, with his consent, be designated
as senior advocate if the Supreme Court or a High Court is of opinion that by virtue of his
ability [standing at the Bar or special knowledge or experience in law] he is deserving of such
distinction.).
128
Kaleeswaram Raj, supra note 119.
129
For details, See, Marg, Needs Assessment Study of the Legal Services Authorities in the States
of Madhya Pradesh, Jharkhand, Bihar, Uttar Pradesh, Odisha, Rajasthan and Chhatisgarh,
Department of Justice. Government of India and UNDP (2012), http://www.in.undp.org/con-
tent/dam/india/docs/DG/needs-assessment-study-of-selected-legal-services-authorities.pdf.
32 JOURNAL OF INDIAN LAW AND SOCIETY [Vol. 5 : Winter]
roles and do not receive adequate remuneration. The National Legal Services
Authority (Free and Competent Legal Services) Regulations 2010 which lays
out the procedures and criteria for selection of panel lawyers, establishment of
monitoring committees are not yet fully functional in the assessed states.130
This shows that the poor are not entitled to either zealous131 or adequate132 legal
representation.133 The MARG study made certain recommendations to address
the gaps in the existing legal aid system such as development of a transparent
and systematic empanelment process for lawyers, monitoring and evaluation
through case tracking and client feedback, training of empanelled lawyers and
regular payment of lawyers fees.134
This apathy towards the poor seeking justice is closely linked to the kind
of training that is imparted in law schools. Most students do not learn how
to appreciate or value their clients during their legal training.138 At the same
time, lawyers who represent the poor are not always respected by the bar and
130
Id., at 125
131
Lawyers have a strict ethical responsibility to advocate zealously on behalf of their client.
Zealous representation does not mean a lawyer should strive to win a case at all costs,
if that means harming third parties and adversaries unnecessarily in the process. It means
doing everything reasonable to help a client achieve the goals set forth at the outset of the
representation.
132
Indigent defendants who are represented by appointed lawyers are entitled to adequate rep-
resentation. But adequate representation does not mean perfect representation. Adequate
representation not only covers the right to have a lawyer present at a trial in a court of law
but also that the lawyer is competent in arguing cases in a court of law.
133
Stephen B. Bright, Legal Representation for the Poor: Can Society Afford This
Much Injustice, 75 Miss. L. Rev. 710 (2010), available at http://scholarship.law.
m i s s ou r i.e du /c g i /v ie wc ontent .c g i?a r t ic le =3883& c onte x t=m l r& s ei-re d i r=1& re f er-
er=http%3 A%2F%2Fscholar.google.co.in%2Fscholar%3Fhl%3Den%26q%3Dright%2B -
poor%2Blegal%2Brepresentation%26btnG%3D#search=%22right%20poor%20legal%20
representation%22.
134
See supra note 129, at 137-140.
135
Jayanth K. Krishnan supra note 26, at 534.
136
Jayanth K. Krishnan supra note 26.
137
Jayanth K. Krishnan supra note 26.
138
Michelle S. Jacobs, supra note 120, at 274.
NURTURING CARING LAWYERS 33
the bench and are made to feel less professional. They may be perceived as
low-status or incompetent lawyers who cannot get better jobs.139 High case-
loads and poor salaries further alienate lawyers representing the poor which
adversely impacts the quality of legal representation. In addition, courts are
often seen as prioritising procedural and administrative concerns over deliver-
ing justice. Moving dockets trump competent legal representation in many cas-
es.140 Given this reality, it is reassuring to learn that the National Law School
of India University (NLSIU) is submitting a draft policy to the BCI and the
Law Ministry that makes it mandatory for all law schools to establish free
legal aid clinics to be run by law students.141
Many notorious practices of the Bar are overlooked by the rules, such
as bench-fixing,142 suppression of unfavourable legal precedent, asking for
repeated adjournments, charging disproportionately high fees without any
regard for the capacity of the client to pay and the nature of the case, encour-
agement of administrative corruption among court staff.143
He found that very few of these were suo motu proceedings by the
BCI.146 The BCI sparingly uses its powers under Section 35(3) of the Advocates
Act 1961 to reprimand, suspend or remove an advocate from its rolls as
139
Michelle S. Jacobs, supra note 120, at 274.
140
Stephen B. Bright, supra note 133, at 709.
141
Venkata Sushmita Biswas, When your lawyer is a collegian, The Hindu, September 17, 2013,
http://www.thehindu.com/todays-paper/tp-national/tp-karnataka/when-your-lawyer-is-a-colle-
gian/article5136405.ece.
142
Some lawyers may use unfair means to ensure that particular judges sit in particular trials to
influence the ruling in their favour.
143
Upendra Baxi, supra note 103, at 461-62.
144
Upendra Baxi, supra note 103, at 457.
145
Upendra Baxi, supra note 103, at 478.
146
Suo motu proceedings by State Bar Councils are discretionary. (S. 35 of the Advocates Act)
34 JOURNAL OF INDIAN LAW AND SOCIETY [Vol. 5 : Winter]
Those few State lawyers who are dismissed or removed from office on
charges of moral turpitude are allowed to be re-admitted into the Bar after
the expiry of two years since such dismissal or removal.151 Despite the Law
Commission of Indias recommendation that this legal proviso be removed so
that such lawyers remain disqualified for life and that such disqualification
be extended to private legal practitioners, this provision continues to be in
effect.152
The existing code of ethics regulating the legal profession in India are,
on one hand, aspirational in the sense that they set high standards which are
often not reinforced through appropriate disciplinary sanctions153 and discipli-
nary, on the other, as they also attempt to lay down a set of categorical, all-or-
nothing rules, often without reference to context or consequences.154 Whether
aspirational or disciplinary or both, the important question is whether the code
has deterred unethical and unprofessional behaviour and encouraged behav-
iour that is ethical.155 Unfortunately, the BCI, as the sole custodian of the legal
147
The disciplinary proceedings of the Bar Councils are in camera.
148
Upendra Baxi, supra note 103, at 478-79.
149
Although there is a provision for amicus curiae lawyers for unrepresented complainants in dis-
ciplinary proceedings of Bar Councils, Baxis study found that this provision was rarely used.
150
See, Upendra Baxi, supra note 103, at 480-82.
151
S. 24-A(1) of the Advocates Act 1961, http://www.barcouncilofindia.org/wp-content/
uploads/2010/05/Advocates-Act1961.pdf (last visited on October 10, 2013).
152
Law Commission of India, The Legal Education & Professional Training and Proposals for
Amendments to the Advocates Act, 1961 and the University Grants Commission Act, 1956, 184th
Report, (Dec. 2002) 122-24, http://lawcommissionofindia.nic.in/reports/184threport-PartI.pdf.
153
Donald Nicolson, supra note 10, at 606.
154
Donald Nicolson, supra note 10.
155
Donald Nicolson, supra note 10, at 605.
NURTURING CARING LAWYERS 35
VI. C onclusion
The structure and practice milieu of legal practice in India has been rad-
ically altered in the last decade or so. In this context, the legal academy and
the Bar must attempt to develop new approaches to teaching, learning and
practicing professional responsibility which will require a counter-socialisation of
sorts that prioritises social context, moral reasoning, care and connection, intu-
ition and motivation.158
156
Upendra Baxi, supra note 103, at 480.
157
Text of the Bill, available at lawmin.nic.in/la/NALSA.doc.
158
Barbara Bezdek, Reconstructing a Pedagogy of Responsibility, 43 Hastings L.J. 1159, 1160
(1991-92).
159
Donald Nicolson, Making Lawyers Moral? Ethical Codes and Moral Character, 25(4) Legal
Stud. 601, 619 (2005).
160
See generally Donald Nicolson & Julian Webb, Professional Legal Ethics: Critical
Interrogations Chapters 6-8 (1999).
36 JOURNAL OF INDIAN LAW AND SOCIETY [Vol. 5 : Winter]
to the ethical dilemmas and constraints that arise in various practice areas and
help them in making ethically informed career choices.161
However, we must remain mindful about placing the burden of care dis-
proportionately on certain groups of lawyers, for example, women, or blurring
the thin line between care and charity165 when paternalism trumps empathy.
Concerns about legal relativism in the existing legal arena of stable, universal
and predictable rules must also be addressed. Despite this, care and relational
theories hold the power to transform legal discipline and institutions and mer-
its serious consideration from the legal profession in India.
161
Donald Nicolson, Making Lawyers Moral? Ethical Codes and Moral Character, 25(4) Legal
Stud. 601, 623-24 (2005).
162
Stephen Ellman, supra note 5, at 2726.
163
Stephen Ellman, supra note 5, at 2726.
164
Theresa Glennon, supra note 51, at 1186.
165
Theresa Glennon, supra note 51, at 414-15.