【弗洛姆研究】恩利希·弗洛姆的革命希望
【弗洛姆研究】恩利希·弗洛姆的革命希望
【弗洛姆研究】恩利希·弗洛姆的革命希望
VOLUME 4
SERIES EDITORS
SCOPE
Current educational reform rhetoric around the globe repeatedly invokes the language of 21st century learning and
innovative thinking while contrarily re-enforcing, through government policy, high stakes testing and international
competition, standardization of education that is exceedingly reminiscent of 19th century Taylorism and scientific
management. Yet, as the steam engines of educational progress continue down an increasingly narrow, linear,
and unified track, it is becoming increasingly apparent that the students in our classrooms are inheriting real world
problems of economic instability, ecological damage, social inequality, and human suffering. If young people are
to address these social problems, they will need to activate complex, interconnected, empathetic and multiple ways
of thinking about the ways in which peoples of the world are interconnected as a global community in the living
ecosystem of the world. Seeing the world as simultaneously local, global, political, economic, ecological, cultural
and interconnected is far removed from the Enlightenments objectivist and mechanistic legacy that presently
saturates the status quo of contemporary schooling. If we are to derail this positivist educational train and teach
our students to see and be in the world differently, the educational community needs a serious dose of imagination.
The goal of this book series is to assist students, practitioners, leaders, and researchers in looking beyond what they
take for granted, questioning the normal, and amplifying our multiplicities of knowing, seeing, being and feeling to,
ultimately, envision and create possibilities for positive social and educational change. The books featured in this
series will explore ways of seeing, knowing, being, and learning that are frequently excluded in this global climate
of standardized practices in the field of education. In particular, they will illuminate the ways in which imagination
permeates every aspect of life and helps develop personal and political awareness. Featured works will be written in
forms that range from academic to artistic, including original research in traditional scholarly format that addresses
unconventional topics (e.g., play, gaming, ecopedagogy, aesthetics), as well as works that approach traditional and
unconventional topics in unconventional formats (e.g., graphic novels, fiction, narrative forms, and multi-genre
texts). Inspired by the work of Maxine Greene, this series will showcase works that break through the limits of the
conventional and provoke readers to continue arousing themselves and their students to begin again (Greene,
Releasing the Imagination, 1995, p. 109).
Joan Braune
Mount Mary University, Milwaukee, Wisconsin, USA
A C.I.P. record for this book is available from the Library of Congress.
Foreword ix
Acknowledgments xi
Introduction xiii
Conclusion 191
Epilogue (Polemical Postscript) 197
References 205
Abbreviations 215
vii
FOREWORD
We are pleased to present this book on the work of Erich Fromm by Joan Braune
during these crucial and dark times of perpetual war, economic uncertainty and
the relentless drumbeats toward standardization in education. Joans outstanding
scholarship came to our attention when we were researching the intersections
between the lives of Erich Fromm and Paulo Freire. We were thrilled to discover that
these two men spent time together, but more than that held similar views on the role
we play in creating hope as active, dynamic, and forward-looking. For Fromm, hope
that is not acted upon is not hope at all. And for Freire, hope is so essential to what
it means to be human that he describes it as an ontological need. Both Fromm and
Freire saw hope as active and productive, and a necessary driving force for social
change. Dr. Braunes innovative reading and elaboration of Fromms prophetic
messianism fits precisely into this critical view of radical hope that refuses to accept
the present order while actively imagining and engaging in transformative praxis in
present local and global contexts. We present this book as a beacon of active and
persistent hope in the midst of prevailing and often hopeless conditions in education.
It is our hope that in the spirit of Fromm and Freire, this book will both inform and
inspire teachers, students and cultural workers everywhere to imagine and transform
schools, neighborhoods, cities and countries into dynamic places of sustainable life,
radical love and the undiminished light of humanity at its best.
Tricia Kress and Robert Lake
ix
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
This exhilarating and consuming project could not have come to fruition without
feedback from and fruitful dialogue with many people. I would like to thank my
dissertation committee, especially my advisor, Arnold Farr, along with the rest of
the committee: Christopher Zurn, Richard Wolin, Ronald Bruzina and Theodore
Schatzki. Arnold Farr was incredibly insightful and supportive throughout the
dissertation process, and it has been a pleasure to work with him and to join in the
Marcuse Society conferences. Oliver Leaman also provided helpful feedback.
I would also like to thank Robert Lake, co-editor of this series with Tricia Kress,
both of whom have done much fine work in bringing Critical Theory into wider
circles of education, including among emancipatory educators. I am publishing
through this series at Bobs invitation, and I am eager to do so, not least because
I think the material is timely for the left today, as well as for Critical Theory and
critical pedagogy. I am very pleased that this book will form part of the series on
Imagination and Praxis: Creativity and Criticality in Educational Research.
My parents, Nick Braune and Linda Braune, were immensely helpful. I am
incredibly fortunate that my parents were very interested in my research and had
many ideas to offer and discuss. My father in particular was a dialogue partner,
and we have presented on Fromm together at a range of conferences. Both my
parents offered more proofreading help than anyone ought to ever do for free. I am
immensely grateful.
My grandmother Yvonne Braune, besides knowing a slew of labor history and
being in other ways equally awesome, deserves tremendous thanks for her financial
assistance in helping me through both undergraduate and graduate education.
Rainer Funk, the director of the Erich Fromm archive in Tbingen, Germany and
director of the International Erich Fromm Society helped to answer some questions,
including sharing with me some of Fromms correspondence via e-mail, and it has
been an honor to participate in two of the European conferences he helped to organize
on Fromms work. I am also grateful to the Thomas Merton Center at Bellarmine
University, where I was able to study the original correspondence between Thomas
Merton and Erich Fromm. (I also viewed documents by Fromm at the New York
Public Library and University of Kentucky Special Collections Library.)
I would also like to thank Beth Rosdatter, John Connell, Tiffany Rogers, Kimberly
Goard, and Craig Slaven for their proofreading assistance or related feedback
at different stages of the writing process. I would also like to acknowledge the
encouragement of strong networks of graduate student friends, including a writers
group and an online goal-setting group.
It is a pleasure to thank all those who helped me bring this work to fruition,
not all of whom can be listed here. Naturally, all weaknesses of the book are my
responsibility and not that of anyone mentioned here.
xi
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
***
This is a book about a radical tradition, and my life is partly the product of radical
traditions, although anyone who chooses to be part of such traditions is part of
them. When my mothers grandmother Ida Solowey fled czarist Russia for New
York City, after having gotten into some trouble over illegally redistributing grain
to peasants, I imagine she expected the revolution would come soon. When my
paternal grandfather Paul Braune left behind a Catholic seminary when the reality of
the Great Depression shattered his political complacency, and when he later went to
work as a lawyer for draft dodgers and Black Panthers, there must have been times
when he also expected the revolution to come soon. So too, probably, did my parents
in the 1960s. I, too, want to choose for the revolution, and I too expect the revolution
soon. When I look back and realize how many before us felt the same way, I see it
not as evidence that we will fail but as a promise to live in and if necessary (though
I want to win), to pass on. Thank you, to all who have gone before in the struggle.
xii
INTRODUCTION
xiii
INTRODUCTION
inevitable consequences, not only for society as a whole but for the individuals
who compose it.
Catastrophic (or apocalyptic) messianism, the type of messianism that Fromm
criticizes and rejects, holds that radical change can occur only through a catastrophe
that creates a dramatic break from all preceding history. According to a prominent
version of this type of messianism, in a time of catastrophein fact, at the moment
of humanitys greatest corruption and failuresome kind of external force will
rescue humanity and inaugurate a utopian-like future. This salvation could come in
any of several forms: a political leader, a pre-determined law of history according
to which crises must produce their own resolutions, a self-declared party vanguard,
a deity, a small excluded minority, or an intellectual or artistic elite. Whichever
form it takes, this saving force is perceived as entering society from the outside. In
contrast to the horizontal longing of prophetic messianism, catastrophic messianism
is characterized by a vertical longing, a longing for forces or authorities to descend
from outside the usual pattern of human affairs, as a force majeure, to redeem a
fallen and helpless humanity (YSB 133).
According to catastrophic messianism, the vertical intervention into history by
the messianic event creates a dramatic rupture, severing the messianic future from
all preceding history. Scholar of Jewish mysticism Gershom Scholem was one of the
leading exponents of catastrophic messianism, and the concept of rupture is central
to his understanding of messianism (OBH 142). Scholem posits a lack of transition
between history and redemption (The Messianic Idea 10). In an oft-quoted passage,
he explains,
The image of the coming of the messianic age as a bolt of lightning from above differs
profoundly from Fromms prophetic messianism, which conceives the messianic age
as a product of ongoing human action in (horizontal) history.
According to Fromm, catastrophic messianism has dangerous psychological and
social consequences. Although catastrophic messianism may appear hopeful in its
expectation of dramatic change, it is actually based upon a form of despair that
gives the false appearance of hope (ROH 8). At its most benign, it is characterized
by an illusory hope that manifests itself as passive, inactive waiting, sometimes
combined with busy consumption of consumer goods and mass entertainment, as
the depressed and socially isolated individual fills up her time while expecting to
be rescued by some authority figure (ROH 6-12). At its most malignant, the illusory
hope of catastrophic messianism generates attempts to force the Messiah, such
xiv
INTRODUCTION
xv
INTRODUCTION
religion of reason. At the time when Cohen was developing this philosophy,
the prophetic messianic spirit still held considerable sway over socialist and
anarchist movements. Cosmopolitan, humanist, socialist, and calmly rational,
Cohens messianism influenced a generation of German-Jewish intellectuals. But
the rational, universalist messianism of the likes of Cohen and Leo Baeck stands
in sharp contrast to the later, cataclysmic, semi-Romantic messianism of some
German-Jewish intellectuals of the 1920s. Cohen thus came to represent a mainstay
of Enlightenment optimism and Kantian rationalism that the young radicals of the
1920s repudiated as outmoded.
Before joining the Institute for Social Research, Fromm participated in the Freies
Jdisches Lehrhaus in Frankfurt. The Lehrhaus was a hub of leftwing Jewish intellectual
life in 1920s Germany; its many famous participants included Martin Buber, Gershom
Scholem, Franz Rosenzweig, Leo Lwenthal, Ernst Simon, Leo Baeck, and Abraham
Heschel. During this time, Fromm was influenced by Hermann Cohens workhe
later called Cohen the last great Jewish philosopher and praised him for grasping the
connection between messianism and socialism (OBH 143). Yet Buber, Rosenzweig,
and many others in the Lehrhaus circle who were initially drawn to Cohens ideas
eventually broke away from Cohens thought (Lwy, Redemption and Utopia 59).
A new messianismromantic, nihilistic, anarchic, and catastrophicenvisioned a
messianic future that would arrive not as a product of human progress or planning
but suddenly, in a time of disorder and despair, through a dramatic rupture with all
prior history. Fromm stands, sometimes isolated, as a prominent Marxist theorist who
continued to defend the pre-war universalistic messianism well into the 1960s and who
saw it as true to Marxs vision. His commitment to this ideal set him apart from many
of his contemporaries, including his colleagues in the Frankfurt School.
Today the questions raised by Fromms messianism are more relevant and vital than
ever. The twentieth century was plagued by the problem of the future, and the current
century appears likely to remain troubled by the same problem. Nearly all ways of
thinking about the future are enmeshed in dangers, which become ever more evident
in light of the tragedies of the twentieth century. On the one hand, determinism with
regard to the end of history can foster quietism, whether of a blindly optimistic
or cynically pessimistic sort. If the determinist acts at all, she is likely to act with
destructive nihilism, viewing her action as essentially meaningless. On the other
hand, despite the dangers of determinism, political hope might seem to lack all
foundation or justification without the certainty that historical determinism provides,
and hope for a better future seems to be a necessary component of any effort to
improve society. Nearly all the empirical evidence appears to suggest that humanity
is faced with an uncertain future, and if things end at all, they will likely end badly,
so what could possiblyone might rhetorically askprovide a basis for hope, save
a blind, deterministic faith? Yet Fromm provides us with a real alternative.
xvi
INTRODUCTION
xvii
INTRODUCTION
xviii
INTRODUCTION
xix
INTRODUCTION
***
xx
INTRODUCTION
Bloch and Georg Lukcs. Finally, the chapter touches upon the peculiar affinities of
the Stefan George circle to Critical Theory.
In Part II of the book, I turn towards a theoretical and interpretive approach to Fromm.
Fromms account of messianic hope and his philosophical defense of it are explored
in light of both historically situated and perennial concerns. Chapter 3 focuses upon
hope, examining Fromms negative and positive definitions of it, his philosophical
defense of hope, and the phenomenological experience of hope. The three negative
definitions of hope are explained at length: (1) hope is not mere desiring or wishing,
(2) hope is not passive or inactive waiting, and (3) hope does not attempt to force
the Messiah. Although he holds that less can be said positively and propositionally
about hope, Fromm connects hope with life and growth and provisionally defines
it as an awareness of [the] pregnancy of the present. Fromm argues for an ethical
obligation to anticipate the future with hope, including an obligation to seek out
signs of potential in the present, as opposed to finding only evidence suggesting that
humanity is doomed. Responding to the obligation to hope reveals the crucial choice
of alternatives with which humanity is faced, and without hope (a hope that is far
from politically neutral), the alternative remains hidden. The idea of what one might
call an epistemologically privileged subject is also found in Lukcss assertion of the
privileged standpoint of the class-conscious proletariat, and specifically on the topic
of hope, in Catholic existentialist philosopher Gabriel Marcels essay in Homo Viator.
I draw upon Marcel in order to uncover something that Fromm appears to be trying to
say but does not articulate as fully or as clearly as does Marcels account.
Chapter 4 focuses at length upon Fromms messianism and argues that Fromms
messianism is indeed (despite some evidence that could be interpreted to the
contrary) faithful to the pre-war messianic model of Hermann Cohen, not the later,
more apocalyptic or catastrophic model. Arguing against Eduardo Mendietas and
Rainer Funks interpretations of Fromms messianism, which reflect a widespread
mis-categorization of Fromms messianism, I suggest that a lack of understanding of
Fromms uniqueness in relation to the rest of the Frankfurt School has caused him
to be incorrectly categorized with the apocalyptic/catastrophic camp of messianism.
In the process, Fromms sort of messianism has been nearly forgotten, or is often
discounted as not truly messianic.
Most of Chapter 4 is structured around a response to a summation offered by
Eduardo Mendieta of the collective messianic outlook of the Frankfurt School, a list
that Mendieta draws and builds upon from the criteria outlined by Anson Rabinbachs
book In the Shadow of Catastrophe: German Intellectuals between Apocalypse and
Enlightenment. I break down these criteria into a list of five themes: (1) Rupture,
(2) Historical Golden Age and Anamnesis, (3) the Enlightenment, (4) Progress and
Catastrophe, and (5) Utopia and Imagining/Conceiving the Future. I demonstrate
that on each of these five themes, Fromms messianism differs significantly from the
account offered by Mendieta/Rabinbach. This exploration is followed by a daring
reply to Rainer Funks account of Fromms messianism, wherein I argue that Funk
incorrectly portrays Fromms messianism as a kind of esoteric Gnosticism.
xxi
INTRODUCTION
NOTES
1
Most of the books Fromm published during his life directly addressed the theme of messianism, as
did a range of his articles and posthumously published manuscripts. The books that directly discuss
messianism include: The Sane Society (1955), Let Man Prevail: A Socialist Manifesto and Program
(1960), Marxs Concept of Man (1961), May Man Prevail? An Inquiry into the Facts and Fictions of
Foreign Policy (1961), Beyond the Chains of Illusion: My Encounter with Marx and Freud (1962),
You Shall Be as Gods: A Radical Interpretation of the Old Testament (1966), The Revolution of Hope
(1968), To Have or To Be? (1976) and his unfinished, posthumously published manuscript Marx and
Meister Eckhart on Having and Being (in On Being Human).
2
The clearest summation of Fromms position on Marx can be found in the introductory chapter to his
Marxs Concept of Man:
I shall try to demonstrate that[Marxs] theory does not assume that the main motive of man
is one of material gain; that, furthermore, the very aim of Marx is to liberate man from the
pressure of economic needs, so that he can be fully human; that Marx is primarily concerned
with the emancipation of man as an individual, the overcoming of alienation, the restoration of
his capacity to relate himself fully to man and to nature; that Marxs philosophy constitutes a
spiritual existentialism in secular language and because of this spiritual quality is opposed to
the materialistic practice and thinly disguised materialistic philosophy of our age. Marxs aim,
socialism, based on this theory of man, is essentially prophetic Messianism in the language of
the nineteenth century. (MCM 3)
3
E.g., cf. Jrgen Habermas, Religion and Rationality: Essays on Reason, Religion, and Modernity
(Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, 2002).
4
Jacques Derrida, of course, employs the term messianism and revitalizes it; the key text is Specters
of Marx. On Judith Butler, see her essay Prophetic Religion and the Future of Capitalist Civilization
in The Power of Religion in the Public Sphere, ed. Eduardo Mendieta and Jonathan Vanantwerpen
xxii
INTRODUCTION
(Columbia, 2011). For Agamben on messianism, see The Time that Remains: A Commentary on the
Letter to the Romans (Stanford University Press, 2005). Cornel West is noteworthy in this regard
for his defense of hope and the prophetic, although he is not heavily engaged in postmodern debates
about messianism. For Kristeva, cf. Strangers to Ourselves (Columbia University Press, 1994).
ieks frequent talk of the Holy Spirit as a loving community or emancipatory collective bears
ties, historically and theoretically, to messianism. For texts that can be read as a iekian account of
messianism, see First as Tragedy, Then as Farce (Verso, 2009), especially the concluding chapter, and
In Defense of Lost Causes (AK Press, 2011), as well as God in Pain: Inversions of Apocalypse (Seven
Stories Press, 2012).
5
Although Walter Benjamin was never a formal member of the Frankfurt Institute for Social Research,
he is generally classed among the members of the broader category of Frankfurt School thinkers.
6
For example, Svante Lundgrens The Fight Against Idols: Erich Fromm on Religion, Judaism and
the Bible offers a helpful overview of Fromms thought on various religious matters, and the question
of messianism is treated, although Lundgren seems to miss its significance for his thought and the
important historical context surrounding the issue. Rudolf Sieberts The Critical Theory of Religion
grasps the importance of messianism for Fromms thought, but Siebert does not seem to differentiate
Fromms messianism much from that of other members of the Frankfurt School, while I argue that
Fromms messianism is of a very different sort and somewhat a critique of the messianism of the rest
of the Frankfurt School.
7
Cf. Lawrence Wilde, Erich Fromm and the Quest for Solidarity (New York: Palgrave MacMillan,
2004), and Lawrence Wilde, Against Idolatry: The Humanistic Ethics of Erich Fromm in Marxisms
Ethical Thinkers, Ed. Lawrence Wilde (Houndmills, U.K.: Palgrave, 2001).
8
Redemption and Utopia: Jewish Libertarian Thought in Central Europe: A Study in Elective Affinity.
Trans. Hope Heaney. (Stanford, California: Stanford University Press, 1992); Anticapitalist Readings
of Webers Protestant Ethic: Ernst Bloch, Walter Benjamin, Georg Lukacs, Erich Fromm Logos
Journal (http://logosjournal.com/2010/lowy/).
9
Several examples of note:
Education: Rafael Pangilinan, Robert Lake
Ethics: In addition to Lawrence Wilde, there is Francisco Illescas, Reflexiones ticas a partir de
Erich Fromm: Una propuesta para el humanismo del siglo XXI.
Sociology: Neil McLaughlin, Anderson and Quinney
Psychology: Towards Psychologies of Liberation by Mary Watkins and Helene Shulman.
Jewish Studies: Material Culture and Jewish Thought in America by Ken Koltun-Fromm (Indiana
University Press, 2010)
Jewish theology: Rabbi David Hartman
Sociology of Religion: Seyed Javad Miri, in Iran (Rereading Fromms Conditions of the Human
Situation Volume 11. December 2010; Transcendent Philosophy: An International Journal
for Comparative Philosophy and Mysticism; Religion and Social Theory in the Frommesque
Discourse Islamic Perspective. No. 4. 2010).
10
Michael Lwy is one of the best contemporary scholars of this cultural milieu and of the theme of
messianism, but he defines the prophetic tradition out of messianism from the start, and he writes
that Scholem is universally recognized as the greatest authority in this area [Jewish messianism and
political implications] (Jewish Messianism 106).
Although Wolin, Rabinbach, and Lebovic offer a compelling critique of apocalyptic messianism and a
defense of the Enlightenment as a radical project, they tend to use the term messianism to refer only
to its apocalyptic variant. For Rabinbach, for example, see Rabinbachs four criteria of messianism in
Chapter 4 below. For Wolin, cf. the chapter on messianism in Labyrinths: Explorations in the Critical
History of Ideas, which proved exceedingly useful for this book but is problematic in certain respects,
perhaps largely due to its reliance on Gershom Scholems account of messianism. Wolin has been
wary of messianism, treating it partly as a nostalgic, restorative enterprise and seeing it as reliant on an
undialectical intervention of transcendence into history, an account of messianism that Fromm rejects,
as we shall see (Wolin, Labyrinths 4950).
xxiii
PART I
3
CHAPTER 1
will establish that he brought his own, original ideas with him to the Institute.
Following an overview of Fromms pre-Institute work, I offer an exploration of
Fromms work during the approximately ten years of his membership in the Institute.
Fromm contributed significantly to the development of the Institutes early research
program. Far from being a mere product of the Institute, Fromm was one of its
leading architects.
Although Fromm was one of the earliest members of the Frankfurt Institute for
Social Researchhe became a formal, tenured member in 1930, before both Herbert
Marcuse (in 1933) and T. W. Adorno (in 1938)and although he played a central
role in the Institutes early years, Fromm was virtually written out of the history
of the Frankfurt School until recently. His legacy in Critical Theory has fallen
victim to an origin mythas McLaughlin puts it, drawing upon the sociology of
knowledgethat accords him a marginal role (McLaughlin, Origin Myths). Over
the past two decades a renaissance has occurred with regard to Fromms work and
the history of Fromms role in Critical Theory through the work of Stephen Eric
Bronner, Lawrence Wilde, Kevin Anderson, Michael Lwy, Neil McLaughlin, and
Thomas Wheatland, among others. The old origin myth of the Frankfurt School,
however, continues to exert its influence over some current scholarship, and this myth
fundamentally mislocates Fromms contribution. It ignores that Fromm was an early
member of the Frankfurt Schools core circle and that his theoretical and empirical
work were central to the Institutes program. The myth also downplays or fails to
properly credit Fromms tremendously important synthesis of the psychoanalytic
and Marxist methods and his related development of the theory of the authoritarian
personality, which formed the basis for much of the Institutes later work.
Fromms marginalization was not the result of mere scholarly error, nor the
consequence of some historically contingent series of events that rendered his ideas
less serviceable or less noticeable. On the contrary, Fromms role as a persistent gadfly
in every institution and tradition to which he belonged did not ingratiate him to Critical
Theorists, some Marxists, or orthodox psychoanalysts, and his marginalization from
canonical historical accounts of these fields was often intentional and systematic.
After the 1960s protest movement faded, Fromm was also unintentionally sidelined
because his messianic hope was out of sync with the prevailing, pessimistic Zeitgeist,
as we will see in later chapters. His refusal to confine his work to a single academic
discipline or to obediently toe the line of any school of thought also had much to do
with his marginalization during the 1970s and 80s.
In many works surveying the history or main ideas of the Institute, Fromm is
barely mentioned. For example, Trent Schroyers The Critique of Domination: The
Origins and Development of Critical Theory (1973) and Zoltn Tars The Frankfurt
School: The Critical Theories of Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno (1985)
say almost nothing about Fromm (McLaughlin, Origin Myths 113n7). Schroyers
4
ERICH FROMMS LEGACY AND CONTRIBUTION TO THE EARLY FRANKFURT SCHOOL
book only mentions Fromm once in passing (Schroyer 203). To be fair, the book is
not so much a history of the Frankfurt School as an exploration of certain themes,
with a heavy focus on Marx and Habermas, but its lack of engagement with Fromm
is symptomatic of the problems of the genre. Tars book, meanwhile, is closer to
an historical account of the Frankfurt School, yet it equates the early Frankfurt
School with Horkheimer, ignoring the contributions of Fromm and others to the
early Frankfurt School. The title of the book alone perpetuates the myth that the
Frankfurt School was essentially a product of Max Horkheimer and T. W. Adorno.2
And the most important recent book on Horkheimer, John Abromeits 2011 Max
Horkheimer and the Foundations of the Frankfurt School, while it gives Fromm
more attention than some of the older texts, still treats Fromms role in the early
study of the German working class as confined mainly to gathering empirical
data and supplying psychoanalytic categories, with Horkheimer as the theoretical
mastermind (Abromeit 219).
Nor does Fromm fare better in bland and supposedly unbiased reference works.
Despite the rediscovery of Fromm, even some recent reference works still play into
the origin myth. For example, the German Library (Continuum) volume on the
Frankfurt School includes selections from Horkheimer, Adorno, Walter Benjamin,
Herbert Marcuse, and Leo Lwenthal, but nothing from Fromm. Likewise,
The Cambridge Companion to Critical Theory (2004) does not contain an essay
devoted to Fromm, and Fromm is mentioned only twice in the volume. He is
mentioned only once and quite briefly in the essay on the marriage of Marxism and
psychoanalysisthe very project for which Fromm was hired by the Institute!
and he is mentioned once more in Raymond Guesss contribution, which classifies
Fromm with Franz Neumann and Walter Benjamin as having had a perhaps more
distanced and idiosyncratic relation to the central group of the Institute (Whitebook
75; Guess 105). That Fromms role in the Institute was anything but distanced or
peripheral will become clear shortly.
When Fromm is not summarily dismissed, he is often gravely misrepresented.
Three of the earliest, most important works on the history of the Institute for Social
Research gravely misconstrue Fromms contribution: David Helds Introduction
to Critical Theory: Horkheimer to Habermas (1980), Rolf Wiggershauss The
Frankfurt School: Its History, Theories, and Political Significance (1986), and
Martin Jays The Dialectical Imagination: A History of the Frankfurt School and
the Institute of Social Research, 19231950 (1973). In this section, I examine the
weaknesses of Helds, Wiggershauss, and Jays accounts of Fromm as presented in
these three books. I am not concerned here with the merit of any of these books as
a wholeeach constitutes an important contribution to the study of the Frankfurt
Schoolbut only with their role in establishing the origin myth about Fromms
role in the Institute.
First, David Helds Introduction to Critical Theory offers a small number of scattered
comments on Fromm, in the course of which Held distances Fromm from the early
Institute. Held treats Fromm as a merely marginal member and sometimes not even as
5
CHAPTER 1
a member at all. In fact, Held incorrectly claims that Fromm did not become a formal
member until after the Institutes exile to the United States, though in fact Fromm had
become a member three years earlier and had helped facilitate the groups transition to
the United States (Held 111). Held even contrasts Fromm with the Institute and the
Institutes members, while referring to times when Fromm was still a formal member
of the Institute (119). He also misconstrues the reasons for Fromms later removal
from the Institute, writing that Fromm left the Institutein order to spend more time
on clinical work and to develop a psychology that was more explicitly sociological and
less Freudian, while in fact Horkheimer decided to cut Fromms salary, and Fromm
believed that he was being fired for being too Marxist and demanded a hefty severance
packagemore about that shortly (111). Helds tone towards Fromm is dogmatic and
priestly in the bureaucratic, gate-keeping sense.3 To socialists, the claim that Fromm
left the Institute because he wanted to develop some other theoretical approach may
sound alarmingly reminiscent of the typical excuses of some socialist party that has
just kicked out a perceived troublemaker: We didnt purge him; he abandoned our
line, so in effect hed already split from the Party anyway.
When it does not airbrush Fromm from the history of the Institute as completely as
Helds book does, the origin myth often makes Fromm perform a magical vanishing
act after leaving the Institute. On the rare occasions when it must be mentioned,
Fromms post-Institute work is dismissed in the literature as unserious, not radical,
or excessively optimistic. A typical example of the first two of these charges against
Fromms later work can be found in Wiggershauss book, while the last charge
(optimism) is made in Jays book.
Compared to David Held, Wiggershaus has a fairly significant amount to say
about Fromm. However, Wiggershaus presents Fromm as an unserious, flaky thinker
who abandoned radicalism. According to Wiggershaus, Fromms early thought was
mired in insoluble contradictions that eventually led him to irrational escapism. Since
Wiggershaus does not want to make the Frankfurt School itself look flaky, he seeks to
demonstrate that Fromm abandoned some early, more sensible standpoint after leaving
the Institute. Thus, following a relatively useful summary of Fromms contribution to
the early Frankfurt School, he sums up by exposing a dubious contradiction in Fromms
early thought, followed by an odd dismissal of Fromms later work:
First, it was shown [by Fromm] that the tight functioning of society would not
permit any radical change in the conditions of life; then it was said that only a
radical change in the conditions of life would be able to change the behaviour
of the masses. But even this sort of change in the conditions of life would only
lead to the creation of the new ideological superstructure which the economic
and social base would require. With views such as these, it was only a matter
of time before someone like Fromm, who was convinced that fulfillment in life
was possible for everyone, turned resolutely towards a messianic humanism
which offered an ever-present escape from the endless chain of being and
consciousness. (Wiggershaus 60)
6
ERICH FROMMS LEGACY AND CONTRIBUTION TO THE EARLY FRANKFURT SCHOOL
7
CHAPTER 1
8
ERICH FROMMS LEGACY AND CONTRIBUTION TO THE EARLY FRANKFURT SCHOOL
No matter how much truth there may be in the claims that Fromm is traditional or
idealist when these claims are properly qualified, the lack of adequate explanation
typically accompanying these claims encourages a different reading. The implied
meaning is that Fromm was not revolutionary (i.e., that he favored tradition over
transformation), and that Fromm was idealist as opposed to materialist, and ergo,
according to the prevailing wisdom, not Marxist. I argue elsewhere in this book
that Fromm was a revolutionary (not a reformist) and was certainly Marxistin
fact, Fromms exile from the Institute probably had more to do with him being too
Marxist and with his desire to be involved in left-wing activism.
3. Finally, Wiggershaus bases his claim of Fromms conservatism on the premise
that Fromm believed that the solution to contemporary problems was found in the
individual and spontaneity (Wiggershaus 270). Here Wiggershaus appears to
take the line of Adorno, who, in a letter to Horkheimer, opined that Fromm was
not a Marxist but either a social democrat or an anarchist, and that Fromm ought
to read Leninmore on that letter shortly (McLaughlin, Origin Myths 118).
Although there are anarchist influences on Frommhis The Sane Society engages
with several anarchist thinkers, and the thought of anarchist revolutionary Gustav
Landauer was an enduring influence on Frommit is also the case that others in
the Frankfurt School were similarly influenced by anarchism and some more so
than Fromm. Fromms philosophy may be called communitarian socialism, or to
use his more common term, socialist humanism (SS 283). His anarchist affinities
are definitely not of Max Stirners individualistic type, critiqued by Marx and
Engels in The Germany Ideology. Furthermore, Fromms interpretation of Marx,
especially by the 1960s after Fromm had studied Marxs early writings, held that
Marx placed great value on the individual, and Fromms enduring appreciation
for Marxist revolutionary Rosa Luxemburg could explain his openness to the idea
of spontaneous revolt (the mass strike), a concept Luxemburg also believed was
rooted in Marx. Fromms concern with the individual and with spontaneity was
chiefly a Marxist critique of Stalinism, not a call for anarchism.
If Wiggershauss book provides an archetypal example of the common charges that
Fromm was not a serious thinker and that he abandoned his early radicalism, it is
to Martin Jay that one can turn for a look at the common claim that Fromm was
excessively optimistic. Martin Jays The Dialectical Imagination, the last of the three
early canonical books on the history of the Frankfurt School to be examined here,
provides a useful and detailed summary of Fromms early work. Although it focuses
upon Fromms theory and does not discuss his directorship of empirical studies very
much,4 Jays account of Fromms early theoretical work is relatively unproblematic.
It is when describing Fromms post-Institute work that Jays narrative becomes
ambiguous and weak.
Jay prefers Herbert Marcuses theories to Fromms on the topic of psychoanalysis,
and he also views Marcuse as the most Marxist member of the Frankfurt School. Jay
occasionally allows this position to distort his scholarly objectivity: for example,
9
CHAPTER 1
10
ERICH FROMMS LEGACY AND CONTRIBUTION TO THE EARLY FRANKFURT SCHOOL
As McLaughlin points out, to those who were accustomed to hearing the word
in a different context, this sounded like a charge that Fromm was a Marxist
revisionist (Bernsteinian reformist/social democrat as opposed to revolutionary
Marxist) and thus insufficiently radical. Jay cites a personal interview with Fromm
in which Fromm supposedly commented that Horkheimer had discovered a more
revolutionary Freuda quote that Jay almost certainly took out of context, since
it is entirely inconsistent with the rest of Fromms oeuvre (Dialectical Imagination
101). Fromm always sought the revolutionary implications of Freuds work, but he
also excoriated Freud for his authoritarianism, nationalism, and sexism, reiterating
throughout his work that Freud was limited by his bourgeois, Victorian context.
From Fromms standpoint, the revolutionary implications of Freuds thought could
be found only through the method that Marcuse, Horkheimer, and Adorno rejected
as an unjustified revisionism.
Helds, Jays, and Wiggershauss dismissals of Fromm helped to cement until
recently the common charges that Fromm was a marginal member of the Institute,
that he was excessively optimistic and conservative, and that he was a flaky,
unserious thinker. In concluding this overview of the origin myth concerning
Fromms role, it is worth noting that often what is most problematic about the
canonical interpretations of Fromms role in Critical Theory is not the interpretations
themselves but the blithely presumptive way in which they are asserted. These
writers and many other writers on Critical Theory seem to feel no need to justify the
assumptions that optimism is undesirable, that drawing upon classic concepts of
philosophical or religious traditions constitutes de facto conservatism, that orthodox
Freudianism is more radical than revisionist Freudianism, and so forth. Fromms
marginalization has been so total that, until recently, scholars of the Frankfurt School
typically have felt obliged to justify neither their rejection of his later work nor
their casual swipes at his early work. The story told about the Frankfurt School by
Horkheimer, Adorno, to some extent Marcuse, and sometimes Habermas has been
taken at face value for decades. What has resulted is a peculiarly ideological, gate-
keeping defense of the Frankfurt School line that has, until the mid- to late 1990s,
remained uncontested.
11
CHAPTER 1
one of the earliest goals of the Institute. (He was the Institutes only trained
psychoanalyst.) Under Max Horkheimers directorship, the early Frankfurt School
was committed to studying the totality of society through interdisciplinary methods
and drawing connections between theory and practice, while steering clear of
orthodox Marxist reductionism. Fromms social psychology, melding the insights of
Freud and Marx, sought to avoid reducing social phenomena to purely libidinal or
economic causes, instead offering multi-layered explanations, as we shall see. His
early work on Freud and Marx led him to novel explanations of the role of family,
political power, religion, and other social structures in shaping the psychological
character of individuals and the pervasive psychological character orientations
within societies. Before joining the Institute, however, Fromms thought was shaped
by his early experiences in left-wing Jewish intellectual circles in Germany, by his
doctoral studies in Sociology in Heidelberg under Alfred Weber, and by his study
and practice of psychoanalysis.
Fromm had more exposure to Jewish religious observance in his upbringing
than others of his generation of the Frankfurt School.5 His father was descended
from a long line of Talmudic scholars and was embarrassed to be a businessman;
he had probably hoped that Erich would become a rabbi. Fromm later wrote that
he felt himself to have grown up in the feudal world, not the modern world, and
that in his childhood he looked upon business careers as shameful (Funk, Life and
Ideas 6, 8). In the late 1910s and early 1920s, he split his time between university
study in Heidelberg, where he completed a doctorate in Sociology, and social life in
Frankfurt, where he studied Judaism under prominent rabbis and Talmudic scholars
and was active in left-wing Jewish intellectual circles.
In Heidelberg, Fromm completed a dissertation in Sociology under Alfred
Weber, Max Webers brother, who authored an important history of philosophy
with a strong emphasis on Spinoza, Kant, and Hegel, and became famous for
pioneering studies in economic geography.6 I had only one non-Jewish teacher
whom I really admired and who deeply influenced me, Fromm later wrote, and
that was Alfred Weber, the brother of Max, also a sociologist, but in contrast
to Max, a humanist, not a nationalist and a man of outstanding courage and
integrity (AS 251). Fromm also took courses from Heinrich Rickert (who
also had a profound influence upon Walter Benjamin) and Karl Jaspers (Jay,
Dialectical Imagination 202; Lwy, Redemption and Utopia 152). His 1922
dissertation was entitled Jewish Law: A Contribution to the Study of Diaspora
Judaism and explored the way that the Jewish law was interpreted by the
Karaite, Hasidic, and Reform Jewish communities (Lundgren 86). Like many
young left-wing German Jews of the time, Fromm rebelled against the status
quo by becoming interested in Hasidism. Martin Buber had embraced Hasidism
for his project of utopian renewal, and it seemed to Fromms generation
like a plausible alternative to the staid, bourgeois Orthodoxy of their parents
generation. Fromms dissertation also employed Hermann Cohens thought and
Max Webers work on the Protestant ethic to discuss how the Jewish perspective
12
ERICH FROMMS LEGACY AND CONTRIBUTION TO THE EARLY FRANKFURT SCHOOL
on labor differed from the perspective of the Puritans (Lundgren 101, 83). The
distinction between meaningful and alienating dimensions of labor is an ongoing
theme throughout all periods of Fromms work.
Meanwhile, in Frankfurt, Fromm was active in the loosely socialist Jewish youth
movement, the Blau-Weiss. A Jewish alternative to the German youth movement
(which was unfriendly to Jewish membership), the Blau-Weiss took hikes in the
countryside and sang songs about their unique Jewish identity. Fromm was still a
member of the Blau-Weiss for a couple of years after 1922, when the organization
formally declared its commitment to Zionism and began urging its members to
emigrate to the newly forming kibbutzim in Palestine. But under the influence of
Hermann Cohen, who was one of the leading Jewish opponents of Zionism, and the
influence of Fromms mentor and Talmud teacher, the socialist Russian exile Salman
Rabinkow, Fromm soon came to see Zionism as just another of the pernicious
nationalisms to which he was opposed (Funk, Life and Ideas 40).
Like Cohen, about whom more will be said in Chapter 2, Salman Rabinkow was an
interesting figure with a circle of close students. Fromm met with Rabinkow nearly
daily for five years, studying philosophy and sociology in addition to the Talmud
and discussing Fromms thesis work (AS 251). Rabinkow was remembered by his
students as a humanistic and gentle person, an opponent of religious fanaticism. He
differed from similar teachers in Frankfurt in that he employed the less formalistic
Lithuanian method of Talmudic study, which stressed psychological depth, deeper
comprehension of the spirit of Jewish law, and the organization of unified points
of view (Schacter 98). Studying from morning to night with great enthusiasm,
Rabinkow refused to confine himself to a particular academic discipline, refused
to take payment from his students, and never sought a professorial or rabbinical
position. His many students, from Ernst Simon to Nahum Goldmann, later spoke of
him with tremendous admiration (Schacter).
Along with studying under Rabinkow and coming into contact with Cohen,
Fromm was also part of a circle around the Rabbi Nehemiah Nobel, a highly
respected Conservative7 rabbi who was rooted firmly in the progressive tradition of
the Jewish Enlightenment (the Haskalah). Nobel took an interest in Fromms studies,
and the two used to take long walks together, including on the Sabbath when it was
forbidden, a precursor to Fromms eventual break from Orthodoxy (Funk, Life and
Ideas 39; Lwenthal 19). The circle around Nobel was radical, heavily influenced
by both socialism and Jewish mysticism (Lwenthal 19). In circles such as these in
early 1900s Germany, becoming aware of ones Jewish identity was a process that
was often intimately tied to revolutionary politics.
In 1920, Fromm helped to found the Freies Jdisches Lehrhaus (Free Jewish
Study-House) out of the circle around Nobel. The Lehrhaus became a hotbed of
left-wing German-Jewish intellectual life.8 It would be difficult to over-estimate
the environment of electric intellectual excitement that surrounded the Lehrhaus,
whose many famous participants included Martin Buber, Gershom Scholem, Franz
Rosenzweig, Leo Lwenthal, Ernst Simon, Leo Baeck, and Abraham Heschel. It is
13
CHAPTER 1
safe to say that already, approximately seven years before joining the Institute for
Social Research, Fromm was developing some of his own ideas about the type of
messianism that he wished to promote; messianism was a topic of heated debate at
the Lehrhaus. Fromm taught a course on the Book of Exodus there, while Gershom
Scholem (the nemesis of Fromms messianism) taught a course on the Book of
Daniel. Fromm later used Exodus as a paradigm of the struggle for liberation, and he
rejected apocalyptic versions of messianism presented in texts like Daniel (Funk,
Life and Ideas 42; YSB 90-116; ROH 18).
In 1924, Fromm became interested in psychoanalysis and was trained and
psychoanalyzed by Frieda Reichmann, whom he married in 1926. He had first met
her in the early 1920s at the expensive sanitarium near Dresden where she was
serving wealthy clients while seeking donations from them to treator rather, to
build a sort of commune out ofthe members of the Blau-Weiss, including Fromm
(Hornstein 29, 53).9 She was a mother figure for these Jewish youth, bringing them
food and allowing them to hang around and socialize in her living quarters during
the daytime while she was treating wealthy clients (53-4). Rejecting assimilation,
she supported the burgeoning Zionist youth movement as a rediscovery of a separate
Jewish identity (63). For close to four years, Reichmanns biographer writes, this
sanitarium within a sanitarium functioned as a model community...Patients helped
each other in whatever ways they could: one would give Hebrew lessons, and another
would mend his socks in return (54). Reichmann moved to Heidelberg in 1924 to
set up her own sanitarium, the Therapeuticum, with plainly religious and utopian
motivations. The principle was that ritual practices didnt have to be compulsions
performed in a rote way out of fear of punishment by God; they could be the basis
for deep spirituality (64). As Reichmann later explained,
We thought we would first analyze the people, and second, make them aware
of their tradition and live in this tradition, not because the Lord has said so, but
because that meant becoming aware of our past in big style. Then we would
do something not only for the individuals but also for the Jewish people.
(Silver 20)
The point of communes like the Therapeuticum was a rediscovery of Judaism as
a unique identity that stood outside the mainstream of German society. Although
the anti-assimilationist Jewish youth did not always define their commitment in
such terms, according to Leo Lwenthal this revolt against assimilation was often
motivated by opposition to capitalism more than by a defense of an ethnic or religious
identity (Lwenthal 19).
Founded together with Fromm, Reichmanns Therapeuticum was so heavily
influenced by Jewish thought and spirituality that it became known as practicing
a Torah-peutic method, serving kosher meals and celebrating Jewish holidays
(Kellner Erich Fromm, Judaism 3, Lwenthal 26). The clientele were primarily
Jewish intellectuals, including Leo Lwenthal, Ernst Simon, and Rabinkow (Funk,
Life and Ideas 61). It was seen as radical and cutting edge; psychoanalysis was
14
ERICH FROMMS LEGACY AND CONTRIBUTION TO THE EARLY FRANKFURT SCHOOL
not yet popular and was still viewed with suspicion. Lwenthal later credited
the Therapeuticum with influencing the Frankfurt School project of melding
psychoanalysis and Marxism (Lwenthal 26). By that time, it should be noted,
Fromm was becoming increasingly politically radicalized, probably largely through
his experiences at the Lehrhaus and through the influence of Rabinkow. Gershom
Scholem described Fromm in 1926 as an enthusiastic Trotskyite who now pitied
me for my petit-bourgeois parochialism (by which parochialism he probably
meant Zionism) (From Berlin 156).10
Reichmann, approximately ten years Fromms senior, employed a therapeutic
method based upon the Jewish idea of tikkun (redemption, making-whole) and the
Hasidic messianic proverb that to redeem one person is to redeem the world. There
were no neutral actions: every moment and every encounter with another person
was an opportunity to release the divine sparks hidden within creation (Hornstein
28, 42). (The belief in these hidden sparks was a product of the Lurianic Kabbalah,
which influenced Hasidism as well as some interesting revolutionary moments in
Jewish history.)
At the time that Reichmann met Fromm, both were still steadfastly Orthodox
in accord with their upbringing; Reichmann had kept kosher through medical
school and had refused to work on the Sabbath throughout her time as a doctor
treating brain-injured soldiers during the war (Hornstein 53). Under the influence
of psychoanalytic ideas, however, Fromm and Reichmann drifted away from their
earlier religious assumptions. Fromms decisive break with Orthodox Judaism came
in 1928. For Fromm, the stage had already been set for his break from Orthodoxy by
the contacts he had made through the Lehrhaus, and his walks with Rabbi Nobel on
the Sabbath, which broke the rules of the Sabbath observance, would have already
raised the question in Fromms mind.
Reichmanns biographer Gail Hornstein states that Fromms and Reichmanns
1927 articles psychoanalyzing the Sabbath ritual and kosher laws, published in
Freuds journal Imago, already marked their initial, public break from Orthodoxy.
Reichmann later said of the publications, Thats how we announced we were through
[with Orthodoxy], in big style, like two real Jewish intellectuals! (Hornstein 66). A
more complete break followed in 1928, when they went to a park during Passover
(feast of unleavened bread) and ceremoniously and silently shared a loaf of leavened
bread (66). Perhaps with a tinge of sadness, Reichmann later joked that they were
afraid at the time about the folk belief that Jews who abandoned Orthodoxy were
cursed to die childless; neither of them believed in the curse, of course, but neither
Reichmann nor Fromm ever did have children (Silver 22).
Reichmann later became renowned as an extraordinarily gifted and humane
psychoanalyst, famous for refusing to give up hope on even the most challenging
cases. Fromm and Reichmann separated in 1930, after which Fromm had romantic
relationships with Karen Horney (from around 1933 to 1943) and with African
American dance artist and anthropologist Katherine Dunham in the early 1940s,
before marrying Henny Gurland in 1944, and Annis Freeman in 1953 after Gurlands
15
CHAPTER 1
death (Hornstein 68). (Regrettably little research has been done upon the relationship
with Dunham, whose pioneering work on Caribbean dance and connection to the
ngritude movement merit study in their own right. Lawrence Friedmans new
biography of Fromm is one of the first works on Fromm to discuss Dunham in the
context of U.S. culture; Rainer Funks illustrated biography of Fromm mentions
the relationship but does not mention that Dunham was African American. Dunham
speaks highly of Fromm as a humanist in her 1969 memoir of her time in Haiti,
Island Possessed.)
With Fromms help after their separation, Reichmann obtained a position at an
important mental hospital in the U.S., which she directed for many years. In a feat
that Freud had considered impossible, she famously used psychoanalysis to cure
a patient of schizophrenia, as memorialized in the famous book and film I Never
Promised You a Rose Garden. Fromm and Reichmann kept in touch a bit over the
years after their separation and were amiable in their later years (Silver 21).
Despite some weaknesses, Fromms 1927 article on the Sabbath was significant
for his later work; it was Fromms first formal attempt to apply psychoanalytic
theory to a concrete sociological phenomenon. The article was a bit reductionist,
concluding that the Sabbath was a ritual of repentance for the Oedipal desire for
the mother and the killing of the father (Funk, Life and Ideas 61).11 It was Fromms
first published text dealing with messianism, though it lacked the complexity of
his later work on the theme. Nature and the earth, symbolically associated with the
mother (Mother Earth), were not to be violated upon the Sabbath; the Sabbath
sought to restore the harmony and oneness experienced in the womb, symbolized
in Jewish thought by Paradise (Lwy, Redemption and Utopia 152). According to
Michael Lwy, the article demonstrated a brief brush by Fromm with restorative
messianism (153). Fromms mature writings interpreted Jewish messianism not as a
restoration of a prelapserian golden age but rather as a dialectical synthesis of history
and pre-history.
Fromms dissertation on the Jewish law and his article on the Sabbath both
examine the nature of labor and point towards radical transformation of working
conditions. Both express hope for a messianic future free of misery and toil (Lwy,
Redemption and Utopia 153). In the Sabbath article, Fromm speaks of a total absence
of work in the messianic age, harking back to Marxs and other early socialists
calls for an abolition [Aufhebung] of labor (Lwy, Redemption and Utopia 153;
Zilbersheid).12 Fromms dissertation speaks similarly, though not of an abolition of
labor but of the transformation of labor into something pleasurable. He rejected the
asceticism of the Protestant work ethic and urged a return to the Jewish view of work
as something good though not an end in itself (Lundgren 83).
In concluding this overview of Fromms life and work prior to joining the Institute,
it seems that there is abundant evidence that Fromm brought his socialist radicalism
with him to the Frankfurt School and that Fromms radicalism was not due chiefly to
his involvement in the Institute. Through his dissertation on the Jewish law and his
article on the Sabbath, Fromm was exploring the nature of labor and envisioning a
16
ERICH FROMMS LEGACY AND CONTRIBUTION TO THE EARLY FRANKFURT SCHOOL
messianic future in which labor would be liberated and leisure would be increased.
The general milieu of young enthusiastic Jewish socialists in which Fromm found
himself before joining the Institute, along with the influence of Rabinkow, Hermann
Cohen, and Rabbi Nobel, would have encouraged him to interpret his religious
background in a radical, socialist light, as would the radical excitement of the
rising psychoanalytic movement and the experience of Reichmanns commune-like
sanitarium within a sanitarium near Dresden and the Heidelberg Therapeuticum.
Scholems claim that Fromm was a Trotskyist in 1926, while spoken with derision,
provides further evidence that Fromm was drawn to Marxism. In the following
section, we will explore how Fromm came into contact with the Institute for Social
Research, the work he did while allied with it, and the reasons for his parting from
the Institute approximately ten years later.
Now that Fromms pre-Institute work has been examined, the reader has a sense of
the ideas and experiences that Fromm brought with him to the Institute. Fromms
collaboration with the Institute for Social Research began in 1928 or 1929 when
Fromm began working with Max Horkheimer, before Horkheimer took over as
director (Abromeit 194). Fromms friend Leo Lwenthal, whom Fromm had once
introduced to the Lehrhaus circle, returned the favor by introducing Fromm to
Horkheimer (Funk, Life and Ideas 72). In 1930, shortly after Horkheimer took over
from Friedrich Pollock as director of the Institute, Horkheimer hired Fromm as a
tenured member to head the Institutes social psychology division (Bronner 79). This
was before Marcuse and Adorno joined the Institute. At this time, Fromm was a core
member of the Institute, though Horkheimer later downplayed his centrality to the
Institutes history (Funk, Courage 296-7).
Despite the Institutes heritage of a dictatorship of the director (as earlier
director Carl Grnberg had approvingly quipped), one must not overstate the extent
to which Horkheimer set the agenda for the early Institute. It is true that Horkheimer
saw the need for bringing psychoanalysis into conversation with Marxism, and
his interest in psychoanalysis had been stimulated by Lwenthals stories about
being psychoanalyzed at Fromm and Reichmanns Therapeuticum (Jay, Dialectical
Imagination 87). As was popular among intellectuals of the time, Horkheimer had
also undergone psychoanalysis himself (under Karl Landauer, who was also one
of Fromms analysts) (Abromeit 188; Roazen, Exclusion 3). However, the mere
fact that Fromm was already in touch with Horkheimer in 1928 or 1929, before
Horkheimer became director of the Institute, casts some doubt on the standard
narrative. According to that narrative, Horkheimers famous opening lecture as
director of the Institute was a solitarily-conceived blueprint for the Institutes future
work, and Fromms effort to synthesize Freud and Marx conveniently just happened
to be what the early Institute was seeking. But it is more likely that Horkheimer stated
this commitment in his opening lecture because he was fully aware that Fromm was
17
CHAPTER 1
already engaged in this project, and because he intended to hire Fromm. The same
goes for Horkheimers articulation in the speech of plans for an upcoming empirical
study of the German working class, which Fromm later led.
In his opening lecture, Horkheimer also expressed his commitment to an
interdisciplinary research program that would seek to understand the social totality. In
the tradition of Karl Korsch and Georg Lukcs, both of whom had challenged Marxist
orthodoxy in favor of a Hegelian emphasis on historical totality, Horkheimer sought
to foster a radical, loosely Marxist social theory that drew upon Hegel and steered
clear of economic reductionism and positivism. He also was wary of philosophical
systems from the outset. He hoped to link theory with practice, exploring concrete
examples of socio-historical phenomena while avoiding scientism and positivism
(Jay, Dialectical Imagination 41).
By drawing upon Freud, Fromm would forge a path for Critical Theory avant la
lettre that avoided narrow reductionism and explored multiple social phenomena,
such as the family, religion, and law. Much of his work shortly before joining the
Frankfurt School and while a member of the Frankfurt School in the 1930s was
devoted to creating a theoretical synthesis of Freud and Marx and exploring its
applications to concrete institutions and practices, such as the legal system, early
Christianity, and the politics of the German working class. Fromm was intimately
involved in the Frankfurt Schools early project of doing theory in a way that spoke to
contemporary problems and that discovered the intersections of the socio-economic
totality within the lives of individuals.
Fromms early work, however, may already have been in tension with some of
Horkheimers aims. Fromms humanism, manifesting itself by the 1940s in the
assertion that, despite other sources contributing to the development of individual
character, there is nevertheless a certain unchanging human essence which would
reach its fulfillment in the future, would have been anathema to Horkheimers
hesitancy about the idea of an enduring human nature, his rejection of the idea of a
meaning of history, and his affinities with Schopenhauers pessimism (Abromeit
148-9; Jay, Dialectical Imagination 55-6). Fromms early work may have avoided a
possible confrontation on this issue; Fromms most overt arguments for humanism
and messianism come later, beginning in the 1950s. He would later title his political
program socialist humanism, and nearly all of Fromms work after leaving the
Frankfurt School addressed questions of an enduring human nature and its future
fulfillment. Another, related factor at work in Horkheimers evolution from
excitedly hiring Fromm to nervously distancing himself from him may have been
Horkheimers evolution of ideas with regard to the Enlightenment; as Abromeits
biography suggests, the early Horkheimer seems to have been a defender of the
Enlightenment ideal of reason against proto-fascist and lebensphilosophische
ideologies (Abromeit 171). This defense of the Enlightenment would have meshed
well with Fromms own concerns until Horkheimers disappointment stemming from
the Moscow Trials and the conformist character of U.S. culture led Horkheimer to
a greater degree of hesitancy with regard to the Enlightenment promise of freedom
18
ERICH FROMMS LEGACY AND CONTRIBUTION TO THE EARLY FRANKFURT SCHOOL
through reason, education, and democratic equality. We will return to the events
surrounding Fromms break from the Institute later in this chapter.
In what follows I offer a chronological overview of Fromms writings and their
significance, from the time when Fromm first came into contact with the Institute
in 1929 to the time of his parting with the Institute in 1939. This is necessary in
order to show that Fromms early writings made a significant contribution to the
Frankfurt School and to present some of the ideas that Fromm would later develop
in greater detail, which will be explored further in later chapters. Later in this book
it will become evident that Fromms post-Institute work emerged logically out of his
earlier work and is usually in harmony with it, seriously engaging many of the same
themes, contra the common charge that Fromms post-Institute work flew off on an
irrational and flaky tangent.
We can begin by exploring Fromms early article Psychoanalysis and Sociology.
The article was written at the end of 1928 and published in 1929 in a psychoanalytic
journal, before Horkheimer became director of the Institute in 1930 (Funk, Major
Points 2). In that article Fromm laid out the basis of his synthesis of Freud and Marx,
explaining psychoanalysiss need for sociology and vice versa. It pointed to Freuds
recently published Future of an Illusion as an indication that Freud recognized
the need for exploring the historical genesis of the psyche (Psychoanalysis and
Sociology 2). Kevin Anderson suggests that the essay might better have been titled,
Psychoanalysis and Marxism and that Fromms commitment to a revolutionary
Marxist position is already evident in it (Anderson [2000] 92). Marxism is the only
sociological theory addressed in the article, and Fromm calls Marx the greatest
sociologist of all (92). Fromms essay concludes with a quote from The German
Ideology that expresses an idea of Marxs that Fromm would frequently reference in
his later work on messianism: History does nothing, it possesses no immense wealth,
it fights no battles. It is instead the human being, the real living person, who does
everything, who owns everything, and who fights all battles (92; Psychoanalysis
and Sociology 3). As Anderson rightly notes, Marxist themes recur throughout
Fromms work, including his early essays, which frequently offer a radical critique
of the reformism of Social Democrats Kautsky and Bernstein (95).
In 1930-1, Fromm published three studies on criminology in psychoanalytic
journals and a lengthy class analysis and psychoanalysis of early Christianity, The
Dogma of Christ. Despite the surface appearance of a large divergence between
the two topics, the criminology essays and the essay on early Christianity address
relatively the same issue: the way in which authority is maintained through becoming
internalized in the psyche of the individuals subject to it, who sado-masochistically
seek punishment for their repressed desire to rebel.
The three essays on criminology explored the social function of punishment in
maintaining the authority of the state. Fromm reflects that the threat of punishment
does not deter crime, since most crimes either have economic causes or result from
unconscious motives, not rational premeditation (State as Educator 124). Although
punishment rarely deters crime, the purpose of punishment does not seem to be mere
19
CHAPTER 1
20
ERICH FROMMS LEGACY AND CONTRIBUTION TO THE EARLY FRANKFURT SCHOOL
and turned to the Church and to the cult around Mary as images of the forgiveness
and love that could be obtained through obedience and passive acceptance of
authority (93-5).
The Dogma of Christ was hailed by a review in the Institutes Zeitschrift as
(Michael Lwys paraphrase) the first concrete example of a synthesis between
Freud and Marxno small achievement (Lwy, Redemption and Utopia 155).
The Dogma of Christ was also a political statement: as Michael Lwy points
out, Fromm intended his analysis of early Christianity as a criticism of the Soviet
Union (155). The decline of the early Christian communes with their revolutionary
enthusiasm and the rise of a hierarchical Church structure, obediently submissive
to the Roman ruling class, was an allegory for the collapse of the early, enthusiastic
workers councils (soviets) and the submission of the Russian working class to the
Stalinist state after the death of Lenin (155).13
Importantly, the essay also contained a political critique of Gnosticism. Fromm
was writing at a time when a sizeable subculture, including some proto-fascists
as well as some sincere leftists, were claiming to be returning to the worldview
of ancient Gnosticism, especially its despairing belief in the worlds fallen-
ness and its vision of goodness and the messianic future as wholly other. Fromm
described the ancient Gnostics as the well-to-do Hellenistic middle class[who]
wanted to accomplish too quickly and too suddenly what [they] wishedbefore
the consciousness of the masses could accept it (DC 75). They wereone might
paraphrasethe ancient worlds Romantic nihilists. In The Dogma of Christ,
Fromm stressed that there was an alternative to the failed options of compliant
obedience (Stalinism), revisionism (Bernstein and Kautskys reformism), and
Gnosticism (romantic or reactionary yearning for destruction or return to the past)
(75). In early Christianity, Montanism emerged as an alternative to these failed
options. The Montanist movement was a revolt against the conforming tendencies
of Christianity and sought to restore the early Christian enthusiasm (75). It is not
clear where Fromm located the contemporary equivalent of the ancient Montanist
rebirth of messianic enthusiasm, such as whether he would have equated it with
Trotskyism or some other emerging movement, or whether he would have described
it as something that he wished for and did not yet see happening. Wherever Fromm
may have seen hope for change in his context, however, his essay was plainly radical
and was plainly critical of Stalinism, reformism, and nihilist Gnosticism. One may
justifiably assume that it was more than Fromms Jewish background that caused
the Nazis later to add the The Dogma of Christ to their list of prohibited reading
materials (Roazen, Exclusion 2).
Some would argue that The Dogma of Christ presents an inaccurate account
of the history of Christianity, but the point is somewhat irrelevant to the aims of
Fromms essay. The Dogma of Christ was not primarily about Christianity. In
addition to critiquing the situation of the left of the time, the essay addressed the
same important question that Fromms work on criminology had addressed: the
way in which external political authority becomes internalized in the psyche of
21
CHAPTER 1
22
ERICH FROMMS LEGACY AND CONTRIBUTION TO THE EARLY FRANKFURT SCHOOL
23
CHAPTER 1
(Noll 164). In the ideological battleground of the 1920s, however, Bachofen had
made a comeback. Among proto-fascists, his work was taken as a mythical, Teutonic
alternative to Freuds more rationalistic approach to psychoanalysis. Fromm warned
of this right-wing enthusiasm surrounding Bachofen, and he also pointed out that
Bachofens work had been used by Engels and other radicals, not just the right-wing,
and thus might be salvageable.
Fromm responded to and defended the radical interpretation of Bachofen, arguing
that the differing political interpretations were made possible by the contradictions
in Bachofen himself, an aristocrat discontented with capitalism and fascinated by the
past, though not a Romantic (CP 92). Fromm writes of Bachofen:
There is obviously a sharp contradiction between the Bachofen who admires
gynocratic democracy and the aristocratic Bachofen of Basel who opposed
the political emancipation of womenIt is a contradiction that crops up
on several different planes. On the philosophical plane, it is the believing
Protestant and Idealist over against the Romantic and the dialectic philosopher
over against the naturalistic metaphysician. On the social and political plane,
it is the anti-Democrat over against the admirer of a Communist-democratic
social structure. On the moral plane, it is the proponent of Protestant bourgeois
morality over against the advocate of a society where sexual freedom reigned
instead of monogamous marriage. (93)
These contradictions in Bachofen made possible the varying interpretations of his
work, but it is Marxism, according to Fromm, that can best account for the dialectical
contradictions in Bachofens work. Though it is not a return to the past, Marxism is
the heir of the pre-historic matriarchal system, of its values of equality and fraternity
(108-9).
The Bachofen articles represented a further development of the dialectical approach
of Fromms Dogma of Christ and demonstrated greater nuance than Fromms
Method and Function. In the more substantive of the two Bachofen articles, one can
see Fromms emerging commitment to a highly future-oriented messianism, away
from any restorationist desires for a mere return to Paradise. The proto-fascists
Ludwig Klages, Alfred Bumler, and Alfred Schuler praised Bachofens theory
because they looked back to the past as a lost paradise, while the radicals (Marx,
Engels, Bebel, and others) praised Bachofens theory from an opposite standpoint,
since they looked forward hopefully to the future (CP 85). Everyone at that time
would have known that Klages and Bumler had turned to Bachofen in search of
a psychology that would provide an alternative to Freudian psychoanalysis and in
search of a lebensphilosophische alternative to Neo-Kantianism, which was now
perceived as stale and bourgeois (Lebovic, Beauty and Terror 2, 10). (For further
discussion of Klages and Lebensphilosophie in relation to the Frankfurt School,
see Section 2.4 in Chapter 2.) Unlike his proto-fascist contemporaries Klages and
Bumler, Fromm was not abandoning Freuds rationalism in favor of Bachofens
irrationalism. Rather, he was drawing upon Bachofen in an attempt to transcend
24
ERICH FROMMS LEGACY AND CONTRIBUTION TO THE EARLY FRANKFURT SCHOOL
the limitations of both Freud and Bachofen through a dialectical synthesis of the
pre-historic matriarchy envisioned by Bachofen with the modern, Enlightenment
insights of psychoanalysis.
In the same essay on political responses to Bachofen, one can see Fromms
emerging psychoanalytic critique of Nazism, which he would revisit and rework
throughout his career, even exploring the question at great length in his very late
work The Anatomy of Human Destructiveness (1973). In the early essay, Fromm
analyzed the desire among the masses for regression to a state of helpless infancy
and dependence upon an all-giving, all-nurturing mother. This mother figure
was to be honored symbolically through passive submissiveness towards nature
(manifested by belief in history as fated or cyclic), a strong preference for those
to whom one is related by blood, a predilection to honoring the dead through rigid
repetition of rituals, and an attachment to land and soil, symbolically associated
with motherhood and feminine fertility. The conservatives looked to Bachofens
theory of matriarchy for these traits, which were already being exalted by the Nazi
Party. Although the fascist movement oppressed women, Fromm points out that
the reactionaries sympathies for Bachofen did not conflict with their opposition to
womens liberation. Rather, the reactionaries liked Bachofens theory of matriarchy
because they liked the idea that there were natural, essential differences between
the sexes (which, while not Bachofens main point, was a point on which Bachofen
agreed), and because they were attracted to the submissive acceptance of fate that
had supposedly characterized the matriarchal world (CP 90).
In 1933, the Institute collided with Nazi power and sought refuge in Geneva, and in
1934 it moved to New York. Although the Nazis had closed the Institute, it may have
been possible to remain a while longer. But considering Fromms psychoanalysis of
Nazism, the members of the early Institute were not surprised by the Nazis rise to
power, and they knew that they needed to escape Germany quickly (Lwenthal 27).
The pathologies of Nazism and the trend towards compliant obedience among the
German working class were ever on Fromms mind. Furthermore, Fromms theory
and personal experiences had given him cause to fear nationalism. Nationalism had
long been a major intellectual concern for Fromm. One of the formative experiences
of his adolescence was his startled discovery of the irrationality of the patriotic
fervor in support of World War I (BC 7). Moreover, his early participation in and
rejection of the Zionist movement added to his concerns about nationalism.
In addition to his worries about nationalism, Fromms research project on the
German working class convinced him that the danger of Nazism was far greater
than most of his contemporaries yet realized. His study of the German working class
was based upon the premise that, although most German workers were ideologically
opposed to Nazism, this was not sufficient indication that they would resist the
Nazis (DC 151).15 It was unclear whether the German working class opposition
to Nazism was merely superficial or rooted in [their] character structure (151).
The study concluded that the majority of the German citizens would be neither
enthusiastic Nazis nor dissidents but would quietly acquiesce to the rise of National
25
CHAPTER 1
Socialism, since their professed support for freedom was only superficial. Even
more worryingly, the study found that some workers affiliated with the left would
be drawn into the Nazi movement by their love of authoritarianism. For example,
asked to list their heroes, some left-wing participants responded with a list like,
Marx, Lenin, Nero, and Alexander the Great, while others responded to the effect
of, Marx, Lenin, Socrates, and Pasteur (OD 35). While both respondents professed
support for socialism, for the former respondent socialism was a mere ideology
or rationalization covering over a love of power, while the latter respondent
truly admired benefactors of mankind (35). While the latter respondent would
likely support the resistance, the former might support the Nazis. Not surprisingly,
considering the results of this study, the Institute moved almost as far away from
Germany as geographically possible, leaving Europe entirely, long before many
others fled.
By 1935, as the Institute settled into its new home in New York, the seeds of
Fromms expulsion from the Institute had been planted. Fromm was popular in the
U.S. and probably felt at home more quickly than others in the Institute, since he
already had many contacts in the U.S. through psychoanalytic circles. (However,
Wiggershauss claim that Fromms popularity implied that Fromm had friends
who were less radical and that this caused his break from the Frankfurt School is
dubious.) Frequently traveling, Fromm was not in New York as steadily as the other
members of the early Institute were. In addition to his ability to settle comfortably
into the U.S. more rapidly, perhaps his work on Bachofen had created some tension
between him and others in the Frankfurt School. Some in the Institutes broad social
circles may have disagreed with Fromms attack on Ludwig Klages in that work,
and Fromms critique would not have gone unnoticed by Adorno or by Adornos
friend Walter Benjamin, both of whom had crossed paths with Stefan Georges and
Ludwig Klagess Cosmic Circle and had formed their own opinions on the Bachofen
debateI will return to this briefly in Chapter 2.
Despite these factors that may have brought into question Fromms role in the
Institute, it was the response to Fromms 1935 essay for the Zeitschrift, The Social
Determinants of Psychoanalytic Theory that most explicitly demonstrated the rift
that was growing between Horkheimers close circle of followers and Fromm.16
Adorno at this time was trying to get closer to Horkheimer but was still an outsider
and knew little about the Institutes earlier work. He responded to Fromms article
with a polemical rant in a letter to Horkheimer, accusing Fromm of being a reformist
who needed to read more Lenin:
[Fromms article] is sentimental and wrong to begin with, being a mixture
of social democracy and anarchism, and above all shows a severe lack of the
concept of dialectics. He takes the easy way out with the concept of authority,
without which, after all, neither Lenins avant-garde nor dictatorship can be
conceived of. I would strongly advise him to read Lenin. And what do the anti-
popes opposed to Freud say? No, precisely when Freud is criticized from the
26
ERICH FROMMS LEGACY AND CONTRIBUTION TO THE EARLY FRANKFURT SCHOOL
left, as he is by us, things like the silly argument about a lack of kindness
cannot be permitted. This is exactly the trick used by bourgeois individualists
against Marx. I must tell you that I see a real threat in this article to the line
which the journal takes... (McLaughlin, Origin Myths 118-9)
It is a perplexing rant indeed, especially the admonition to read Lenin. If Adorno
were genuinely concerned that Fromms approach were reformist or anarchist, then
he might have turned to Marx for a critique, not Lenin. Perhaps Adorno believed
that Horkheimer was an orthodox Marxist and would be concerned about deviation
from orthodox Marxism, but Adorno seems to miss the fact that that debate would
have been about Stalin, not Lenin. Nor does Adorno seem to realize that one of
the Institutes main theoretical projects to that point had been a study of authority
commissioned by Horkheimer. There is a certain absurdity in Adornos claim that
Fromms study took the easy way out with the concept of authority.
Although Adorno ends up looking confused, the letter is significant because it
suggests the flawed equation that would later be used in an attempt to marginalize
Fromm from the left: Freudian revisionism = Marxist revisionism = reformism.
It should be pointed out that although critical of Freud, Fromms article was not at
all critical of Marx or of revolutionary sentiments; the articles Freudian revisionism
was in no way connected to Marxist revisionism. In fact, the article condemned
the weaknesses in Freuds theory and Freuds personal character as essentially
the results of a bourgeois, class bias on the part of Freud, and the article harshly
criticized the merely reformist, liberal attitude of mainstream psychoanalysis,
which was condescending and authoritarian despite its appearance of objectivity
and tolerance. According to Fromm, the orthodox Freudian psychoanalyst subtly
sends the following message to the patient:
Here you come, patient, with all your sins. You have been bad, and that is
why you suffer. But one can excuse you. The most important reasons for your
misdeeds lie in the events of your childhood for which you cannot be made
responsible. Furthermore, you want to reform, and you show this in coming
to analysis and in giving yourself up to my directions. If, however, you do not
complythen you cannot be helped. (Social Determinants 158-9)
In contrast to this patriarchal and authoritarian attitude towards the patient, Fromm
urged an attitude of unconditional (matriarchal) love for the patient. But far from
suggesting that such love was absent in Marx or Marxism, Fromm presented
his article as a critique of bourgeois attitudes and also rejected any Romantic or
unscientific return to feudal values (for which he critiqued Groddeck) (159). The
article plainly suggests that psychoanalysis must struggle to transcend both feudalism
and capitalism, though the article is focused primarily on a critique of Freudian
psychoanalysis and does not proceed to discuss socialism directly.
By 1935 Fromm had already challenged Freudian orthodoxy on a variety of
points, but his critique had not previously been so vehement. Almost from the very
27
CHAPTER 1
28
ERICH FROMMS LEGACY AND CONTRIBUTION TO THE EARLY FRANKFURT SCHOOL
1920s: the role of the state in socialization as it took over a role once consigned
to the family (the rise of the state as educator, as Fromm had put it), increased
sadomasochism among the masses, and a loneliness that craved authority (Bronner
82). Horkheimers earlier work had focused more upon philosophical questions
concerning social totality, ontology, the relation between theory and practice, and the
Institutes research program in relation to various other philosophical and theoretical
approaches in vogue at the time (positivism, orthodox Marxism, phenomenology,
Neo-Kantianism). The Studies development of the theory of the authoritarian
personality and its relation to the family was almost entirely a product of Fromms
theoretical work.
It was not until 1939 that Fromm formally broke from the Institute. It should be
clear by now that the break was not due to a lack of substantive contributions on his
part. In fact, it was quite the opposite. It is difficult to determine, however, whether
Fromms break from the Institute was mainly caused by Horkheimer, Adorno, or
both equally. In The Frankfurt School in Exile (2009), Thomas Wheatland lays the
blame squarely on Horkheimer. By contrast, Neil McLaughlin stresses Adornos
role in Fromms break from the Institute; some evidence for this view is already
suggested by Adornos angry response to Fromms 1935 article.
According to Wheatlands interpretation, as the Institute adjusted to exile in
New York in the late 1930s, Horkheimer was solidifying his relationship with new
alliesAdorno, Otto Kirchheimer, Franz Neumann, and Walter Benjaminand
distancing himself from some old ones, especially Fromm (Wheatland 61). Fromms
centrality to the Institute and his public persona were making Horkheimer nervous.
Wheatland writes,
Of all the Horkheimer Circles members, Fromm became the most visible and
popular at Columbia during his first years in the United States. He was less
guarded than his colleagues, and he was in a position, as the groups functional
director of social research projects, to develop strong contacts with U.S. social
scientists. (76)
Horkheimer was frequently concerned about maintaining the loyalty of members
of the Institute, and his often authoritarian grip made the Institute resemble the
authoritarian family structures it was researching (80). This view of Horkheimers
authoritarian grip upon the Institute corresponds to Jrgen Habermas later assessment
of Horkheimers character in the 1950s. According to Habermas, Horkheimer was
an authoritarian and bullied all the young assistants (Specter 32). In a 1934 letter
to Pollock, Horkheimer wrote,
[Fromm] does not particularly appeal to me. He has productive ideas, but he
wants to be on good terms with too many people at once, and doesnt want to
miss anything. It is quite pleasant to talk to him, but my impression is that it is
quite pleasant for very many people. (83)
29
CHAPTER 1
30
ERICH FROMMS LEGACY AND CONTRIBUTION TO THE EARLY FRANKFURT SCHOOL
In the first years of the Institute, while it was in Frankfurt and Geneva,
Horkheimer has [sic] no objection to my critique of Freud, which began very
slowly before I left the Institute. It was only in the years after the Institute had
been for some time in New York, and maybe since I began to write Escape
from Freedom, that Horkheimer changed his opinion, became a defender of
orthodox Freudianism, and considered Freuds attitude as a true revolutionary
because of his materialistic attitude towards sex. A strange thing for Horkheimer
to do incidentally, because it is pretty obvious that Freuds attitude toward
sex corresponded to the bourgeois materialism of the 19th century which was
so sharply criticized by Marx. I remember that Horkheimer was also on very
friendly terms with [Karen] Horney in the first years of [Horkheimers] stay
in New York, and did not then defend orthodox Freudianism. It was only later
that he made this change and it is too personal a problem to speculate why he
did so. I assume partly this had to do with the influence of Adorno, whom from
the very beginning of his appearance in New York I criticized very sharply.
Considering the whole situation of the Institute it is not surprising that when
Horkheimer made this change, Lowenthal and Pollack [sic] did the same.
Adorno was in this respect probably not influenced by Horkheimer, but rather
the other way around. (McLaughlin, Origin Myths 119n21, italics mine)
This passage strongly suggests that Adornos mid-1930s letter to Horkheimer, with
its polemical admonition that Fromm should read Lenin (as though Fromm hadnt
read Lenin!) was indeed an indication that Adorno was seeking to push Fromm out
of the Institute in order to work more closely with Horkheimer. However, in spite
of this conclusion, one must also bear in mind Horkheimers powerful position in
the Institute and Fromms remark elsewhere that the unwillingness of Horkheimer
to publish [the study on the German working class] was one of the many conflicts
which led to [Fromms] departure (116).
Whatever the causes, Fromms firing resulted in a major set-back for the Institute
both financially and for its public image. Not only did the Institute have to pay
Fromm a sizeable severance package$20,000 was no paltry sum in the Great
Depressionbut Fromms firing resulted in the Institute losing funding from
Columbia University. Fromm had played a crucial leadership role in the studies of
the German working class and on authority and the family, and in the late 1930s he
had directed empirical research studies of unemployed men in Newark and female
students at Sarah Lawrence College (Wheatland 66, 70). Prominent Columbia
sociologist Robert Lynd, a friend of Fromms, was angered by the Institutes treatment
of Fromm and denounced the Institute with the claim that Fromm had been fired for
being too Marxist, an assessment with which Fromm himself concurred (85). And
since Fromm had been considered the leader of the Institutes empirical research,
and since Columbias Sociology department emphasized empirical research, which
was the trend in academic sociology in the U.S. in 1939, it appeared to Columbia
that the Institute no longer had much to contribute. At Lynds recommendation,
31
CHAPTER 1
another research group (Paul Lazarsfelds) replaced the Institutes former position
at Columbia (86). The Institute then turned to research on anti-Semitism, partly in a
desperate search for grant funding (88).
We are not concerned here with the Institutes further work after the break with
Fromm, so we leave off this historical account at the point of Fromms break from
the Institute. In Chapter 2, some Frankfurt School figures appear again in relation
to the messianic milieu of fin de sicle Germany and the apocalyptic Zeitgeist of
the 1920s. We also return in Chapters 3 and 4 to the work of some members of
the Frankfurt School, especially Herbert Marcuse, along with some examination of
Walter Benjamin and others, in relation to Fromms work on messianic hope.
As has been demonstrated, although he has long been marginalized by canonical
historical accounts of the Institute for Social Research, Fromms contributions to
Critical Theory were vast. Before joining the Institute, he had already explored the
theme of alienated labor through his dissertation under Alfred Weber and had begun
a theoretical synthesis of psychoanalysis and Marxism, applying psychoanalysis to
societal questions in his article on the Sabbath. After being invited into the Institute
by Horkheimer, Fromms explorations of the possibility of a theoretical synthesis of
Marx and Freud helped to shape the Institutes inter-disciplinary research program.
Fromm applied his synthesis of Marx and Freud to studies on criminology, early
Christianity, the Russian revolution (the underlying theme of The Dogma of Christ),
Bachofens theory of matriarchy, the family, and the authoritarian personality, all
while working with the Institute. As we have seen, Fromms thought evolved over
the course of his membership in the Institute, as he rejected biological and economic
reductionism, explored Bachofen while criticizing his reactionary acolytes, and
finally concluded that orthodox Freudianism (though not psychoanalysis itself) had
to be rejected. Fromms daring critique of Freud, his popularity, and perhaps his
desire to become involved in radical political activism may all have played a role in
his eventual exclusion from the Institute. Personal conflicts among members of the
Institute and the emerging intellectual partnership between Horkheimer and Adorno
probably contributed as well.
Whatever the reasons for Fromms break with the Institute, it should now be
evident that Fromms work during his approximately ten years of involvement with
the Institute was substantial and central to the Institutes program. Further, it should
be evident that Fromm was not merely a peripheral member of the Institute, was not
conservative or a liberal reformist, and was not an unserious or merely derivative
thinker. Instead, he was central and radical, forging a bold theoretical synthesis
between psychoanalysis and Marxism, applying this method to concrete problems,
and developing important critiques of the psychoanalytic establishment, orthodox
Marxism, and fascism. Although one must reject the claim of some that all the
essential ideas of Fromms later thought are contained in his 1930s writingsin
particular, his later writings were transformed by his encounter with the writings
of the early Marxthe explorations of human nature, history, and political power
in these early works were central to Fromms later work (Knapp 23). More
32
ERICH FROMMS LEGACY AND CONTRIBUTION TO THE EARLY FRANKFURT SCHOOL
Almost immediately after his exodus from the Frankfurt School, Fromm became
publicly engaged in left-wing activism. He also continued to challenge Freudian
orthodoxy, and he did so publicly and for a wider audience, including through a
controversial book-length case study of the master himself, Sigmund Freuds Mission.
I have examined Fromms early life, demolishing some common misconceptions
about Fromms place in Critical Theory. The later events in Fromms life do not need
to be covered at equal length here, but I will elucidate Fromms later life and work
briefly with respect to two themes: psychoanalysis and the left.
To explore Fromms later life and work with regard to psychoanalysis, I begin by
tracing Fromms professional migration from Freuds psychoanalytic organization, the
International Psychoanalytic Association, to his role in founding a new international
psychoanalytic movement, the International Federation of Psychoanalytic Societies,
which is still large and active today. Finally, I address Fromms psychoanalytic
legacy and his critique of orthodox Freudianism.
Due in large part to his public rejection of orthodox Freudianism and his scathing
critique of Freud and his circle, Fromm had rocky interactions with the International
Psychoanalytic Association (IPA).17 The IPA was the professional psychoanalytic
organization founded by Freud and representing Freudian orthodoxy. Although
some facts regarding the history of Fromms interaction with the IPA are unclearin
part because his last wife destroyed large amounts of Fromms correspondence after
his deaththe following facts are known. In 1935, Fromm was contacted by Carl
Mller-Braunschweig, then head of the Berlin branch of the IPA, known as the DGP,
which was still operating in Berlin under Nazi rule. Mller-Braunschweig rather
pointedly demanded that Fromm pay the dues he owed to the DGP. Fromm offered
to pay by installments, but in the spring of 1936, he withheld his last payment,
33
CHAPTER 1
34
ERICH FROMMS LEGACY AND CONTRIBUTION TO THE EARLY FRANKFURT SCHOOL
I have never wanted to form a school of my own. I was removed by the International
Psychoanalytic Association, and I am still [1971] a member of the Washington
Psychoanalytic Association, which is Freudian. I have always criticized the
Freudian orthodoxy and the bureaucratic methods of the Freudian international
organization, but my whole theoretical outlook is based on what I consider Freuds
most important findings (Jay, Dialectical Imagination 89-90)
It was the dispute over what those most important findings were that undergirded
Fromms exclusion from the IPA. He had been told that he could apply for re-
admittance and that it was unlikely that anyone who agreed with the basic tenets of
psychoanalysis would be excluded, but Fromm realized that what was at stake was
exactly the identity of those basic tenets.
35
CHAPTER 1
Today one can find few serious defenders of the death instinct, the primal
horde or orthodox libido theory. Most of the interesting work in psychoanalysis
rejects instinct theory and deals with, as Fromm suggested it must, relatedness
and identity. Fromms neo-Freudian former collaborator Karen Horney is now
being rediscovered as an early proponent of feminist object relations. Sullivans
work has given rise to the emergence of interpersonal psychoanalysis, an
important school of thought within contemporary Freudian theory. In addition,
Fromms position on Freudian theory has gained new influence in recent years.
(McLaughlin, Origin Myths 8)
Few of Fromms ideas have been credited to him in the canon of psychoanalytic theory
today. These ideas are generally viewed in disjunction from Fromms contribution to
Critical Theory. It is telling, for example, that an Oxford Dictionary of Psychology
lists Horkheimer, Adorno, and Marcuse under its definition of Frankfurt School
and does not mention Fromm, although it does have a separate entry on Fromms
[character] typology (Colman 287, 290).
Although Fromm is still too often overlooked, the ideas he and others advanced
are now more widely accepted, which has paved the way for an ongoing revival
of Fromms contributions to psychoanalysis. In Europe, his insights are enriching
certain psychoanalytic circles, such as the circle around the recently deceased
Italian psychoanalyst Romano Biancoli. In Mexico, the International Federation of
Psychoanalytic Societies (IFPS) holds conferences that seek to draw from Fromms
psychoanalytic insights. The editorial of a 2000 issue of the journal of the IFPS
was headlined, Erich Fromm: A Rediscovered Legacy. In 2009 a new introductory
book to Fromms psychological thought was published, Annette Thomsons Erich
Fromm: Explorer of the Human Condition. While encumbered by a sometimes
overly simplistic style of argumentation,19 the book discusses ways in which Fromms
insights underlie developments in psychology that are now widely accepted.
Fromms work is also currently contributing to the development of psychologies of
liberation (cf. Shulman and Watkins, Bruce Levine).
Much remains to be done towards recuperating Fromms psychoanalytic legacy.
As Paul Roazen writes, A central silence in the official story of the history and
development of psychoanalytic thought has to do with Erich Fromms contributions
(Roazen, Escape 239). The time is ripe for a revival of interest in Fromms
humanistic psychoanalysis. The reputation of psychoanalysis itself has suffered since
the 1950s and 60s, especially as the Reagan-era drug war and neoliberal laudations
for individual responsibility found the behaviorism of B. F. Skinner more useful for
36
ERICH FROMMS LEGACY AND CONTRIBUTION TO THE EARLY FRANKFURT SCHOOL
its ideological aims. Although Skinner rejected the use of punishment (aversives)
as a means of behavior modification, others were less humane. That was a time
in which James Dobson of Focus on the Family, with his manuals on corporal
punishment of children, was at an all-time height of popularity, as the progressive,
humanistic approach to childrearing of Benjamin Spock (who worked with Fromm
on peace activism through anti-nuclear weapons organization SANE) was losing
popularity. In that era, behaviorism supplanted psychoanalysis. Although the tide of
professional opinion has turned against the more aggressive versions of behaviorism
of the past (electric skin shock and other aversive therapies, for example), it
remains the case that behaviorist and pharmaceutical methods are privileged over
talk therapy.20
37
CHAPTER 1
Fromms critique of Freuds loyal followers builds upon the critique of Freuds
authoritarian personality. From Freuds own modus operandi arose an organization
that nearly killed the radical, non-conformist, revolutionary faith of early
psychoanalysis, replacing it with a conservative bureaucracy and staid ideology.
(There are parallels here, of course, to the Soviet Union. As with Fromms critique
of early Christianity in the The Dogma of Christ, Fromms critique of orthodox
psychoanalysis serves also as an implicit critique of orthodox Marxism.)
Aside from his critiques of Freuds personality, Fromms remaining critiques
of orthodox psychoanalysis may be summarized in two points: (1) orthodox
psychoanalysis was fanatical, and (2) orthodox psychoanalysis as a professional
discipline was bureaucratic, dehumanizing, and gate-keeping.
Firstly, Fromm asks of psychoanalysis as he asked also of the Frankfurt School
and Marxism: How could psychoanalysisbe transformed into this kind of
fanatical movement? (DC 143; italics Fromms). He traces the problem to Freud
himself, whose youthful desire to participate in political struggle was channeled
into the formation of an apolitical psychoanalytic International. According to
Fromm, the fanatic is a narcissist who deals with her removal from the world and
withdrawal into herself by means of a cause that becomes her source of strength
and connection (156). Fromm characterizes the fanatic as burning ice, motivated
by cold passion (156). When it was not fanatical, psychoanalysis was conformist,
Fromm assertednot only internally, but in its relationship to society, orthodox
psychoanalysis was a bulwark of the status quo.
Secondly, Fromm issues a prophetic call for psychoanalysis to abandon its
sterile bureaucracy and recommit itself to the quest for truth (DC 148). According
to Fromms theory of religion, all human societies are religious in some way, but
the religion they actually believe and practice is not necessarily the one they profess
to follow. When a religion deteriorates from a living system into a dead ideology,
bureaucracies arise. These bureaucracies are then administered by priestsnot
prophetswho keep tradition alive through rituals, after the beliefs that animated
the religion have become stagnant (have become idols) (MPP 124). Fromm states
that members of each psychoanalytic school had to be properly ordained,
implying that their members were priests, not prophets (AB 65).
Fromm was unique in unabashedly criticizing Ernest Joness three-volume,
hagiographic court biography of Freud. He responded to Jones repeatedly,
including in Sigmund Freuds Mission, in his essay PsychoanalysisScience or
Party Line?, and in The Crisis of Psychoanalysis (SFM passim; DC 135-138; CP
9-12). For example, he objected to Joness branding of Sndor Ferenczi and Otto
Rank as mentally unstable at the time of their break from orthodox Freudianism
(CP 19; DC 136). Fromm probably knew that Joness book also involved a degree
of cover-up of the situation of psychoanalysis in Nazi Germany. Jones claimed
in the biography, This year [1934] saw the flight of the remaining analysts from
Germany and the liquidation of psychoanalysis in Germany, a claim that Jones
probably knew was false or at least grossly oversimplified, since Jones had written
38
ERICH FROMMS LEGACY AND CONTRIBUTION TO THE EARLY FRANKFURT SCHOOL
Fromm was an activist. As we have seen, Fromm was certainly an organizer even
before arriving at the Institute for Social Research (and his radicalization long
preceded his contact with the Institute). We turn now to Fromms activism after his
exodus from the Institute, at which point, freed from Horkheimers restrictions on
political involvement, Fromm was more able to engage in activism and soon joined
the Socialist Party of America (SP-SDF). Among Fromms first major political
endeavors in the United States was his involvement in the founding of the leading
anti-nuclear weapons organization in the U.S., SANE (named after his book The
Sane Society), for which he went on an important national speaking tour. Later
he assisted with anti-war protest candidate Eugene McCarthys Presidential bid
(even writing suggested speeches for McCarthy), continued his extensive activist
speaking tour, collaborated with Trappist monk and peace advocate Thomas Merton
in the attempt to coordinate an international conference on peace to be sponsored
by the pope (which never came to fruition but had many endorsers), fought to get
his leftist cousin Heinz Brandt freed from political imprisonment in East Germany,
andprobably his crowning organizing achievementorganized and published an
international symposium of socialist humanists seeking a socialist alternative
to capitalism and Soviet Communism (Socialist Humanism: An International
Symposium). He corresponded and collaborated with a range of leading activists
39
CHAPTER 1
40
ERICH FROMMS LEGACY AND CONTRIBUTION TO THE EARLY FRANKFURT SCHOOL
guru of the New Left obscures Fromms contribution and misconstrues Marcuses.
(Consider as an example of this obscuring of Fromms contribution to the left, the
recent book Scriptures for a Generation: What We Were Reading in the 60s; the
book contains approximately fifty entries on authors who influenced the 1960s, and
there is no entry on Fromm, though there is one on Marcuse [Beidler 140, 179].)
To turn to the problem of the myth of Marcuse as guru of the new left, one
must consider the way in which Marcuses role has tended to displace Fromms
in histories of the New Left. For example, Jamison and Eyermans Seeds of the
Sixties explores Fromm along with Marcuse, C. Wright Mills, Hannah Arendt, and
a few others. Although Jamison and Eyerman consider Fromms contribution, they
malign Fromm peculiarly (though characteristically, for the genre), while presenting
Marcuse as a radical upstart:
When his old [i.e., former] colleague Erich Fromm grew too successful in his
popular psychoanalysis and turned radicalism largely into a personal quest for
mental health, Marcuse took him on and questioned whether Marxism was
really a humanism at all, as Fromm claimed. Unlike Fromm, Marcuse never
ceased beingor at least trying to bea revolutionary. Marcuse sought to keep
the radicalism of Marx from being watered down, from being transformed into
a toothless liberalism; but he also resisted the attempts to freeze Marxism in its
own past, to reify the writings of Marx as dogmatic truths that were in no need
of amendment. (Jamison and Eyerman 120)
Jamison and Eyerman never present an argument for what they take to be obvious
truths: Fromms alleged conformism, liberalism, dogmatism, and lack of
radicalism. These criticisms echo the typical presentation of Fromm according to
the origin myth of the Frankfurt School addressed earlier.
It is an oft-repeated adage, first proclaimed by Time magazine and later reinforced
by Douglas Kellner, that Herbert Marcuse was the guru of the New Left, a claim
that seems to displace Fromms contribution and a claim that Marcuse himself
desperately tried to put to rest (cf., for example, video footage of Marcuse contesting
this claim in Herberts Hippopotamus, and Wheatland 269) (Kellner, Introduction
xi, xxxvi; N. Braune 5). Although the New Left had no single guru, Fromm was
significantly more influential on the New Left in its early stages. The myth that
Marcuse was the guru of the New Left is only now being debunked (cf., Bronner
2002, Wheatland 2009). Although Marcuses writings show that he was attentive to
changes on the New Left, it seems that, as Wheatland puts it, the New Left meant
more to him than he meant to the New Left (Wheatland 334). Marcuse was more of
a student of the New Left than its mentor (334).
[Marcuse] neither set the waves of student protest in motion nor shaped U.S.
student opinion on a large scale once the New Left was on the rise. Instead,
he recognized the significance of the Movement and the events that he was
witnessing, and he sought to counsel the New Left as it grew and tried to
articulate a new agenda for the late 1960s. (334)
41
CHAPTER 1
It was only in the late 1960s that Marcuse began to gain the attention of parts of
the left in Europe and in the U.S., especially the Weather Underground (N. Braune
5). There were some left activists in the U.S. who were seriously influenced by
MarcuseAngela Davis, Ron Aronson, Mike Davis, Stanley Aronowitzbut
Marcuse was almost never discussed in the leading publications of the New Left:
New Left Notes, Studies on the Left, and Ramparts (317).
It has been suggested that Marcuse did not initially catch on with the New Left
because they found his writing inaccessible, presupposing philosophical knowledge
and drawing upon such thinkers as Plato, Rousseau, Schiller, Kant, Hegel, Marx, and
Freud (Wheatland 298). Anti-intellectualism on the left and Marcuses opposition to
this anti-intellectualism further increased the distance between Marcuse and the New
Left (298). There is a great deal of truth in both these claims. The sheer difficulty of
reading Marcuse, enhanced by his struggles with writing in English, and the anti-
intellectual mood of the left would not have worked to his advantage. Although
Fromm also drew heavily upon the history of philosophy, his style of writing was
more publicly readable.
However, perhaps another reason that Marcuse was inaccessible was that he was
not trying to be accessible. Fromm had consciously decided to write for a wide
audience and had written books for the general public since 1941. Marcuse, on the
other hand, may have believed it impossible to reach the masses with his message
in the 1960s (as is suggested by the pessimism of One-Dimensional Man) and
consequently did not attempt it. One can observe a significant change in Marcuses
style in the late 1960s.22 Along with others in the Frankfurt School of the 1950s, it is
possible that Marcuse had accepted the Flaschenpost method, sending out messages
in a bottle for a future time at which the culture of the masses would be capable of
seeing their value (Wheatland 88, 203, 267-8).
David Wellman, though not a key player on the left at the time, is worth
quoting at length, since his comments typify the opinion of the 1960s left
towards Marcuse:
Im not surprised that you havent found much mention of Marcuse in the
archival materials on the American New Left. I dont remember him being
an important figure to us during the Radical Education Project. Our idea of
education during that period didnt pertain to theoretical, philosophical issues
but much more basic understandings of American society and how to change
it. That said, I remember people reading One-Dimensional Man later onI
cant estimate how many other people were reading it. I guess there was
some interest since I recall discussing it with people in informal settings. I
personally was turned-off by the book. It struck me as incredibly pessimistic
and unhelpful to people trying to make change. I read him to be saying that
change was impossible given the one-dimensionality of modern society and
since that was what I was trying to do, the book was less than useful to me. It
was an argument for why my activism was doomed to failure. I did, however,
42
ERICH FROMMS LEGACY AND CONTRIBUTION TO THE EARLY FRANKFURT SCHOOL
43
CHAPTER 1
the early 1970s, where he remained a prominent public figure to his death, and his
influence in Europe grew as it waned in the U.S.
Fromms impact over the course of his career was global. Paulo Freire, the founder
of contemporary critical pedagogy, was considerably influenced by Fromm (Freire
11). (Fromm also points to the importance of Freires work [ROH 116].) Freire and
Fromm met at Fromms home in Cuernavaca, Mexico, through the introduction of
Ivan Illich, who was a friend of Fromm in Mexico (Freire 44, 90). (Fromm also
wrote a nice introduction for Illichs book Celebration of Awareness.) Fromm also
influenced socialist humanists in Eastern Europe (especially the Yugoslav Praxis
Group), with the help of his important book/organizing project, Socialist Humanism:
An International Symposium.
Various reasons have been offered for Fromms decline in popularity in the
New Left towards the end of the 1960s. I hold that Fromm seemed too hopeful
or optimistic in the climate of growing despair, as some on the left began to feel
helpless, in the wake of Cointelpro and protracted struggle, and as some turned to
drugs, violence, and spiritual escapism. As will become apparent in Chapter 3, such
escapist responses were the very kinds of things Fromm was warning against and
to which he was presenting messianic hope as an alternative. Stephen Eric Bronner
explains Fromms fall from popularity thus: With the fragmentation of the New
Left and the rise of postmodernism, [Fromms] work appears almost quaint. The
old concern with inner development and the emancipatory content of new social
relations is no longer what it once was (Bronner 171). Fromm was unlikely to be
the hero of desperate or retreating activists, which was the majority by that point. I
argue in the Epilogue that current political developments make Fromm more relevant
today than ever, in a present resurgence of resistance.
As has been shown, Fromm had considerable influence upon the early
development of the New Left. His radical critique of society, combined with his
popularity, won him both enemies and friends. Now that we have surveyed Fromms
work up through the end of his life with regard to his early theoretical synthesis
of Marx and Freud, his break from the Frankfurt School, and his interactions with
and critiques of psychoanalysis and the left, it is necessary to discuss the context of
the debates concerning messianism in which Fromm was engaged, the tumultuous
situation of German intellectual life from shortly before the First World War to the
late 1920s.
NOTES
1
Although I sometimes follow the convention of using the terms Frankfurt School and Institute
interchangeablyFromm was certainly a member of bothit should be remembered that the
Frankfurt School is sometimes interpreted as a broader category that can include scholars like Karl
Korsch and Ernst Bloch, who were not members of the Institute for Social Research.
2
Fromms absence in the book is particularly unfortunate considering that Tars thesisi.e., the
Institute became pessimistic (partly through the influence of Schopenhauer on Horkheimer) and
abandoned Marxismjibes with Fromms own concerns about the Institute.
44
ERICH FROMMS LEGACY AND CONTRIBUTION TO THE EARLY FRANKFURT SCHOOL
3
Fromm distinguishes between the bureaucratic priest and the revolutionary prophet. I return to
these concepts later in this chapter.
4
Jay is a bit vague about who should be given the most credit for the study of the German working
class, noting that the study was mentioned in Horkheimers inaugural lecture as director of the
Institute but, unlike some other scholars accounts, Jays does not give Horkheimer all of the credit
for the idea or the research (Dialectical Imagination 93).
5
Although Leo Lwenthal is known to have engaged seriously with Jewish thought, his parents were
not religious. He accompanied Fromm at the Lehrhaus and at Fromm and Reichmanns experimental
religious commune/psychoanalytic treatment center, the Therapeuticum, but like most members of
those circles, he was rebelling against his parents secularism and rediscovering Judaism for himself.
Max Horkheimer was raised in a Conservative Jewish family but had less exposure to Jewish
tradition and broke from the practice of Judaism more quickly than did Fromm.
6
Fromm cites Alfred Weber in The Sane Society, where he mentions his scheme of historical
development which has some similarities to the one in my [Fromms] text. He assumes a chthonic
period from 4000 to 1200 B.C. which was characterized by the fixation to earth in agricultural
peoples (SS 51). Alfred Weber seems to have been an influence on Fromms concern about
reactionary attachments to land and soil.
7
Of course, I am referring here to Conservative Judaism (as opposed to the Orthodox, Reform, or
other branches) and not to Nobels politics, which were left.
8
Although Franz Rosenzweig is often credited as founder, Fromms involvement in the Lehrhaus
predates Rosenzweigs, who later became the director (cf., Funk, Jewish Roots 2).
9
Fromm and Reichmann are also said to have met through Friedas childhood friend Golde Ginsburg,
whom Fromm was dating and who later married Fromms friend Leo Lwenthal (Hornstein, Funk).
10
Scholems book is peppered with similarly biting remarks about others in these circles who rejected
Scholems interpretation of Judaism and messianism, so one need not assume that Fromms
demeanor towards Scholem was offensive or condescending.
11
Fromms later work on the Sabbath also highlighted the Sabbaths radical implications as a foretaste
of the messianic time, in which labor would be ended, harmony restored, time and death conquered,
and enjoyment instituted (FL 2479; TB 42).
12
Zilbersheids article The Idea of Abolition of Labor in Socialist Utopian Thought and his book
Jenseits der Arbeit. Der vergessene sozialistiche Traum von Marx, Fromm und Marcuse suggested
that Fromm and Marcuse both followed upon Marxs conception of an Aufhebung of labor, with
Fromm interpreting this Aufhebung with an emphasis upon the transformation of labor (into a free,
creative process) and Marcuse stressing the aspect of an Aufhebung as abolition of labor (freedom
from the misery of toil).
13
This use of allegory is not especially surprising. Fromm often employs historical narratives (such
as that of Robespierre or of seventeenth century false messiah Sabbatai Zevi) and myths (Antigone,
Adam and Eve, etc.) to present subtle critiques of contemporary problems. Even when he is
explicitly critiquing a contemporary social movement (for example, psychoanalysis), it often seems
that his criticism is directed elsewhere (for example, towards the current direction of the socialist
movement). For example, Fromms book Sigmund Freuds Mission, which mocks Freuds attempt
to form a psychoanalytic International, should probably be read as a not-too-subtle critique of
orthodox Marxism, not just orthodox Freudianism. Fromms use of historical narratives and myths
is in some sense of a typical Freudian trope; psychoanalysis frequently draws from mythology,
literature, and history to discuss basic human neuroses. However, Fromms application of this
method to a critique of contemporary social problems is unique.
14
For an example of an interesting contemporary application of Fromms theories of the authoritarian
personality and escapes from freedom, see Max Blumenthals use of Fromm for building a
compelling critique of the U.S. religious right in Republican Gomorrah: Inside the Movement that
Shattered the Party (New York: Nation Books, 2009).
15
Incidentally, Rolf Wiggershaus also misunderstands the premise for the study of the German working
class. He condemns it as pessimistic about revolution, and he objects that one cannot determine
whether an individual will support a socialist revolution through exploring their authoritarian
45
CHAPTER 1
sentiments (for example, as manifested in their attitude towards the role of women in society, or
their support for or opposition to corporal punishment of children). What Wiggershaus misses is
that the study never was trying to determine whether the workers in Germany professed support for
a socialist revolutionin fact, the study was begun with the knowledge that many of the German
workers were self-professed socialists. Rather, Fromms study was evaluating the contradictions in
the thinking of the German workers and examining what results could be expected from political
engagement on the part of the workers. Even if an upheaval of some sort could be expected, the
question was not whether it would choose to label itself a socialist revolution but whether its
consequences would be more like Stalinism or more like the society envisioned by Marx in which
human freedom would be its own end. Wiggershaus asks rhetorically whether most workers in
Russia before the revolution, if surveyed, would have supported equality for women and humane
treatment of children; the answer of course is no, but that is not the point; authoritarian attitudes
are relevant to the long-term success of a revolution, and Fromm did not view the Soviet Union as
fully socialist. Wiggershaus conveniently ignores that the so-called gloomy, pessimistic study
was proven correct in its prediction that the German working class was not ready to lead a socialist
revolution or an effective anti-fascist resistance.
16
Marcuse, interestingly, loved this essay by Fromm, lauding it later in Eros and Civilization even
in the midst of pillorying much of Fromms other work (Eros and Civilization 243). Although it is
ironic that Marcuse praises the most manifestly anti-Freudian of Fromms early essaysMarcuse at
the time was condemning Fromms Freudian revisionismit is not surprising that Marcuse would
like the essay. The essay challenged the Freudian illusion of the analysts political and philosophical
neutrality and rejected the bourgeois value of tolerance (the subject of a later, important essay
by Marcuse), and it condemned contemporary society as overly sexually repressive.
17
In this section on Fromms interaction with the IPA, I am chiefly indebted to Paul Roazens essay,
The Exclusion of Erich Fromm from the IPA.
18
Incidentally, Fromm sounds irked in every quotation from correspondence with Martin Jay that is
quoted in Jays Dialectical Imagination. This is probably because, judging from the criticisms that
Fromm is quoted responding to, Jays letters to Fromm accused him of being an optimistic Pollyanna
and of abandoning psychoanalysis.
19
For example, Thomson suggests that Fromms discussion of the similarities between world religions
is encumbered by his failure to discuss the Bhai Faith--a point which she does not explain further.
More problematic is her odd dismissal of Fromms socialist humanism on the grounds that his
suggestions gnaw away at the very essence of our Western and arguably global system of capitalism
(as though Fromm did not know this!) (Thomson 139).
20
Aversive therapy is not wholly a thing of the past. Some more aggressive programs of behavioral
reward and punishment still exist, including (as this goes to press), the controversial Judge Rotenberg
Educational Center in Canton, Massachusetts, which employs painful electric skin shocks to patients
as an aversive. The Centers practice has been condemned by the United Nations as torture.
21
In The Sane Society, Fromm still labels himself as a member of humanistic psychoanalysis, though
he becomes hesitant about this label later and does not want to be classified as a member of the
humanistic school.
22
For example, consider the difference in tone between Eros and Civilization (1955) and Essay on
Liberation (1969). Here is Eros and Civilization: The Orphic and the Narcissistic Eros engulfs
the reality in libidinal relations which transform the individual and his environment; but this
transformation is the isolated deed of individuals, and, as such, it generates death (209). And here
is Essay on Liberation: The majority of the black population does not occupy a decisive position
in the process of production, and the white organizations of labor have not exactly gone out of their
way to change this situation (Essay on Liberation 58).
23
This claim applies only to Horkheimers generation; in the next major generation of Critical Theory,
the young Jrgen Habermas did have some influence on the New Left in Germany.
46
CHAPTER 2
A sea change began in German thought during the First World War. The new
rebels (Peter Gays outsiders as insiders) of fin de sicle Germany rejected the
old Enlightenment ideals of culture and cultivation (Kultur), popular education
towards morality and autonomy (Bildung),1 immanent historical progress, reason,
and humanism. Such ideals were now scorned as overly safe, under-confrontational,
liberal. The new view reveled in the apocalyptic, the Gnostic, and the occult,
and it glorified the aesthetic over the rational and the ethical. It wanted to confront
social structures head on and in toto, and it demanded immediate change. The new,
more apocalyptic messianism was not a marginal trend but was nearly ubiquitous in
German culture, including in Jewish intellectual circles. Nearly everyone in German
intellectual circles of the time advocated some sort of messianism and defined his or
her projects in relation to it.
This chapter cannot provide an overview of the philosophical perspective of each
of the thinkers it touches upon; rather, it focuses on certain elements, especially their
attitude towards the future and their interpretations of messianism. The groundwork
laid in this chapter makes it possible to contextualize Fromms work in later
chapters. Of course, the period was massively complex. For example, some of the
new apocalyptists rejected the concept of totality and were critical of universals,
preferring a return to the individual. Others, however, viewed society as an organic
whole and were caught up in what Peter Gay has called the hunger for wholeness
(Gay 70).2 Further, one finds that a common vocabulary does not always indicate a
common political outlook. As Anson Rabinbach writes,
In Germany protagonists of the earthly kingdom and prophets of the
divine, enthusiasts of the war and its more pacifistic opponents, left-wing
revolutionaries and fascists avant la lettre, all shared a similar vocabulary of
decline and destitution, and many competed to portray themselves as avatars
of the new man. (Shadow of Catastrophe 6)
The new messianism was spread across the political spectrum, although the new,
apocalyptic version of messianism appears to have been more heavily concentrated
among the revolutionary left and the proto-fascist right than among moderates.
Given complexities such as these, and given the moral gravity of the questions
surrounding the time due to the atrocities that followed, there is far from being a
scholarly consensus upon any interpretation of Weimar culture. This chapter does
not attempt to explicate all or even most of these complexities but to clarify some
themes that are necessary for making sense of Fromms messianism.
47
CHAPTER 2
After the bloody defeat of the 19181919 socialist and anarchist revolts in
Berlin and Mnich, the Social Democratic compromise pleased almost no one.
The way forward was unclear, however, and revolt did not seem viable. The
avant garde of Weimar Germany sought liberation neither through revolution
by the proletariat (as had Karl Marx and Rosa Luxemburg) nor reformist social
programs; rather they envisioned a return to a primordial state and a nihilistic
break with the given. In a Kulturpessimismus crisscrossing political divides,
they sought to escape from declining European culture and return to cult.
The attitude of the time was encapsulated in the motto origin is the goal,
by Vienna journalist Karl Kraus, quoted by Walter Benjamin in his Theses
on the Philosophy of History (Rabinbach, Between Enlightenment 84;
Benjamin, Illuminations 253). Only a rejection and refusal of the fallen world
and a return to pre-civilizational innocencein allegorical terms, to the Garden
of Edencould liberate humanity from the toilsome cycle of history and the
burden of Zivilisation. Apocalyptic or catastrophic messianism proclaimed a
new age that would arise from that destructive (nihilistic) break from history.
That break could occur through the intervention of seemingly transcendent
powers, such as charismatic leaders, artistic novelties, magic, or calculated
violation of social norms, either in a controlled and ritualized or abrupt and
total fashion.
Most thinkers straddled the divide between the earlier and the later messianism,
caught between progress and apocalypse, reason and Gnosis, humanistic culture and
chthonic myth, the anticipatory vision and the backwards glance, and a myriad of
other dichotomies characterizing the age. Thus, the messianic thinkers of the time
range along a spectrum, from the more prophetic to the more apocalyptic.
After outlining some characteristics that make it possible to locate thinkers along
this spectrum, this chapter discusses the shift from the prophetic to the apocalyptic,
beginning with some of the more prophetic thinkers, like Hermann Cohen and
Rosa Luxemburg. Martin Buber, addressed after Cohen, is an intermediary figure,
while Gershom Scholem and Franz Rosenzweig appear to fall into the apocalyptic
camp, each in a different way. I then show how two young friends in Heidelberg
Ernst Bloch and Georg Lukcsmade a different shift, from the apocalyptic back
to the prophetic. Finally, the chapter explores one of the triumphs of the apocalyptic
ZeitgeistStefan Georges circleand its influence upon some members of the
Frankfurt School avant la lettre.
In order to demonstrate the shift from prophetic to apocalyptic/catastrophic
messianism, some related shifts in the intellectual climate need to be addressed. The
issues include (1) the shift in emphasis from Geist to Seele, (2) discourse of life
and the popularity of Lebensphilosophie, (3) neo-Gnosticism, and (4) nihilism and
antinomianism. After an overview of these themes, I offer an overview of political
options available to left-wing Jews in fin de sicle Germany, including Marxism,
anarchism, and Zionism.
48
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
Spirit [Geist] is the watchword for all the Joachimites,3 from the Spirituals
Mntzer and Sebastian Frank, to Bhme, Lessing, and German Idealism.
Armed with the spirit, they join in battle with the sacrament of the Catholic
Church, the word of the Lutheran Church, the dogma of the Orthodox Church,
the dogmatism of philosophy and the systems of bourgeois society (Taubes
[2009] 139).
The subsequent rejection of Geist in the name of Seele was an exultation of the
emotional over the rational. Geist, after all, is not just spirit but also mind or
intellect. To a lesser extent, the shift rejected the radical power of the masses in
favor of a focus on the individual.
The proto-fascists of the Cosmic Circle, examined in the final section of this
chapter, certainly embraced Seele and shunned Geist. The Cosmics produced titles
such as Stefan Georges Das Jahr der Seele (1897) (The Year of the Soul) andone
of the central texts of the debate over Seele and GeistLudwig Klagess three-
volume Der Geist als Widersacher der Seele (1929) (Spirit/Mind as the Adversary
of the Soul) (Gay 80). Carl Jung, likewise, analyzed the soul, which in his thought
had racial connotations, as the concept did for many of the Nazis.4 However, the
exultation of Seele over Geist was a complex phenomenon, not confined to those
who actively identified with the political right. There were also those on the avant-
garde left, including the early Georg Lukcs, who sided with Seele. Before his turn
to Marxism, Lukcss early, Romantic book on aesthetics was significantly entitled
Soul and Form (Seele und Formen).5 The book finds the expression of soul in
a yearning that is conveyed within the finitude of artistic form. (Lukcs did not
remain a partisan of Seelelater in this chapter, I trace Lukcss return to the prewar
radicalism of Geist.)
Sometimes the war against Geist was promulgated not in the name of soul but in
the name of life or inwardness, as one also finds in Lukcss Soul and Form.
49
CHAPTER 2
50
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
fascist necrophilia can only be understood as a response to an era that exalted death
for the forces of reaction, an era in which Wagner had characteristically written, I
havefound a sedative which has finally helped me to sleep at night; it is the sincere
and heartfelt longing for death: total unconsciousness, complete annihilation, the
end of all dreamsthe only ultimate redemption (Janaway 121). Although the
enthusiasm for death was also at its core reactionary, Weimars enthusiasms
for life and for death were often oddly not at odds; Lebensphilosophie was not
concerned chiefly with the preservation of life, and if there is anything life is (at
least in the biological sense), it is finite, ending in death. Fromms messianism,
by contrast, resists this finitude by its paradoxical faith in a future fulfillment of
human hopes.
The rise of a neo-Gnosticism, like the rise of Seele, was a sign of the increasingly
apocalyptic mood. Anson Rabinbach draws the connection between the new
apocalyptic messianism and an attraction to secret knowledge: Whereas the
prophetic tradition involved public testimony, the messianic9 tradition involves
an esoteric or even secret form of knowledge (Shadow of Catastrophe 32). Neo-
Gnosticism and apocalyptic messianism went hand in hand. The apocalyptic/Gnostic
mood was ever watchful for omens of the approaching cataclysm. It was perhaps in
this spirit that Walter Benjamin uttered the famous line attributed to him by Gershom
Scholem, A philosophy that does not include the possibility of soothsaying from
coffee grounds and cannot explicate it cannot be a true philosophy (Buck-Morss,
Dialectics of Seeing 13).
A prominent source in discussions of the neo-Gnosticism of Germany is Hans
Jonass important book The Gnostic Religion: The Message of the Alien God and the
Beginnings of Christianity. Though published in 1957 and focused upon the history
of Gnosticism as an early Christian heresy, the book concludes with a discussion of
Heidegger and other contemporary Gnostics; the book may be used to describe an
aspect of the tenor of fin de sicle Germany (Jonas 335-8). This chapter takes some
cues from Jonas. However, one can also find references to Gnosticism directly in
the texts of the time, including frequent praise of Marcion of Sinope, partly under
the influence of Ernst Blochs Spirit of Utopia (1918) and of Adolf von Harnacks
important text in 1921 defending Marcionism as useful for Protestantism due to
Marcionisms opposition between grace and the world (Taubes, Cult to Culture 140).
One also notices in the literature of the time the presence of the Gnostic tropes of
secret knowledge, the message of a God that is wholly other, the myth of a fall
and return, and the rebellious retelling of classic myths in which the roles of villain
and hero are reversed. Benjamin Laziers recent book God Interrupted: Heresy
and the European Imagination between the World Wars (2008) is also a useful
resource; Lazier masterfully distinguishes pantheist and gnostic mysticism in
Weimar Germany.10
51
CHAPTER 2
Recall from the previous chapter that Erich Fromm challenged the rising Gnostic
movement in his Dogma of Christ and in his critique of Bachofens right-wing
interpreters. The well-to-do Hellenistic middle class sought to force the creation of
the society they wanted before the consciousness of the masses could accept it (DC
75). Although generally Gnosticism refers to an early Christian heresy combated
by neo-Platonists like Plotinus and Church fathers like Irenaeus and Tertullian,
in 1920s Germany it described a cultural phenomenon ranging in influence from
Theosophist educator Rudolf Steiner (Steiners Lucifer-Gnosis) and Stefan George
to Walter Benjamin and (to a more limited extent) Ernst Bloch (Lazier 28, 29, 32).
According to Lazier, this cultural phenomenon spanned the intellectual environment
from Gershom Scholem, Walter Benjamin, Franz Rosenzweig, Leo Strauss, and
Ernst Bloch to crisis theologians including Karl Barth and Adolf von Harnack in
his Marcion: Das Evangelium vom fremden Gott (1921) (29, 32). All were attracted
to the gospel of the alien God, the message of a spiritual reality that was wholly
other, antithetical to worldly creation (31).
Although it negates the world in its entirety and therefore might at first blush seem
very radical, Gnosticisms negativity should not be equated with that of Marxist
or Hegelian dialectics, as has sometimes been done.11 Gnosticisms negativity
conceives the world as evil, the product of an inferior god (literally or metaphorically).
Gnosticism wages war not against the present state of the world but against history
and the world as such. There is a revolutionary, potentially dialectical alternative to
Gnosticism, sometimes associated with neo-Platonism or pantheism, though it may be
independent of both. There is no universally acknowledged name for this alternative,
but one finds in many thinkers the view that there are good forces immanently at
work, moving the world towards redemption, and that humanity may participate in
this work of redemption. This revolutionary alternative refuses to deify or reify any
part of the whole (perhaps, like Fromm, condemning such a practice as idolatry).
Instead, it values the whole as a self-conscious, unfolding process. (Fromm would
likely have identified this view with some of his predecessors: Spinoza, Hegel, Marx.)
Gnosticism, as a Christian heresy, was generally hostile to Judaism. Second
century Gnostic Marcion of Sinopes plainly anti-Semitic views make him an odd
hero for 1920s Jewish leftists. Lazier writes,
Marcion had undertaken to emancipate early Christian teaching from its Jewish
corruptions. If Christianity evolved out of Judaism, it nonetheless ought to
be understood as its strictest opposition. The God of the Old Testament he
described as an evil demiurge and all creation his malicious work. The God of
the new dispensation, incarnated by Christ and best described by Paul, was in
turn the God of salvation, love, and mercy. (Lazier 29)
There was thus an irony and indeed rebelliousness in Jews like Gershom Scholem
and Walter Benjamin flirting with Gnosticism. Scholem is often referred to as a
Gnostic, and conservative Jewish intellectual Harold Bloom actually embraced the
title of Gnostic (Spirer 4).
52
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
Scholems friend, the rabbi Jacob Taubes, agreed that Gnosticism had an anti-
Semitic past, but nevertheless he found Gnosticism salvageable for his apocalyptic
messianism:
It is certain that the protest of late ancient Gnosticism is deeply connected with
the rebellion against antimythic Jewish monotheism. But this counterattack
comes not only from outside, from the pagan surroundings but also is carried
out from within, from the environment of early Judaism. (Cult to Culture 72)
What attracted twentieth century Jewish radicals to Gnosticism was in large part
its doctrine of an absolute divide between God and creation, such that creation was
totally fallen and God wholly other, like the dramatically other messianic age that
they longed to see dawn. Although a vision of a totally fallen world may not be
universal in Judaism, it certainly appealed to many Jewish radicals who wanted to
see a dramatic transformation of society.
Although the new Gnosticism had radical dimensions, I will show that it was not
the property only of the left, and in fact, some of its political implications are quite
reactionary. Finally, in addition to this neo-Gnosticism of Weimar Germany and the
shift away from the social radicalism of Geist to the individualized inwardness and
spiritual resoluteness of Seele and Leben, a final theme of the times, that of nihilism
and antinomianism, remains to be examined before we can unfold the narrative to
which Fromms writings on messianism were a response.
Fourthly and finally, we turn to the theme of nihilism, and what can be categorized
as a species of it, antinomianism. At the time there was a renewed fascination with
the Jewish Sabbatean heresy and its doctrine of redemption through sin, discussed
below in section 2.2 (under The Anarchic Break-in of Transcendence). The term
nihilism can be used in many different ways, though it originates in a description
of a movement of Russian anarchist revolutionaries in the 1860s. Here I use the term
to point to the fulfilled yearning for annihilation as a political project. It is this sense
of nihilism that concerned Fromm.
One might say that there are basically two types of antinomianism. Isaac
Deutscher, Leon Trotskys biographer, offers two poignant stories that I suggest can
be taken as examples of these two antinomianisms. The first story involves a knave
who sought to corrupt Deutscher in his youth, encouraging him to sneak away from
his family on Yom Kippur to violate the fast by eating in secret in a graveyard.
Deutscher felt pressured to participate and later that day felt ashamed and burdened
by the secret of his participation in this ritual. The second was a tale that influenced
him in his youth, a tale of an honored rabbis scholarly and heretical mentor, who
respected the rabbis obedience to the Law but himself found it too constraining and
disobeyed it. I suggest that the former, the knave, symbolizes an antinomianism that
forces the Messiah through seductive, magical means. This antinomianism is
53
CHAPTER 2
2.1 THE GERMAN JEWISH LEFT AND THE MILIEU OF WEIMAR GERMANY
Now that some underlying controversies have been outlined, we can offer a
preliminary overview of the left-wing political options available to German Jews
in the 1910s and 1920s. Before and during the First World War, many European
Jews saw an international socialist or anarchist revolution as a viable expression of
Judaism. Many in this group rejected the Zionist movement because they viewed
it as nationalist.12 Others, especially in Fromms parents generation, opposed
Zionism because it seemed too radical and fringe, a rebellious youth movement. Yet
many leftists and internationalists opposed it because they believed that Jews had a
politically radical, religious mission to spread throughout the world and proclaim
the coming of the revolution and the messianic age. For example, Erich Unger
speaks this way: The Jews owe the psychic force they may now possess to their
tradition and to their exceptional non-territorial position, as does Walter Benjamins
friend Rudolf Kayser, who argued for replacing the Zionist movement with a radical
Jewish alliance (Bund) to make the earth a homeland of men (Lwy, Redemption
and Utopia 173; Lowy, Jewish Messianism 113). The focus on settling a particular
land seemed to endanger that mobile, international mission.
54
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
55
CHAPTER 2
56
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
Those who stayed in the socialist movement after its 1919 collapse in Germany,
for various reasons tended to feel obliged to choose between religiously observant
Judaism and an ethically, Jewishly-motivated commitment to the revolution, and
many chose the latter. In a sense, they converted to Marxism. In his wonderful little
book The Non-Jewish Jew, Isaac Deutscher explained why he still identified as Jewish
despite joining the Communist movement, opposing Zionism, and abandoning
Jewish religious practice and belief. Deutschers non-Jewish Jew transcends
Judaism from within, turning to atheism and communism as the solution to, one
might say, the antinomies of Judaism. As a demonstration of this attitude, Deutscher
recounts a midrashic tale that influenced him in his childhood, of the saintly Rabbi
Meir and his intellectual mentor, a heretic named Akher (The Stranger). This
story was mentioned briefly above, as an example of a humanistic antinomianism.
As Deutscher tells the tale:
Once on a Sabbath Rabbi Meier was with his teacher, and as usual they became
engaged in a deep argument. The heretic was riding a donkey, and Rabbi Meir,
as he could not ride on a Sabbath, walked by his side and listened so intently
to the words of wisdom falling from his heretical lips that he failed to notice
that he and his teacher had reached the ritual boundary which Jews were
not allowed to cross on a Sabbath. The great heretic turned to his orthodox
pupil and said: Look, we have reached the boundarywe must part now;
you must not accompany me any farthergo back! Rabbi Meir went back to
the Jewish community, while the heretic rode onbeyond the boundaries of
Jewry. (Deutscher 25)
The young Deutscher, raised in an Orthodox Jewish home, was puzzled and
enthralled by the tale. This tale from his youth became a metaphor for Deutschers
solidarity with the heretics of Marxist internationalism. He writes:
My heart, it seems, was with the heretic. Who was he? He appeared to be in
Jewry and yet out of it. He showed a curious respect for his pupils orthodoxy,
when he sent him back to the Jews on the Holy Sabbath; but he himself,
disregarding canon and ritual, rode beyond the boundaries. (26)
Deutscher explains,
The Jewish heretic who transcends Jewry belongs to a Jewish tradition. You
may, if you like, see Akher as a prototype of those great revolutionaries of
modern thought: Spinoza, Heine, Marx, Rosa Luxemburg, Trotsky, and Freud.
You may, if you wish to, place them within a Jewish tradition. They all went
beyond the boundaries of Jewry. They all found Jewry too narrow, too archaic,
and too constricting. They all looked for ideals and fulfillment beyond it,
and they represent the sum and substance of much that is greatest in modern
thought. (26)
57
CHAPTER 2
Deutscher eventually concluded that the truth of Judaism lay in its sublation.
Judaism was not a race, a nation, or a religion but unconditional solidarity with the
persecuted and exterminated (51).
One such non-Jewish Jew, Gustav Landauer, was particularly influential
on radical Jewish thought in early twentieth century Germany. In the following
section, we are not concerned primarily with his connection with Jewish religious
belief and practice, of which he had little, but rather with Landauers expression
of a commitment to mobile, international revolution. Although Landauer saw
something worth preserving in individual cultures and languages, and although
shades of Romanticism color his thought, he was most of all an heir of the German
philosophical and Enlightenment tradition.
In his 1955 Sane Society, Fromm offers this stunning line: When [Rosa Luxemburg]
and Gustav Landauer were murdered by the soldiers of the German counter-
revolution, the humanistic tradition of faith in man was meant to be killed with
them (SS 239). Todayor even in the 1950s, when Fromm wrote this lineone
would likely be taken aback to find Fromm saying that the 1919 assassinations of
Gustav Landauer and Rosa Luxemburg were meant to deal a deathblow to prophetic
messianism. Today one would expect Fromm to speak of Luxemburg and (Karl)
Liebknecht, not Luxemburg and Landauer. The great anarchist revolutionary
Gustav Landauer has been all but forgottenfor that matter, so has the threat of
prophetic messianism (at least as known by that name) to the established order.
But both thinkersLuxemburg and Landauercould have represented many things
to a thinker like Fromm: international revolution and the Jewish contribution to
revolution, the dream of a very different future, the possibility of universal human
emancipation, and martyrdom at the hands of reactionaries and anti-Semites. Beyond
that, Luxemburg and Landauer together represented an era at the turn of the century
when optimism for international revolt was high and pessimism and obsession with
decline were yet to take hold.
Luxemburg stood closer to the Enlightenment than did Landauer. Landauer
thought socialism could be constructed from communal land ownership, national
spirit (Volksgeist), and in some part, it seems, a return to the Middle Ages (Aufruf
3; For Socialism 34). Of course, as an anarchist, Landauers enthusiasm for the
Middle Ages was no nostalgia for monarchyhe was trying to recover a time when
the bonds of community were stronger and based upon less flimsy ground. Despite
his use of some language (like Volksgeist) that sounds worrying in retrospect,
Landauers watchword was spirit, not soulhe was not a proto-fascist partisan of
Seele over Geist. Nevertheless, Landauers use of Volksgeist (national spirit) sets
him apart from Hermann Cohens assertion in Religion of Reason that Volksgeist is
outdated and has been superseded by Hegels Weltgeist (world spirit) (Religion of
Reason 360).
58
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
59
CHAPTER 2
60
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
61
CHAPTER 2
There are prophets with poetic visions who anticipate and create the
future; and there are fanatical speakers appealing to our consciousness
with clarity and insight. It is the latter who bury the past by understanding
and pronouncing the horror of the present. When the common qualities of
the individuals who form societies turn into words and battle cries, when
inwardness and confidence turn into opposition and demagogy, then an
intensity and combativeness is created that might appear youthful and
newyet in reality it only proves that the old is disappearing without hope.
(Revolution 138)
To an extent, Landauers thought was grounded in a worldview preceding the three
matters of dispute outlined at the beginning of this chapter (Geist and Seele, neo-
Gnosticism, and the interconnected themes of nihilism and antinomianism). He was
not impacted by these divisions in the same way as later thinkers, who lived under
the Weimar Republic.
Further, Landauers writings demonstrate a plenitude of psychological and
spiritual insights that are echoed (whether under Landauers direct influence or not)
in Erich Fromms work. For example, in Landauer, self-transformation and class
consciousness are key to revolution. He even mentions the unconscious, buried
knowledge of the workers and their inability to face themselves and think their own
thoughts (Revolution 226).
Like Fromm, Landauer abandoned Jewish religious practice in his twenties,
was influenced by Buddhism and German mysticism (e.g., Meister Eckhart),
and considered himself an atheist in spite of profound interest in religious topics.
Landauer was also drawn to Hasidism under Bubers influence, as was Fromm.
Further, Landauer and Fromm shared a devotion to the value of human life that
excluded all war and terroristic action (for example, see Landauers response to the
incident of the McNamara brothers (Revolution 258-9) and Fromms pamphlet for the
American Friends Service Committee, War Within Man). Fromm did not condemn
violence without qualificationin that sense, he was not strictly a pacifistbut
he was deeply troubled by the impact of violence upon the human psyche, as his
multiple references to Simone Weils profound essay on violence attest (e.g., DC
188; WW 9; October 1955 letter to Thomas Merton).17
Landauers statement in a newspaper interview on the difference between hope
and certainty closely resembles Fromms own understanding of hope and faith:
Certain? No, I definitely cannot be certain! It signifies the decay of our times
that people always want external certainties. In reality, this only increases the
external uncertainty of their situation, and the unstableness of their mind and
their conviction. When it comes to our ultimate means to preventing atrocity,
we can neither rely on God nor on Marx to provide us with any certainty. We
need certainty in ourselves. This is the certainty that has always led the way to
victory; it is called courage. We need to have the will to be victorious, and we
have to try. (Revolution 224)
62
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
Like Fromm, Landauer held that radicalismthat is, in the sense of going to the
rootmust be differentiated from frenzied activism and fanaticism. Even wild
agitation and excessive hate can be very superficial. On the other hand, quietness,
contemplation, and caution can be very radical. I see Tolstoy as an eminently radical
figure, much more so than many who have risked their lives (258). There is a
parallel here to Fromms assertion that the true revolutionary is a person of strong
conviction who still shuns fanaticism (DC 151). Fighting in a revolution is not a
sufficient condition for being a true revolutionary, as Fromm explains in his essay
on the revolutionary character (154). Rather, the true revolutionary loves life and
does not desire power, while the mere rebel is envious of those in authority and
secretly wants their appreciation and acceptance (163, 165, 154). Further, notice that
Landauer, like Fromm, rejects determinism (certainty).
Finally, Landauer warned of the rising Gnosticism and apocalypticism that he
saw lurking in German culture:
The minds of the workersand nowhere is this truer than in Germanyare
twisted and wrecked. They are not sober people, and it is difficult to rely on
their ideas; they put all their hopes in spontaneity, in the unknown, in miracles.
They have no understanding of hope to realize ideas step by step and stone by
stone, and this is why all they do is feverishly dream of a sudden transformation
in which night turns to day and mud to goldTheir entire idea of socialism
is a fairy-taleYet, we must not despair. Rome was not built in a day either.
(Revolution 226)
Despite Landauers warnings, the German fairy tale would turn into the Nazi
nightmarebut only later. The rise of the nightmare was precipitated by the loss
of a worldview yet to be described, i.e., of the messianic optimism of neo-Kantian
philosopher Hermann Cohen and the various responses to it. Landauers ardent
revolutionism has a surprising amount in common with the sober Kantian socialism
of Cohen.
63
CHAPTER 2
most widely known book is entitled), Baeck envisioned the kingdom of God on
Earth as a distinctive trait of Jewish messianism, while ascribing an escapist attitude
to Christianity, which attitude he saw evidenced in St. Augustines civitas dei (Idel
29). Baeck also wrote of Judaisms ability to handle paradox and considered it a
synthesis between transcendence and immanence (Baeck 174). Like others of his
time, he stressed that Judaisms role was to be active in transforming history and
society and, like Cohen, he was not a Zionist. Nevertheless, since Cohen ended up
being of particularly great significance in the messianism fight, with his philosophy
held up as an exemplar of the old messianism that was to be rejected, we will focus
upon Cohen here as opposed to others, like Baeck, whose approach to messianism
was very similar.
According to Hermann Cohen, messianism was the core of Judaism, and the
Messiah was humanity as a whole, making world history togetheran idea that
was first advanced by the Hebrew prophets (Poma 236). The possibility of world
history and the idea of a universal humanity were products of the prophets and of
the idea of monotheism (235). Monotheism was most significant not quantitatively
(in terms of the number of gods) but qualitativelywhat was most significant about
monotheism was the idea of a God who was universally the creator of all people;
Jewish monotheism was the source of the idea of a universal humanity (Religion
of Reason 35, 238-9; Poma 236). The Jewish people, as the first recipients of the
message of monotheism, were chosen to proclaim it and to live as a symbol of it,
through their willingness to suffer religious persecution for the monotheist idea and
for their rejection of idolatry (Poma 236, 245). However, individuals awareness of
belonging to a universal humanity is still only partial; until the messianic age arrives
and this consciousness becomes universalized, humanity does not yet fully exist, and
nor in fact does any individual have full selfhood (237; Cohen, Religion of Reason
235 and passim). The messianic age both fulfills human nature and completes the
process of individuation.
Cohens messianism contrasts sharply with the later, cataclysmic, semi-Romantic
messianism of some German-Jewish intellectuals. Explicitly rejecting talk of the end
times, Cohen contrasted his messianism with the myth of eschatology (Fiorato
135). Cohen writes:
Messianism, however, in opposition to eschatology remains in the climate
of human existence. And if it makes the future of mankind its problem, then
it is the task of the historical future, the future of the infinite history of the
human race, which becomes the task of the holy spirit of man. (Religion of
Reason 307)
Cohens messianism is teleological but deeply anti-eschatological. He foresees a
future in which human beings will be more capable of pursuing virtue, continually
approaching the ideal of perfection; the messianic future concludes the struggle of
humanity in history but not the struggle of the individual to be ethical. Although
historys goal will be reached, time will not end. For Cohen, messianism must be
64
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
radically future-oriented, but the messianic event does not result from a complete
rupture with the present (Poma 237). A bridge must be maintained between the
vision of the ideal and the concrete, material world. If the messianic age is conceived
as existing beyond the end of time, humans are incapable of conceiving how to bring
it about and are unable to fulfill their ethical obligation to do so.
Cohen rejected Zionism, criticizing the idea of a Jewish nation as well as any
proposals for Jewish isolation from culture (Kultur), an isolation that he held was
connected with Zionism. In Cohens view, the idea of a nation as a naturally given
fact was outdated, long superseded by the state. The state was now being superseded
by the (Kantian) idea of a confederation of states, establishing world peace and
fulfilling the messianic promise (Cohen, Religion of Reason 361). Thus, according
to Cohen, the backwardness of Zionism with regard to the concept of the nation
should be overcome through a rejection of the cultural isolation that he identified
with it (362). In the sense that Jews were to remain isolated, it was only in the realm
of religious practice. Jewish religious isolation was to sublate itself and be seminal,
spreading virtue and enhancing the culture of society (69). Notice that Cohens
critique of Zionism is not chiefly directed against the idea of a Jewish state, as per
the discussion of anarchist Jewish anti-Zionism above. Although Cohen holds that
Judaism was an advance over Greek culture precisely because Judaism had no need
of a state either in theory or in practice, he wants to get beyond the state dialectically,
not return to a past historical situation (251).
According to The Religion of Reason, the arrival of the (universal, non-
nationalistic) messianic age depends upon humanity becoming the object of its
own knowledge and love. Cohen seems to agree with Marx that human nature
(species-being) is yet to be fulfilled. Until world history becomes possible through
knowledge and love, humanity does not fully exist (Poma 237). Because he holds
that humanity evolves through knowledge and love, Cohen rejects any equation of
Jewish messianism with a pagan mythology of a pre-historic Golden Age (Religion
of Reason 248). The messianic age is not a Rousseauian state of nature; it is a new
heaven and a new earth (248, 250). Intervening between prehistoric Eden and the
present is the irreversible birth of human knowledge and culture, and the messianic
future does not relinquish these achievements (130-1, 248). Knowledge of Gods
law made possible the first sin, Adam and Eves disobedience, which was the
origin of culture insofar as its consequence is the establishment of labor (130-1).
The first serious sin, for Cohen, is represented not by Adam and Eves disobedience,
which God rewards through encouraging human culture (agriculture), but rather
the fratricide by Cain, that is, the crime against the brotherhood of humanity.
Cains fratricide symbolizes war, which the peace of the messianic age brings to
an end (130-1).18 The messianic age redeems humanitys lost innocence through
the universalization of knowledge. The redemption occurs through a more equitable
distribution of intellectual life, not through a return to the state of nature. Cohen thus
categorically rejects the idea of a past Golden Age, as he rejects idolatry and
magic as pagan (i.e., pre-monotheist) (248, 232).
65
CHAPTER 2
66
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
Martin Buber, Franz Rosenzweig, and others in the Lehrhaus circle who were
influenced by Cohen eventually broke from identification with his thought. One of
the leading reasons was Cohens jarringly inconsistent endorsement of the German
entry into World War I. The war itself, however, and the defeat of the Berlin and
Mnich uprisings in its aftermath, also trampled the optimistic messianism that
had been associated with Cohen and Baeck. Symbolically, after Cohen died in
1918 and Marburg neo-Kantianism disintegrated, Martin Heidegger was the new
rising star at Marburg (Norton 628). Heidegger was a figure of the new gnosis,
as his student Hans Jonas later pointed out, and Fromm identified Heidegger
as one of the figures of despair in the wake of the world wars and Stalinism
(Jonas 334-7; HOM 15). Erich Fromm stands out as one of the few intellectuals
of this context who remained devoted to Cohens Enlightenment-style humanism
and optimism.
The Frankfurt Freies Jdisches Lehrhaus was a bustling hub of Jewish intellectual life
in 1920s Germany. In chapter 1, we saw that Fromm helped to found the Lehrhaus,
which emerged out of the circle around the charismatic Rabbi Nehemiah Nobel.
Hermann Cohen died before the founding of the Lehrhaus but was also central to its
conceptualization. The list of the participants was a whos who of German-Jewish
intellectual life in the 1920s: Martin Buber, Gershom Scholem, Franz Rosenzweig,
Ernst Simon (a close friend of Fromm), Abraham Heschel, Eduard Strauss, Richard
Koch, Rudolf Hallo, Siegfried Kracauer, S. Y. Agnon (Frieda Reichmanns cousin),
Bertha Pappenheim, Leo Strauss, Leo Lwenthal, and Nachum Glatzer (Funk, Life
and Ideas 39; Pollock 25; Hornstein 63; Knapp 14).
In this chapter, I explore three figuresMartin Buber, Gershom Scholem, and
Franz Rosenzweigwho were part of the Lehrhaus circle and developed three
prominent and very different strands of contemporary messianic thought. All three
remained faithful to religious Judaism, and all three emigrated to Palestine. Michael
Lwy groups them with Leo Lwenthal as representatives of religious Jews tending
to anarchism (Lwy, Redemption and Utopia 47). Theirs was a quiet anarchism that
sometimes spoke of mighty cataclysms but was lived out peacefully amid utopian
communities or religious ritual. Nevertheless, I suspect that their messianism is
not as demure in its implications as one might infer from their lives. Scholem, the
strongest in his defense of catastrophic or apocalyptic messianism, also issued some
of the strongest warnings against it, and by the end of his life, he defended it only
with tremendous caution.
Paths in Messianism
67
CHAPTER 2
1900s, Martin Bubers renewal movement represented another option for German
Jews, one not of outward revolutionary struggle but of inward (yet social) spiritual
transformation.
The similarities between Buber and Fromm are frequently noted (Jay, Dialectical
Imagination 89; Hausdorff 50; Bronner 168). Both were committed to ethical
socialism. Like Fromm, Buber held that utopian thinking encourages people to strive
for a better future, as opposed to disempowering them by leading them to seek the
impossible (Buber 58; MFH 3020). Buber was a leader in propagating revolutionary
messianism in Germany in the early 1900s, with the publication of his Three
Speeches on Judaism (1909, 1911) (Wolin, Labyrinths 49). He was probably a major
influence on Fromms distinction between prophetic and apocalyptic messianism
and Fromms concept of alternativism. Buber distinguished between prophetic
and apocalyptic messianism and defended the former against the latter in his Paths
in Utopia (which Fromm cites in his Sane Society), and in his essay Prophetie
und Apocalyptik, Buber argued that apocalypticism was not essential to Judaism
and was, in fact, foreign to Judaism (Iranian in origin) (Buber 8; SS 258; Biale,
Gershom Scholem 526). In Paths in Utopia, Buber prioritizes the prophetic over
the apocalyptic and contrasts rupture with revolutionary continuity (Buber 13).
However, unlike Fromm, Buber did not consider Marx messianic, although Buber
did consider the utopian socialists messianic (10).
Like Fromm, Buber asserts that the prophet poses alternatives, while
apocalypticism rejects alternatives (Taubes, Cult to Culture 13-4). Judaism was
alternativist, emphasizing the possibility of changing the future through either
human repentance or Gods turning towards humanity (both meanings captured by
the Hebrew word teshuva) (xxvi). Paths in Utopia concludes with a reflection on
crisis, in a chapter that includes the offering of an alternative for contemporary
man: Can he or can he not decide in favour of, and educate himself up to, a
common socialistic economy? (Buber 133). And, like Fromm, Buber rejected the
cultural Gnosticism of the time. At a time when many were praising Marcion,
Buber charged that Marcion had made an intellectual contribution to the destruction
of Israel (Taubes, Cult to Culture 141).
It is not surprising that Buber would have influenced Fromm, since in fact Buber
was profoundly influential on an entire generation of young Jewish radicals. Fromm
was personally acquainted with Buber through the Lehrhaus, and he employed three
of Bubers texts in his dissertation on the Jewish law (Die Geschichten des Rabbi
Nachman, Vom Geist des Judentums, Der groe Maggid und seine Nachfolge) (JG
191). However, Buber had stronger affinities with anarchism than did Fromm. Svante
Lundgren writes that [Bubers] socialism was not as Marxist as Fromms and that
Buber was closer to the anarchist tradition through his friend Gustav Landauer
(Lundgren 103). Buber also saw potential in the Kibbutzim and chose Zionism,
seeing it as a utopian socialist movement, which as we have seen, Fromm rejected
as a political option. Buber emigrated to Palestine in 1938 (Lwy, Redemption and
Utopia 57).
68
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
***
Now that some similarities and differences between Buber and Fromm have
been addressed, we can offer a brief overview of Bubers life before delving
more deeply into his messianism. In 1899-1901, Buber studied in Berlin with
two scholars who were influential for Lebensphilosophie: Georg Simmel and
Wilhelm Dilthey (Swedberg and Reich 30-1; Morgan 98). In 1900, he joined the
Berlin Neue Gemeinshaft (New Community) group, where he first met Gustav
Landauer, who became his friend and profoundly influenced Buber (Lwy,
Redemption and Utopia 49; Schaeder 24). Buber later participated in the Bar-
Kochba Club (around 1909-11), the German Jewish organization of Prague
(Lwy, Redemption and Utopia 49; Lebovic, The Jerusalem School 108). In
an important lecture to Neue Gemeinschaft, Buber argued for a new community
based not upon national origin but elective affinities (Wahlverwandtschaft), i.e.
the free choice of its members (Lwy, Redemption and Utopia 49).21 According
to Buber, the new community would be a new social arrangement differing
from the modern city, feudalism, and primitive life (49-50). From 1909-1913,
he was extremely influential in the revival of Judaism (Rabinbach, Between
Enlightenment 88). His renewal movement emphasized personal, inward
religious experience and Lebensphilosophie (88-9). In the early 1920s, he became
involved with the Frankfurt Lehrhaus, along with Fromm, Scholem, Rosenzweig,
and others (Lwy, Redemption and Utopia 151).
After Buber eventually migrated to Israel, he stayed in contact with Fromm
periodically, working with him on a couple of causes. In 1948, he agreed at Fromms
request to sign a statement for The New York Times for the rights of Palestinians22
(Funk, Life and Ideas 146). The letter was also signed by Leo Baeck, Albert
Einstein, and others (146). Buber was also among the international sponsors of anti-
nuclear weapons group SANE, which Fromm helped to found (Katz 71). There was,
however, some tension over Bubers Zionism; in a 1957 letter to Norman Thomas,
Fromm expressed frustration with Bubers refusal to sign a petition supporting a
Palestinian right of return (Lundgren 104, 109).
***
69
CHAPTER 2
a profound rupture with history; the messianic age would be a renewal. For by
renewal, he explained, I do not in any way mean something gradual, a sum total of
minor changes. I mean something sudden and immense (Ungeheures) by no means a
continuation or an improvement, but a return and transformationone should desire
the impossible (52).23 While phrases like sudden and immense and by no means
a continuation may sound far placed from Bubers commitment to revolutionary
continuity mentioned earlier, one notices that crucial extra piece: both a return and a
transformation. For all his hostility to Hegel, Buber was a deeply dialectical thinker.
According to Buber, Zionism was a Lebensphilosophie, and he offered a
romantic recasting of Hasidism, but he himself remained distant from the Hasidic
Eastern European Jews (Rabinbach 1985, 89). (In this, he differed from some young
radicals, such as Leo Lwenthal, who were volunteering their time to help Eastern
European refugees in Germany.) In terms of the distinction drawn at the opening of
this chapter between Seele and Geist, one might say that Buber was on the side of
Seele, not Geist; his concern centered upon the individual in relationship to other
individuals, not the moving force of the collectivity. This is the wider context of
Bubers hesitancy about Hegel. Buber was not, however, one of the neo-Gnostics
of Weimar Germany who stressed the absolute fallenness of the world and the
impotence of all immanent forces.
Like Fromm, Buber believed that human beings could play a role in bringing about
the messianic age. According to Michael Lwy, Buber more than any other modern
religious Jewish thinker, placed the active participation of men in redemptionas
Gods partnersat the heart of his messianism (Lwy, Redemption and Utopia
52). This was not a rejection of divine omnipotence; rather, according to Buber, God
does not will redemption without the participation of man (52). Buber saw the
messianic event as both a result of human effort (moving forward, horizontally)
and divine intervention (vertically, from above), holding that the messianic age
required both human effort and divine intervention. Although Buber also drew a
distinction between between messianic eschatology and utopia (the former requiring
divine intervention, the latter being capable of resulting from human will alone), in
both cases, human action was required (57). Bubers commitment to the participation
of a universal humanity in messianic transformation, along with his simultaneous
Zionist commitments, led to confrontation between Buber and Hermann Cohen
around issues of humanism and national identity.
Initially caught up in enthusiasm for World War I, Buber was persuaded by
his friend Gustav Landauer to repudiate the war (Lwy, Redemption and Utopia
53). Buber commenced a debate with Hermann Cohen, in which he critiqued
Cohens capitulation to German nationalism by chastising him with Cohens own
philosophy: Humanityand to say that, Professor Cohen, is now more than ever
the duty of every man living in Godis greater than the state (53). Bubers and
Cohens positions on the emerging Zionist movement were also a major cause of
the rift between the two thinkers, even more so than their positions on World War I.
Buber wrote an open letter to Cohen on Zionism, to which Cohen responded with
70
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
his own open letter. Cohens response was a peculiar mix of particularism and
universalism. On the one hand, he argued that Jews were patriots of the European
countries to which they belonged. On the other hand, he opposed Zionism on the
grounds that true Judaism was a message for all people, not a single nation. The
connecting thread between Cohens German particularism and his humanist, Jewish
universalism was his commitment to Aufklrung. Cohen posited an innermost
accord between the German spirit and our Messianic religiosity; the German spirit
is the spirit of classical humanism and true universalism, he wrote (Reason and
Hope 168-9). Cohens messianism does not seek the restoration of a lost Golden
Age: The classical concept of our religion points towards the future of mankind,
and not towards the past of an ethnic community whose holiness, rather than being
tied down to a geographical location, is bound up with its historical idea (170).
In summary, perhaps one could accurately say that Buber moved from Gustav
Landauers optimistic, humanistic messianism to the dark apocalypticism of the
post-war eraafter all, Buber tempered his messianism with a mystical turn towards
individuality and inwardness. And according to Jacob Taubes, In the later writings of
Buber (after the First World War) the mystic-immanent interpretation of messianism
gives way to a more religious transcendent view (Cult to Culture 18). However,
the assessment that Buber moved from a prophetic to an apocalyptic messianism
would be true only in a very limited sense. Buber stands with a complex network
of affinities, many of them shared by Fromm. To an extent, Buber belongs to an
earlier era. Although Buber does not belong to Cohens messianism, his socialism
and Zionism were forged before Weimar and cannot be neatly categorized in terms
of that era. A much clearer case of the catastrophic or apocalyptic messianism that
Fromm opposed can be found in the work of Gershom Scholem, whose messianism
is addressed in the next section.
71
CHAPTER 2
72
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
apocalyptic and pessimistic messianism was at the core of the true Jewish tradition, and
Enlightenment-style messianism was a recent invention in contradiction to Judaism:
We have been taught that the Messianic idea is part and parcel of the idea of
the progress of the human race in the universe, that redemption is achieved by
mans unassisted and continuous progress, leading to the ultimate liberation
of all the goodness and nobility hidden within him. This, in essence, is the
content which the Messianic ideal acquired under the combined dominance
of religious and political liberalism--the result of an attempt to adapt the
Messianic conceptions of the prophets and of Jewish religious tradition to the
ideals of the French Revolution. (The Messianic Idea 37)
The idea of messianism that Scholems generation had been taught was essentially
that of Hermann Cohen. In Chapter 4, I show how Fromm revived this idea of
messianism, embracing a cautious critique of the Enlightenment but still situating
his messianism within the Enlightenment tradition.
***
73
CHAPTER 2
with his older brother Werner and distributed the Marxist journal Die Internationale,
which was tied to the radical faction of the Social Democratic Party that would
eventually become that of Luxemburg and Liebknecht (Scholem, From Berlin 52).
However, Scholem reported later that he had been more interested in the non-Marxist
socialism of Proudhon, Kropotkin, and Landauer than the supposedly scientific
kind of socialism, and he was particularly impressed by Landauer and devoured
his Aufruf zum Sozialismus (52-3).25 Scholem states in his autobiography that he
later began to have doubts about anarchism as a political program after his initial
enthusiasm (53). Scholem was also initially impressed by Buber, meeting him while
Scholem was a youth, and was influenced by Franz Rosenzweig, though he rejected
the options Buber and Rosenzweig represented (55). Scholem critiqued Rosenzweigs
Star of Redemption for its profound tendency to extract the apocalyptic sting from
the organism of Judaism and for being insufficiently catastrophic (Moltmann 36).26
Scholems apocalyptic messianism played well into the philosophical and cultural
phenomenon of life philosophy and the prevailing antinomianism. The sudden
catastrophe and apocalyptic transformation would occur almost by law of nature,
the result of an anarchic life force that refuses to be controlled or repressedthe
anarchic promiscuity of all living things (Lazier 187). For Scholem (as Benjamin
Lazier explains), Life is anarchic. It is wild and ungovernable. It defies in the end
every effort to bring it to order, to subdue it to the dictates of law, any law. It is the
wellspring of lawlessness, a primary earthly force (Lazier 187).
74
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
75
CHAPTER 2
According to Scholem, the doctrine of redemption through sin (or the holiness
of sin) led to a belief that the material world and ones external actions upon it are
irrelevant and essentially unreal (Major Trends 319). Obviously, there is a resonance
here with Gnosticisms eschewal of created and material reality, but Scholem insists
that Sabbateanism was a rejection of the abstracted, rational, philosophical God of the
Gnostics and an affirmation of the God of Israel, whom the Gnostics rejected (323).
The unreality of the world followed from both of the major Sabbatean interpretations
of the doctrine of redemption through sin. One interpretation suggested that the
messianic age had already come for the elect who had accepted Zevis message
and that the law had hence been abrogated. The elect could not sin, as even what
was adjudged to be sin on their part was really holiness in disguise. The alternate
interpretation was that although the messianic age had not yet arrived, it was holy to
sin if necessary to combat evil. Whichever interpretation one adopted (that the world
was already secretly already redeemed or that it would be redeemed through sin that
was secretly good), the existing world was illusory. In consequence, two possible
approaches could be taken, each with political implications: quietism (withdrawal
into inwardness) or nihilism (319).
Although Zevi was by no means the first Jew to announce himself as the Messiah
and achieve a popular following, Sabbateanism had surprisingly far-reaching
philosophical and political influence. Later, the Sabbateansand the Jews broadly,
by proxywere accused of fomenting the French Revolution when a new Messiah-
figure, Jacob Frank, claimed to be the incarnation of Zevi. (While Zevi converted
to Islam, Frank eventually converted to Catholicism.) Sabbateanism undoubtedly
played an explosive role in Judaism, but it is a matter of debate whether it contributed
meaningfully to substantive revolutionary change. (Predictably, considering
Scholems anti-Enlightenment proclivities, Scholem despised the Frankists, although
he expressed qualified admiration for them in his essay Redemption through Sin
[Lazier 143, 144].)
According to Scholem, the doctrine of redemption through sin arose from the
Lurianic Kabbalah, which conceived creation as a three-part process: zimzum (Gods
contraction/withdrawal), shevirah hal-kelim (breaking of the vessels), and tikkun
(restitution/redemption) (Bloom, Kabbalah 39). According to this narrative, since
God is infinite and the existence of two infinities is logically impossible, God could
not create a perfect, infinite creation. God had to withhold some of Gods goodness
in order to create something other. The concept of zimzum was Isaac Lurias unique
contribution to Kabbalah (Scholem, Major Trends 260). Zimzum differentiated
Lurianic Kabbalah from pantheism, Scholem points out, because the doctrine of
zimzum affirmed unequivocally that there had to be at least something that was not
God. Notice, then, that this places Lurianic Kabbalah, and Scholems enthusiasm for
it, away from the pantheism option, in the possible alternative of pantheism and
Gnosticism (262).
God created vessels of goodness, the Lurianic account goes, which burst and
shattered their containers; the resultant sparks of goodness were lost and scattered,
76
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
and now remain concealed throughout creation (Bloom [1975] 40-1). The task of
human life is to assist in the redemption by freeing these sparks through good deeds.
Drawing on Scholem, Harold Bloom argues that according to Lurianic Kabbalah,
God could create only through destruction (shattering of the vessels), and this
was surely a standpoint that appealed to many activists of the time (and earlier, to
Bakunin under Nietzsches influence28) (41). Scholem eventually interpreted Zevis
story as a cautionary tale about the dangers of religious nihilism (Habermas 144;
Magid 7). Messianism was potentially explosive, but it only became truly dangerous
when united with secular movements. As Scholem stated in a 1975 interview:
Ive defined what I thought was the price the Jewish people have paid for
messianism. A very high price. Some people have wrongly taken this to mean
that I am an antimessianist. I have a strong inclination toward it. I have not
given up on it. But it may be that my writings have spurred people to say that
I am a Jew who rejects the messianic idea because the price was too high.
(Wolin, Labyrinths 53)
Rather than simply rejecting messianism, Scholem warned that the failure to
distinguish between messianism and secular movements is apt to trip up movements
and that such a mix-up becomes a destructive element (53). Since he was
convinced that all true messianism posited a total rupture from preceding history,
one can see why he would fear that it would lead to violence if mixed with politics.
Such an absolute break requires the destruction of many existing structures. Without
a political impetus, however, it would seem that messianism is reduced to quietist
waiting, with its grand vision of cosmic transformation bracketed away and kept safe
from the realm of the political.
Scholems ambivalent discourse on technology resembles his ambivalent attitude
towards messianism, expressing both a fear and a celebration of destructive power.
His 1965 use of the Jewish folk tale of the Golem seemed to condemn technologys
destructive power and simultaneously revel in it (Lazier 191). According to Scholem,
humanity will eventually be defeated by nature, which will rise up against it. Lazier
writes, Like the pit of promiscuity out of which all that lives comes to be, this
tellurian power both gives rise to creation and undoes it (192). Scholems vision
of the threat of humanitys creations rising up to destroy humanity resembles that
of others in the romantic tradition, including Mary Shelleys Frankenstein (192-3).
Scholem appears to have shifted his position on messianism over time. In his
youth he had even toyed with the idea that he personally was the messiah, but by
the late 1970s, the rise of extreme conservative political factions in Israeli politics
(Menachem Begin, Likud Party, Gush Emunim) appears to have led him to issue
warnings about the dangers of messianism (Lazier 195-6). At that time he made
an effort to differentiate Zionism from messianism, defining Zionisms aims as
merely temporal (Lazier 196). Even as early as the 1930s, however, Scholem was
wary of mixing messianism with politics, since he was opposed to Communism and
considered it a manifestation of messianism (Dubnov 144).
77
CHAPTER 2
The conclusion that Scholem eventually reached while in Israelthat the dangers of
apocalyptic messianism must be rejected in favor of quietism and inwardnesshad
been reached far earlier in post-WWI Germany by the young scholar of Judaism,
Franz Rosenzweig (1998-1929).
In 1913, Rosenzweig was on the brink of converting to Lutheranism when
he recommitted to Judaism (MacIntyre 150-1). One month after his reversion,
Rosenzweig attended a lecture by Hermann Cohen, and he was influenced by
Cohens reading of Kant for some time thereafterso much so, in fact, that he
reports in a letter to his parents that he gushed with praise of Cohen to a Russian
child who merely asked what Rosenzweig did for a living (MacIntyre 152; Bouretz
101). Rosenzweig was especially influenced by Cohens later work (the period of
Cohens The Religion of Reason), which he saw as a move away from idealism
towards existentialist, dialogic thought, focusing not on universal humanity but on
man as a concrete individual and God as his interlocutor (Poma 303).
Although Rosenzweig was not the sole founder of the Lehrhaus as is sometimes
claimed, he was its leader and heavily involved in organizing the group. Rosenzweig
later broke from Cohen, accusing him of having betrayed the messianic idea
through his emphasis upon gradual progress (Lwy, Redemption and Utopia
59). After the catastrophe of World War I, Rosenzweig published The Star of
Redemption in 1921. He had already published an important two-volume work
on Hegels political philosophy, but Star was unquestionably one of the most
important twentieth century works of Jewish thought, urging European Jews to stop
assimilating and seek redemption from history as opposed to redemption through
history (Moltmann 33). Like Scholem later, Rosenzweig held that the messianic age
would be a complete change, the complete changethat would put an end to the
hell of world history (Lwy, Redemption and Utopia 59).
Change was in the air. Along with Rosenzweigs Star, Karl Barths Epistle to the
Romans appeared in the early 1920s. Romans marked a shift in Christian theology
that paralleled the shift occurring within Jewish theology, from immanence to
transcendence, and from the prophetic to the apocalyptic. The pendulum had swung
away from the Hegelian God-in-history. The coming God was a God who would
78
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
end history, who would triumph over it rather than complete it, who would through
transcendent intervention reveal the contingency of all temporal and human affairs
(Lilla 264, 267-8).
Just as Scholem is often taken as canonical despite the fact that he was presenting
a new interpretation, Rosenzweig is often taken as a mere defender of traditional
Judaism in the midst of upheaval when, in fact, he was doing something new and
contesting tradition in certain respects. Rosenzweigs return to Orthodoxy, as well
as his adherence to a messianic hope based on ritual practices and distanced from
revolutionary upsurge, might seem to represent the Judaism of an earlier time. And, in
fact, a good many Jews of the time, having not really read it, presumed that Star was
a mere apology for Judaism. Everybody thinks [the book] is an admonition to eat
kosher, Rosenzweig complained (Galli 4). Yet Rosenzweig was a child of his time,
enraptured by the rich possibilities of the present into which the Messiah could enter.
Although Barth and Rosenzweig are classed as exemplars of neo-orthodoxy, in
both cases one should lean heavily upon the neo and lightly upon the orthodoxy
(Lilla 267). Just as Jewish and leftist messianism were shifting from prophetic to
catastrophic in the wake of World War I, so too was Christian eschatology, and Barth
was an exemplar of this shift in Christian theology; Barths Romans was imbued with
esoteric gnosticism (262). Likewise, comparisons are drawn between Gnosticism
and some of Rosenzweigs thought (Lilla 277; Pollock 6).
Enraptured by the spirit of the times, Margarete Susman wrote (in a review of
Rosenzweigs The New Thinking) a passage worth quoting at length, if for no
other reason than that it so neatly encapsulates the apocalyptic mood discussed at the
opening of this chapter. (Note the themes of inwardness, otherness, transcendence,
destiny, and fate.)
A peculiar life is commencing today in our country. At the moment when all
the stars above it seem extinguished, and when its reality stares at us greyer
and more wasted than ever, an odd lightning and flashing is beginning above it
in the sky of its spirit, as if from new, unknown stars. Strange cloud formations
and configurations of light gather above its head: Forms of pure inwardness
arose, appearances foreign to everything that pertains to the life of the day, and
yet finally determined and winged, again to transcend it. One asks oneself, in
view of these manifold and yet essentially profoundly interrelated formations,
whether it will not nevertheless at all times be Germanys fate and destiny
to be thrown back again and again into its inwardness, whether its ultimate
destiny cannot, despite all threats and dangers of annihilationindeed because
of them, be determined only in its inwardness. (Susman 106)
The apocalyptic tone of this passage, a tone so widespread throughout contemporary
literature, is impossible to miss. These strange cloud formations and configurations
of light are omens of the end, the annihilation.
While Moses Hess, Hermann Cohen, and other progressive philosophers of
Judaism had challenged Hegels exclusion of the Jews from future world history,29
79
CHAPTER 2
80
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
Like Landauer, Rosenzweig saw the messianic age as the product of an organic,
natural human development and creativity. God in his love freed the soul for the
freedom of the act of love, just as he gave creation the power to grow vitally within
itself (Rosenzweig 267). In a section titled Hope, Rosenzweig emphasizes that
life is incomplete and growing (284). Hope was the last of a Joachimite progression
of three ages: As Augustine loves, and Luther believes, so Goethe hopes. And thus
the whole world enters under this new sign (284).
***
Ernst Bloch and the young Georg Lukcs were both of Jewish origins, although they
were not members of the Lehrhaus. Both were socialists whose spirit, like Fromms,
may be described as atheistic religiosity. Like many of their time, Bloch and Lukcs
longed to fill the chasm of meaninglessness that followed in the wake of the First World
War, and they entered Marxism through an experience akin to religious conversion.
Unlike many of the Lehrhaus thinkers, however, Bloch (to an extent) and especially
Lukcs found fidelity to a pre-war messianic vision as the solution to their intellectual
difficulties. For Bloch and Lukcs, the initial path to that vision may have been an
existential, absurd choice, not a mere rational argument along Kantian lines, as would
have been expected by Hermann Cohens tradition. Both also had early flirtations
with Romantic, pessimistic, or gnostic tendencies, yet both Bloch and Lukcs, in
different ways, eventually ended up affirming reason, hope, prophetic messianism,
and the unfinished project of the Enlightenment. Their move to Marxism was not a
flight from reality but a way of accessing the this-sidedness (Diesseitigkeit), to use
Marxs term,31 of truth. Both realized that hope depended upon a unity of theory and
practice, and only from the standpoint of this unity could one advance the revolution.
81
CHAPTER 2
Ernst Bloch (1885-1977) and Georg Lukcs (1885-1971) were both members of
Max Webers circle in Heidelberg from 1912-1914 (Lowy, Capitalism as Religion
71). In the first decades of the twentieth century, Max Weber and Stefan George were
Heidelbergs intellectual celebrities (Bouretz 426). Both derived their influence from
their lack of affiliation with the University of Heidelberg, marking them as outsiders,
which at that time translated into a peculiar kind of cultural capital. Webers group
met on Sunday afternoons at his house. According to Bloch, half of the Stefan
George Circle also attended the Weber gatherings (Interview with Ernst Bloch
35). In recalling those years later, in the 1970s, Ernst Bloch resisted Michael Lowys
suggestion that the Weber circle was radical and anti-capitalist and indicated that a
separate grouping of radical thinkers existed in Heidelberg, including Bloch, Lukcs,
and Karl Jaspers, among others (35).
Bloch and Lukcs were close friends and intellectual collaborators. They were
developing a method unlike anything Weber had seen before, but which he found
promising. Ernst Bloch said later that as he got to know Lukcs, [they] quickly
discovered that [they] had the same opinion on everything, so much so that [they]
founded a wildlife preserve (Naturschutzpark) for [their] differences of opinion, so
that [they] wouldnt always say the same things (Interview with Ernst Bloch 36,
italics Lowys). Weber felt forced to choose allegiances between the two students,
who were bright and seemed to be in total agreement. Weber chose Lukcs, whom
he saw as the more theoretical of the two; Bloch, by contrast, seemed not to have
his feet on the ground (Bouretz 427). Weber described Lukcs as one of the types
of German eschatologism, at the opposite pole from Stefan George (Lwy,
Redemption and Utopia 147). (George will be discussed further in the following
section.) However, [Bloch] is possessed by God, Weber concluded, and I am a
scientist (Bouretz 427). Max Scheler apparently agreed, describing Blochs early
writings as a running amok to God (427).
Although he was an atheist, Ernst Bloch employed Christian and Jewish concepts,
history, and symbols throughout his scholarly career. Bloch has been a formidable
intellectual influence upon Christian theologians including Gustavo Gutierrez,
Jrgen Moltmann, and Wolfhart Pannenberg (Gutierrez 124). Although Bloch did
not consider himself a theologian, it is constantly tempting to read him as one; what
Gershom Scholem said of Walter Benjamin might be equally true of Ernst Bloch: he
was a theologian marooned in the realm of the profaneor, to play upon the title of
Blochs book on the German peasant revolt, a theologian of the revolution. (As we
will see, one might say that there are also theological moments in Lukcs, although
he would have rejected the title of theologian with even greater vehemence.)
Contrary to some Marxists who consider religion mere ideology and demand
that theological language be jettisoned, Bloch was convinced that Marxists needed
to employ the language of religion and myth. This was partly for tactical purposes, to
prevent such tools of persuasion from becoming the exclusive property of Marxisms
82
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
political enemies. In fact, the basic thesis of Blochs 1935 book Heritage of Our
Times is that the left permitted the rise of fascism and was partly culpable, since the
left had failed to engage with the myths that were captured and repurposed by fascist
ideology and propaganda. But Bloch also saw an intrinsic value in some aspects
of religion, as did Fromm. Humanitys highest hopes throughout history had been
expressed in religious language, Bloch reasoned, and thus a theory of the socialist
future would have to draw from this intellectual resource. The realization of human
hopes could only occur through a critical yet empathetic engagement with religious
thought. Socialism was not a mere negation of religionMarx himself had pointed
that out in his critique of Feuerbachbut was the heir of the yearnings of the past
and was in Blochs view a new religious movementthe red faith (Bloch, Man
on his Own 146). (Aufhebung, after all, the German word for dialectical synthesis,
means both cancelation and preservation; socialisms defeat of religion is also
religions realization.)
Many thinkers affected by this timeWalter Benjamin, Theodor Adorno,
and the vastly underrated Simone Weil, among othersturned to the desolate
theological realm, now abandoned by its God, in search of an antithesis to the sunny
Enlightenment and an account of the darkness of human suffering (Waggoner 5).
What the mature Ernst Bloch sought from theology, however, was different. He
sought not an understanding of the depths of suffering so much as that light of reason
and liberation for which the Enlightenment had come (somewhat inaccurately) to be
the reigning symbol. Some have commented that Simone Weil understood the cross
(suffering) but not the resurrection (hope, promise).32 In these terms, one might say
that Bloch understood both the cross and the resurrection.
Blochs messianism is eschatological and more focused on rupture than continuity.
To some extent, Bloch supports an unpredictable, transcendent intervention into
history, although in his later work he warned against the desire for transcendence.
An opening epigraph of his Atheism in Christianity states, What is decisive: to
transcend without transcendence (viii). In contrast to Buber and Fromm, Bloch
was sympathetic to Gnosticism, and he defended the Gnostic Marcion throughout
his career (as Jacob Taubes points out), from the time of Blochs early book, The
Spirit of Utopia, to The Principle of Hope in the 1950s and Atheism in Christianity
in 1968 (Taubes, Cult to Culture 142). (Blochs discussion of Marcion in Spirit of
Utopia in 1918 preceded Harnacks book on Marcion in 1921 and thus helped to
shape the debate that followed.) Bloch never completely broke from the neo-Gnostic
apocalypticism that influenced his first edition of The Spirit of Utopia (1918), but he
underwent a significant shift away from it.
The first edition of The Spirit of Utopia may be understood as Marxist, and it
distinguished Marxism from state socialism (Lwy, Redemption and Utopia 140).
It was skeptical of Zionism and included a section entitled Symbol: die Juden,
which argued along the lines of Hermann Cohen that the Jews, along with the
Germans and the Russians according to Bloch, were to play a crucial role in bringing
the Messiah, but definitely not through Zionism (141-2). Bloch was giving a nod
83
CHAPTER 2
to the cultural eastward tide, not to Palestine in this case but to Russia; still, he
continued to see Germany as integral to the revolution. The section Symbol: die
Juden was later absent from the 1923 edition, which removed about a hundred
pages from the original text, including laudations for Stefan George and for other
esoteric teachers (Geheimlehrer), along with a lengthy philosophical discussion of
Kant, Hegel, Nietzsche, Bergson, and Husserl (Geist der Utopie 237342). In 1923,
Bloch was distancing himself from some of his earlier ideas. However, the strangely
apocalyptic, mysterious final chapter, aptly entitled Karl Marx, Death, and the
Apocalypse, remained in the second edition, suggesting that Bloch was conflicted
on this issue.
After the first edition of Spirit of Utopia in 1918, Blochs next major undertaking
was a text on the leader of the sixteenth-century German peasant revolt: Thomas
Mntzer als Theologe der Revolution (1921). The book posited the persistence of
utopian longing throughout history but did not link it well to changing historical
developments. It proved to be a breaking point between Bloch and Lukcs, who
harshly criticized it in 1923 (Toscano 80). Perhaps Lukcs underestimated the
importance of religious motivations in sparking the German peasant revolt, but
his critique of Blochs utopianism as endorsing quietism is interestingBlochs
Gnostic and apocalyptic leanings are compatible with quietism, he argued
and he claimed that Blochs views represented an inaccurate account of human
nature (82).
When Bloch and Lukcs were reunited following the First World War, they found
that they had developed significant disagreements. According to Bloch in a late
interview, one of the major disagreements was over Schopenhauer (Interview with
Ernst Bloch 37-8). Bloch saw Schopenhauer as radical due to his complete negation
of the world and was attracted to Schopenhauers view that, The world as it exists
is not true (37, Lowys italics). Lukcss subsequent rejection of Kierkegaard
and Dostoyevsky, which Bloch chocked up to Lukcss conversion to the Party,
marked a further division, about which more will be said later (38-9).
84
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
85
CHAPTER 2
Conversion to Totality
The following section explores the second theologian of the revolution, Georg
Lukcs. Together with Karl Korschs Marxism and Philosophy, Lukcss History
and Class Consciousness revived the study of Hegel for Marxism and returned the
focus of Marxist thought to human nature and history, while opposing economism
and determinism. Lukcss Marxist philosophy was made possible by a shift in
focus more complete than any undergone by Bloch, a dramatic conversion that
moved Lukcs and his philosophy from the standpoint of the spectator to that of the
86
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
What Lukcs calls orthodox Marxism is a far cry from what mainline Soviet
Marxists call orthodox Marxism (which is what usually goes by the name). Lukcs
issues a daring challenge to reigning orthodoxies. The true essence of Marxism,
he argues, lies not in any particular statements made by Marx but only in Marxs
dialectical method. Genuine orthodox Marxism is the scientific conviction that
dialectical materialism is the road to truth (History and Class Consciousness 1).
It is a method or standpoint, the method of dialectical materialism or, what is the
same thing, the standpoint of totality. This method is revolutionary and provides the
crucial link between theory and practice (2).
The dialectical method conceives of reality as a unity, a social totality that is
continually becoming. All of existence is a product of human activity, and thus the
totality is a human creation, which includes humanity itself (19). One might say the
totality is the process of humanitys self-creation. All of the parts of the process of
production (distribution, exchange, consumption, etc.), which appear as so many
distinct, static entities in bourgeois economics, are really only interconnected parts
of this single, total process, which is reality itself (13). The goal of this total, social
processthe emancipation of the proletariatis immanent, and Marxism is the
prophet of this emancipation (234).
However, the standpoint of totality has not been attained by the blinkered
empiricist, who focuses only upon individual facts, wrenched from their social-
historical context, and who fails to see the total process (5). Numerous problems
result from the attempt to treat facts in isolation from the totality; the blinkered
empiricist cannot recognize the following truths:
87
CHAPTER 2
Lukcs believed that Rosa Luxemburg, like himself, understood the significance
of the standpoint of totality. Unlike reformists like Bernstein, Luxemburg was a
revolutionary who knew that revolution is the product of a perspective on totality
and cannot be an isolated act (History and Class Consciousness 29). (Her account
of capitalist accumulation places accumulation into the context of totality [36].)
In order to choose Marxism, one must declare ones theoretical commitment to the
standpoint of totality (30). This involves rejecting the specialization of knowledge,
refusing to [confine] oneself to the analysis of isolated aspects in one or other of
the special disciplines (30). And since Marx realized economic reality is not
governed byeternal laws of nature, to reduce Marxism to a series of formulae
(Aristotles M-C-M, C-M-C discussed in Capital, etc.) is erroneous; the Marxist
must realize that these formulae are only a part of the total picture (31).
In contrast with the simplistic, formulaic approach of Marxs vulgar interpreters,
Hegel, Marx, and Luxemburg realized that attempting to understand even one thing
historically leads to an historical explanation that is broader in scope (34). Historical
investigation of phenomena through Hegels method reveals the identity of the
philosophy of history and the history of philosophy and the fundamental unity of
thought and existence (33-4). This historical method goes far beyond the bourgeois
tradition of taking the achievements of their forerunners into account (35).
88
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
Luxemburg rightly distinguishes, according to Lukcs, the total and the partial,
the dialectical and the mechanical view of history (39-40). The partial/mechanical
perspective leads to the attempt to force the revolution through small-group
conspiracies and coups (Blanquism, which in Fromms terms would be a form of
forcing the Messiah) (40). By contrast, the total/dialectical perspective finds the
unity of theory and practice in the whole proletariat (not a small group who force the
revolution upon others). The proletarians come to know themselves and transform
society through the same act. By recognizing its situation [the proletariat] acts. By
combating capitalism it discovers its own place in society (40).
As neat and clean as such summaries soundknow by acting, act by knowingin
reality the proletariats merger of theory and practice is spontaneous, unpredictable,
not mechanical; in short, it is messy (40-1). As anyone who has participated in social
activism knows, the success of events is inscrutable; an excellently organized event
sometimes draws a turn-out of two people, while a poorly planned, last-minute
endeavor suddenly wins over hundreds, who enthusiastically crowd into the back
rows and aisles. Luxemburg wrote of the mass strike, wherein the working class
suddenly, world over, begins to reach the same realizations. 1968, to use a more
recent example, was a mass strike year; for reasons that will never be entirely
clear, there were revolts all over the world.
According to Lukcs, the (messy) class consciousness of the proletariat takes
the form of the Party. Hence, he rejects bureaucratic or mechanical understandings
of the Party. The Party is not simply a form of organization (41). The Party is
the effect, not the cause, of revolution. It gives expression to the free, conscious
action of the proletariat and is the incarnation of the ethics and consciousness of
the proletariat (41-2).
Lukcs concludes the essay with what one might call a profession of faith
(i.e., faith in Fromms non-religious sense of the term: a paradoxical certainty
that something uncertain will occur [ROH 14]). Responding to those who sneer
that Marxism is religious faith, Lukcs does not reply, as one might expect, by
insisting that Marxism is not a faith but a science. In fact, he responds by criticizing
science and stating that there is no material guarantee of the proletariats
success (History and Class Consciousness 43)! He then professes his certitude that
regardless of all temporary defeats and setbacks, the historical process will come to
fruition in our deeds and through our deeds (43). Here Lukcs expresses a faith in
the coming of socialism, not a scientific conclusion that the coming of socialism is
determined (43).
Granted, Lukcs goes on to say that the fall of capitalism will result from
method, which sounds a bit more scientific (and safer!) than faith. But what
Lukcs means by method is something that cannot be proven on mere theoretical
grounds but can only be proven through a transformation of the life of the proletariat,
in their commitment to living and dying for the revolution (43). He finishes by
stating that it is just as impossible to understand Marxism for a mere a scholar of
Marxism, unengaged in this revolutionary struggle of living and dying, as it is for
89
CHAPTER 2
the economic determinist (43). Marxism can only be understood from the inside.
This presents a problem: It seems that one must adopt Marxism before one can
understand it. Surely this is paradoxical?
90
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
ancestors. The Chassidic Baal Shem. Now he too has found his ancestors and his
race. Only I am alone and forlorn (Rabinbach, Between Enlightenment 80; Lwy,
Redemption and Utopia 146, italics in original). Shortly before his conversion to
Marxism, he had begun to speak of a revolution that would be Christs advent (Lwy,
Redemption and Utopia 148). The faith of the atheist revolutionaries, according to
Lukcs, was a faith in a new, silent God, who needs our help (148). At this time,
Lukcs was also drawn towards the thought of Kierkegaard and Dostoevsky, and in
1913 he began work on a book that would synthesize Kierkegaard and Hegel, which
he never completed (Jay, Marxism and Totality 87).
In 1915, after a break from Max Weber around German nationalism and World
War I, Lukcs returned to his native Hungary (MacIntyre 157). Lukcs soon
after published his The Theory of the Novel, in which he contemplated whether
Dostoevsky might be the herald of a new age that would synthesize art and political
life. Lukcs was still pessimistic, considering his time an age of absolute sinfulness,
in Fichtes expression (Theory of the Novel 152-3; Lwy, Redemption and Utopia
147; MacIntyre 158). But he also envisioned a new unity, an end to all dualisms:
a world of pure soul-reality in which man exists as man, neither as a social being
nor as an isolated, unique, pure and therefore abstract interioritya new complete
totality could be built out of all its substances and relationships. It would be a
world in which our divided reality would be a mere backdrop (History and Class
Consciousness 152). His full conversion to Marxism came in 1918, when he declared
the proletariat to be the Messiah-class of world history and formally joined the
Hungarian Communist Party (Lwy, Redemption and Utopia 149; MacIntyre 154).
MacIntyre calls Lukcss conversion to Marxism a deliberate act of faith and
states that as Lukacs had approached the question of Bolshevism he had confronted
himself with a recognizably Kierkegaardian Either-Or, a choice so fundamental that
it cannot be supported by reasons (MacIntyre 159-60). Only after his conversion
did Lukcs develop a philosophically-grounded defense of Marxism as the resolution
to the antinomies of German idealism (also in History and Class Consciousness)
(160). MacIntyre explains,
To become a Marxist is through participation in such practice to move beyond
the limitations of pre-Marxist philosophy and so to become able to identify
those limitations. And Lukcs understands himself as someone who has
achieved this new standpoint. Where in 1918 and 1919 he had still spoken
in Kierkegaardian terms, so that his choice of Marxism was represented as
an act of arbitrary, nonrational faith, now he presents his Marxism as the
rational solution of his earlier philosophical difficulties. His new standpoint
excluded what he was in the future going to characterize as Kierkegaardian
irrationalism. (160)
The fact that Lukcs had moved from bourgeois philosophy to Marxism through
an existential leap of faith would not have been well-received by all of his new
comrades, and this was a fact that he never openly discussed (MacIntyre 157).
91
CHAPTER 2
92
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
misunderstanding of Lukcs in the interview is that Lukcs finally made the decision,
the leap or conversion, that both of them were seeking, while Bloch chose not to and
to remain somewhat an outsider. Perhaps Bloch resented Lukcss fame, considering
that Bloch probably saw himself as having more integrity for remaining independent
in spite of how much he could have gained by committing himself to the West, to the
East, or to Christianity or Judaism. But Bloch was wrong if he believed that Lukcss
rejection of Kierkegaard, Dostoyevsky, and Schopenhauer was a cheap capitulation,
i.e., that Lukcs was deceiving himself and accepting the Soviet Union as the coming
of the Messiah. Lukcss conversion experience simply opened up new truths to him
that were not available to Bloch, partially because of Blochs lingering tendency to
see historical change as an interruption from outside. Although Lukcs was wrong in
his assessment of the Soviet Union (and Bloch was also, for at least a time), Lukcss
standpoint as an epistemologically privileged revolutionary subject granted him a
hope and optimism denied to Bloch. Seeing totality as a process that is moving
towards redemption, and consequently rejecting the pessimism of Schopenhauer,
was not a sunny daydream or a self-deception; it was simply how the world looked
to Lukcs as a subject in the midst of a revolutionary moment.
The ideology of the Stefan George circle was far removed from the emancipatory
intent of Ernst Bloch and George Lukcs. The George circle represents another
kind of response to the widening abyss perceived between the corrupt present and
the messianic, fulfilled future. For Stefan George and his conservative admirers,
the abyss between present and future was so wide it that could only be bridged
by irrational, magical, or aesthetic means. Styling themselves the protectors of
a subterranean secret Germany that would one day ascend to reign, Georges
elite group was not engaged in debates in left-wing Jewish intellectual circles over
the meaning of messianismin fact, it was a rather anti-Semitic grouping, despite
having some Jewish membersbut it nevertheless possessed a peculiar type of
messianic tendency. Their messianism was in large part a deference to a leader, a
Messiah-figureStefan George. Their ideology was conceptually linked to some
previously discussed figures and movements by its gnostic orientation and by its
sense of doom, decline, and apocalyptic expectation.
Stefan George (1868-1933) was a mysterious figure, a poet and the leader of a
kind of cult. His circle emerged out of the Cosmic Circle, founded at the turn of
the century by Ludwig Klages in the Bohemian borough of Schwabing in Mnich
(Lebovic, Beauty and Terror 27). Stefan George, Ludwig Klages, and Alfred
Schuler used to walk the streets of Munich disguised in Dionysian masks and robes,
sometimes carrying knives (Lebovic, Dionysian Politics 5). The Cosmic Circle
lasted until 1905, when the more virulently anti-Semitic faction represented by
Klages and Schuler (who later became infamous as the popularizer of the swastika)
93
CHAPTER 2
split from George (Lebovic, Beauty and Terror 27; Norton 153, 585-6). After the
disintegration of the Cosmic Circle, George created his own circle in Heidelberg.
Heidelberg became the secret capital of the Secret Germany, where one could
catch a glimpse of that celebrity, Stefan George: I certainly saw him, Walter
Benjamin said later, even heard him. It was not too much for me to wait for hours
on a bench reading in the castle park in Heidelberg in expectation of the moment
when he was supposed to walk by (Norton 475).
Georges circle was ostensibly a literary circle, but everyone knew it was far more
than a writers workshop. It preached the message of a secret- and sacred Germany
that could be recuperated through a return to Germanys primordial Teutonic and
heroic past. Like radical Vienna journalist Karl Kraus, George viewed the origin as
the goal; it was through rupture with the ordinary that one could return to the past,
and it was from the past that the new order (or Reich, as in the title of Georges 1928
chapbook Das Neue Reich) would emerge (Norton 679).
Although George was anti-Semitic, anti-Semitism does not seem to have been
the primary source of his reactionary politics (Norton 155-6). Several in Georges
circle were Jews, including most notably Friedrich Gundolf and Karl Wolfskehl. The
Circles ritual practices and its hierarchical, secretive nature do more to suggest its
political affinities. In Secret Germany: Stefan George and His Circle, Robert Norton
writes:
Elitist, hierarchical, antidemocratic, and deeply suspicious of all forms of
rationalism, George held many of the beliefs and values that were shared by
antimodern intellectuals in early-twentieth-century Germany. For George and
his followers, who typically expressed nothing but contempt for the democratic
experiment of the Weimar years, their own Secret Germany provided a
surrogate ideology that looked back to a heroic European past for cultural and
political models to provide the patterns to inform some futureGerman
state. Stefan George and his circle, then, offered kind of miniature model of the
way that state might look: enthusiastic followers who submitted themselves
without question to the example and will of their charismatic leader, who they
believed possessed mysterious, even quasi-divine powers. (xi)
The George circle organized secret costume parties at which members dressed as
mythological deities, conducted orgies to Wagnerian drumbeats, and formed
a cult of veneration around select teenage boys (Norton 311ff, 329-330; Lebovic,
Dionysian Politics 5). Although they consciously and deliberately violated the
norms of their society, their movement was not recruiting widely. Theirs was a
conservative revolution not intended for the masses.
Although the George circle should be considered proto-fascist, it does not appear
to have collaborated directly with the Nazi regime. When Hitler came to power,
George moved to Switzerland. At the time, his disciples claimed this did not indicate
opposition to Hitler, though they later explained that it was a strategic retreat
from Nazism (Cartwright 3). After Georges death in 1933, two of his followers,
94
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
the von Stauffenberg brothersamong the young men celebrated by the circle for
their beautyattempted to assassinate Hitler. The assassination was motivated by
aristocratic, not democratic aspirations. Claus von Stauffenberg is said to have faced
the firing squad proclaiming, Long live sacred [or secret] Germany! (Norton 745).
The George circle was fascinated by J. J. Bachofens theory of a pre-historic
matriarchal society, and Bachofens book Matriarchy has been called the bible of
the Cosmic Circle (Norton 361). Recall from Chapter 1 that Fromms essay on the
radical and reactionary adherents of Bachofen had targeted Ludwig Klages, Alfred
Bumler, and Alfred Schulerall were members of the Cosmic Circle. The revival
of Bachofen was tied to post-Nietzscheanism and Lebensphilosophie, and like
so many of the Cosmic Circles concerns, the Bachofen controversy centered upon
the political implications of the yearning for return to a prehistoric past (Lebovic,
Beauty and Terror 26).
Cosmic Circle member Ludwig Klagess book Vom Cosmogonischen Eros, which
opened with a note of gratitude to Bachofens work on matriarchy, was hugely
popular in Germany and was considered a contribution to Lebensphilosophie. It also
had a profound effect on some left-wing Jewish thinkers, including Walter Benjamin.
In The Destruction of Reason, Georg Lukcs later identified Klages as the founder
of a fascist Lebensphilosophie (Lukcs, Destruction of Reason 526-7). Klagess
magnum opus was a three-volume work positing a conflict between soul (Seele)
and mind (Geist), Der Geist als Widersacher der Seele (Gay 80). Mind (Geist) he
identified with the killing of life, and he foresaw a resurgence of soul, when an
extra-mundane power [would] burst into the sphere of life (Lukcs, Destruction of
Reason 524). At this apocalyptic moment, the old forces of myth would rise up to
take vengeance on the forces of intellect and to save the soul; the struggle for soul
was a return of the past, a rescuing of myth, and in turn, its enemy was the future
(which was not a property of real time) (525).
Georges influence was certainly in the air in post-World War I Germany, and
his admirers were not confined to the political right. As noted above, in 1918
Ernst Blochs first edition of Spirit of Utopia praised Stefan George, though
Bloch removed the remarks for the second edition in 1923. Bloch later attacked
Ludwig Klages in Heritage of Our Times (1935).33 Walter Benjamin carried on a
correspondence with Klages, an interesting matter that will be explored later. T. W.
Adorno and the early, pre-Marxist Georg Lukcs both wrote admiringly of Stefan
George (Fleming 98-9 and passim; Lukcs [2010] 98-110). Although George is
now almost forgotten, in 1929, a newspaper published a photograph of [George]
alongside the likenesses of Woodrow Wilson, George Clemenceau, Hindenburg,
Gandhi, and Lenin proclaiming them contemporary figures who have become
legends (Norton ix).
Georges circle is a particularly important example of the many cultish circles of
the time and was one of the more influential ones, but it was far from being the only
circle of this type. Along with Stefan Georges circle, some similar figures such as
Oskar Goldberg, Carl Jung, and Rudolf Steiner had circles of followers that shared
95
CHAPTER 2
Considering the peculiar history of the Cosmic Circle it is interesting to consider its
wide influence. In particular, it would be worth exploring the following question,
which I propose to treat at some length: Why does Herbert Marcuse quote Stefan
George in One-Dimensional Man and conservative nineteenth-century writer
Heinrich von Kleist in Eros and Civilization? This question also opens up an
exploration of an apocalyptic/catastrophic tendency within Marcuses work. This
enquiry naturally divides into two parts, the first concerning Stefan George and
One-Dimensional Man and the second concerning Heinrich von Kleist and Eros
and Civilization. The latter enquiry will take us away for a moment from the George
circle, but the themes of Marcuses encounter with Kleists work are related, as
we shall see.
First, a disclaimer: This is neither an exercise in guilt-by-association nor an
attempt to ascribe to Marcuse a reactionary conservatism which Marcuse himself
would disavow. Even in his early years, Marcuse joined the Spartacist uprising of in
Berlin, later recalling his admiration for Rosa Luxemburg as a great orator. Of course,
he was politically active on the left again later as well, in the 1960s in San Diego
and into the 70s. Fromm offered high praise for Marcuses Reason and Revolution:
Hegel and the Rise of Social Theory (1941) (MCM 60-1). Marcuses moments of
hope and optimism are to be found most prominently in Reason and Revolution
and again in Essay on Liberation, at the height of the New Left. Nonetheless, I
argue, with Fromm, that Marcuse had a crisis of despair that is manifested itself in
Eros and Civilization and One-Dimensional Man. To point out Marcuses affinities
with conservative or even reactionary thinkers during the pessimistic period of his
Eros and Civilization34 and One-Dimensional Man merely highlights questions
concerning the history of Critical Theory and the continuing influence of Weimar
culture upon it, questions that have often been fearfully avoided in the literature
on the Frankfurt School. Richard Wolin has begun to break through this wall and
has suggested that the key to understanding Walter Benjamin is not, as many have
suggested, Benjamins alleged 1924 conversion to Marxism (the date of which
should probably be set later). Instead, Wolin suggests that the key to Benjamins
philosophy may in fact be 1922, when he was in discussion with Ludwig Klages
(Benjamin Meets the Cosmics 4). Benjamin has plenty to offer to left theory, and
he was not a reactionarythose were complicated times, and not even hindsight is
20/20. But it may mean that Benjamins work needs to be read differently in light of
that history. Similarly, facing the inconsistencies in Marcuses oeuvre does not force
one to reject Marcuse, but rather opens up space for new readings that are cognizant
of the complex history out of which his work emerged.
96
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
Marcuse quotes Stefan George twice in One-Dimensional Man, both times without
translation. The first quotation is simply a phrase: Luft von anderen Planetenair
from other planets (One-Dimensional Man 65). The line is from Georges poem
Rapture (Entrckung), which was set to score in Arnold Schnbergs String
Quartet No. 2. (In its atonal rejection of the status quo and its meditation upon
the experience of exile, Schnbergs quartet was almost as significant as Georges
poetry to the spirit of the times [Taubes, Cult to Culture 344n1]). Marcuses second
quotation from George refers to worries about over-population: Schon eure Zahl
ist Frevel!even your number is an outrage (One-Dimensional Man 244). After
some brief historical context, I explore these quotations within the context of One-
Dimensional Man.
I suggest that Stefan Georges circle and Herbert Marcuse expressed aspects
of an apocalyptic messianism, if one is willing to treat messianism as a broader
cultural phenomenon that is no longer limited to religious Judaism but expressed
the revolutionary sentiments of Europe at the turn of the century. With Gershom
Scholem, Walter Benjamin and others, Herbert Marcuse was caught up in an
enthusiasm for a sudden and total transformation of society. This messianism
differed from the prophetic messianism of Hermann Cohen, Rosa Luxemburg, and
Erich Fromm, among othersprophetic messianism is more open to Enlightenment
ideals and to reason. While it may take either a revolutionary or reformist form,
prophetic messianism warns strongly against trying to force the messianic age
to arrive without the involvement of the masses. Apocalyptic messianism, by
contrast, posits a future that emerges from a dramatic rupture with the present,
ushering in something that is totally other. Therefore, for apocalyptic messianism
the future is necessarily unthinkable from the standpoint of the present. From the
prediction of a total break between present and future emerges a kind of nihilism
or antinomianism. The attempt to bridge the abyss between the present and the
future may occur through irrational, magical or aesthetic means; as we have
seen, many thinkers of the time rejected both gradual reformism and organizing
for mass revolt, preferring to compel the intervention of mysterious, transcendent
forces into history.
Marcuse may not have met Stefan George or other members of the George Circle,
but he certainly knew Walter Benjamin, who had been influenced by Ludwig Klages.
The director of Marcuses Ph.D. thesis on the German artist-novel (Der Deutsche
Knstlerroman), Philip Witkop, was also influenced by Stefan George (Kellner,
Herbert Marcuse 18). Further, according to Douglas Kellner, Marcuses dissertation
drew heavily from the pre-Marxist Georg Lukcs, including Lukcss Soul and
Form, which contains a chapter praising Stefan George and which serves as a prime
example of the Romantic anti-capitalism of the pre-Marxist Lukcs that the later
Lukcs decried. Any direct contact between George and Marcuse is unlikely to have
occurred and it is unclear to what extent even Georges published writings influenced
97
CHAPTER 2
Marcuse. Nevertheless, Marcuse quotes Stefan George not once, but twice in One-
Dimensional Man, and this with very little clarification of the mysterious quotations
or of his reasons for employing George.
Let us now examine the two George quotes in the context of One-Dimensional
Man. The first quotation, about air from other planets, occurs in the course of a
discussion about aesthetics. According to Marcuse, all works of art participate in the
Great Refusal, regardless of any particular artworks explicit political content and
regardless of the artists intent. Art creates a rupture with social reality through either
magic or rational transgression and by refuting, breaking, and recreating (63). Art
thus renders the familiar strange, and in virtue of this, ushers in the air of other planets.
Rather than operating immanently within the established order, art is a disruption of
the here and the now, which makes Marcuses Great Refusal possible. Art is a means of
confrontation with established norms, which art violates in order to open up space for
further refusal, beyond the limits of art. Air from other planets is an apt image for the
yearning for a messianic age that would be totally other, something not of this world.
Arts transgression may be rational, according to Marcuse, or irrational,
magic (One-Dimensional Man 63). Magic has a host of connotations, of course,
from the Romantic magical idealism of Novalis to aspects of Kabbalah. To speak
of magic and transgression is to invoke the fascination of Weimar Germany with
Rauschecstatic, trance-like intoxication (Lebovic, Dionysian Politics passim).
For Nietzsche, the Dionysian spirit was one of Rausch: the result of all great
enthusiasmsall the extreme movements; the Rausch of destruction, the Rausch of
cruelty; the Rausch of meteorological influence, for example, the Rausch of spring;
or the influence of narcotics (3). For Nietzsche, according to Nitzan Lebovic,
transgression was not a free choice but was written into the nature of reality; existence
itself was returning to its prehuman state, was itself transgressing social norms (3).
Georges Bataille is another figure in the background of Marcuses reference to
magic and transgression. For Batailles vitalism, transgression for transgressions
sake, like war and violence broadly, could liberate the life forces of humanity and
create an organic community (Wolin, Seduction of Unreason 159, 163). By placing a
reference to George beside this call for magic or rational transgression, Marcuse is
doing more than making an idle literary reference; he is recalling an era and bringing
George back into the discussionperforming a metaphorical sance.35
Why would Marcuse want to bring Stefan George back into the conversation?
This is somewhat different from the question of Heideggers possibly problematic
influence on Marcuse, considering that unlike Heidegger, George could not be
described as an academic philosopher. (In fact, Georges cult influence relied on his
distance from academia and his lack of affiliation with the University of Heidelberg.)
Whatever his poems offer, it does not seem to be propositional, so much as a
sometimes peaceful and melodic, sometimes thundering succession of images. They
seem to capture the mood of intoxication and trance that swept through Germany,
perhaps the sort of trance in which Lwenthal describes writing his early essay on
the the Demonic (Lwenthal 49).
98
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
99
CHAPTER 2
is not evident, but it raises interesting questions concerning which aspects of the
cultural milieu of Weimar Germany, a milieu which remains under-explored by the
contemporary literature on the history of the Frankfurt School, Marcuse is seeking
to re-examine or revive.
On a broader scale, Marcuses presentation of the topic of living space seems
to miss the significance of inter-subjectivity and historicity. Although there is much
to be said about the loss of privacy in modern society, and while he is surely right to
mock the shallowness of contemporary capitalist societys confidence in teamwork,
community life, and fun, he still seems to be missing something about the importance
of inter-subjectivity (a charge Fromm also makes against Marcuse in The Art of Loving
[AL 131]). Rather than seeing community, solidarity, or love as tools for dismantling
totalitarian technical control of the mind, Marcuse seems to propose increased isolation,
unlike, for example, Axel Honneth, who has recently emphasized the role of inter-
subjectivity in relation to structures of reification. No doubt many in contemporary
society, especially the poor, suffer from a lack of time and space for quiet reflection,
as Marcuse rightly notes, yet one finds it doubtful that placing them in situations of
increased isolation would spark revolutionary transformation. In addition to neglecting
the significance of inter-subjectivity in his discussion of living-space, Marcuses
account at this point in the text also does not appear to give proper weight to historicity;
it presumes, in remarkably un-dialectical fashion, that the individual can break free
of the limits of capitalism and think in other categories entirely of her own making.
This is either remarkably nave or a hypothetical example intended to demonstrate the
futility of trying to liberate society due to the impossibility of this exercise. This is
Marcuse at a moment of despairing pessimismit is later, as a student of the New
Left, that his hope is rekindled and that he is able to contribute to revolutionary change.
To his credit, in One-Dimensional Man Marcuse rejects the idea of a return to
a mythological Golden Age. This rejection of return occurs in the context of an
argument that modern progress makes it impossible to discuss certain concepts in
ways that do not seem mythical (188-9). He distances himself from reactionary
destructiveness like that of Ludwig Klages, following his critique of a mythological
Golden Age with a critique of Lebensphilosophie and irrational pseudo-philosophies
(189). He also states that critical theory only needs to engage mythological concepts
because of the irrational nature of capitalism itselfin this, he is like Ernst Bloch. In
One-Dimensional Man, Marcuse is clearly trying to avoid flying off on any strange
mythological tangent, because he is aware of the complexities of the history he is
engaging. He is somewhat less cautious in his earlier work Eros and Civilization,
which bears further affinities to the George Circle and the Weimar era yearning for
return to the past.
Now that the two quotes from Stefan George in One-Dimensional Man have been
addressed, we may turn to the other mysterious quote mentioned in the introduction
100
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
to this section, the Heinrich von Kleist line about eating from the tree of knowledge
quoted in Marcuses Eros and Civilization. Marcuse writes: If the guilt accumulated
in the civilized domination of man by man can ever be redeemed by freedom, then the
original sin must be committed again: We must eat from the tree of knowledge in
order to fall back into the state of innocence (198). The line about eating again from
the tree of knowledge is a quotation from Kleist, whom he cites (198n1). Marcuses
use of this puzzling image, like the air of other planets image, reveals something
about his context and the uniquely apocalyptic nature of his messianic yearning.
Simply referring to Heinrich von Kleist is not all that odd, but it is awkward,
because Kleist was held up as a hero by the Nazis. It seems more awkward from
the standpoint of an American audience than referring to Nietzsche, who, although
he was also held up by the Nazis, was more widely known in 1950s America and
had a wider berth of adherents. Kleist lived well before the Nazi era, from 1777
to 1811, and was a prominent German playwright and short story writer, and there
is no consensus on the political implications of Kleists work. Kleist was being
rediscovered in Weimar Germany. As Peter Gay points out, the Weimar revival of
Kleist meant different things to different people: for some, Kleist was the tormented
Christian, for others the aristocrat out of his time, for others a rebel, for the Nazis,
the pure strong German, for Stefan Georges circle, the poet of the lonely elite,
for the Communists, an early revolutionary, for others, simply a German patriot
(Gay 62). Not long before this revival, however, Kleist had been considered a hero
of the conservative anti-Enlightenment. Nietzsche coupled Kleist with Hlderlin
as a victim of pretentious cultivationthat cursed German Bildung and painted
Kleist as an opponent of Enlightenment ideals of progress (60). Friedrich Gundolf, a
member of the Georgekreis, wrote a book on Kleist (Norton 615). According to Peter
Gay, the ultimate result of the Kleist hoopla in Weimar Germany was that the so-
called better interpreters of Kleist only gave new respectability to the love affair with
death that loomed so large over the German mind (Gay 62). Kleists plays about war
seemed to celebrate German nationalism, while his eerie story of a post-earthquake,
quasi-sacrificial slaughter is disturbing (The Earthquake in Chile); his political
writings against Napoleon are also notorious for their hypernationalistic sentiments.
Marcuse was surely aware of the debate about Kleist; it would have been
impossible to ignore it in Freiburg (where Marcuse studied under Martin Heidegger)
and Frankfurt in the 1920s. Marcuses later writings, like Fromms, hark back to
that time. Even the title of Marcuses Eros and Civilization invokes a troubled past,
a time in German culture when Eros was celebrated and the Enlightenment ideal of
Zivilisation, condemned. Ludwig Klagess 1922 work Vom Cosmogonischen Eros
almost certainly crossed Marcuses mind. Marcuse was dredging up the past. It is not
clear, however, to what purpose.
The quote about eating from the tree of knowledge is from Kleists short text The
Puppet Theater (or On the Marionette Theater), a kind of anti-humanist parable.
The narrator recounts a discussion with a friend whom he takes to be very wise.
The friend suggests that an unconscious puppet is a better dancer than a human,
101
CHAPTER 2
You mean, I said rather tentatively, that we must eat again from the tree of
knowledge in order to relapse into the state of Innocence?
Certainly, he replied. That is the last chapter of the history of the world. (88)
The suggestion quoted by Marcuse that humanity must eat again from the tree
of knowledge resembles his remark in One-Dimensional Man that art is radical
because of its ability to contribute to transgression.36 Kleists parable exemplifies a
mysticism of return: according to Kleist, humanitys telos is the return to innocence
God and non-conscious matter are alike in their innocence, while the fallen human
soul is on a journey of return: origin is the goal, as Vienna journalist Karl Kraus
had quipped. This quasi-Romantic yearning for return was a thread running through
Weimar culture and is a prime example of the theme of neo-Gnosticism addressed at
the opening of this chapter.
The difficulty is that one cannot encounter the world from a standpoint abstracted
from human history, as Marx masterfully argued in the 1844 Paris Manuscripts.
(Man is no abstract being squatting outside the world [Early Writings 43]). We
have no concept of life before myth, theology, or other attempts at the worlds
explanation. Thus, a return to primordial innocence lies beyond our powers of
conceptualization, outside of all of our categories. We are being asked by Marcuse to
create a future that is, in effect, impossible to describe. There can be no blueprints or
utopian models. Marcuses messianic event is unlikely to be a product of strategizing
and movement-building (at least for Marcuse in the period of Eros and Civilization
and One-Dimensional Man). One wonders if Marcuses eventual embrace of third
world revolutionismin a 1968 Paris interview, he stated that a revolution in the
United States would be impossibleis related to a desire for the intervention of
what lies outside (The New Left 106). One can yearn for a return to innocence, but
the gates to Paradise are barred behind us.
Eros and Civilization lacks some of the careful qualifications Marcuse offers later
in One-Dimensional Man. In Eros, Marcuses affinities with Klages, George, et. al.,
appear in high relief. The Kleist quote is situated in a discussion of the need to return
to a state prior to civilization, in order to jettison surplus repression. According to
Marcuse, liberation from surplus repression will necessarily appear to be a regression
to a pre-civilizational state (Eros and Civilization 199). The return to innocence
would be possible only through a transgression of the present order that could only
appear as barbarism from the standpoint of that order (198).
We can now return to the question asked at the outset of this section on Marcuse
and apocalyptic messianism: Why does Marcuse quote Stefan George and Heinrich
102
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
von Kleist in One-Dimensional Man and Eros and Civilization? This question
will not be answered here, as the reader was warned at the outset. However, one
may suggest an avenue for further exploration. In the mid-1950s to early 1960s,
Marcuse was re-evaluating the optimistic Hegelian Marxism of his early Reason and
Revolution, which he only recovered in An Essay on Liberation, albeit in a modified
form, with greater emphasis upon the role of catalyst groups as an alternative
to the proletariat. Essay on Liberation recaptures the enthusiasm of his earlier
Marxist work of the 1940s, and this did so under the influence of the 1960s protest
movements. It concludes not with the ambiguity of One-Dimensional Man, which
ends with a statement about loss of hope and an absence of concepts bridging the
gap between the present and the future, but instead with the clarity he received from
a young Black militant saying, For the first time in our life, we shall be free to think
about what we are going to do (One-Dimensional Man 257; Essay on Liberation
91). But it is not this recovery of hope that concerns us here, but the period of Eros
and Civilization (1955) and One-Dimensional Man (1964). We turn now to the final
thinker to be addressed by this chapter: Walter Benjamin.
In 1914, Walter Benjamin (1892-1940) met Ludwig Klages in Mnich and invited
him to speak to the Berlin Free Students Association, and he corresponded again
with him in 1920 (Lebovic, Beauty and Terror 28; Wolin, Benjamin Meets the
Cosmics 11). Benjamin also published contributions to the Bachofen fight, and
according to Lebovic, Benjamins texts, after this debate, are filled with hidden
and explicit references to this debate, a fact largely unrecognized in the fertile
Benjaminian scene (Beauty and Terror 24). In the early thirties, as Fromm was
writing on Bachofen for the Institutes Zeitschrift and rejecting the idea of the
collective unconscious, Benjamin considered writing a book about the theory of
the collective unconscious, relying on the insights of Klages and Carl Jung, focusing
on Klagess theory of Eros and its relevance for politics (Funk, Introduction 7;
Lebovic, Beauty and Terror 30).
In 1929, Benjamins essay Surrealism: The Last Snapshot of the European
Intelligentsia sought out sources of profane illumination, like esoteric love
(175). He wrote of the need for a history of esoteric poetry (presumably including
Stefan George and Dada) presenting it less as an historical evolution than as a
constantly renewed, primal upsurge (177). Apparently George circle member Max
Kommerells The Poet as Leader in German Classicism (Der Dichter als Fhrer in
der deutschen Klassik) (1929) did not fit the bill, however (Norton 670). According
to Benjamin (as Norton summarizes Benjamins review of the book), Kommerells
talk of sacrifice and death, his worship of sharp blades and flashing lances, and his
glorification of the inexorable German conquest, were no mere figures of speech
but rather the solemn tenets of a shared and lived faith, a faith which Benjamin
rejected (674).
103
CHAPTER 2
Despite the influence of the George circle on Benjamin, he also poked fun in
1930 at the habitus of the chthonic forces of terror, who carry their volumes of
Klages in their packs (Lebovic, Beauty and Terror 24). He harshly criticized
two publications by members of the George circle. And Benjamin was critical
of Friedrich Gundolfs polemical book on Goethe, which was a thinly disguised
encomium to Stefan George (Goethes Elective Affinities passim; Norton 585).
According to Martin Jay, the essay critiquing Gundolf on Goethes Elective Affinities
led to Benjamin being ostracized from the scholarly world into which [the George
circles] influence extended (Dialectical Imagination 204). Ostracism may be
an exaggeration, however; it is possible that Benjamin was simply involved in an
internal faction fight among people belonging to the broad social circle influenced
by George and relatively sympathetic to him.
It is difficult to know how to assess the influence. Benjamin was a person of
deep and profound contradictions. He was drawn to Romanticism but also to the
Enlightenment, to anarchism but also to socialism, influenced by conservatives like
Carl Schmitt and leftists like Lukcs (Lwy, Redemption and Utopia 102-3). He was
excited by surrealism and advances in technology but feared the loss of the sacred
aura that surrounded the things of the past. As we noted above, Richard Wolin has
suggested that Benjamins connections to the political right may be the Rosetta stone
to his esoteric philosophy. Although Benjamins messianism was unquestionably
catastrophic/apocalyptic, like his friend Scholems, Benjamin shared messianism
and atheistic religiosity (negative theology, in Richard Wolins terms) with
Fromm, Lukcs, and Bloch (Buck-Morss, Walter Benjamin 744).
104
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
105
CHAPTER 2
106
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
***
The options represented by Hermann Cohen and Gustav Landauer had virtually
vanished by the time of Fromms best-selling Sane Society in 1955, in which he
affirmed the tradition of prophetic messianism that had been nearly crushed by the
assassinations of Landauer and Luxemburg (SS 239). In the movement for socialist
humanism, Fromm sought a renewal of the prophetic-messianic spirit, after the
Freies Jdisches Lehrhaus had long since been divided by questions pertaining to
Zionism, Marxism, and religion, and after a Gnostic proto-fascism had crept over the
political and cultural landscape. Perhaps Bloch and Lukcs, after going their separate
ways, come closest of the figures in this chapter to representing the messianic hope
that Fromm defended.
It would be difficult to over-estimate the degree to which the trauma of World
War I, worsened by the brutal defeat of the leftist uprisings of 19181919, the rise
of Nazism, the Holocaust, and subsequent historical developments, have threatened
prophetic messianism. The result of the series of catastrophes marking the twentieth
century has been a socio-political shattering of hope (in Fromms terms, discussed
in Chapter 3) on a grand scale. Writing in honor of his cousin Heinz Brandt, who
spent many years as a political prisoner both of Hitler and of East Germany, Fromm
calls him a member of a generation of authentic revolutionaries,37 of socialists
and Communists born before the First World War who stood against both the
Social Democrats and Stalin (Foreword to Brandt xii). This generation of authentic
revolutionaries has almost been forgotten, writes Fromm, and this was not only
because many were killed by Stalin and Hitler and others were fooled by Stalins
claim of fidelity to Marxism (xii). This generations revolutionary legacy was nearly
forgotten and lost due to the despair that arose at the time of the First World War:
Events since the First World War have increasingly shaken and shattered illusions
about ideas and principles. A cynical attitude of disbelief, which is presented as
realism, has become dominant, and persons who uncompromisingly adhere to
their beliefs and their principles are frequently viewed as neurotics, madmen,
or worse. (xii)
In few places does Fromm so poignantly display his devotion to the dreams of the
earlier, Enlightenment-inspired generation to which he remained loyal, as his own
generation abandoned its hopes in favor of a newfound pessimism, cynicism, or
despair. Heinz Brandts story, writes Fromm, is not only a human document
of faith, courage, and independence, but also an important historical document,
above all because only a few eyewitnesses of this epoch have survived whose vision
has not been blurred by helplessness, cynicism, or disenchantment (xvi).
In the following chapter, I outline Fromms definition and defense of hope.
Responding to the crisis of the First World War, Fromm argued for the need for
hope. His concept of hope is closely related to his concept of messianism: hope
must be actively engaged in trying to transform the world. Nevertheless, hope
107
CHAPTER 2
does not attempt to force the time but recognizes the need for a combination
of patience and impatience. The fourth and final chapter of this book outlines the
main characteristics of Fromms messianism and how it differs from the prevailing
account of the messianism of the Frankfurt School.
NOTES
1
The German ideal of Bildung had blossomed from an intellectual movement which had been
designed to fly beneath the radar of government censorsFriedrich Schillers Gedankenfreiheit
(Gay 72). This is partly why it was later seen as overly conformist by some in Weimar. The
term has a complicated history, popping up in the work of mystics like Meister Eckhart and later
employed by Pietists speaking of education in virtue and by progressive reformers seeking to give
aesthetic experience a more central role in education. In the 1800s, however, it became identified
with the training of bourgeois youth for their future economic success, so it is not surprising for
this reason too that the term came to be rejected (Cocalis passim). Unfortunately, however, the idea
of popular education that Bildung once represented seems to have been rejected by apocalyptic
messianism along with related baggage accruing to the term.
2
They tended to be united, however, by a rejection of traditional humanism; under the influence
of late Romanticism, the desire for wholeness was manifested in a yearning for union with the
non-human cosmic, not with the totality of humanity or of human history (Lebovic, Dionysian
Politics 3).
3
Followers of Joachim of Fiore (1135-1202), the medieval Franciscan who predicted a coming Age
of the Holy Spirit that would end oppression and inter-religious strife.
4
Jung writes: The Aryan unconscious has a higher potential than the Jewish; that is both the
advantage and the disadvantage of a youthfulness not yet fully weaned from barbarism. In my
opinion, it has been a grave error in medical psychology up to now to apply Jewish categories
which are not even binding on all Jewsindiscriminately to German and Slavic Christendom.
Because of this the most precious secret of the Germanic peoplestheir creative and intuitive depth
of soulhas been explained as a mass of banal infantilism, while my own warning voice has for
decades been suspected of anti-Semitism (Goggin and Goggin 75).
5
Form was an ambiguous term as well, sometimes used to describe the conservative revolution
(Gay 84). Much later, in The Destruction of Reason, Lukcs himself classified form as one of the
central categories of a proto-fascist vitalism and linked it to Oswald Spenglers morphology and
Ernst Jngers esotericism (Lukcs, Destruction of Reason 528, 530, 532).
6
The environmental movement in Weimar Germany is well known to have included significant ties
to the right, and considerable research has been done on the continuation of environmental concerns
under the Nazi regime.
7
Incidentally, the rhetoric about political movements (Bewegungen) was as odd as that about life
(Leben). The Nazis spoke of themselves as a movement, rather than a static Party, as a way of
expressing a commitment to conceiving society as an organic whole (Gay 77).
8
Thomas Mann linked aristocracy to death and democracy to life (Gay 126).
9
Like many of those involved in recent scholarship on messianism, Rabinbach uses the term
messianism only to describe the apocalyptic/catastrophic variant. This is of course one of the
problems in the scholarship that this book is trying to correct.
10
Lazier concludes that pantheism was a catchall for many tendencies of the time (Lazier 73). Since
pantheism does not seem to offer an adequate contrast for Gnosticism for our present endeavor, I
focus here on Gnosticism, though there are similarities between the fight over Gnosticism in Weimar
Germany and the Pantheismusstreit over Spinoza approximately a century earlier.
11
Cf., e.g., Jacob Taubes, Ernst Topitsch, J. J. Altizer. (At the end of Chapter 4, I critique Rainer Funks
use of Topitsch and Funks classification of Fromm as a Gnostic.)
108
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
12
Walter Benjamin and Ernst Bloch, for example, both came to this conclusion around 1912
(Rabinbach, Shadow of Catastrophe 43). Erich Unger, of the Oskar Goldberg circle of Kabbalistic
Nietzscheans, likewise rejected the Zionist program in favor a mobile Jewish revolutionary mission
(Lwy, Redemption and Utopia 173; Rabinbach, Shadow of Catastrophe 58).
13
Here is the young Gershom Scholem writing in his diary about Theodor Herzl and defending an
anarchist Zionism against Herzl: We reject Herzl. He is to blame for the Zionism of today []
which is an organization of grocers, who grovel before everyone powerful! (Lowy, Messianism
in the Early Work 180). And, [Herzls] only thought was the Jewish State. And that we reject. For
we preach anarchismWe do not go to Palestine to found a stateoh, you little Philistines!and to
ensnare ourselves in new chains [forged] out of the old, we go to Palestine out of thirst for freedom
and yearning for the future, for the future belongs to the Orient (Lazier 150; italics Scholems). (In
addition to anarchism, one notices here a kind of determinism that is evident in Scholems workthe
direction of the future is pre-decided--a theme we will return to later. Also, notice the turn towards
the Eastthe future belongs to the Orient.)
14
This eastward tide did have earlier influences. For example, according to Jacob Taubes, Kireyevski,
Bakunin, Belinsky, Dostoevsky, and Count Czieskowski interpreted the role of the Slavic nations in
messianic terms (Cult to Culture 15). One also finds this attitude in Moses Hess, following in the
footsteps of Czieskowski.
15
For example, in her 1905 essay, Socialism and the Churches, Luxemburg argues that Christianity
is at its basis socialistic and charges the clergy, especially the Russian clergy, with abandoning their
principles and perpetuating exploitation. Here she proclaimed, The bishops and the priests are not
the propagators of Christian teaching, but the worshippers of the Golden Calf and of the Knout which
whips the poor and defenceless (3). In her stirring conclusion, she again references the Golden
Calf and issues a prophetic condemnation of the clergy, in a tone that sounds like something straight
of out of Amos:
Also: These servants and worshippers of the Golden Calf support and applaud the crimes of the
Czarist Government and defend the throne of this latest despot who oppresses the people like Nero.
But it is in vain that you put yourselves about, you degenerate servants of Christianity who have
become the servants of Nero. It is in vain that you help our murderers and our killers, in vain that
you protect the exploiters of the proletariat under the sign of the cross. Your cruelties and your
calumnies in former times could not prevent the victory of the Christian idea, the idea which
you have sacrificed to the Golden Calf; today your efforts will raise no obstacle to the coming
of Socialism. Today it is you, in your lies and your teachings, who are pagans, and it is we who
bring to the poor, to the exploited the tidings of fraternity and equality. It is we who are marching
to the conquest of the world as he did formerly who proclaimed that it is easier for a camel to
pass through the eye of a needle than for a rich man to enter the kingdom of heaven (1920).
16
Regarding Kautskys critique of the mass strike, she charges Kautsky with advocating one, final,
pure political mass strike, disengaged from economic strikes: which once only, but with absolute
conclusiveness, smashes down like thunder out of the clear blue sky (Theory & Practice, 1).
17
For further on the connection of Simone Weil to Erich Fromm and Thomas Merton, see my Erich
Fromm and Thomas Merton: Biophilia, Necrophilia, and Messianism in Fromm Forum and
reprinted in Reclaiming the Sane Society: The Life and Scholarship of Erich Fromm in Critical
Theory for the 21st Century (Sense Publishers, 2014). On Mertons encounter with Weil in particular,
see Mertons essay The Answer of Minerva: Pacifism and Resistance in Simone Weil and his book
A Vow of Conversation (citation information below under References).
18
Fromm notes that he was inspired by Cohen in You Shall Be as Gods (YSB 13). The book includes
an account of the disobedience in the garden as the libratory first act of human history. I explore this
allegory further in Chapter 4.
19
Cohens radically future-oriented messianism is also reflected in his Ethics (Ethik des reinen
Willens). There Cohen stresses that history, not nature, is the realm of human freedom (Deuber-
109
CHAPTER 2
Mankowsky 175). The will is temporal and oriented towards the future, and because it is concerned
with the will, ethics must also be future-oriented (175-6).
20
Utopias are visions of ends before the realization of means, yet they are not meaningless; on the
contrary, some have contributed greatly to the progress of thought, not to speak of what they have
meant to uphold faith in the future of man (MFH 30n17).
21
The theme of elective affinities was drawn from Goethes novel by that name and Max Webers use
of the concept in The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. It acquired further significance
later with Walter Benjamins important critical review of a book on Goethe by Friedrich Gundolf, a
member of the Stefan George circle.
22
Svante Lundgren suggests that Buber may have initiated this (Lundgren 108).
23
According to Ernst Bloch, this rupture was illusory and was only a return to past, as I will discuss
in Section 2.3.
24
This classification of Scholem is discussed further in Chapter 4.
25
Scholem met with Landauer between 1915 and 1916, when the anarchist philosopher was lecturing
to Zionist circles in Berlin; the subject of their conversations was their common opposition to the war
and their criticism of Martin Bubers positions on it (Lwy, Redemption and Utopia 65).
26
In a 1922 letter to Rudolf Hallo, Rosenzweig expresses contempt and suspicion of Scholem, labeling
him a nihilist and an ascetic with Ressentiment and rejecting Scholems Zionism (Lazier 189-
90).
27
Harold Bloom also considered himself a Jewish Gnostic (Spirer 4). Scholems reading seems to
me to account much better [for] the whole nightmare of Jewish history than the normative Jewish
religion can possibly do, Bloom states (5). For Bloom, Scholem represented an alternative to the
normative tradition in Judaism, Cohens sort of Judaism (Spirir 4; Bloom, Scholem 220).
28
The joy of destruction is a creative joy, Landauer writes, quoting Bakunin (Revolution 160).
29
According to Hegel, the Jews were part of the Oriental world and thus stagnant and incapable
of producing world-historical subjects (Avineri 52). Hegel held that the Jews had initiated the
break between East and West, and that their involvement in world history had ended with this
act (Kouvelakis 122). Naturally, this was a contention to which the Young Hegelians were forced
to respond. Moses Hess responded by arguing that through going into exile, the Hebrews had in
fact become capable of being intermediaries between the East and West (Avineri 53). Their
mobilitytheir exilewas evidence that the Jews could be makers of history and were not part of
the apparently unchanging, non-historical Oriental world (53). In his early work The European
Triarchy (1841), Hess argued that messianism was the Jews chief contribution to world history
(25, 6970). Jewish messianismcharacterized by restlessness, lack of rootedness and stability, and
dissatisfaction with the world in its present statewas actually the engine of world history (70). This
conception of messianism seems to contrast sharply with Hess later advocacy for the establishment
of a Jewish state in Palestine.
30
This classification of Ernst Bloch and Georg Lukcs is a satisfying one for a number of reasons,
although it runs the risk of confusing the reader into thinking either that the two thinkers were
theologians by professional discipline or that they were simply obscurantists, neither of which is the
case. I am adopting this terminology of theologians of the revolution from Richard Wolin and will
return to this terminology again shortly (Wolin, Labyrinths 45).
31
The question whether objective truth can be attributed to human thinking is not a question of theory
but is a practical question. Man must prove the truth, i.e., the reality and power, the this-sidedness
[Diesseitigkeit] of his thinking, in practice (Theses on Feuerbach 1).
32
This is partly on the basis of her famous statement that if the Gospel omitted all mention of Christs
Resurrection, faith would be easier for me. The Cross by itself suffices me (Johnston 4).
33
In a section on Klages in Heritage of Our Times, Bloch argues, contra the proto-fascist yearning for
return to the primordial, that it would be impossible to return to the beginning of time, because one
cannot find an original human being to tell us what that state was like. (Marx makes a very similar
argument in the 1844 Paris Manuscriptsimagining a world prior to human beings involves one in
a contradiction, Marx argued [Early Writings 166].) Continuing, Bloch asks: But did this original
human being, this untreated new wine ever exist? And even if he should have existed, is there a
110
WEIMAR GERMANY, PROPHETIC TO APOCALYPTIC
living witness to the fact anywhere to be found, is there a way back to this unknown Adam anywhere
to be found? (Heritage of Our Times 304).
34
Eros and Civilization is sometimes contrasted with One-Dimensional Man as the optimistic book to
which One-Dimensional Man can be counter-posed as pessimistic (Farr 77). There is some truth in
the claim that Eros and Civilization is a more optimistic work than One-Dimensional Man, certainly
in the sense that Eros and Civilization very clearly expresses the possibility of revolution and of
sloughing off excess repression through liberation of the drives and instincts. Fromm thought the
book possessed a sort of childlike naivet, a claim that may be compatible with my assessment.
However, as this section will make clear, Eros and Civilization has affinities with the pessimistic
ideology of decline that could be found in Weimar Germany. Marcuses turn to Eros as a source
of liberation from Zivilisation should be revisited in the context of Ludwig Klages and the George
Circle.
35
Another reference to this prior time in One-Dimensional Man is Marcuses allusion to the
controversies of Vienna journalism during and after the First World War, a reference to Karl Kraus
(196).
36
There may also be a connection here to the fascination in some despairing German Jewish left
circles, after the crushed socialist uprisings of 1919, with the history of the seventeenth century
heretical Sabbatean sect and its doctrine of redemption through sin, mentioned above, according
to which the messianic age would be brought about through violation of social norms or of certain
elements of religious law.
37
Fromms use of authentic revolutionaries here harks back to his distinction between the true
revolutionary and the illusory revolutionary, the mere rebel, mentioned above in the section on
Gustav Landauer.
111
PART II
The next two chapters explore Erich Fromms interconnected concepts of hope and
messianism, terms that Fromm appropriates from disputes among German-Jewish
intellectuals of his time. He frequently couples his discussion of hope with the theme
of messianism. The opening of The Revolution of Hope provides Fromms most
thorough discussion of hope, including a three-part negative definition and a more
restricted positive definition. You Shall Be as Gods follows a discussion of false
Messiahs throughout Jewish history with a section of the book entitled The Paradox
of Hope.
Fromm distinguishes two conflicting types of messianism: prophetic
messianism and catastrophic messianism, both of which are viewpoints on
political struggle. He sees prophetic messianism as hopeful and progressive,
motivating the Old Testament prophets denunciations of injustice and the radicalism
of the Enlightenment and Marxism, and catastrophic messianism as despairing and
regressive. Catastrophic messianism awaits a messianic event that will follow a
catastrophic situation, into which some force or individual from outside of history
will intervene to save a corrupted humanity from itself. Prophetic messianism views
the messianic event as the outcome of historical progress and united human effort.
Fromms support for prophetic messianism and opposition to catastrophic
messianism served as a challenge to certain predominant political perspectives on the
left, including within the Frankfurt School. Within Critical Theory, Walter Benjamin
and Herbert Marcuse advocated a messianism more rooted in the catastrophic than
the prophetic. Although the following chapters focus on Fromms conceptions
of hope and messianism, they also indicate how Fromms messianism challenged
other prevailing conceptions of messianism, including those of other members of
the Frankfurt School. The differing implications and consequences of the prophetic
and catastrophic outlooks, I argue, demonstrate that Fromms prophetic messianism
is more useful to political praxis than catastrophic messianism.
113
CHAPTER 3
Hope is central to Erich Fromms prophetic messianism. Far beyond simply inspiring
people to work for the messianic age, hope, properly defined, offers an account of
the relationship between the present and the future and of the implications of that
relationship for social change. Furthermore, hope is the chief proof that Fromm
offers for the attainability of the messianic age: it is only from the standpoint of
hope that the possibility of the messianic age becomes visible. Hope stems not from
a scientific conclusion but from an act of faith. Holding in tension a confident faith
in the future with the urgent need for action, hope is paradoxical. Although hope
is not based upon empirical calculations of probability, according to Fromm, it is
ultimately the most realistic approach to political problems, because it expresses
something central to human life itself and reveals the potential latent in the present.
This chapter focuses upon Fromms definition of hope and his philosophical
justification for hope. The chapter begins by addressing Fromms negative definition
of hopethe three things hope is notfollowed by his intentionally terse positive
definition of hope. A careful explication of Fromms The Revolution of Hope:
Towards a Humanized Technology (1968) forms the substance of the definitional
work. Following this definitional work, I discuss the philosophical basis for hope in
Fromms thought, beginning with his more moderate, early account of hope grounded
on a distinction between existential dichotomies and historical contradictions,
and then addressing the more radical account of hope he developed later, in the
1960s. Throughout Fromms career, his defense of hope is grounded upon humanism.
Hope springs from faith in human nature and in the future; it is not a conclusion
inferred from empirical data. Drawing on Gabriel Marcel, who may have influenced
Fromms work on hope, I then distinguish between the philosophical justification
for hope and the phenomenological experience of hope. Hope is not experienced as
an object of the will but rather as the only possible response to human suffering, or
sometimes as a gift from something beyond the self. The standpoint of hope provides
access to truths not accessible without first adopting the position of hope.
At first approach to the topic, one might propose to define hope simply as a desire
or wish for something combined with the expectation of obtaining it. This definition
seems to accord with the way that hope is often spoken of in ordinary discourse
(e.g., I hope I remembered to roll up the car windows before it started to rain.).
115
CHAPTER 3
116
WHAT HOPE ISNT AND IS
There are three reasons that hope cannot be mere desiring or wishing (although Fromm
does not list them but discusses them together): (A.) hope requires expectation,
which is closely linked to Fromms idea of faith (paradoxical certainty), (B.)
hope is active, and (C.) only some objects of desire can serve as objects of hope.
(A.) Fromm uses the term faith to describe the expectation of the achievement
of hopes object. Faith for Fromm is not propositional, and it is not a scientific
hypothesis concerning future events. Rather, it is a paradoxical certainty regarding
the future achievement of the desired object. Desire can exist without such faith.
Fromm employs the term faith to describe much more than what is usually associated
with specifically religious faith. Not surprisingly considering his warnings against
idolatry,1 Fromms definition of faith is mainly negative and avoids linking faith to
any slogan or formula that could become an idol. (Even his account of religious
experience he denotes with a mere X, too cautious to assign it a name [YSB 58].)
Fromm consciously limits his discussion of faith, writing, Can one say more about
the practice of faith? Someone else might; if I were a poet or a preacher, I might
try. But since I am not either of these, I cannot even try to say more (AL 128).
However, Fromm does offer us the following rather limited definition of faith:
[Hope] is closely linked with another element of the structure of life: faith.
Faith is not a weak form of belief or knowledge; it is not faith in this or that;
faith is the conviction about the not yet proven, the knowledge of the real
possibility, the awareness of pregnancy. Faith is rational when it refers to the
knowledge of the real yet unborn; it is based on the faculty of knowledge and
comprehension, which penetrates the surface and sees the kernel. Faith, like
hope, is not prediction of the future; it is the vision of the present in a state of
pregnancy. (ROH 13, italics Fromms)
While not propositional, faith is both knowledge and vision; it beholds the seeds
of potential planted in the present.
That hope requires faith suggests that the object of hope must be attainable and
that the person who hopes must know that it is attainable. One may certainly desire
the unattainable, or daydream about various odd things that would be nicethe
ability to fly like an eagle or swim like an octopusbut desire or dreaming are
not a sufficient condition for the attainment of what one desires. Yet even when
one desires something that is both attainable and worthwhilefor example, if one
desires to end global starvationone is not hopeful if one does not believe that the
object of ones desire is attainable. If one simply gives upWell, the problem of
global starvation can never be solved, because too much power rests in the hands of
global corporations and banksthen one lacks hope, even if one simultaneously
agrees that, for example, It would be desirable to end global starvation. I wish that
we could.
117
CHAPTER 3
(B.) A second reason that hope cannot be mere desiring or wishing is that hope
requires activeness aimed at bringing about its object. In fact, the activeness of
hope is the reason why Fromm is wary of associating hope with waiting, as we
shall see in the following section (Hope is not passivity or inactivity). For now
it suffices to note that the person who desires or wishes may in fact be completely
inactive, and whether a person takes action on behalf of her desires has much more
to do with whether she is hopeful than with the strength of her desires. One only has
to consider the example of unrequited love for it to be quite evident that strong desire
can coexist with inactivity and the absence of hope.
(C.) A final reason that hope cannot be reduced to mere desiring or wishing
concerns the content of hope. Unlike mere desiring or wishing, which can have
any object, hope is not indifferent to content. One reason has already been offered:
if hope requires expectation (paradoxical certainty, faith), then it follows that the
object of hope must be seen as attainable. (For example, one must believe that it is
possible to end global starvation in order to be hopeful about doing so.) Nor is it
sufficient for hope if a person erroneously believes, with great strength of conviction
but ignoring all the evidence to the contrary, that an unattainable object is attainable.
There must be at least some possibility (even if the probability is low) of actually
achieving the object of hope. The grieving mother who witnessed her childs death
yet retreats into denial, insisting that the child has not died and can still be saved,
is not thereby hopeful when she arms herself and sets out fearlessly to rescue her
already-dead child from its attackers. As will become apparent in later sections of
this chapter (on forcing the Messiah and grounds for hope), although hope is
not based upon a scientific calculation of probable outcomes, hope must maintain a
degree of contact with present reality. Far from being a nave, dreamy optimism that
turns its eyes away from the harsh reality of human failure, hope looks reality in the
face and beholds it with greater accuracy than the cynical despair that claims to be
wise to the ways of the world. Hope, not cynicism, is the true realism for Fromm.
Objects of hope are humanly achievable.
The content of hope must be specified further: even achievable objects of desire
are not necessarily objects of hope. Some achievable objects of desire contradict the
nature of hope (e.g., a desire for the destruction of the human race) or are simply
too trivial to be objects of hope (e.g., a desire for an iPhone). In the former case,
the desire for the destruction of humanity is not hopeful because hope is always
connected with love of life. In fact, as we shall see, Fromm holds that all living things
are at least unconsciously hopeful, while he identifies hopes opposite, despair, with
hatred of life. The reasons why Fromm connects hope with life will be explored
subsequently, in the section on Fromms positive definition of hope. In the latter case
(the desire for an iPhone), Fromm rejects consumerist desires as contrary to hope
because, despite the fact that it involves being busy, consumerism is passive, while
hope is fundamentally active. The enthusiastic consumer of commodities wants to
drink in the world rather than transform it. She misconceives supreme happiness
or heaven as a world in which one may consume anything that one wants, rather
118
WHAT HOPE ISNT AND IS
than the experience of creativity and of being in relationship with others (Mike
Wallace Interview).
Although hope can be expressed in ordinary, everyday activities, according to
Fromm, hope is directed towards a goal that is central to human life, not to just any
particular, everyday goal. A particularly useful example of this can be drawn from
existentialist philosopher Gabriel Marcel, who offers a similar account of the proper
content of hope in his essay Sketch of a Phenomenology and a Metaphysic of Hope
in Homo Viator. According to Marcel as well as Fromm, hope is not indifferent to
content (Marcel 29). For example, Marcel suggests that only a diluted kind of
hope is expressed in the statement, I hope that James will arrive in time for lunch
to-morrow and not just in the afternoon. Even if I should like to have James with
me for as long as possible, and I have reason to think that what I want will come
about: I know that he does not intend to return to his office and could therefore catch
an early train, etc., this is not hope in the highest sense of the term. Hope is more
than just a wish and a certain belief (the conventional definition of hope, which
both Fromm and Marcel contest) (29). Hope can have as its object only that which
must be, by its very nature, the object of hope. Such necessity does not adhere to
the desire for Jamess arrival. Whether or not one desires Jamess punctual arrival is
contingent on various factors. If one needed some extra time to clean up the kitchen,
for example, or if one knew that James is just the sort of person who is always late,
then one would not hope for him to arrive on time. The case of James arriving
early or late differs, however, from the hope for salvation or the hope for liberation
from a state of fundamental captivity. While it makes equal sense to hope that
James arrive late or on time, it does not make sense to hope that one will not be saved
or that one will not be liberated. Marcel writes:
The I hope in all its strength is directed towards salvation. It really is
a matter of my coming out of a darkness in which I am at present plunged,
and which may be the darkness of illness, of separation, exile or slavery. It is
obviously impossible in such cases to separate the I hope from a certain type
of situation of which it is really a part. Hope is situated within the framework
of the trial, not only corresponding to it, but constituting our beings veritable
response. (30)
Hope comes into the darkness of human suffering to offer the light of another
possibility.
Although Fromm might disagree that hope must always be a response to acute
sufferingin fact, Marcel qualifies this claim later in the essay, linking hope to
the fundamental human desires to create and to love, a connection Fromm also
drawsFromm would agree with Marcel that hopes object must be central to the
human condition, not a contingent desire, such as a desire for James to arrive early
or late (Marcel 57-8, 66). (If one wishes to push the example, of course, one can
imagine a situation in which James arriving on time to lunch would be at the very
center of ones hopeif, for example, James will arrive bearing with him a letter
119
CHAPTER 3
of pardon from the governor, sparing my sister from her imminent execution for a
crime of which she is innocent and I am guilty. However, Marcel means to point to
a boring, everyday wish: lunch is usually a pretty mundane affair.) Later, we will
see that Fromm links hope to life (as does Marcel, incidentally) and even goes so
far as to equate hopelessness with death; hope is so fundamental a component of
human experience that despair (hopes opposite) stands in opposition to human life
itself (67).
A large portion of Fromms definition of hope has now been articulated in the
process of explaining why hope cannot be mere desire or wish. We have established
that, according to Fromm, hope must be coupled with faith, the object of hope must
be attainable, and the object of hope can neither be trivial nor contradictory to life
itself. However, even the confident expectation of the future attainment of some lofty
object of desire (fuller life, liberation, salvation, revolution) is insufficient
for hope, according to Fromm, if this confident expectation does not lead to action.
The claim that hope is active (or, more precisely, the claim that hope is not inactive)
is one of the three central components of Fromms negative definition of hope, and
as such, it requires a lengthier explication.
The second part of Fromms three-part negative definition of hope is that hope is
not passive, inactive waiting (ROH 6). True hope actively seeks to bring its goals
into reality (6). Although hopes activeness need not be frantically busyin fact,
it might not even look active to those who imagine activity as frantic consumption
or paid laborhopes orientation towards the world is one of involvement and
transformation. Through its alliance with activity, hope expresses something
fundamental to human nature. Fromms socialist humanism seeks to liberate
humanity for a fuller, freer expression of activeness. In contrast to Herbert Marcuses
charge that Fromm was advancing the performance principle of capitalist society,
I argue that Fromms understanding of hopes activeness is a radical challenge to
capitalist profit-making efficiency.
Passive waiting, by contrast with true, active hope, can become a cover for
resignation, mere ideology, or even idolatry of history or progress, in which
history and progress become gods to which humans submit rather than realities that
they actively shape (ROH 6). (Here Fromm references Marxs adage, History is
nothing and does nothing. It is man who is and does [8].) As mentioned in Chapter
1, according to Fromms account, ideology and idolatry render living things dead
and easily administrable, but in the process, ideology and idolatry become purely
cerebral and renounce affective ties to the ends they seek. The cold, scientific
prediction of a coming international revolution in Soviet ideology was detached
from any actual hope of building an international socialist movement. If one accepts
historical determinism, one need only wait passively for history to do its work.
This passive waiting is antithetical to hope, according to Fromm.
120
WHAT HOPE ISNT AND IS
Passive hope is dangerous. Even when the hoped-for event presents itself as a
very real possibilitywhen, one might say, the revolution is imminentthe person
who has cultivated a false, passive form of hope may, like the man in Kafkas parable
of the gatekeeper in The Trial, be unable to seize the opportunity and take action
(ROH 6-7). In Kafkas parable, the main character seeks entrance into the Law,
the object of his hope, but instead of entering the gate by simply shoving aside the
gatekeeper, he spends his life submitting to his bureaucratic commands and waiting
to be allowed in, until at last he is too old and tired to disobey the gatekeepers
orders, to fight him if necessary, and to obtain entrance. Similarly, Fromm offers
this tale:
[A] man, trapped in a fire, stands at the window of his room and shouts for
help, forgetting entirely that no one can hear him and that he could still escape
by the staircase which will also be aflame in a few minutes. He shouts because
he wants to be savedand yet it will end in complete catastrophe. (EF 175)
This example is from Fromms first published book, on the psychological allure of
fascism to those seeking to submit to leaders (Escape from Freedom). The person
who has the ability to rescue herself may not do so if her attention is fixed upon
the expectation of a salvation that will come from outside, from external forces or
authorities.
Although Fromm states that hope requires activeness, he is quick to clarify
that not all activities qualify as the activeness he advocates. The contemporary
consumerist trend-follower, for example, as she busily fills her shopping cart, is not
hopeful. While people in our society often appear to be busy, that does not mean
that they practice activeness. He writes,
Our whole culture is geared to activityactivity in the sense of being busy,
and being busy in the sense of busyness (the busyness necessary for business).
In fact, most people are so active that they cannot stand doing nothing; they
even transform their leisure time into another form of activity. (ROH 12)2
Thus, although hope cannot be passive and inactive, hope need not look frantically
busy either, like the harried shopper.
Nor must activeness be miserable toil. Here is where Fromm is able to respond
to Marcuses performance principle critique. Indeed, the truly active person,
in Fromms sense of the term, despises exploitation and would be useless to many
employers. In Man for Himself (1947), he explains that true productivity or activeness,
which is central to human nature, can run up against a societys established division
of labor:
The statement that productiveness is an intrinsic human faculty contradicts the
idea that man is lazy by nature and that he has to be forced to be active. This
assumption is an old one. When Moses asked Pharaoh to let the Jewish people
go so that they might serve God in the desert, his answer was: You are lazy,
121
CHAPTER 3
nothing but lazy. To Pharaoh, slave labor means doing things; worshipping
God means laziness. The same idea was adopted by all those who wanted to
profit from the activity of others and had no use for productiveness, which they
could not exploit. (MFH 106)
Here Fromm suggests that his concept of activity or productiveness is one that
inherently makes exploitation impossible. One imagines how useless, from the
point of view of the employer, a factory worker becomes, if a new-found love of
contemplation leads her to become less focused upon her work. Similarly, Fromms
thought on the radicalism of the Jewish Sabbath ritual emphasizes that the Jewish
Sabbath is a time of activity despite its appearance of calm. Giving people a day
off from work every week hardly seems advantageous for a capitalist who wishes
to exploit workers to the fullest possible extent, and as long as there is a reserve
army of the unemployed, one can easily find new workers when the old ones wear
out through overwork. (The modern first-world weekend was a product of workers
agitation, not of the capitalist quest for efficiency.) Yet even if the Sabbath appears
as laziness or inefficiency to the employer, it is not experienced by the practitioner
as a time of passivity.
Fromms point is that activeness flourishes in a state of human freedom. This is
in contradistinction with Herbert Marcuses later claim, in the epilogue to Eros and
Civilization, that Fromms concept of productivity contributed to the performance
principle of capitalist society (Eros and Civilization 242, 259). According to Marcuse,
Fromms conception of human nature was not explosive of the current order but
rather encouraged adjustment, by not challenging the values of capitalist society.
A point that Marcuse glosses over in this discussion, however, is that pre-capitalist
ideas can take on radical implications within a capitalist system. By employing pre-
capitalist concepts, Fromm presents the inadequacies and contingency of capitalist
arrangements.
In claiming that human beings are naturally productive, Fromm is not admonishing
the working class to keep its nose to the grindstone. Rather, he emphasizes that
leisure time (which socialist humanists like Fromm hope to increase) need not be a
time of mere recuperation from the strain of labor, as it so often is. Under capitalism,
Marx argues in his early writings, leisure becomes a time for satisfaction only of
our most brutish, least human needs (eating, drinking, and procreating), while our
uniquely human activities are stunted by alienation (MCM 82). Although Fromms
debate with Marcuse in Dissent magazine and in the pages of Eros and Civilization
and The Art of Loving preceded Fromms later study of Marxs 1844 Manuscripts,
Fromm would at least have known Marxs famous remark in The German Ideology.
There, envisioning a future in which human flourishing would be its own end (to
paraphrase the Grundrisse) and in which abundant leisure time would be filled
with a multitude of activities, Marx wrote of a coming society in which it would be
possible for me to do one thing today and another tomorrow, to hunt in the morning,
fish in the afternoon, rear cattle in the evening, criticise after dinner, just as I have a
mind (MCM 34).
122
WHAT HOPE ISNT AND IS
123
CHAPTER 3
it happen, this is only partly the case. Recall that hope retains contact with reality
and does not desire the impossible. Hope is impatient in the sense that it does not
postpone action out of the belief that human action is unnecessary. But hope is also
patient, in the sense that it is always tempered by the limits presented by reality.
To force the Messiah is essentially to fail to acknowledge reality and to try to
institute the messianic age (the object of hope) before it is possible to do so.
According to Fromm, hope is a paradoxical combination of patience and
impatience. The impatience of hope pushes the hopeful to act and presents the
situation as urgent, yet hopes patience ensures that hope remains in harmony with
reason and does not attempt to force the impossible. Following this same theme,
Fromm refers to two conflicting trends within the socialist movementa tendency to
(impatiently) believe that the new Socialist society, a new age for humankind, will
be achieved now (or has already been achieved) and a tendency towards endless
patience based on a scientific [prediction] of how things had to be (PN 74-5).
According to Fromm, both of these currents were mistaken. The proper standpoint
(a dialectical synthesis of the two) could be found in the Messianic paradox, by
which I mean patient and impatient at the same time (75).
In one of Fromms essays on psychoanalytic practice, he compellingly
describes the tension between hopes patience and impatience in a discussion of
the psychoanalysts hope for the cure of a client. There he calls hope a kind of
patience-impatience, a concept drawn from Talmudic literature (Fromm, Being
Centrally 11). To be a human being, he argues, is to be constituted by paradox,
which includes the paradox of being a fundamentally unique individual while also
fundamentally lacking individuality and uniqueness, through being formed by and
influenced by society (10-11). With regard to time, he then states, the proper human
attitude is also one of paradoxthat of patience-impatience (11). In the case of
the psychoanalyst, this means that the recognition that the patient could wake up
and become psychologically liberated at any moment must be held in tension with
the knowledge that it will probably take many years for the patient to achieve this.
This two-sided approach to the patient enables the psychoanalyst to avoid despair
when the patient is not cured quickly but also keeps open the possibility of change
in the patient, rather than blocking it through conveying to the patient a sense that
the cure is impossible or will be long delayed (11). Fromm is acutely aware that the
concept of patience-impatience in the Talmudic tradition concerned the proper
attitude towards the coming of the Messiah. According to Jewish tradition, one must
be prepared every moment for the coming of the Messiah, but one also knows that
it may happen now or in thousands of years (11).
Although it is an exhortation to a certain kind of patience, the prohibition of
forcing the Messiah is not, in Fromms view, an admonition to be submissive to
divine authority. Jewish tradition is in favor of forcefully confronting God, as Fromm
points out. He even references a Hasidic tale that illustrates a narrow sense in which
it is permissible to force the Messiah: A man informs a rabbi that he had bargained
with God that if God would forgive him for his own, minor sins, he would in turn
124
WHAT HOPE ISNT AND IS
forgive God, whom, he charges, [has] separated mothers from children and permitted
people to starve (YSB 152; PR 47). The rabbi responds that the man was foolish to
demand so little and should instead have forced God to send the Messiah (PR 48).
Fromm clearly likes this story; it illustrates the non-authoritarian religious attitude that
he prefers to the authoritarian one. He sees the heart of the Jewish tradition as anti-
authoritarian, which he frequently contrasts with the authoritarianism of Lutheranism
and Calvinism. According to Fromm, the story of the Hasidic rabbi demonstrates that,
If God fails to put an end to the suffering of man as he has promised, man has the
right to challenge him, in fact to force him to fulfill his promise (48). Here forcing
God to send the Messiah means something like commanding or being pushy with
God, not issuing elliptical, gnostic or occult predictions, nor instigating catastrophes
that would pressure the populace to change quicklypractices that are among the
chief targets of Fromms critique of forcing the Messiah. Although God is generally
considered sufficiently powerful to resist human commands, far from smiting pushy
people, God does not seem to mind being commanded. The Old Testament is full
of prophets who argue with God and speak to God in a demanding way, as Fromm
was definitely well aware. It is not necessarily irreverent to call God out on Gods
failure to intervene in the world to stop injustice. A demanding prayer made to God is
quite different from claiming gnosis about Gods coming, claiming that the Messiah
has already arrived, when in fact it has notif one looks about, it should be evident
that a world of justice and peace has yet to be attainedor attempting to force God to
send the Messiah through nihilistic action.
The concept of forcing the Messiah plays a multitude of roles in Fromms
thought, as a critique of fascism, Zionism, Stalinism, the psychoanalytic movement,
and some 1960s first-world revolutionists. Forcing the Messiah was the attitude of
the false Messiahs and the Putsch leaders, who had contempt for those who did not
under all circumstances prefer death to defeat, Fromm writes (ROH 8). This is a
political critique on Fromms part, no doubt including a critique of fascisms attempt
to make leaders and nations into Messiahs, as the reference to the Beer Hall Putsch
clearly implies. More interestingly, the critique of forcing the Messiah applied
also to left politics, including Soviet Communisms attempts to make leaders or
the Party into Messiahs and its claim to have created real, existing socialism (a
false/idolatrous image of the messianic age, in Fromms sense of idolatry). (It is
not surprising that the Soviet Union was referred to by Cold Warriors as the God
that failed.) It was also a critique of certain anarchist or Blanquist strategies of
small-group sabotage, i.e., trying to force revolutionary change without building a
movement and winning the support and involvement of the masses. Furthermore,
Fromm employed the critique of forcing the Messiah as a critique of Zionism, as
we shall see, and even of Freuds psychoanalytic movement in Sigmund Freuds
Mission, which stresses Freuds peculiarly authoritarian pleasure in molding his
students into loyal followers and discusses his creation of a quasi-political, secretive
psychoanalytic International at the head of which he was to be a kind of Messiah-
figure, a new Moses.
125
CHAPTER 3
Why would Fromm employ such an archaic concept as forcing the Messiah
to critique contemporary political and social movements? The answer begins with
Fromms adamant opposition to Gershom Scholems catastrophic messianism, along
with Scholems peculiar fascination with the enigmatic seventeenth century false
Messiah Sabbatai Zevi. In Fromms radical interpretation of the Old Testament,
You Shall Be as Gods, he offers a brief history of some messianic figures in Jewish
history, from Bar Kochba in the second century to Jacob Frank in the eighteenth
(YSB 143, 147). Among those he discusses is Zevi, the subject of Scholems famous
biography. Scholem and others celebrated the Sabbatean (Zevis) movements
doctrine of redemption through sin, i.e., that in order to save humanity, Zevi had to
descend to the lowest level of human life through infidelity to his faith. The doctrine
of redemption through sin was popularized in the 1910s and 1920s, as the German
Jewish left gradually shifted its allegiance from the ideals of Aufklrung to the new,
apocalyptic vision of a transcendent intervention into history. Since this change
was perceived to be a product of extra-human, extra-mundane forces, redemption
through sin held appeal as a metaphor for the coming revolutionary upheaval. The
dream was that one could force the messianic age to arrive through antinomian
practices, i.e., through dramatic disruption of established societyas seen in the
thought of Gershom Scholem, Walter Benjamin, and Ernst Bloch in his more
apocalyptic momentsor through the ritualistic violation of social norms as seen
in Stefan George and Ludwig Klagess Cosmic Circle. In Chapter 2, we noted how
such practices became characteristic of the new messianic radicalism that abandoned
Cohens messianic radicalism in favor of apocalypticism.
Fromms You Shall Be as Gods is largely a response to Gershom Scholem,
though not explicitly. As we saw in Chapter 1, Fromm saw both Scholem and
Zevi as exemplars of a catastrophic messianism, so it would not be surprising if
Fromms critique of Zevi and forcing the Messiah were also a critique of Scholem.
You Shall Be as Gods is in large part an argument for the legitimacy of prophetic
messianism against the view of Scholem and others that Jewish messianism is
fundamentally apocalyptic and catastrophic. Several pages are devoted merely to
refuting Scholems claim that Hasidism (which Fromm likes) was not messianic.
And although Fromm does not say so in You Shall Be as Gods, he would certainly
have known that Scholem had published his massive, definitive biography of Zevi
several years earlier. In Fromms mind, Scholems insistence upon catastrophic
messianism would have been seen as an endorsement of forcing the Messiah and
of the doctrine of redemption through sin, since catastrophic messianism left only
nihilistic antinomianism as a course of rebellious action.
Fromms critique of forcing the Messiah was no doubt also an adamant
denunciation of the Messiah-figures of the lost generation, from Stefan George to
Oskar Goldberg, Rudolf Steiner to Martin Heidegger, and of their admiring, often
uncritical followers. The catastrophic/apocalyptic exaltation of Messiah-figures
penetrated political theory and eventually, at the hands of Nazi legal theorist Carl
Schmitt, was employed as an endorsement of Hitlers rule. In the absence of the
126
WHAT HOPE ISNT AND IS
Against the passive hope of those confronting the end of the world, Taubes
emphasized in 1947 the need for an immediate decision: the time for a Buberian
veiled choice had passed. Taubes had in mind a Schmittian operation from
within the destructive situation: it involved using and abusing destruction as
a tool, acknowledging its inevitability. The apocalypse, he argued, entailed a
form-destroying and a forming power...If the demonic, destructive element is
missing, the petrified order, the prevailing positivity of the world cannot be
overcome. (Lebovic, The Jerusalem School 106-7)
The influence of apocalyptic messianism on Israeli politics would not have been lost
on Fromm. Beginning in the late 1920s, Fromm considered Zionism an abandonment
of Jewish principles and an attempt to force the Messiah, a nationalist movement
with a false, idolatrous image of the messianic age. By 1966, when he was writing
You Shall Be as Gods, the early, anarchist-utopian ideals of the Zionist movement
played a minimal role in guiding Israeli politics. In a sympathetic, almost pleading
tone, Fromm writes, even one of the greatest humanists among the sages, [Rabbi]
Akiba, could not withstand the seduction of the false hope (YSB 153). He wrote
this knowing that he was writing for close friends like Ernst Simon, then in Israel,
trying to convince them to redirect their political efforts and change their allegiance
(Funk, Life and Ideas 39; Lundgren).
Fromms critique of forcing the Messiah was also a warning to the left in the
United States and Europe, where he worried about the rise of a destructive left-wing
nihilism. Fromm suggests that, in the context of politics, the hopelessness that
leads to forcing the Messiah is characterized by phrase making and adventurism
and disregard for reality (ROH 8). He writes that such hopelessness is rapidly
becoming characteristic of his time (8).
In a 1968 note for the Eugene McCarthy presidential campaign, possibly intended
as a campaign speech, Fromm warned of what he called the Maoist alternative in
the U.S. left:3
This [Maoist] alternative proceeds from the premise that the system is moving
towards catastrophe, and that no reform of any kind can change this course.
The only chance for avoiding the catastrophe is a change of the system itself,
and this change can occur only through revolution on an international scale,
127
CHAPTER 3
meaning that when all the underdeveloped countries turn against the industrial
countries, and particularly their leaderthe United Statesthey will be able
to overthrow the system, just as the Chinese peasants overthrew their rulers in
the cities. (OBH 53)
What Fromm objects to is not the proposal for international revolution but the
pathologically self-destructive and nihilistic desire of the young Maoists,
including their desire that their own country (implicitly, themselves) be destroyed by
revolutionists from the outside. Their aim was not really to create a more just society
but to see their own society obliterated in an act of gloriously destructive, aesthetic,
cosmic justice. As we saw in Chapter 2, the exaltation of the aesthetics of violence,
so frequently identified with fascism, appears also in thinkers identified with the left,
including Walter Benjamin, Gershom Scholem, and Georges Sorel.
Not long after the publication of The Revolution of Hope, groups such as the
Weather Underground in the United States and the RAF/Baader-Meinhof in Germany
arose, attempting to force a revolution without building a mass movement. The
Baader-Meinhofs explicit goal was to reveal the truly destructive, fascistic power
of the state by forcing the state to employ violence against them. In 1976 Fromm
turned down an invitation to testify for the defense in the trial against the Baader-
Meinhof in Germany, and in To Have or To Be?, published that same year, he was
critical of such terroristic impulses (TB 62, 85).
At the request of their lawyers, Jean-Paul Sartre had agreed to meet with the
Baader-Meinhof in prison. He denounced the conditions of their imprisonment and
portrayed them as martyrs, giving a quick boost to their public image. However,
the lawyers still needed the support of a public figure like Fromm, whose German
Jewish background and psychoanalytic training made him a prime candidate for
a persuasive expert witness for the defense in the trial of the Baader-Meinhof
(Fedderson). Knowing that his appearance as witness for the Baader-Meinhof could
be taken as an endorsement of their tactics, Fromm brusquely declined (Fedderson).
He wrote in reply to the lawyers:
I very much appreciate your wishthat is, the wish of the accusedto meet
with you and Frau X. But I must confess that I am rather astonished that the
accused wish to have this meeting, since they must know my work. I would have
thought that my political beliefs would be repellent to them, the same way theirs
are to me. To put it bluntly, I am completely against your strategy and tactics,
which I view as totally repulsiveboth politically and humanly. (Vickrey 1)
128
WHAT HOPE ISNT AND IS
It is often the case that people who have lost the capacity to love replace
this inability with the thought of sacrificing their own life, and then take this
self-sacrifice as some kind of proof that they can indeed love. In some cases
terror is the only escape from a completely hopeless and desperate situation.
(Vickrey 1-2)
Fromms analysis appears to be borne out by Meinhofs suicide and the subsequent
suicides of the other leaders of the organization (2).
In The Revolution of Hope, Fromm had written, foreshadowing his later concern
with the RAFs desperation and destructiveness:
In these days, this pseudo-radical disguise of hopelessness and nihilism is not
rare among some of the most dedicated members of the young generation. They
are appealing in their boldness and dedication but they become unconvincing
by their lack of realism, sense of strategy, and, in some, by lack of love for life.
(ROH 8)
The desperate, nihilistic side of the left critiqued by Fromm failed to account for
reality; they despaired in many cases because they expected the world to accord
too quickly with their vision for it, without taking the necessary steps between the
present and the future. According to Fromm in The Revolution of Hope, Herbert
Marcuse had fallen prey to a similarly reality-disregarding, false-messianic hope,
adding in a footnote after the above passage, Such hopelessness shines through
Herbert Marcuses Eros and Civilization and One-Dimensional Man (8). He then
quotes from Marcuses conclusion to One-Dimensional Man:
The critical theory of society possesses no concepts which could bridge the gap
between the present and its future; holding no promise and showing no success,
it remains negative. Thus it wants to remain loyal to those who, without hope,
have given and give their life to the Great Refusal.
Fromm replies to this passage:
These quotations show how wrong those are who attack or admire Marcuse
as a revolutionary leader; for revolution was never based on hopelessness, nor
can it ever be. But Marcuse is not even concerned with politics; for if one is not
concerned with steps between the present and the future, one does not deal with
politics, radical or otherwise. Marcuse is essentially an example of an alienated
intellectual, who presents his personal despair as a theory of radicalism
This is not the place to show in detail that it is a nave, cerebral daydream,
essentially irrational, unrealistic, and lacking love of life. (ROH 8-9)
Despite Fromms uncharitable tone, these statements are more than a mere ad
hominem jab. Fromms Revolution of Hope is largely a reply to Marcuses One-
Dimensional Man, even though Marcuse is only discussed in a footnote. Revolution
of Hope was initially to include a full chapter on Marcuse, but as Fromm explained
129
CHAPTER 3
in a letter to Raya Dunayevskaya, he removed the chapter because he did not want to
focus negative attention on Marcuse, because during the summer of 1968 Marcuse
had been receiving death threats (Anderson and Rockwell 158, 165n.48).
As a psychoanalyst and social psychologist, Fromm attempted to diagnose
pathologies that he observed in society at large, especially in certain sectors of the
left. There is some important truth in the claim that the attempt to force what cannot
be forced had become prevalent on the left at the time (the late 60s), and there
certainly was a climate of despair and a lack of life-lovingness in the air, which was
manifested not only in the behavior of organizations but in the psychological states
of individuals. Moreover, Fromm held that Marcuses Great Refusal was unrealistic
as a revolutionary strategy, lacking hope due to its expectation of a revolution that
would be fundamentally explosive and an apocalyptic end to time, coming from
outside the mainstream social order, not a process of planning, emerging from a mass
movement. More will follow about this in Chapter 4, however, where I distinguish
Fromms concept of messianism from the prevailing view of radical, messianic
thinkers of his time, and I will contrast Marcuses understanding of the relationship
between the present and future with Fromms.
It is a bit too simplistic to say that Marcuse rejects hope; he merely draws hope
from different sources. However, the variation between his sources and Fromms
sources indicates a crucial difference between the two thinkers conceptions of
hope. These sources, in Marcuse at that time, were largely aesthetic and libidinal.
(Memory also served as a source of hope for the messianic age in Marcuses work
[e.g., One-Dimensional Man 98; Eros and Civilization 232-3].) Fromms concern
about the nihilism of Marcuse4 and some of the New Left is related to Fromms
other major criticism of Marcuse, that Marcuses thought encourages psychological
regression to the state of the satiated baby. The lack of alternatives that Marcuse
finds in the present leads him to seek return to a Golden Age of the past, not a Golden
Age of early human history or pre-history but within each individual lifetime, an
early childhood Golden Age from which surplus repression was absent. Fromm sees
Marcuses Great Refusal as a mere rebellion, not revolutionary, and as a vision of
mere freedom from (from rules, restrictions, repression) as opposed to freedom
to (TB 62).5
To grasp the implications of Fromms citation of the conclusion from One-
Dimensional Man, it must be further noted that Marcuses book technically concludes
not with Marcuses own words, but with a quote from Walter Benjamin: It is only
for the sake of those without hope that hope is given to us (257).6 Although Fromm
does not mention Benjamin or include the quote in his footnote about Marcuse,
it is likely that Benjamin was also a chief target of the critique. There may have
been personal reasons why Fromm never mentions Benjamin in any of his published
writings, despite the fact that Benjamins messianism stands in sharp contrast with
his own: Fromms second wife, Henny Gurland, was among the last people to see
Benjamin alive on his final journey through Spain. However, Benjamin was also not
widely read in the United States at that time, in comparison with Marcuse.
130
WHAT HOPE ISNT AND IS
131
CHAPTER 3
himself into the arms of a powerful authority (the Church, or a political party,
or a leader) to regain his faith. Often he overcomes his despair at having lost
faith in life by a frantic pursuit of worldly aimsmoney, power, or prestige.
(HOM 29-30)
The shattering of hope can be so painful as to cause the individual to seek escape from
the world and from consciousness. This occurrence is further elaborated in Fromms
account of the three mechanisms of escape, which he describes in Escape from
Freedom: sadomasochism, destructiveness (usually combined with narcissism),
and conformity (AHD 233; EF). Sadomasochism enables the individual to escape
his unbearable feeling of aloneness and powerlessness and to escape freedom
through symbiosis with the other (EF 173). Destructiveness is also founded upon
the desire to overcome separateness, yet it seeks to annihilate its object rather than
maintain it as dominator or dominated (202). The individual defends herself through
destructiveness when she feels threatened or her potentialities are thwarted, for
example by societal norms (204). Destructiveness in particular may result from the
shattering of hope:
Precisely because men cannot live without hope, the one whose hope has been
utterly destroyed hates life. Since he cannot create life, he wants to destroy it,
which is only a little less of a miraclebut much more easy to accomplish. He
wants to avenge himself for his unlived life and he does it by throwing himself
into total destructiveness so that it matters little whether he destroys others or
is destroyed. (ROH 21)
The third escape, automaton conformity, seeks to overcome isolation through
withdrawal from the world or through inflation of oneself psychologically to
such an extent that the outside world becomes small by comparison (EF 208).7 In
the struggle to get beyond these traps, one requires not only a negative understanding
of what hope is not, but also a positive understanding of what hope is.
132
WHAT HOPE ISNT AND IS
133
CHAPTER 3
who was censured by the Vatican), these thinkers believed that there was something
at the heart of reality, beyond all data and beyond all calculations (to paraphrase
Marcel), that coincided with the good will of humanity. For these thinkers, as for
Lukcs, Spinozas natura naturans was simultaneously a human and a divine and/or
natural process, and human beings had the power to consciously direct it.
For Aristotle, Bergson, and Teilhard, hope was embedded into the structure of
human life and was constitutive of the human person. One could even argue that
there is such an implicit hope in Spinoza, for whom Fromm writes so much in praise.
Although Spinoza warned against the emotion of hope when this meant an emotional
attachment to something beyond what reason could know with certainty, Fromm
may have seen himself as the heir of a tradition that saw the universe in Spinozist
terms as a process of becoming (or naturing, naturans), a process of which human
beings can become conscious and which they can then direct to their own ends, and
it is this consciousness of reality-in-process that is so central to Fromms conception
of hope. In German idealism, one finds a similar commitment to this unfolding, most
notably in Hegels conception of Geist but also in Fichtes emphasis upon striving
and conscious activity (Ttigkeit). Thus the hope expressed in the natural world, as
articulated above, is present also in the realm of social life.
Hopes connection to faith is tied to hopes connection with life. As discussed
earlier, Fromm defines faith as a kind of knowledge and as a paradoxical certainty
concerning the future attainment of the object of hope. Hope and faith go hand in
hand, according to Fromm, and each is an intrinsic element of the structure of
life (ROH 13). Faith, like hope, also has an unconscious component; this can be
disastrous, as in the case of ideology, in which a persons malignant faith is concealed
beneath an outward appearance of another faith that really has no meaning for the
person but which is simply a set of slogans or platitudes. But true faith, for Fromm,
is not mere ideology; rather, true faith reflects reality and does not allow itself to
be overpowered by propaganda. True faith is not faith in what is scientifically
predictable (e.g., the Stalinists confidence in the coming revolution), nor in what is
impossible (e.g., the melancholics conviction that her lost loved one will return).
Rather, building upon the distinction between activity and passivity in Spinoza,
Fromm asserts that faith is active and creative; it does not passively absorb the
beliefs of authority figures or mass society (14).
Fromm also links fortitude (courage), a Spinozist concept, to hope (ROH 14).
Negatively defined, fortitudes fearlessness stems neither from a desire to die (only
a disguised fear of life), nor from having a leader to obey (which is only a disguised
fear of disobedience). Fromm would agree with Aristotle that blind acceptance of
all risk without proper precaution is not true courage. Positively defined, fortitude
is the capacity to say no when the world wants to hear yes (15). It is the the
courage of love that arises in its fullest form from enlightenment, from seeing the
whole in process and ones place within it (AL 8; ROH 15).
Paradoxically, Fromm says more about hope by saying what it is not than by
saying what it is. All the same, his discussion of the connection between hope and the
134
WHAT HOPE ISNT AND IS
In addition to Fromms positive and negative definitions of hope, along with the
individual and sociopolitical consequences of hope, the question remains: upon what
foundation does hope rest? There are at least two senses in which one may speak of
the foundation of hope; one might mean the philosophical justification for hope, or
one might mean the cause of the individuals hope. Although there is some overlap
between philosophical reasons and individual motivations for hope, the two must not
be equated. In this section, I focus upon Fromms philosophical justification for hope,
chiefly his optimistic theory of human nature and his account of faith as a basis for
hope. I trace the development of Fromms philosophical justification for hope from
his earlier work on human nature to his later emphasis on messianic hope, under the
influence of Marxs early writings. After exploring Fromms account of human nature
and faith as bases for hope, I conclude the chapter by arguing that the philosophical
rationale for hope is quite different from the cause of hope in an individual, i.e., from
the basis of hope as experienced, phenomenologically, by the hopeful subject. (I
draw heavily from Gabriel Marcel to articulate this distinction.) Although hope can
be rationally justified, the subject who hopes does not do so for reasons, but just the
reverseshe beholds the reasons for hope only because she already hopes.
Fromm called his philosophy socialist humanism, and he was firmly committed
to grounding his philosophical views upon a conception of human nature. According
to Fromm, the socialist movementwas radical and humanistic, radical in the
sense of going to the roots, and the roots being man; humanistic in the sense that it
is man who is the measure of all things, and his full unfolding must be the criterion
of all social efforts (Funk, Courage 206). Unlike Soviet Marxism and other left
paradigms that have grown popular since, such as Louis Althussers structuralism
and Michel Foucaults post-structuralism, Fromms Marxism held that society should
be grounded upon an understanding of human nature, human needs, and the good
life. Lawrence Wilde, a leading scholarly defender of Fromms socialist humanism,
argues that Fromm is unique among social scientists of the late twentieth century
in offering a thoroughly worked-out and well-defended view of human essence as a
philosophical grounding for an appeal to solidarity (Quest for Solidarity 4).
One might say that Fromms major contribution to psychoanalysis was his
attempt to offer an account of psychological health, as opposed to merely diagnosing
pathologies. This also points to what may be his chief contribution to Critical
135
CHAPTER 3
Theory: his commitment to not merely critiquing bourgeois society but presenting
alternatives, and not merely describing pathologies but to providing an account of
psychological (social) health. While other members of the Frankfurt School tended
to confine their work to critiques of existing social conditions, Fromms messianism
offered a positive goal for which to strive: the sane individual (the productive
character) and the sane society.
As a Marxist and as a psychoanalyst, Fromm acknowledged that people are
influenced by socio-economic structures, biological drives, and other environmental
factors, including the accidental characteristics of childhood home life. These
influences are beyond ones control yet profoundly shape ones personality, beliefs,
and way of life. However, Fromm did not believe that individuals were wholly
determined by socio-economic, biological, and environmental forces. The individual
stands in a complex matrix composed of her individual character structure, on the
one hand (for example, her personal tendency to hoard possessions, or her tendency
to make many acquaintances but few close friends) and the universal human
condition on the other.8 The individuals character structure and the universal human
condition constantly influence one another, yet they are nevertheless differentiable.
The human condition is further subdivided into an unchanging and unalterable
human nature and aspects of human life that can be changed in the course of history.
Fromm agreed with Marxs statement in Capital that there are two elements to
human nature, human nature in general and human nature as modified in each
historical epoch (MCM 23).
In addition to the individual character structure, human nature, and the influence
of socio-economic structures, biological drives, and other environmental influences,
Fromm acknowledged a limited possibility for human free will. According to
Fromm, some people have free will and others do not; free will is a function of a
persons character structure (HOM 131). While average people have the ability to
choose, in individual situations, for good or for evil, or for progress or for regression,
some people have character structures that are so exemplary (insert favorite saint-
like person here) or so pathological (insert favorite crazed serial killer here) as to
make this impossible.
Two philosophical foundations for hope In his relatively early book Man for
Himself: An Inquiry into the Psychology of Ethics (1947), Fromm gives his most
thorough account of his theory of human nature. There are some slight modifications
to this theory of human nature in Fromms later work, chiefly a greater degree of
hope for resolving certain fundamental tensions within human experience, which
I will address. I will begin by offering a summary of his account of human nature
in Man for Himself, before addressing his move towards messianic hope and faith.
Although references to messianism can be found in earlier works, Fromms more
serious thought on messianism seems to have come after Man for Himself, in the
1950s through 1970s, beginning with The Sane Society (1955). In order to determine
whether the messianic age is achievable or whether one should hope for it, one
136
WHAT HOPE ISNT AND IS
must understand the foundation upon which hope for its attainment rests: Fromms
conception of human nature. One should bear in mind, however, that one does not
first determine whether the messianic age is achievable before beginning to hope for
it. Whether one is philosophically justified in hoping has very little to do with ones
actual reasons for hoping, as I explain in the final section of this chapter.
In Man for Himself, Fromm states that human beings are differentiated from non-
human animals by a host of factors: humans comparatively diminished instincts
in relation to animals, humans ability to transform their environments rather than
merely adapting to them, their capacity to remember the past, to visualize the
future, and to denote objects and acts by symbols, their use of reason in seeking
to understand the world, and their imagination through which they [reach] far
beyond the range of [their] senses (MFH 39). It is human nature to seek to know
and to be interested in the world (ROH 81). Here he also states that human reason
is not just a blessing but also a curse: it burdens the individual with boredom,
discontentment, and a feeling of having been evicted from paradise due to the
alienation she feels from nature (MFH 40-1).
Also central to human nature, for Fromm, is the desire to be productive or
active. Productiveness resolves the paradox of the human beings struggles for
unity and independence. Further, productiveness is the root of love (MFH 96-7).
According to Fromm, love is not a passion but an activity, and love is not a feeling
but a state of being, brought about through effort, through laboring for what one
loves (99-100). To explain what he means by productiveness or activity, Fromm
draws upon Aristotle and Spinoza, both of whom he takes to be saying that activity
is the actualization of human potentialities towards the fulfillment of human beings
unique function (25-6, 92). (He does not yet employ Marx in Man for Himself
to make the case that human beings are by nature productive. In his later work,
especially after reading Marxs 1844 Manuscripts and studying his idea of species-
being (Gattungswesen), Fromm draws more heavily upon Marxs conception of
human nature.)
According to Fromm in Man for Himself, every human being stands in relation
to humanity and to nature in a complex relation of being both part and whole,
both immanent and transcendent. Although an individual, each is simultaneously a
representative of the whole and bears the whole of humanity within him or herself
(MFH 38). (Fromm seems to see this as a possible foundation for solidarity or
love, since one can see the possibilities for all human behavior within oneself.) In
addition to being caught in a strange relation of being both part and whole in relation
to humanity, the human being is caught in a relation of unity and difference with
regard to nature, since she sees herself as being a part of nature and, simultaneously,
transcending it (40).
Much of the problem of human existence depends, for Fromm, upon the tension
between autonomy and relatedness in the human beings relation to other humans
and to nature. In Man for Himself, this contradiction of autonomy and relatedness
is presented as irresolvable, yet his later works suggest hope for a resolution of this
137
CHAPTER 3
138
WHAT HOPE ISNT AND IS
Fromm does not seem to have done anything more with the distinction
between existential dichotomies and historical contradictions in his later
works.9 It is not clear why. It is possible that he realized that the distinction
was murkier than he initially thought. However, his intervening work on Marxs
early writings probably helped him to move away from this distinction and
towards a greater emphasis upon messianic hope. Marx himself expressed hopes
that existential dichotomies could be overcome through this-worldly action,
writing in his 1844 Manuscripts that communism would be the solution to the
riddle of history, the resolution of the antagonism between man and nature,
and between man and manthe true solution of the conflict between existence
and essence, between objectification and self-affirmation, between freedom and
necessity, between individual and species, a total redemption of humanity,
and the resurrection of nature (Early Writings 155, 58, 157; Marxs italics). At
least in these early writings, Marx expresses (in rather messianic language) hope
that even existential dichotomies can be resolved.
Along with the growing importance of messianic hope in Fromms thought
after Man for Himself, there is a related shift in Fromms concept of faith.
In Man for Himself, Fromm had drawn a distinction between rational and
irrational faith, a distinction he preserves throughout his later work. Irrational
faith is the belief in a person, idea, or symbol which does not result from ones
own experience of thought or feeling, but which is based on ones emotional
submission to irrational authority, while rational faith, by contrast, is a firm
conviction based on productive intellectual and emotional activity (MFH 201,
204). Fromm maintained this basic distinction, never conflating the person of
true faith with the authoritarian personality. Yet while in Fromms 1947 work
true, rational faith coincided with the acceptance of existential dichotomies and
the rejection of any belief in the absurd, Fromms conception of faith takes a
paradoxical turn in his later work (203). In his later work The Revolution of
Hope, Fromm sees faith as a paradoxical certainty that something uncertain
will occur (ROH 14). It is a confidence that human beings will create a better
future, despite the knowledge that progress is not inevitable. Faith still maintains
the connection to rationality and activity that Fromm stresses in Man for Himself,
yet the basis of faith for Fromm now seems to be something more than strong
belief in a logical conclusion of an argument, which seems to have qualified as
faith for Fromm in 1947.
Fromms new articulation of faith as paradoxical and his new commitment to
messianic hope marked an opening from the narrower hope of Man for Himself.
Whereas his earlier work on human nature had urged people to confront historical
contradictions while accepting existential dichotomies, his new approach suggested
that both could be overcome, through radical hope and faith in human potential. A
particular dimension of this radical, messianic hope and faith must be addressed.
An account of human nature alone is insufficient to ground messianic hope for the
resolution of both existential dichotomies and historical contradictions.
139
CHAPTER 3
Hope for the messianic age in the absence of probability of success Even if
humans by their nature are capable of great good and of rising above the chains of
necessity, are there grounds to hope that they will ever actually bring a messianic age
to fruition? This question must be asked, because Fromm does not see the messianic
age as a mere regulative ideal but as a pragmatically achievable goal. At first blush,
the question certainly seems hard to answer in the affirmative, considering that time
and again throughout history, human beings have failed to live up to their potential
and have mired themselves in war and injustice of every kind.
In his social context, Fromm could find few empirical grounds for hope in
the achievement of his (awake, not dreaming) utopian aims (Wilde, Quest for
Solidarity 4). He witnessed in his lifetime the failure of the Soviet experiment and
its devolution into mechanized, bureaucratic state capitalism, two catastrophic
world wars, the Holocaust, nuclear annihilation in Japan, the arms race, and the rapid
growth of U.S. economic and political dominance, coupled with an ever-widening
gap worldwide between rich and poor, powerful and powerless. In the time of his
youth before World War One, many expected to see a successful Marxist revolution
in Germany, yet due to the events that followed, Fromm lived most of his life unsure
if the human race would even consent to its own survival.
Fromm nevertheless sought to find seeds of hope within the present and to hold
out hope for the resurrection of the prophetic-messianic movement after the near-
deadly blows dealt it by the collapse of the Second International. He had no illusions
about the probability for success; in fact, he estimated (more to drive home his point
than as any kind of scientific calculation) that the odds of humanity surviving and
progressing towards greater solidarity were about 2% (TB 160). What mattered
to Fromm, however, was not the probability, but the existence of even a remote
possibility for the messianic age. He wrote,
Indeed, it is part of the probability that the improbable happens, as
Aristotle put it. The question is, to use a Hegelian term, of a real possibility.
Possible here means not an abstract possibility, a logical possibility, a
possibility based on premises which do not exist. A real possibility means
that there are psychological, economic, social, and cultural factors that can be
demonstratedif not their quantity, at least their existenceas the basis for
the possibility of change. (ROH 142)
He believed that such possibility could be found through an honest assessment of
human nature, which he saw as neither wholly good nor wholly evil.10 Clinging to
the hope that human potential could be realized was the only solution to the problems
of his time.
Fromm was an activist, and as such he valued programs for action. He suggested
a number of programs for political action himself, including his pamphlet Let
Man Prevail: A Socialist Manifesto and Program, written for the Socialist Party
of America (SP-SDF). His The Sane Society concluded with a call for worker
cooperatives. His The Revolution of Hope concluded with a call for people to form
140
WHAT HOPE ISNT AND IS
clubs to discuss creating a more hopeful society and included a mail-in clip-out
page for those who wanted to sign up to join the clubs. His May Man Prevail?
included recommendations for ending the nuclear arms race. His To Have or To Be?
concluded with a call for leftists to unite with others in a campaign against the spread
of consumerism and overly seductive techniques in advertising.
As an activist, Fromm was a defender of humanistic planning; he firmly
believed that the future achievement of the messianic age would depend upon prior
planning and productive action by many people, not upon mere destructiveness or
the coup-like actions of small groups of leaders playing Messiah (ROH 95). Fromms
own proposed programs for action include some insightful recommendations but
may sometimes also seem impractical, despite his great effort to make practical
recommendations. But Fromms prophetic messianism is not grounded on any
particular program for action. It is grounded on a commitment to the development
of programs for action: through reason, dialogue, planning, solidarity or love, and
productive creativity. Prophetic messianism asserts hope in the face of hopelessness,
clinging to even the smallest indication of possibilities for societal change. Clinging
to a paradoxical, active, and rational hope is the only ethical and psychologically
healthy course of action in a world that stands on the brink of catastrophe.
141
CHAPTER 3
subject. This choice of terms is not accidental. Like Georg Lukcs, Marcel believes
that the position of subjectivity reveals truths denied to the detached observer. The
subject understands the whole (including the observer), in a way that the detached
observer cannot. (Fromm certainly agrees with Marcel and Lukcs that access to the
truth requires not an unbiased and uninvolved viewpoint but active and committed
engagement with the world.11) The committed, hopeful subject, according to Marcel,
has reached a state of understanding in which the question, Are there sufficient
reasons to hope? is no longer relevant or even coherent. Marcel explains:
[I]f the subject hopes, it would surely seem that the reasons for hoping are
sufficient for him, whatever the observer may think about them.
But in reality the question which the subject is supposed to ask himself [Are the
grounds for my hope sufficient?]does not arise for him unless he detaches
himself in some degree from his hope. Actually, it comes from a different
register and springs from a calculating factor of reason which, with the very
approximate means at its disposal, proceeds to carry out a regular balancing up
of chances. Without any doubt it may happen that, upon consideration, hope
gives in for a variable space of time to those calculations of the reason; above
all if the subject is engaged in a discussion with someone whom he wants to
convince: It is none the less true, however, that hope and the calculating faculty
of reason are essentially distinct and that everything will be lost if we combine
them. (64-5)
The point of this richly insightful passage can be clarified through focusing on the
case of a hopeful political activist who is engaged in a Frommian project of trying
to build the messianic age. Let us examine whether such an activist would be able to
explain the reasons and justifications for her hope to a disengaged observer and what
would happen when she attempts to offer such an explanation.
Let us assume that the activist (the subject) is being asked by a non-activist (the
observer), Does activism work? Is there reason to hope that society can be changed
to accord with your vision of it? If the observer merely means to ask about the
effectiveness of some particular course of action, such as mass demonstrations,
and is not objecting to activism in toto, then the subject will find the question
unobjectionable. (Activists themselves constantly discuss questions of strategy and
tactics, seeking effective means to their desired ends.) But when the question at
hand is really, Why try to change society? What if you cant succeed? the question
seems very odd to the subject.
Upon discovering that the world is deeply mired in systemic injustice, many
people immediately feel obligated to act. Shocked by the worlds problems and
by the hypocritical discrepancy between the cheerful picture of the world painted
by ideology and the harsh reality of the exploitation and oppression that ideology
defends and covers over, many people suddenly find themselves asking (rather than
choosing to ask), What should I do? They do not first ask, Should I do something?
142
WHAT HOPE ISNT AND IS
They immediately ask, What should I do? They do not so much choose to ask the
question as experience the question happening to them. I remember, for example,
a discussion with a fellow student at my alma mater as an undergraduate. She was
planning to go to medical school and was taking a philosophy course focusing on the
atomic bomb during her last year of undergraduate coursework. Suddenly horrified
by the reality of nuclear weapons, she questioned whether she could pursue a career
as a wealthy and satisfied physician or whether her life might have to take some
other course. The question was experienced by her almost as an external attack. I
wish I didnt know this, she explained to the professor, but now that I do, I feel
like I have to do something. Hope often springs from such an experience, from the
knowledge that there simply must be some solution to the horrors of the present,
since I am compelled to act in opposition to these horrors. It is therefore unsurprising
that hope has traditionally been considered one of the three theological virtues
(along with faith and love), a product not of ordinary, freely willed human action,
but of divine grace. Hope is not experienced as the result of ones own choice but
as something that shakes up the placidity of experience, while helping the subject
to cope with the burden of a new-found responsibility. If predisposed to do so, the
subject may interpret this gift in theistic terms, as a special divine grace.12
Because hope is something that happens to the subject, the subject does not know
how to reply when the observer asks, Why do you hope? If one believes that the
world is broken and that one has an obligation to assist in its repair if possiblea
belief that the observer often claims to havethen not acting due to doubt about
ones effectiveness seems irrational. All the same, the subject may be caught off
guard by the observers question and may begin to offer empirical examples that
demonstrate that well-intentioned people who stand up for what they believe in
can make a difference in society and that history has not been wholly a history of
failures. She makes a brief foray into calculative reason, as Marcel would put it,
bracketing her hope in order to defend it: Gandhis salt march she begins to
say. The Montgomery bus boycott But deep down, she is puzzled by her own
reply, since the observers question strikes her as somehow incoherent. She would
rather ask the interlocutor simply, Why do you ask? She herself did not choose to
act on the basis of stories about the effectiveness of other peoples action but simply
because it seemed imperative upon her to involve herselfat least to try to succeed
in the struggle, even if she were to fail.
The disconnect between the observer and subject is made more acute by the fact
that, in a certain sense, the subject is already in the messianic age. The messianic age
has always been already but not yet. In the objective sense, of course, the subject
is plainly not in the messianic age; she looks around and sees all the same horrors
as the observer. Yet she has faith, a vision of the pregnancy of the present. Because
she has decided to work for the coming of the messianic age, she looks around for
tools to use for that purpose, and the only material available to her is found in the
present. She is forced to look for potential within the present if she does not wish to
relinquish her hope. The subject thus has had a glimpse of the messianic age, which
143
CHAPTER 3
now presents itself to her as a goal towards which she can move, that is, towards
which she can orient all her activity. It becomes real to her through her practical
interaction with it. The observers questionWhy are you doing this? How do
you know whether it will get you there?strikes the subject as odd, because in a
way the subject is already there, and she knows it, at least unconsciously. What is
present to her as a goal remains a mere abstract idea to the observer. The subject will
continue forward until she reaches the goal or gets as close to it as she can, while the
observer has not yet brought herself into relationship with that goal.
The subject can also understand the observers true situation in a way that the
observer cannot. To the subject, it looks as though the observer is simply standing
around, wanting to get there, waiting and wishing and desiring, but not moving.
(And they look at me like Im unrealistic and a nave dreamer! the subject exclaims
in exasperation.) To the subject, the observer is like the man Fromm describes in
Escape from Freedom who waits at the window of a burning building, shouting for
help and wanting to be rescued, desiring to be saved, when all he has to do is turn
around and take the stairs out of the building in order to escape the fire (EF 175).
NOTES
1
Fromm links idolatry and ideology. Ideology involves the profession of a religious belief that is not
ones true religious belief (TB 138). Ideology arises through an individuals or a societys attempt
to deceive both itself and others about the real motivations for its actions and beliefs (MMP 122).
Nevertheless, one is not fully conscious of holding an ideology. For example, Fromm points out,
although by 1961 the Soviet Union had become relatively isolationist, millions of Americans believed
that a Soviet attack was imminent and could be prevented only through the threat of mutually assured
destruction.
According to Fromm, the belief in such an exaggerated Soviet threat could not be explained on the
mere basis of media disinformation or government propaganda; that is, the problem was not just that
U.S. citizens did not know certain empirical facts. Their pathological fear could only be adequately
accounted for through reference to the concept of ideology, through the widespread attempt of the
society to deceive itself. Further, Fromm states that although the majority of Americans professed
support for democracy, this did not entail that they would take action to defend it if it were threatened;
their professed support for democracy was a mere ideology (PR 61-2). Ideology coincides with the
deadening of beliefs that had once startled people out of indifference and which now produce purely
cerebral, alienated thought, instead of authentic experiences, and Fromm warns that this alienated,
unemotional, robotic thought is beginning to replace all authentic experience (MMP 122).
2
In a study of female college students at Sarah Lawrence College, Fromm found that most of
the students were terrified at the thought of spending several days sitting around reading classic
literature.
3
Fromm adds the disclaimer that he is referring to a trend in the United States, not to Mao or other
Chinese thinkers. It is not exactly clear which people or what group he is referring to here.
4
Fromm likens Marcuses philosophy to nihilism as early as their 1950s debate in Dissent magazine
(McLaughlin, Origin Myths 9). There Fromm charged that Marcuses nihilism left only the
options of martyrdom or insanity, suggested by Marcuses claims in Eros and Civilization that
curing the psychoanalytic patient would mean curing the patient to become a rebel or (which
is saying the same thing) a martyr and by Marcuses assertion of the tension between health
and knowledge (Ibid.; Eros and Civilization 258, 261). Fromm repeats the charge of Marcuses
nihilism in The Art of Loving and The Revolution of Hope (AL 131; ROH 8).
144
WHAT HOPE ISNT AND IS
5
Fromm develops the distinction between the revolutionary and the rebel in his essay What is a
Revolutionary? in The Dogma of Christ: And Other Essays on Religion, Psychology, and Culture.
6
The original source of this quote is the conclusion of Walter Benjamins essay Goethes Elective
Affinities (Benjamin 356). The quote also concluded a 1946 talk by Adorno critiquing Fromms
psychoanalysis, and the quote recurs in Adornos Negative Dialectics in a section arguing that reason
must defend the tradition of nihilism from attack (Jay, Dialectical Imagination 103, 105; Adorno 378).
7
In a sense, sadomasochism and destructiveness are less worrying than conformism. In the case
of sadomasochism or destructiveness, one is at least trying to relate to the other, either through a
power relationship or by annihilating the other, yet in the case of conformity one is not seeking
to relate to the other, even violently or submissively, but simply to avoid the reality of the other.
In Fichtean terms, conformism does not distinguish the I from the not-I; it beholds a single,
undifferentiated reality. The conformist does not even reach the beginning of Hegels account of
the struggle for recognition, i.e., of the dialectic of lordship and bondage. The individual seeking
pure destructiveness lies at the very beginning of that dialectic, where two self-consciousnesses
become aware of one another as self-conscious and enter into the struggle to the death to annihilate
the other and return to being the sole self-consciousness. Relationships of masochism and sadism
are only able to exist after that point, once the slave submits to the rule of the lord, establishing
a relationship of power and domination. But the conformist does not actively confront the
problem of living in a world of other self-conscious beings. Instead, the conformist sacrifices
her own self-consciousness in a sort of intellectual death, rather than attempting to preserve self-
consciousness in a perverted or incomplete form. If one could place the conformist at a level of
Hegels Phenomenology of Spirit, that level would probably occur in one of the sections preceding
that of Self Consciousness, such as that of Sense-Certainty or Perception.
8
Chapter 1 of Man for Himself is structured by this distinction and divided into two sections, The
Human Situation and Personality.
9
Of course, Fromm continues to speak dialectically in terms of historical contradictions. There is
also a reference to existential dichotomies in Fromms 1966 book You Shall Be as Gods, although
the switch in emphasis is apparent, since there Fromm presents the messianic age as the resolution
of existential dichotomies, although he does not explain how this is to occur beyond offering the
allegory of the fall that will be discussed in Chapter 4 (YSB 123).
10
This is the theme of the first chapter of The Heart of Man and the first section of War Within Man. He
argues that human nature is neither that of a vicious wolf nor a compliant sheep, but that humans
have the capacity to be either, or something better.
11
Truth for both Fromm and Marcel is experienced affectively, not purely cerebrally, and it is found
through an encounter with the whole, totality, or reality, not in fragments but in a viewpoint that
includes both the other and the self (Treanor 8, 11; SFM 7; MMP 122; TB 16; AL 29). For Marcel, a
higher level knowledge is gained through an encounter with mystery (as opposed to mere problems),
and a mystery poses a question that necessarily includes the subject who asks it (Treanor 8).
Similarly, for Fromm, the courage of love brings one into contact with a reality that is in process, not
fixed and dead. For both Marcel and Fromm, the attitude of love for the other leads one to reject an
understanding that seeks to dissect an object in order to understand it; Fromm is particularly worried
by the attempt to manipulate or force human beings to reveal the secret of the human mystery (the
attitude of the torturer) rather than to understand by love and relationship (AL 29).
12
Thomas Merton challenged Fromm on whether the absence of a divine, transcendent being
in Fromms thought is problematic for his notion of hope. In an addendum to Fromms antiwar
pamphlet War Within Man, Merton associates hope with grace:
Still I would like to conclude on a note of hope. It is precisely because I believe, with
Abraham Heschel and a cloud of witnesses before him, that man is not alone, that I find
hope even in this most desperate situation. Man does not have to transcend himself in
the sense of pulling himself up by his own bootstraps. He has, rather, to respond to the
mysterious grace of a Spirit which is at once infinitely greater than his own and yet which,
at the same time, offers itself as the total plenitude of all Gift, to be in all reality his own
spirit (WW 50).
145
CHAPTER 3
Merton suggests Fromms messianic hope points beyond itself, indicating the need for a transcendent
deity. Whether or not this is the case, Mertons writings express quite well the experience of hope as
gift. Perhaps, like Lukcs standpoint of totality discussed in Chapter 2, Mertons thought can only
be understood from the inside, in this case from the standpoint of Mertons Catholic faith.
146
CHAPTER 4
147
CHAPTER 4
messianic view acknowledges that human beings really might fail to bring about the
messianic age. Although prophetic messianism involves a certainty based on inner
experience (a certainty grounded in hope, not in empirical proof), this certainty is
paradoxical and does not see the future fulfillment of its hopes as inevitable (YSB
156-7). Rather than a form of determinism, prophetic messianism is what Fromm
calls an alternativism. In The Revolution of Hope, Fromm contrasts the prophets
emphasis on alternatives with the determinists emphasis on prediction (ROH
18). Given free will, it is impossible to predict the future, but it is possible to be
aware of what is at stake and of the possibilities latent in the present.
Fromms alternativism posits that freedom of the will is neither unlimited nor
nonexistent. Rather, ones freedom of will is contingent upon making certain
fundamental choices correctly and upon the malleability of ones character and
ones awareness of the options and likely consequences of each choice (HOM
119; Application of Humanistic Psychoanalysis 243). Making certain choices
incorrectly may lead to lack of freedom later, while choosing correctly may lead to
the further expansion of ones freedom.
Fromm often states that the Hebrew prophets presented people with alternatives
and the likely consequences of each choice (e.g., Stop extorting widows or your city
will be destroyed.). Marx, Freud, and Spinoza were likewise alternativists, and
Rosa Luxemburg, as a prophet of socialism, presented a similar alternative when
she spoke of the need for humanity to choose between socialism or barbarism
(HOM 119; Application of Humanistic Psychoanalysis 243). Acutely aware of the
centrality of the question of socialism or barbarism for his time, Fromm writes:
[I]n contrast to the men of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries who had
an unfailing belief in the continuity of progress, we visualize the possibility
that, instead of progress, we may create barbarism or our total destruction.
The alternative of socialism or barbarism has become frighteningly real today,
when the forces working towards barbarism seem to be stronger than those
working against it. (BC 187)
Fromms warnings of the threat of nuclear annihilation also present a crucial
alternativedisarmament or deathwhich was coupled towards the end of his
life with an alternative between solving the ecological crisis and facing catastrophe
(HOM 141; TB 7). The prophet does not force the people to pick one alternative over
anotherthe people are free to choosebut each choice will carry certain inevitable
consequences; the choice of one side of the alternative limits freedom and progress,
while the choice of the other enhances freedom and progress. When faced with an
alternative in this sense, there must be only two choices, because the alternative
is fundamentally a choice for productivity or destructiveness, or, in similar terms,
for life or for death. Practical tactical considerations come later, after this basic
existential choice.
In the life of individuals, and therefore also in societies confronted with the
possibility of catastrophe or progress, alternativism rather than determinism or
148
FROMMS CONCEPTS OF PROPHETIC AND CATASTROPHIC MESSIANISM
absolute freedom is the rule (HOM 139). Fromm frequently speaks of pathological
character orientations as consequences of failed choices between alternatives.
For example, he considers the destructive character orientation (the focus of
Fromms psychoanalytic magnum opus, The Anatomy of Human Destructiveness) to
be the result of a choice against hope and in favor of destructiveness. Psychologically
speaking, destructiveness is the alternative to hope, just as attraction to death is the
alternative to the love of life, and just as joy is the alternative to boredom (ROH 22).
One does not necessarily have freedom of choice when confronted with the crucial
alternativeat any rate, the difficult and transformative choice may be so dramatic
in its break from the past and the future it initiates that it may be experienced almost
as a miraclebut ones freedom may increase or decrease as a result of the choice
(HOM 127-8, 138).
By rejecting determinism, of course, Fromm nuances the oft-oversimplified
Marxist account of base and superstructure. He writes,
If one speaks of inner lawfulness in individual and in social life, then there
is usually no unilinear causal chain of the type A causes B. This type of
determinism is usually false. One can, however, usually say: A can lead to one,
two, three or four choices, but only to these and no others. We can ascertain
and determine that only a certain few choices are possible under the given
conditions. Sometimes there are two, sometimes there are more. Without
wanting to [prophesy] anything, I believe that today there is essentially only
one choice for modern man and for the people of the earth in toto: the choice
between barbarism and a new renaissance of humanism. (OBH 29)
Fromms alternativist, non-determinist philosophy of history enables him to
ground messianic hope on a more stable foundation than mere empirical evidence
of the probability of success and the narrow conception of causality that would
be required to sustain a socialist determinism. Prophetic messianism is based
upon hope, which as shown in the previous chapter is based upon the slightest
possibility, not probability, of success. Prophetic messianism is not a scientific
conclusion about the likelihood of progress. Fromm holds that the world is teetering
on the brink of catastrophe, that humanity is at great risk of being thrown into a
state of barbarism, and that this is very likely to happen. Consequently, prophetic
messianism has to be based upon a choice, not upon an empirical probability or
certainty of success. Fromm compares prophetic messianism to a physician faced
with a patient whose condition seems difficult, possibly impossible, to cure, but
who nevertheless proceeds to offer care. If a sick person has even the barest
chance for survival, no responsible physician will say, Lets give up the effort, or
will use only palliatives; the physician will attempt to save the life of the patient
Certainly, a sick society cannot expect anything less (TB 160). Attempting to
avoid the collapse into barbarism is not merely optional for a moral or rational
person, who is morally and rationally mandated to fight such a decline if there is
the slightest chance of success.
149
CHAPTER 4
Fromm argues for a need to seek out empirical evidence of the attainability of
the future messianic age (TB 160). There is no need to hope for the impossible and
no way to rationally do so.3 Fortunately, however, Fromm does think that there is
available evidence for the possibility of the messianic age, as we noted in Chapter
3, evidence deeply rooted in human nature and life itself. The standpoint of hope
enables us to see the seeds of potential that are latent in the present.
In addition to being a distinction between alternativism and determinism, the
distinction between prophetic messianism and catastrophic messianism is a distinction
between two historical trajectories. According to Fromm, prophetic messianism
originated with the Hebrew prophets, as he outlines in You Shall Be as Gods, his
radical interpretation of the Old Testament. Following its origin in the prophets,
the prophetic-messianic idea re-entered history on numerous occasionsin certain
radical elements in early Christianity and the Middle Ages; in Renaissance humanist
thinkers; in Spinoza; in Enlightenment thinkers and French revolutionaries; in the
work of Lessing, Fichte, Hegel, and Goethe; in utopian socialists like Saint-Simon;
in Young Hegelians Moses Hess, Heinrich Heine, and Karl Marx; and in some early
socialist thinkers following Marx, including Rosa Luxemburg and Gustav Landauer
(MCM 54; OBH 144-5; SS 236). The socialist movement itself was, as Hermann
Cohen, Ernst Bloch, and a number of other scholars have stated during the past
decades[,]the secular expression of prophetic Messianism (TB 126).
Fromm believed that prophetic messianism was under threat in his times,
endangered by a catastrophic messianism that had dealt it near-deadly blows in the
twentieth century, through the capitulation of the Second International to nationalism
before the First World War and the crushing of the 1918-1919 German uprisings,
the degeneration of the Soviet experiment into bureaucratic state capitalism, the
rise of fascism, and the destructive psychological forces manifested by the nuclear
arms race (SS 239; MMP passim). Fromm later worried, as we have seen, about a
catastrophic messianism that he observed on the left in the 1960s.
In a 1961 speech Fromm expressed the same puzzlement about the First
World War:
Until the First World War, European humanity was ruled by its belief in the
fulfillment of these [prophetic/utopian] hopes and idealsI have spoken of
the birth process of new societies. I would almost like to say that twentieth-
century man seems to be a miscarriage. What has happened, so that everything
has seemed to break down at the moment when man appeared to stand at the
crowning pinnacle of his historical endeavors? (OBH 21)
Before World War I, there were already cultural tendencies in Europe celebrating the
creative potential of destruction and violence. Fromms prophetic messianism stands
in sharp contrast with this mentality, as well as other conceptions of messianism
prevalent in the Frankfurt School, most notably Walter Benjamins and also perhaps
Herbert Marcuses. Due to a dearth of Fromm scholarship, some characterizations
of the Frankfurt Schools messianism exclude Fromms prophetic messianism and
150
FROMMS CONCEPTS OF PROPHETIC AND CATASTROPHIC MESSIANISM
present the Frankfurt Schools messianism as wholly catastrophic. One finds this in
the work of Eduardo Mendieta and Anson Rabinbach (as we shall see), as well as
Michael Lwy and Richard Wolin, among others (Lwy, Jewish Messianism 106;
Wolin, Labyrinths 49-50). (Those who warn against this catastrophic messianism,
especially Richard Wolin, perform a particularly valuable service. All of these
thinkers have done important work exploring the complicated influence of Weimar
thought on the Frankfurt School and Marxism.)
It is an oft-repeated claim that World War II and the Holocaust were the chief
source of catastrophic messianism and of the skepticism concerning utopias, after
the catastrophe of the Holocaust caused some thinkers to reject speculations about
theodicy as unconscionable and to embrace difference as opposed to a unitary picture
of human progress. There is some truth in the idea that this shift occurred and that it
contributed to the rise of catastrophic messianism. Adorno famously asked whether
poetry or even life itself was possible after Auschwitz (see Can One Live after
Auschwitz?). Yet concerns about theodicy and utopia were already on the rise before
World War II, even on the left. In fact, catastrophic messianisms pessimism, in its
attempt to change the world through mere negation rather than building upon the
present, may have contributed to the rise of Nazism.4 Catastrophic messianism was
reflected to an extent in the attempt at total eradication, the drive for Lebensraum,
and widespread destructive impulses melded with a determinist fascination with
destiny and fate.
In Escape from Freedom (1941), Fromm quotes a Nazi ideologue and draws the
connection between catastrophic messianism and Nazism:
One of the ideological fathers of Nazism, Moeller van der Bruck, expressed
this feeling very clearly. He writes, The conservative believes rather in
catastrophe, in the powerlessness of man to avoid it, in its necessity, and in the
terrible disappointment of the seduced optimist. In Hitlers writing we shall
see more illustrations of the same spirit. (EF 194)
This insight is prefigured by Fromms earlier work, as we saw in the first chapter,
in his thinly veiled critique of his gnostic contemporaries in The Dogma of
Christ. Since many prominent thinkers with affinities with Nazism, including
Carl Schmitt, Martin Heidegger, and Oswald Spengler, adopted the catastrophic-
messianic yearning for transcendent intervention, it may be surprising that
catastrophic messianism remained prominent after World War II, and even on the
left. The survival of catastrophic messianism as a respectable academic and left
perspective after World War II seems possible only in light of the fact that many
thinkers, including Theodor Adorno, Karl Lwith, and even Heidegger5 suggested
that the catastrophe of World War II and the Holocaust had been the outcome not
of apocalyptic visions and catastrophic messianism but of humanism and reason (or
instrumentalized reason, which they did not always differentiate from reason as such
[Wolin, Seduction of Unreason 159]). The prophetic messianist would likely see
fascisms idolatry of leaders as one possible expression of catastrophic messianism,
151
CHAPTER 4
152
FROMMS CONCEPTS OF PROPHETIC AND CATASTROPHIC MESSIANISM
153
CHAPTER 4
1. Rupture
154
FROMMS CONCEPTS OF PROPHETIC AND CATASTROPHIC MESSIANISM
that a mere utopian vision or blueprint of the society that one wants to construct is
sufficient. As Fromm writes, One cannot construct submarines by reading Jules
Verne; one cannot construct a humanist society by reading the prophets (142).
Planning is slow, tedious, and entangled in specific considerations; it does not look
only at the final goal but looks also at the many and painful steps between the present
and the future.
Another way of saying that Fromms messianism avoids rupture is to say that it
rejects eschatology. Fromms messianism is a teleology, but it is not an eschatology.
Unlike eschatologies, which speak with certainty of events concerning an end to
time, teleologies are not necessarily determinist. Although for Fromm history has
a telos, in the sense of a proper aim or goal, humanity might not attain it. Fromms
philosophy of history is teleological in the sense that Aristotles anthropology
may be seen as teleological; although many do not attain eudaimonia, eudaimonia
remains the proper aim of human life. For Fromm, history might not reach its telos
humanity could retreat into barbarism, or simply destroy itselfbut the messianic
age is the proper aim of human history.
The idea of rupture is linked to a specifically eschatological messianism. The
telos of history for Fromm is not the end of time but if it is the end of anything, it is
the end only of history, or in Marxist terms, the end of prehistory. In fact, Fromm
thought that eschatology manifested a worrying pathology; he was attuned to
unconscious desires for the end of earthly human existence. He found abhorrent and
dangerous the view that one might be living in a divinely ordained eschatological
time of crisis, an end times. Like his forbear Hermann Cohen, Fromm was actively
anti-eschatological. Later in this chapter we return to this point, in the context of a
critique of Herbert Marcuse.
The second of Mendietas claims that needs to be addressed is the claim that Fromm
rejected a restorative messianism that seeks to return through anamnesis to a past
golden age. Although Fromm does reject restorative messianism, contra Mendieta
he also rejects mythical anamnesis and the yearning for return. Before proceeding,
however, we must carefully define and qualify three problematic terms that Mendieta
employs in this regard: restorative messianism, anamnesis, and golden age.
Following this initial definitional work, I then present the central allegory of Fromms
messianism (the disobedience of Adam and Eve), followed by an exploration of the
question of whether Fromms account of this myth is gnostic. Secondly, I address
the three interpretations of the allegory that would be legitimate from Fromms
standpoint: the allegory as representing the individuals birth and subsequent
psychological individuation, the rebelliousness of the bourgeois revolutions, or the
struggle against the temptation of fascism. Finally, I address Martin Jays worries
about melancholy, as evidence that Fromm has grasped a central concern in his
rejection of both restorative messianism and mythical anamnesis.
155
CHAPTER 4
156
FROMMS CONCEPTS OF PROPHETIC AND CATASTROPHIC MESSIANISM
157
CHAPTER 4
158
FROMMS CONCEPTS OF PROPHETIC AND CATASTROPHIC MESSIANISM
The coming messianic age will be a dialectical sublation of both the past Paradise
and the present of alienated individuation; it will incorporate elements of each and
simultaneously progress beyond both. Fromm writes, The messianic time is the time
when man will have been fully born. When man was expelled from Paradise he lost his
home; in the messianic time he will be at home againin the world (YSB 123). The
messianic future envisioned by Fromm is a dialectical synthesis of, on the one hand,
the primal oneness with nature and ones fellow humans experienced as the earliest
stage of human lifevariously characterized by Fromm as primitive communism,
matriarchy (following Bachofen), and allegorically as Paradise/Edenand the
individuality and autonomy of persons advanced by humanism and the Enlightenment.
Memory of humanitys early unity and non-alienation can be progressive, for Fromm,
and need not result in a reactionary attempt to flee from the pressures of the present.
One may conceive Fromm as standing somewhere between the two positions of Martin
Bubers renewal and Ernst Blochs Novum, rejecting both the traditionalist, utopian
socialism of Buber and Landauer, and the Total-Futurum of Bloch.
Since the messianic time is a dialectical synthesis of Paradise and humanitys
subsequent achievement of individuation, Fromms philosophy of history is
teleological, not cyclical. Although paradise is the golden age of the past and the
messianic time is the golden age of the future, these two states are quite different
(YSB 123). Fromms notion of history is not cyclical, the future is not simply a
return to the past, and the origin is only half of the goal. The pre-historic golden age
is defined by mans not yet having been born and the messianic age by mans
having been fully born (123-4). Before the rebellion in the garden, the person is
not even aware of being an individual (HOM 20). The coming messianic time is
something never before achieved in human history, representing progress beyond
both the past and the present. It sublates and fulfills all past history.
***
Is Fromms account Gnostic? I will return to this question at the end of the chapter,
but here I offer a preliminary response. The main problem here is that, for Fromm,
the serpent is right: through disobedience, human beings could become like gods. One
might worry that Fromm has made the serpent the hero of Genesis. Hans Jonas points out
that the Gnostics of early Christianity employed allegories that reversed the hierarchical
relations between good and evil; the reversal of these roles is supposed to demonstrate
a deeper knowledge (Jonas 92). Gnostic allegory creates a new mythology and
rebels against established myths (94). The positive interpretation of the role of the serpent
was a shining example of this and figured prominently in Gnostic thought, and, as Jonas
pointed out, some Gnostic cults even named themselves after the serpent (93). But the
hero of Fromms account is really not the serpent but Eve. It is Eve, the first woman,
who gives birth to civilization; Fromms feminism is apparent here: for Fromm, the
archetypical act of emancipatory disobedience, indeed, the act which forced human[s]
on the road to history, is one committed by a woman: Eve (Cheliotis 2).
159
CHAPTER 4
Is Fromm, then, standing in the tradition of Karl Kraus, Stefan George, and
Heinrich von Kleist? Is Fromm quoting Kleists allegory of sneaking into the locked
Paradise, or is he referring to something else entirely? (Kleist wrote: The gates
of Eden are barred against us and the angel drives us on. We must make a journey
round the world and see whether we can perhaps find another place to creep in at
(Kleist 85). Fromm wrote: two angels with fiery swords watch the entrance and
man cannot return (OBH 75).) Our interlocutor might argue that Fromm sees the
origin as the goal. Like Marcuse in his more Romantic moments, one might
argue, Fromm seeks to return to the primordial, to the pre-historic, to the infantile
state of innocence. In that state there is no knowledge of good or evil, and the act
of disobedience can be legitimately enacted and a new era begun. Sin does not
exist there, so redemption through what was sin would now be possiblehumanity
would boldly disobey, eating again from the tree of knowledge. Is Fromms praise
of Adam and Eves act of disobedience therefore a defense of Gnostic nihilism and
libertinism (in Hans Jonass parlance) (Jonas 270)?
A thorough examination of You Shall Be as Gods makes obvious which side
Fromm is on, although he occasionally draws from the insights of his opponents. It
becomes clear what side the book is on when Fromm writes, There is a dialectic
relationship between Paradise and the messianic time. Paradise is the golden age of
the past, as many legends in other cultures see it. The messianic time is the golden
age of the future (YSB 123). This highly significant statement is central to why
Fromms messianism is not, and cannot be conceived as, the restoration of a Golden
Age. Precisely because of this dialectic relationship, Fromms messianism avoids
the excesses of the return to the past found in Karl Kraus, Ludwig Klages, Stefan
George, Walter Benjamin, Herbert Marcuse, and others.
As seen in Chapter 1, Fromms early work on Bachofen condemned Ludwig
Klages as reactionary and denounced the rising cultural pessimism and the yearning
for return to a lost primordial world. Fromms Dogma of Christ also offered
a pointed and thinly veiled critique of the gnostics of his own day, presented
as a critique of ancient Christian Gnostics. There he wrote that second century
Christianity had abandoned its revolutionary roots and become revisionism (DC
75). Against this reformist Christianitywhich Fromm obviously intended to
represent reformist socialismthere were the options of Gnosticism and radical
Montanism. Montanism was truly radical, standing against the conforming
tendencies of Christianity and trying to restore the early Christian enthusiasm
(75). Then there was the Gnostic option: these members of the well-to-do Hellenistic
middle classwanted to accomplish too quickly and too suddenly what [they]
wished, since [they] announced the secret of the coming Christian development
before the consciousness of the masses could accept it (76). Despite attempting
to force change, Gnosticism rejected the real collective change and redemption of
humanity, and substituted an individual ideal of knowledge; Gnosticism endorsed
social hierarchies while dividing the world into initiates and completely fallen non-
initiates (77).
160
FROMMS CONCEPTS OF PROPHETIC AND CATASTROPHIC MESSIANISM
161
CHAPTER 4
162
FROMMS CONCEPTS OF PROPHETIC AND CATASTROPHIC MESSIANISM
revolutionary admirers. Fromms concern with the rise of Nazism is without doubt
a prevailing subtext in all of his warnings against the yearning for return to the past.
***
Fromms view that the messianic age would be a dialectical synthesis of the
prehistoric Paradise and the historic achievements of individuality and enlightenment
contrasts sharply with the restorative messianisms of the lost generation in Germany.
Karl Krauss line origin is the goal became the veritable slogan of a generation of
messianists, while the esoteric writer Oskar Goldberg pronounced a re-enchantment
of the world with his call for society to go back to cult (Rabinbach, Between
Enlightenment 84; Benjamin, Illuminations 253; Assmann, Assmann, and Hartwich
xx). The Cosmic Circles yearning for return to Bachofens prehistoric matriarchy
found little in modernity that it wanted to appropriate for its project of aristocratic
barbarism. But because Fromms future was a dialectical synthesis, not a mere
return and not a total other, Fromms messianism required no absolute rupture.
While initiating a major change in history, the messianic age did not require absolute
negation and could be envisioned and planned for to a certain extent. Wary of the
yearning for return among Georges circle and similar intellectual circles, Fromm
saw restorative-oriented anamnesis as fundamentally dangerous.
One aspect of the dangers of memory that Fromm does not address directly
needs to be dealt with here. Namely, some have suggested that a messianic future is
impossible, because any bright future would still be troubled by memories of past
injustice. Derrida, for example, has spoken of the way in which the past haunts the
present, and in this he follows in the footsteps of Walter Benjamins famous passage
about the Angel of History, which looks back over its shoulder at the wreckage
of progress:
A Klee painting named Angelus Novus shows an angel looking as though he
is about to move away from something he is fixedly contemplating. His eyes
are staring, his mouth is open, his wings are spread. This is how one pictures
the angel of history. His face is turned toward the past. Where we perceive a
chain of events, he sees one single catastrophe which keeps piling wreckage
upon wreckage and hurls it in front of his feet. The angel would like to stay,
awaken the dead, and make whole what has been smashed. But a storm is
blowing from paradise; it has got caught in his wings with such violence that
the angel can no longer close them. This storm irresistibly propels him into the
future to which his back is turned, while the pile of debris before him grows
skyward. This storm is what we call progress. (Illuminations 257-8)
Although this is not the place to examine Derridas or Benjamins arguments,
a possible response to the problem can be proposed briefly. If the future will be
haunted by past victims, there are two possible reasons. First, one may feel a duty
to remember past victims. If that is the case, one has little choice but to be haunted.
163
CHAPTER 4
Although this duty of memory might dampen ones enjoyment of the messianic age,
as long as the messianic age is not one of complete perfection and does not ground
a theodicy, this poses little problem for messianism. Certainly a world in which
the only burden is the memory of past suffering would be a vast advance over the
present. For example, it seems almost comical that the sermon of the futuristic
pastor in Edward Bellamys utopian novel Looking Backward pertains only to how
awful things used to be (Bellamy 183-194).
However, there is a second, pathological way in which the past can haunt the
present. One could be haunted by historys victims because one is simply unable
and unwilling to let go, maintaining pathological ties to the victims. One notices for
example that it is common to console someone who has lost a loved one by saying
that the deceased would want you to be happy. If such advice is given too soon
after the loss, one can predict that the bereaved would only become irritated and
insist upon her right to mourn. But as time passes, the bereaved becomes receptive
to such advice; she learns to laugh, to enjoy, and to love again, without feelings of
guilt. Certainly no one who has lost someone close to them is willing to entertain the
possibility of forgetting the lost loved one, and generally even the suggestion that the
pain of the loss will someday cease is rejected by the bereaved as an impossibility or
an affront. However, the one who is able to grieve in a non-pathological way will be
able to experience happiness and satisfaction in life again and will not transform her
grief into destructive impulses.
To employ a distinction drawn by Freud in his 1917 essay, Mourning and
Melancholia, the person who can cope well with grief mourns without becoming
melancholic (Jay, Force Fields 90). The mourner distinguishes her own identity
from that of the lost loved one. While the mourner may feel that she has lost a
piece of herself, she acknowledges, both consciously and unconsciously, that
she must live on in the face of the loss. Through testing reality, the mourner is
repeatedly reminded of the loss of the other, enabling her to slowly and painfully
withdraw [her] libido from it (93). The melancholic, by contrast, withdraws from
reality and identifies herself completely with the lost victim, experiencing a total
loss of self and regressing into a childlike narcissism (rejecting a reality outside
her) in a failed attempt to regain her lost identity. This narcissism expresses itself
partly in a masochistic desire for punishment, which Freud considered to be the
chief characteristic of the melancholic (91). Melancholy causes destructive behavior
towards the self and others, either through withdrawal from the world or a manic
lashing out at the world. In Martin Jays words, melancholia results in suicidal
fantasies and deeds and may be transformed into a destructive mania, which
discharges a surplus of energy freed by a sudden rupture in a long-sustained
condition of habitual psychic expenditure (91).
Could there be a connection between melancholiathis memory that refuses to
let goand apocalyptic/catastrophic messianism? We have already seen that Fromm
links apocalyptic messianism to despair. Martin Jay draws the connection between
melancholia and apocalypticism:
164
FROMMS CONCEPTS OF PROPHETIC AND CATASTROPHIC MESSIANISM
There is little doubt that the symptoms of melancholy, as Freud describes them,
approximate very closely those of apocalyptic thinking: deep and painful
dejection, withdrawal of interest in the everyday world, diminished capacity
to love, paralysis of the will, and, most important of all, radical lowering
of self-esteem accompanied by fantasies of punishment for assumed moral
transgressions. (Force Fields 92)
Jay raises this issue in the course of a critique of postmodern despair or melancholia
concerning the loss of past historical ideals. He quotes Jean Baudrillards statement
that we are all melancholic due to the disappearance of meaning, and Jean-
Franois Lyotards talk of a kind of grieving or melancholy with respect to the
idea of the modern era (90). However, Jay notes, this problem extends beyond
postmodernism to all instantiations of the apocalyptic imagination:
Jay is wise to offer the disclaimer that he does not embrace psychologizing cultural
phenomena. Psychological profiles of The Utopian, The Revolutionary, or
The Fanatic are too often protean caricatures that are constantly re-adapted to
meet the changing needs of the ruling class. As Alberto Toscano and William T.
Cavanaugh have recently pointed out, the tendency to pathologize social movements
is often employed to anti-emancipatory ends. Toscano points out, for example, that
at one moment the fanatic or Schwrmer was a hot-headed religious seer, and at
another, a coldly calculating, atheistic bureaucratall depending upon the political
needs of the moment. Cavanaughs The Myth of Religious Violence explores how
religious sentiments have been cast in a pathological light to present all religions
(or some religions, since the definition of religion itself is protean) as inherently
violent. Although Jay wisely acknowledges the danger of political pathologizing, he
recognizes a pathology of melancholia and mania within apocalyptic thought that is
so conspicuous, widespread, and problematic that it must be subjected to critique.
It is unfortunate that Jay does not address Fromm in the course of these
speculations, since the critique closely resembles Fromms critique of apocalyptic/
catastrophic messianism and the false hope that forces the Messiah. It is also
unfortunate that Jay does not carry his reflection on the danger of melancholy and
apocalypticism further, to a critique of Adorno, Benjamin, and Horkheimer, since
then he might find a worrying apocalypticism in the work of others in the Frankfurt
School and rediscover Fromm as a possible corrective. (Although Jays work builds
165
CHAPTER 4
3. The Enlightenment
Fromm saw the Enlightenment as radical for its humanism, its devotion to freedom,
and its rejection of authoritarianism (authoritarian idolatry) (SS 235). Like Jrgen
Habermas, Stephen Eric Bronner, Lawrence Wilde, Richard Wolin, Kevin Anderson,
Jonathan Israel, and other scholars today, Fromm saw value in the Enlightenment
as a radical project, a project that remained incomplete and needed to be reclaimed.
Fromm would agree with Habermass characterization of the Enlightenment as an
unfinished project that needs to be continued in certain respects. Further, Fromm
166
FROMMS CONCEPTS OF PROPHETIC AND CATASTROPHIC MESSIANISM
167
CHAPTER 4
Fromms support for the Enlightenment flowed in part from his defense of reason,
although his own understanding of reason gave greater credence to imagination
and affect than one might find in the most stereotypically Enlightenment ideal of
reason. Fromm writes:
[F]or [Freud] reason was confined to thought. Feelings and emotions were per
se irrational, and hence inferior to thought. The enlightenment philosophers in
general shared in this contempt for feelings and affect. Thought was for them the
only vehicle of progress and reason [was] to be found only in thought. They did
not see as Spinoza had seen, that affects, like thought, can be both rational and
irrational and that the full development of man requires the rational evolution of
both thought and affect. They did not see that, if mans thinking is split from his
feeling, both his thinking and his feeling become distorted, and that the picture
of man based on the assumption of this split is also distorted. (SFM 7)
Fromms love of reason can hardly be understood apart from the Jewish enlightenment
tradition to which he was in many respects heir, a tradition profoundly influenced
by the achievement of Hermann Cohen, but which has intellectual roots in Spinoza.
Fromm links Judaism and Enlightenment in his interpretation of Freud:
Freuds Jewish background, if anything, added to his embrace of the
enlightenment spirit. The Jewish tradition itself was one of reason and of
intellectual discipline, and besides that, a somewhat despised minority had a
strong emotional interest to defeat the powers of darkness, of irrationality, of
superstition, which blocked the road to its own emancipation and progress.
(SFM 3)
According to Fromm, Freud was the last great representative of the rationalism
of the Enlightenment (PR 6). Freuds critique of religion was an Enlightenment-
style critique, condemning the tendency of religion to sanctify bad institutions
and endanger critical thinking (12). However, Freud also challenged the limits of
Enlightenment rationalism, which neglected the emotions (6).
It should not be inferred from Fromms defense of the Enlightenment as a radical
and unfinished project, and from his view that the Enlightenment led to Marxism,
that Fromm was an uncritical defender of the Enlightenment, and thus a defender
of the Enlightenments mechanism, scientism, sexism, racism, individualism, and
bourgeois narrowness. Fromm levels a number of insightful criticisms against the
Enlightenment. For example, he criticizes the Enlightenments deterministic view
that all evil in man was nothing but the result of circumstances, hence that man
[does] not really have to choose (HOM 21). This Enlightenment determinism fueled
an idolatry of progress, history, or the future, an idolatry that was linked to
the later destructiveness of Robespierre; in regard to this point, Fromm cites Marxs
line that history is nothing and does nothing; it is man who is and does (ROH 8).
Offering the following Robespierre quote (found in Carl Beckers book), Fromm
discusses Robespierres idolatry of posterity:
168
FROMMS CONCEPTS OF PROPHETIC AND CATASTROPHIC MESSIANISM
O posterity, sweet and tender hope of humanity, thou art not a stranger to us;
it is for thee that we brave all the blows of tyranny; it is thy happiness which
is the price of our painful struggles; often discouraged by the obstacles that
surround us, we feel the need of thy consolations; it is to thee that we confide
the task of completing our laborsMake haste, O posterity, to bring to pass the
hour of equality, of justice, of happiness! (YSB 155; Becker 143)
Although this might seem like a mere rhetorical flourish, here Robespierre presents
posterity as a god to which one may pray for a kind of deterministic rescue, a
troubling image. Fromm might also consider it evidence of a sort of perverse
attachment to memory, not to ones own memories but to the memories that the
future will have of the present. Fromm warns of the danger of allowing humanism
(as a major characteristic of the Enlightenment) to morph into fetishistic idolatry of
humans, resulting in despise of nature (Wilde, Quest for Solidarity 49).
Fromms support for the Enlightenment also did not lead him to hostility towards
religion, the Medieval world, or Christianity. That Fromms work shows the influence
of various religious thinkers is plainly evident. Fromm also evolved towards a
greater openness to Christianity, specifically Catholicism, over the course of his
career. Especially later in his career, Fromm was in dialogue with various radical
and cutting edge Christian thinkers and theologians, including Thomas Merton, Karl
Rahner, Dom Helder Camara, and Ivan Illich (Funk, Life and Ideas 148). However,
in The Art of Loving (1956), Fromm warns oddly that Aristotelian logic14 may be a
source of both the Catholic Church and the atomic bomb, and even earlier, in Escape
from Freedom (1941), he seems to uncritically dismiss Catholicism and the Middle
Ages (AL 80). Later, in a 1954 letter to Thomas Merton,15 Fromm wrote,
I am sure that my picture of the Middle Ages is somewhat oversimplified
Having been brought up in a Protestant country, it took some effort on my
part to overcome the negative attitude toward the Middle Ages which was
conveyed to me in the first 20 years of my life, and you are probably right that
one can still see some of this past in my discussion in Escape from Freedom.
(UK Special Collections Library)
Fromm also saw great potential in Renaissance humanism, and his later works in
general express more optimism about a radical humanist current within Christianity.
For example, he writes in The Heart of Man (1964), The humanists within the
Church and those outside spoke in the name of a humanism which was the
fountainhead of Christianity, listing Nicholas of Cusa, Ficino, Erasmus, Pico de
Mirandola and others (HOM 81). The conclusion to one of Fromms last works, To
Have or To Be? (1976), shows how much his attitude towards Medieval Christianity
had evolved. Here he calls for a synthesis of Medieval Christian messianism and
Enlightenment progress:
Later Medieval culture flourished because people followed the vision of the
City of God. Modern society flourished because people were energized by the
169
CHAPTER 4
vision of the growth of the Earthly City of Progress. In our century, however,
this vision deteriorated to that of the Tower of Babel, which is now beginning
to collapse and will ultimately bury everybody in its ruins. If the City of
God and the Earthly City were thesis and antithesis, a new synthesis is the
only alternative to chaos: the synthesis between the spiritual core of the Late
Medieval world and the development of rational thought and science since the
Renaissance. This synthesis is The City of Being. (TB 164)
Although Fromms support for the Enlightenment was cautious and critical, his
approach differs from that of other Frankfurt School thinkers of his generation.
Unlike Benjamin, Horkheimer, Adorno, and Marcuse, Fromm saw the Enlightenment
as an essentially radical and progressive period of human history, leading to the
development of Marxism. (Horkheimer and Adornos critique of the Enlightenment,
The Dialectic of Enlightenment, was initially supposed to be co-authored by
Horkheimer and Marcuse.) Adorno, Horkheimer, and Marcuses relationship to the
Enlightenment and to the value of reason is no doubt ambiguous, and there is dispute
about whether Horkheimer or Adorno is the more hostile to the Enlightenment
of the pair. Horkheimers Eclipse of Reason, with its critique of the revolt of
nature ideology, and Adornos scathing polemic against Heidegger in The Jargon
of Authenticity might seem to place them as defenders of rationality against the
partisans of irrationality, while Marcuses fairly enduring commitment to Hegel and
Marx does even more to place him in the camp of reason.
Of course, Walter Benjamins long-time collaborator Gershom Scholem was
also an intense critic of the Enlightenment, as we have seen. Scholem identifies
the nihilistic messianism of false messiahs like Jacob Frank with the messianism of
the Enlightenment, rather than distinguishing nihilism and Enlightenment as Fromm
does (The Messianic Idea 84; Habermas 144; Magid 7). Significantly, Scholem also
holds that both Marx and FreudFromms two major intellectual influenceswere
dangerous heretics influenced by the same volatile spirit of the false Messiahs and
of the Enlightenment (Habermas 145). In addition to the three-part distinction of
messianism into restorative, conservative, and utopian tendencies, mentioned
in Chapter 2, Scholem elsewhere employs a distinction between restorative
messianism (based upon the medieval thought of Maimonides, seeking return to an
historical golden age) and apocalyptic messianism (based upon the mysticism of
the Kabbalah, advocating rupture from tradition and history) (Magid 7). Scholem
thought that the two forms of mysticism had become hopelessly fused into a new,
dangerous force once they had entered politics (7).
Although Fromm saw the prophetic-messianic spirit in the Enlightenment,
he believed that the Enlightenment was ultimately undermined by its lack of
true humanism. In a letter to Thomas Merton, Fromm harshly condemns the
Enlightenment, here making the rare comment that the Enlightenment was a setback
for prophetic messianism, because the Enlightenment gave rise to nationalism
(Fromm letter to Merton, February 26, 1962). Instead of truly embracing its vision
170
FROMMS CONCEPTS OF PROPHETIC AND CATASTROPHIC MESSIANISM
of the universal rights of humanity, the Enlightenment fell back into particularism
(just as Jewish messianism later, in large part, capitulated to Zionism, a critique that
surely underlies much of Fromms concern with messianism, although he does not
address it overtly in his major writings). In place of faith in human power as its own
end (to paraphrase Marx), the Enlightenment resorted to the idolatry of mechanism,
progress, science, state, and nation.
Coming from a more medieval world, Fromm may have been better able to observe
the limitations of the Middle Ages and the libratory elements of the Enlightenment. As
noted earlier, most of those in the Frankfurt School had grown up in secular households,
and to the extent that they turned to the resources of Jewish religious thought, it could
be construed as a form of rebellion against their secular parents. Fromm, however,
felt that he had grown up in a medieval world and had been slated to be a rabbi or
Talmudic scholar. He was drawn to the circle around Rabbi Nobel and the Lehrhaus
by a different kind of rebellion, a rebellion against Orthodox Judaism: Fromm and
Nobel took long prohibited walks on the Sabbath, for example. By contrast, when
Leo Lwenthal informed his enlightened secular father of his plans to keep kosher, his
father burst into tears. It had been bad enough when Lwenthal married a woman from
Knigsberg to the east, to which his father had retorted, Youre crazy! Knigsberg,
thats practically in Russia! (Hornstein 402n31). It was a terrible disappointment for
him that his son, whom he, the father, the true scion of the enlightenment, had raised so
progressively, was now being pulled into the nonsensical, obscure, and deceitful
clutches of a positive religion (Lwenthal 20).
A particular dimension of Enlightenment radicalism, the idea of progress,
is discussed in the next section, but with a focus not upon the Enlightenments
interpretation of the concept but Fromms own unique interpretation.
While Walter Benjamin, Herbert Marcuse, and others in the Frankfurt School
foresaw a messianic event arriving in a time of catastrophe, Fromm saw the
messianic event as an outcome of historical progress. Fromm was living in an era
which, like our own, was deeply aware of the possibility of catastrophe but (perhaps
until recently) seemed unwilling to take action to avert the catastrophe. He was
especially disturbed and puzzled by discussions of bomb shelters and the widespread
view that American families could hide themselves below ground in the event of
a nuclear catastrophe, fight off invading hordes attempting to steal their stuff, and
then reemerge and rebuild civilization from the ground up. That so many people
were willing to accept such a possible outcome to human history, Fromm saw as
profoundly pathological. Fromm was involved in founding the anti-nuclear weapons
group SANE, which he himself named and to which the title of his book The Sane
Society is a reference (Katz 24).16 SANE aimed at awakening Americans to the need
to prevent nuclear catastrophe in an insane time of nuclear deterrence. In a 1961
letter to Merton, Fromm wrote,
171
CHAPTER 4
I have been thinking a good deal lately about the increasing discussion of what
people will do in their fall-out shelters in case of an atomic attack. It seems
that most people take it for granted that they would defend their shelters with
guns against neighbors who want to intrudethis whole discussion shows
what kind of life we would have, even if millions of people could stay alive by
protecting themselves from fall-out in shelters. Of course big cities are written
off, and those who would survive would be the part of the population in the
country, removed from the cities. It would be a life of complete barbarism
Neighbor defending his life against neighbor by force, children starving, life
reduced to its most primitive components of survival. Anyone who believes
that in this way we can save freedom, I think, is just dishonest or cannot see
clearly. (Thomas Merton Center archive)
Passages like this one clearly indicate that Fromm thought that people were aware
of the potential for catastrophe yet unmotivated by this awareness to revolt, and if
the catastrophe were actually to occur, it would probably lead to barbarism and not
to socialism. In speaking of barbarism, Fromm no doubt had in mind Luxemburgs
famous speech in which she declared socialism or barbarism! the fundamental
choice facing her times, which Fromm found to be a succinct way of formulating the
fundamental alternativism posited by prophets of socialism (HOM 119).
In May Man Prevail?, Fromm studied the peculiar pathology that enabled
Herman Kahn and other think tank pundits to cheerfully assure the public that
society could be rebuilt in the wake of a nuclear catastrophe (MMP 194). In his
1959 testimony to the Joint Committee on Atomic Energy, Kahn urged the public
to compare the horror of war and the horror of peace and to choose war against
the Soviet Union (196, italics Fromms). According to Fromm, Kahns argument
that Americans should prefer dying in a nuclear catastrophe to living in peace under
Communist rule was not only a false dichotomyevidence did not suggest that
U.S. disarmament would entail annexing the United States to the Soviet Unionbut
also rested upon a moral fallacy (199). That is, although a decision to die to save
anothers life or to defend an ideal can be one of the greatest moral achievements,
it is so only if it is the result of an individuals decision, a decision not motivated
by vanity, depression, or masochism, but by devotion to another life or to an idea
(199, Fromms italics). But those Americans who preferred death to surrender were
propelled by unconscious or pathological motives, not the motives they professed
(such as love of freedom). Furthermore, they were making this choice not only for
themselves but for millions of others, of children, of unborn generations, of nations
and of the human race itself (199).
Benjamin and Marcuse, while they surely would not have been fans of bomb
shelters or nuclear destruction, took a different approach to the theme of catastrophe.
As Anson Rabinbach argues in his book, In the Shadow of Catastrophe: German
Intellectuals between Apocalypse and Enlightenment, leftists like Ernst Bloch and
Walter Benjamin, on the one hand, and rightists like Carl Schmitt17 on the other, shared
172
FROMMS CONCEPTS OF PROPHETIC AND CATASTROPHIC MESSIANISM
173
CHAPTER 4
174
FROMMS CONCEPTS OF PROPHETIC AND CATASTROPHIC MESSIANISM
would not require the absolute renunciation of the present, with all of its ideas, but
could emerge through rational imagination in the present. For Fromm, reason and
imagination are not at odds but rather depend upon one another.
Both Fromms critics and advocates acknowledge a utopian side to his thought,
and Fromms commitment to reason and imagination lies at the root of this utopian
dimension.20 This utopian dimension is not surprising considering that he was
influenced not only by some aspects of the tradition of utopian socialism but also
by some of his contemporaries writings on utopia: Buber, Bloch, Karl Mannheim,
and others (BC 122). Fromms book The Sane Society is an interesting case in
point. I begin by exploring The Sane Society and the mainline Trotskyist critique it
garnered, followed by Fromms writings on utopian and dystopian literature, i.e., his
Foreword to Edward Bellamys Looking Backward and his Afterword to George
Orwells 1984. I then address how Fromms utopianism can in fact be seen as his
chief contribution to Critical Theory and how his related commitment to imagining
the future (as I term it) differentiates him meaningfully from the critical-theoretic
approaches of Herbert Marcuses One-Dimensional Man and of Horkheimer and
Adornos Dialectic of Enlightenment.
The Sane Society is one of Fromms earlier books, and it is a peculiar one in
certain respects. It seems less Marxist than his later works. It repeatedly expresses
admiration for Bakunin, Kropotkin, and other anarchist thinkers, and it is sharply
critical of Marx, parroting typical charges: that Marx was overly optimistic about
human nature (a surprising charge indeed from Fromm!), that Marx neglected the
moral dimension of human existence, and that Marx was narrowly economistic in
his later years (SS 264-6). Fromm would later go to great lengths to refute all of
these charges in Marxs Concept of Man and elsewhere. (He maintained respect for
Peter Kropotkins Mutual Aid and the work of some other anarchist thinkers such as
Landauer [TB 84].)21
As we have already seen, The Sane Society saw the utopian socialism of
Saint-Simon and Comte as expressions of prophetic messianism (SS 236). The
book also referenced various utopian communities and included an interesting,
lengthy discussion of a contemporary workers factory cooperative. The utopian
element of The Sane Society, not incidentally, was roundly condemned across the
political spectrum. Liberal critic William Whyte criticized it in his best-seller, The
Organization Man, while prominent U.S. Trotskyist leader Joseph Hansen snorted
that the book could be easily refuted by reading The Communist Manifesto (Hansen
3). Hansen had chiefly three charges against the book:
1. Fromm presents too cheery a picture of capitalism in the United States (4).
2. Fromms sources are suspect, including anarchists like Proudhon and traditional
figures like Jesus and the Buddha. Hansen implies that Fromm is relying on
fallacious appeals to authority (4, 6).
175
CHAPTER 4
The third of these complaints ties in most directly with our concern in this section, but
a few other notes are in order. In terms of (1), one supposes that Hansen would prefer
the tales of trial and travail of the working classes that filled many socialist leaflets
of the day. Fromm was up to something different. He was not seeking to inspire
revolt with tales of misery. He sought to present a sociological and psychological
account, to provide theoretical tools to the masses. There is nothing cheery at all
about the book, which regards American society in 1950s as literally insane. As
for (2), it seems more like Hansen is engaging in a fallacious charge of guilt-by-
association than that Fromm is fallaciously appealing to authority.
Hansens point (3) concerns us most, since many people would, like Hansen,
reject Fromms claim to Marxism out of hand due to his utopianism and idealism.
The claim of idealism is a slippery one, since the word has more than one meaning.
What Hansen means to imply is that Fromm was not a materialist, not that Fromm
was an idealist in the sense of having high ideals of justice, peace, etc., although
there may be a certain equivocation in his and others presentation of this charge
against Fromm. Tied to the concern about idealism may be a charge that Fromm
is too happy-go-lucky, too sure that revolution will come almost of its own accord.
Again, like the charge that Fromms book is cheery, there is not the slightest
evidence for this in the text, which is one of Fromms darkest books. As for the
traditional distinction between idealist and materialist made in Marxist circles,
the philosophical approach to this question has sometimes been rather lazy. Partly
due to an anti-intellectualism that is all too widespread in Marxist circles, it is often
unknown or ignored to what a vast extent Marx was influenced by the idealism of
Fichte and Hegel, and some would argue that Marx was not simply a materialist
but was attempting to synthesize materialism and idealism. However, Fromm never
claimed to be an idealist, and Hansen does not offer much in the way of support for
the claim. We will move on to explore Hansens charge of Fromms utopianism.
Although The Sane Society and the response to it are instrumental in understanding
Fromms utopian commitments, a more complete understanding of this topic can be
gained through the Foreword that he wrote for an edition of Edward Bellamys
classic socialist utopian novel Looking Backward and an Afterword that he wrote
for George Orwells dystopian classic 1984. In the foreword, Fromm writes, Utopia,
in our materialistic world, means idle dreaming, instead of the ability to plan and
change into a truly human world (vi). Fromm explains:
While the word is taken from the title of Sir Thomas Mores sixteenth-century
Utopia, the more general meaning is that a utopia is a society in which man
has reached such perfection that he is able to build a social system based on
justice, reason, and solidarity. The beginning and the basis of this vision lie in
the Messianic concept of the Old Testament prophets. (vii)
176
FROMMS CONCEPTS OF PROPHETIC AND CATASTROPHIC MESSIANISM
Utopias not only provide a vision of the future; they are related to humanistic planning
(ROH 95). They demonstrate not only the impulse to design a future but to seek
ways to bridge the gap between present and future. According to Fromm, utopia is
the one element that is almost exclusively a product of the Western mind (Foreword
to Brandt vii). Fromms Foreword speaks of a need for utopian literature in a time
dominated by dystopian literature (1984, Brave New World). However, as he points
out in the Afterward to 1984, dystopian literature can serve a useful function if it
presents us with alternatives and motivates us to make the right choice.
For Fromm, the achievement of a human utopia requires theory and praxis, not
mere aesthetic vision or mystical inspiration (TB 142). Fromms openness to utopias
is closely connected to one of Fromms chief contributions to Critical Theory, that
of his commitment to providing not merely a critique of bourgeois society but a real
alternative, not merely a negative but (to use Hegels term) the second negation,
the self-subsisting positive. Perhaps Fromms most significant contributions to
psychoanalysis lie in his attempt not merely to describe pathologies but also to give
an account of psychological health, both social and individual. Similarly, while
other members of the Frankfurt School tended to confine their work to critiques of
presently existing social conditions, Fromms messianism offered a positive goal for
which to strive: the sane individual (the productive character) and the sane society.
His commitment to advancing beyond mere negation and to offering a positive
account of the future can also be seen in his defense of positive freedom, while he
saw Marcuses philosophy as a manifestation of belief in mere negative freedom.
In the following subsection, I show how Fromms utopianism is connected to his
commitment to imagining the future and how this differentiates Fromm from
Marcuses One-Dimensional Man and from Horkheimer and Adornos critique of
enlightenment in The Dialectic of Enlightenment.
Imagining the Future Since prophetic messianisms attitude toward the past has
been addressed, it now remains to address its attitude toward the future and whether
the messianic future is imaginable. In contradistinction to Marcuse, Horkheimer,
and Adorno, Fromm ascribes a high degree of rational imaginability to the messianic
age from the standpoint of the present; for this reason Fromm is profoundly open
to utopian thought. Although Fromm doubtless was sufficiently Hegelian to know
that the Owl of Minerva only flies at duskFromm would certainly consider it
impossible to prescribe, like Fourier, that garbage collection would be handled by
children under socialismFromm nevertheless saw high potential for imagining
the future.
For example, according to Fromm we can legitimately say that the socialist future
would be one of love, and it is not the case that we cannot know anything about
love under capitalism. Fromm writes (largely in response to Marcuse),
[Some] share the opinion of the basic incompatibility between love and normal
secular life within our society. They arrive at the result that to speak of love today
means only to participate in the general fraud; they claim that only a martyr or
177
CHAPTER 4
a mad person can love in the world of today, hence that all discussion of love is
nothing but preaching. [In their famous debate in Dissent magazine, Marcuse
had accused Fromm of sermonizing.22] This very respectable viewpoint lends
itself readily to a rationalization of cynicismThis radicalism results in
moral nihilism. (AL 131)
Fromm continues, defending his view that love is not inconceivable or impossible
under capitalism:
I am of the conviction that the answer to the absolute incompatibility of love
and normal life is correct only in an abstract sense. The principle underlying
capitalistic society and the principle of love are incompatible. But modern
society seen concretely is a complex phenomenoncapitalism is in itself a
complex and constantly changing structure which still permits of a good deal
of non-conformity and of personal latitude. (131-2)
It seems that Fromm is pointing out that the seeds of any new society are present in
the preceding one; while the catastrophic messianism of Marcuses Great Refusal
suggests a radical rupture from current society, Fromm prefers to nurture the seeds
of the next society that are already present within the current one. Thus, Fromm finds
the future more imaginable than Marcuse does.
Marcuse presents Fromms attempt to change individuals as regressive, as an
approach that would render people content and postpone the prerequisite breaking
point that would lead to the upheaval of revolution. But for Fromm, as for Hermann
Cohen, the seeds of the messianic future can be seen in part in the development of
personal change in the present. Fromm objects to the common claim that, When the
revolution comes, then we will have better men:
Marcuse says this, [that] before the revolution any attempt to become a better
man is only reactionary. That is of course plain nonsense in my opinion because
after the revolution comes and nobody has changed, the revolution will just
repeat all the misery of what has happened before. Revolution will be made
by people who have no idea of what a better human life could be. (ALi 163-4)
Although it might be unfair to claim that Marcuse believed that trying to become a
better person under capitalism is simply reactionary, one can understand Fromms
perspective by looking at Marcuses and Fromms debate about psychoanalysis
as it played out in Dissent magazine and in the pages of Eros and Civilization
and The Art of Loving. For Marcuse, Fromms attempt to restore the individual to
psychological health was nothing but a psychology of adjustment that would enable
the individual to function more effectively in the capitalist system and be more
easily exploitable. For Fromm, of course, this was far from being the case, since
Fromm interpreted the healthy, productive character as a revolutionary character,
rejecting Marcuses assertion of the tension between health and knowledge (Eros
and Civilization 261).
178
FROMMS CONCEPTS OF PROPHETIC AND CATASTROPHIC MESSIANISM
Although Fromm may have found the future more imaginable or conceivable
than did the catastrophic messianists he was confronting, there seems to be an
internal tension in Fromms thought on this point. Namely, although Fromm is
drawn towards positive, utopian visions of the future, he also practices a negative
political philosophy, paralleling a tendency in his work that approaches a negative
theology. Wary of detailed descriptions or predictions of the future and wary of
reifying concepts, turning them into idols by offering fixed descriptions, Fromm
is tied to the Jewish tradition of the Bilderverbot (the ban on graven images) that
Horkheimer and Adorno discuss in The Dialectic of Enlightenment. As we shall see
momentarily, unlike Horkheimer and Adorno, Fromm embraces the Bilderverbot not
as a restorative messianism that seeks return to the primordial past but as an ideal
presenting the possibility of imagining the future.
There are multiple reasons why Fromm was attracted to the via negativa, including
his Marxism and his Jewish background. Marx himself offered no blueprints for
a socialist society and is better known for critiques of capitalism than positive
descriptions of socialism.23 Fromm writes in his posthumously published manuscript
on Marx and Meister Eckhart,
[Marx] kept the purity of his vision without having to compromise it by
concrete descriptions that would be obliged to anticipate developments that
could not be anticipated in the old society and by the as yet unchanged man.
Marx only described what communism was not. (OBH 146)
It is interesting that the above quote occurs in a document comparing Marx to,
and praising the negative theology of, Eckhart and Spinoza, the great negator of
all personal divine attributes. Meanwhile, the Jewish tradition in which Fromm
was educated was heavily centered on negative theology. Moses Maimonides, the
Medieval rationalist Jewish philosopher for whom Fromm always held such high
respect, was for example a great master of negative theology. One of the central
themes of Fromms account of true spirituality is negative: the rejection of idols,
which is connected in Jewish thought to the refusal to give a positive description of
God. The rejection of idols is a common thread in Marxism and Judaism, according
to Fromm (BF 90).
How can Fromm reconcile his atheistic via negativa,24 manifested in his adamant
repudiation of all idols, with his view that the coming messianic age is imaginable
and minimally describable (an age of love, peace, justice, and so on)? If Fromm
believed in a God distinct from human beings, there would be no contradiction;
God would be unimaginable, the human future imaginable. But since Fromm does
not make such a distinctionsince humanity is its own savior, is itself becoming
the God it seeksFromm holds in tension an atheistic religiosity (manifesting
itself politically as a radical rejection of the narrow concepts of the present) and the
attempt to see the seeds of the future within the contradictions of the present age.
Fromms and Horkheimer and Adornos differing interpretations of the Jewish
ban on idolatry have implications for the imaginability of the future. According to
179
CHAPTER 4
180
FROMMS CONCEPTS OF PROPHETIC AND CATASTROPHIC MESSIANISM
demonstrate his utopian commitments. His utopianism can in fact be seen as his
chief contribution to Critical Theory, and his related commitment to imagining the
future differentiates him from Marcuse, Horkheimer, and Adorno.
***
For the young author of a dissertation on Erich Fromm to critique Rainer Funks
interpretation of Fromm might be an archetypal Oedipal fantasy. Rainer Funks
contribution to studies of Fromm is immeasurable. A scholar who knew Fromm
personally, published extensively on Fromm, translated many works by Fromm,
became the executor of Fromms literary estate, the director of the Erich Fromm
Dokumentationszentrum in Tbingen, Germany, the long-time leader of the
International Erich Fromm Society, and the editor of its endlessly useful website,
Rainer Funk is the father-figure of all things Fromm. (Fromm even cites Funk and
thanks him for helping him to reach a better understanding of Christianity! [TB xx,
45n., 47, 101].) However, I prefer to think of my critique of Funks interpretation as
analogous to pushing past the gatekeeper, in the Kafka parable discussed above, not
as an Oedipal rebellion.
In an otherwise very useful text surveying Fromms thought (Erich Fromm:
The Courage to be Human), one finds a peculiar chapter on Forms of Fromms
Thought. The chapter argues for identifying Fromms thought with an ecstatic-
cathartic dialectic, a term Funk draws from Ernst Topitsch (about whom more will
be said shortly). According to Topitsch, the ecstatic-cathartic dialectic has its roots
in gnostic myths, which in turn were molded by shamanistic magic and divination
(Funk, Courage 223, Funks words). These myths were formed on the basis of
experiences of superiority over the pressure of the environing world that occur in
states of trance or under the influence of drugs (223). My suggested word for
181
CHAPTER 4
182
FROMMS CONCEPTS OF PROPHETIC AND CATASTROPHIC MESSIANISM
183
CHAPTER 4
184
FROMMS CONCEPTS OF PROPHETIC AND CATASTROPHIC MESSIANISM
the Jewish religion and employs traditions of mythFunk criticizes Fromm for
failing to be sufficiently ecstatic-cathartic! Funk correctly states, as though it does
not undermine his whole argument: The Urgeschichte of religion as Fromm himself
outlines it knows neither an original state that might correspond in some respects to
a final one, nor such a thing as a falling out of this original state (Courage 238). It
is precisely here that Fromm fails, Funk decides, for he does not see mans earliest
development according to the ecstatic-cathartic model (239). Where, then, does
Funk find Fromm employing the crucial Gnostic myth of fall and return? Where,
then, does Fromms supposed Gnostic/ecstatic-cathartic orientation lie, if not in
this central myth of Gnosticism? One is left only with Fromms dialectics and his
openness to mysticism, neither of which is sufficient evidence.
One final issue remains. Just as Funk appears to be nave about Scholem, even
employing Scholems history of Judaism as an authoritative source with which
to correct Fromms definition of messianism (Courage 317-8n80), Funk appears
terribly nave about Topitsch in the chapter. Topitsch was a Cold Warrior who linked
Marxism and Gnosticism not as a compliment but as an insult to both. Some of
the ideas of Topitsch that Funk draws upon in the chapter, Topitsch in turn drew
from Hans Jonas and Jacob Taubes (the apocalyptic thinker, Zionist, Heideggerian,
Schmittian, and friend of Scholem and Marcuse) (Courage 361n28). In short, Funk
is describing Fromms thought in the chapter on the ecstatic-cathartic through the
lens of Fromms enemies, though Funk does not realize this. His only criticism of
Topitsch is that Topitsch was a Neopositivist (222).
In conclusion, even Rainer Funk fails to grasp the differentiation between prophetic
and apocalyptic messianism, casually lumping Fromm into the apocalyptic camp
despite abundant evidence to the contrary. Until we reclaim the distinction between
prophetic and apocalyptic messianism, and until we allow prophetic messianism to
go by its own name (rather than liberal progressivism, Enlightenment optimism,
or other epithets), we will not only fail to understand Fromm as a thinker, but our
knowledge of fin de sicle Germany, the Frankfurt School, 1960s social movements,
Jewish thought, and Marxism will continue to suffer from this devastating omission.
NOTES
1
One may be tempted to contrast this claim with Fromms assertion in To Have or To Be? that the
libratory, humanistic being mode fights time, refuses to submit to it, while the having mode is
confined by past, present, and future (TB 1035). Although prophetic messianism fights time, it does
not end time. Although prophetic messianism posits a future that occurs within time, it does not submit
to time. It is a humanistic victory over time, controlling and channeling time towards human ends.
2
Throughout most of this chapter, I have shortened Fromms term apocalyptic or catastrophic
messianism to catastrophic messianism.
3
Here I am using impossible in the sense of logically contradictory, not in Derridas technical usage
of the term.
4
A contribution from catastrophic messianism to the rise of Nazism was possible in the sense that
catastrophic messianism is not a uniquely Jewish phenomenon but is a way of viewing history, the
present, and the future that is compatible with a range of philosophical and religious worldviews; also
185
CHAPTER 4
consider from Chapter 2 the way in which the anti-Semitic George circle manifested characteristics
of catastrophic messianism and also the discussion in that same chapter of the way in which
Scholems catastrophic messianism challenged canonical accounts of Jewish history and belief.
5
With regard to Heidegger, cf. Heideggers infamous claim that instrumentalized Western rationality
(modern agriculture) caused the concentration camps. The Heidegger Affair of 1987, when new
revelations of Heideggers Nazism were published in Victor Farias account, marked a turning point,
but prior to that time and again since then, one finds that Heidegger is widely accepted by many left
thinkers, although despising his political affiliations, apparently finding his philosophy extricable
from them. (It will be interesting to see if a shift occurs as a result of the recent publication of
Heideggers Black Notebooks, which contain anti-Semitic comments.)
6
Here is the passage from Gershom Scholems On Jews and Judaism in Crisis: Selected Essays that
Mendieta is referring to:
The difference between the modern theology of Revolution, as it comes to us from
so many directions and the messianic idea of Judaism consists to an appreciable extent
in a transposal of terminology. In its new form, history becomes prehistory; the human
experience of which we have spoken turns out not to have redeemed humanity. That
simplified the discussions about the value, or lack of value, of previous history (which
lacked the essential element of mans freedom and autonomy), and thus placed all
discussions about real, authentic human values on the plane of eschatology. That opened
door after door to an uninhibitedly optimistic Utopia, one not even to be described by
the concepts derived from an unredeemed state of the world. That is the attitude behind
the writings of the most important ideologists of revolutionary messianism, such as Ernst
Bloch, Walter Benjamin, Theodor Adorno, and Herbert Marcuse, whose acknowledged or
unacknowledged ties to their Jewish heritage are evident. (287)
7
Rabinbachs first three points are roughly identical to Mendietas, although the fourth differs.
Rabinbachs fourth point concerns the ethical ambivalence of (catastrophic) messianismnihilism
and quietism as two sides of the same catastrophic messianic coin (Shadow of Catastrophe 334).
8
Presumably no one in the Frankfurt Institute anticipated the coming of a single human being as
the Messiah (despite the fact that the left is sometimes tempted to venerate leaders as Messiah-
figures). Lawrence Wilde points out that there is one place where Fromm seems to have faltered in
his commitment to interpreting the messianic event as an outcome of united human effort. Towards
the end of The Sane Society, Fromm suggests that a new humanistic religion must emerge, and
he suggests that it might arise in the next five hundred years, perhaps spurred on by a new great
teacher (Wilde, Quest for Solidarity 54). Wilde rightly points out that there is a danger inherent
in any approach that encourages us to hope for a new savior and that this promotes a feeling of
waiting rather than acting, of being led rather than leading (54). Fromm would share Wildes worry,
and his statement about awaiting a great teacher must be considered inconsistent with the general
tenor of his work. Fromm does make a similar point about a future great teacher or religious leader
elsewhere, such as in The Revolution of Hope, but he is careful to qualify this claim by adding that
an attitude of passive waiting for the arrival of such a figure is dangerous:
Religions are usually founded by rare and charismatic personalities of extraordinary
genius. Such a personality has not appeared yet on todays horizon, although there is no
reason to assume that he has not been born. But in the meantime we cannot wait for a
new Moses or a new Buddha; we have to make do with what we have, and perhaps at this
moment of history this is all to the good because the new religious leader might too quickly
be transformed into a new idol and his religion might be transformed into idolatry before
it had a chance to penetrate the hearts and minds of men. (ROH 138)
9
Mendieta and Rabinbach may be incorrect in their assertion that other members of the Frankfurt School
rejected such a return, in the case of Walter Benjamin, for instance, and Herbert Marcuse in his more
Romantic moments, as suggested in the final section of Chapter 2. Yet Mendieta is definitely correct
that Fromm rejects such a return to a past Golden Age, and this is mainly what concerns us here.
186
FROMMS CONCEPTS OF PROPHETIC AND CATASTROPHIC MESSIANISM
10
Fromms outspoken opposition to Israeli government policies and his subtle digs at the idea of
a Jewish state distinguished him from some other members of the Frankfurt School, apparently
including Marcuse. Raya Dunayevskaya notes in a letter to Fromm that Marcuse was so hesitant to
criticize Israel that he supported the Israeli military intervention over the Suez Canal (Anderson and
Rockwell 207). Further, it may be unclear how much stock to put in a 1977 interview for a San Diego
Jewish student publication, but there Marcuse also stated that the solution to the Jewish problem
was a Jewish state which can defend itself, and although he voiced opposition in the interview
to Israeli arms trade with South Africa, he was also critical of a recent United Nations vote that
according to the interviewer had equated Zionism with racism (Marcuse, The New Left 180-1).
This way of approaching the issue of Israeli political power seems significantly different from
Fromms categorical rejection of the Zionist movement as nationalistic and an aberration from the
true spirit of Judaism.
11
It is also important to remember that the critique of technological hubris was easily appropriated by
earlier thinkers like Ernst Jnger and Martin Heidegger, who had no trouble infusing their critiques
with irrationalist, mythic energies (Force Fields 93).
12
Paul Tillich was around the Frankfurt Psychoanalytic Institute in the late 1920s and early 30s and
had influence there; at the time he was highlighting the humanism of the young Marx (Wiggershaus
55). Fromm came into contact with Tillich again in the 1940s, at meetings of Harry Stack Sullivans
Zodiac Club in Washington (Knapp 42-3). Fromm draws from Tillich the concepts of being
related to the world and the courage to be related to [oneself], as well as Tillichs concept of
ultimate concern (PN 46; MCM 47n1, 49; AL 126). (Fromm points out, Socialism for Marx
was, as Paul Tillich put it, a resistance movement against the destruction of love in social reality
(MCM 49).)
13
This should not be taken to imply that Fromm himself viewed Marxs philosophy as eschatological;
he is simply referring to a series of thinkers who cast it in those terms.
14
Fromms account of human nature and society are in many ways Aristotelian, but like the peculiar,
humanistic, atheist mystic he was, Fromm rejected the law of non-contradiction and was suspicious
of categories that froze living reality into static boxes, leading to reification of historical concepts.
15
Erich Fromm exchanged roughly thirty letters with Thomas Merton over the course of fourteen
years. Fromms part of the exchange is still unpublished, but I obtained access to the correspondence
between Fromm and Merton, some of which is housed in the Special Collections library at University
of Kentucky and some of which is housed in the Thomas Merton Center at Bellarmine University;
both archives kindly allowed me access. Some of Mertons letters to Fromm have been published
in The Hidden Ground of Love: The Letters of Thomas Merton on Religious Experience and Social
Concerns (Ed. William H. Shannon).
16
The Sane Society also came out in 1955, on the heels of Lewis Mumfords In the Name of Sanity
(1954), a book Fromm later references (ROH 44). Fromm had fun with book titles. Like Marxs
usage of the title, The Poverty of Philosophy, in response to Proudhons The Philosophy of Poverty,
Fromm frequently plays with the titles of popular books, titling his own as responses to them. Man
for Himself (a presentation of the potential and goodness of human nature) was written in response
to Karl Menningers Man Against Himself (which argued that suicide stems from natural human
impulses). Similarly, The Art of Loving was likely a joking jab at Norman Vincent Peales The Art of
Living.
17
Along with Karl Lwith, Carl Schmitt was one of the chief public defenders of the secularization
thesis, according to which, in Schmitts words, all significant concepts of the modern theory of
the state are secularized theological concepts (Toscano 233). Although the defense of this thesis
by reactionaries like Schmitt and conservatives like Karl Lwith might lead one to suspect that this
thesis would be of little use to a radical emancipatory political program, thinkers like Fromm and
Bloch also held the secularization thesis and considered it profoundly radical. For Fromm and Bloch,
however, it meant that the human desire for liberation predated modernity and was fundamental to
human nature. Where Schmitt and Lwith found in the secularization thesis evidence for their view
that modern politics lacked a rational foundation (Schmitt celebrating this fact, Lwith lamenting it),
Fromm and Bloch took the secularization thesis to mean that revolutionary change was possible and
in accord with human nature or with long-held human desires.
187
CHAPTER 4
For Schmitt, a particularist and a voluntarist (decisionist), the secularization thesis meant that
politics were irrational and existed in a realm outside law. In Schmitts words, The exception
in jurisprudence is analogous to the miracle in theology (Toscano 233). Therefore, he held that
political change occurs primarily through apocalyptic rupture, not through reason and progress. Like
the miracle that breaks the laws of nature, political change occurs by breaking the laws of the state.
Oddly, Schmitts decisionism, while likely influenced even in his later years by fascist ideology, can
be used not only as a defense of a politics that idolizes a leader who stands outside the law but also
a brand of anarchism, in which the lawless masses declare the state of exception, rupturing from law
and order and drawing the necessary distinction between friend and enemy about which Schmitt
spoke.
Fromm was no believer in miracles, and certainly not in the political realm. Like his hero Spinoza,
or Moses Maimonides (whom Fromm and Cohen, unlike Gershom Scholems camp, admired),
Fromm found radicalism in rational lawfulness. The pre-Enlightenment world was not one only of
superstition and dark, mysterious forces but also a world in which human reason had grappled with
perennial questions and come to solutions not wholly different from those needed today.
18
In a paper presented at the 2008 conference of the International Herbert Marcuse Society.
19
Marcuse presents his thought as highly dialectical and rooted in Hegel, but as Raya Dunayevskaya
suggests in her correspondence with him, it may be that Marcuse is more Schellingian than Hegelian.
Marcuses capitalism is sometimes a night in which all cows are black (Anderson and Rockwell 8,
17n.17).
20
Zilbersheid sees it as Fromms chief strength, while Chaubiski rejects it out of hand. A better
argued though highly critical interpretation of Fromms utopianism is offered by Pietikainen.
21
Petteri Pietikainen, one of Fromms more astute critics, writes:
Fromms moral ideas tally remarkably well with those of classical anarchists, especially
Kropotkin, who emphasized the innate tendency to mutual aid. One could even say that
Fromm, [Otto] Gross and [Wilhelm] Reich were Kropotkins spiritual sons, since they
all believed that we have an innate inclination to reciprocal altruism, solidarity, and
cooperation (Pietikainen 196).
Pietikainens portrayal of Fromm is dangerous, because it undermines Fromms legitimate claims
to being part of the Marxist tradition. However, drawing upon anarchism for a project of socialist
humanism perhaps ought not to be considered taboo, and distinctions between anarchism and
socialism often come down to matters of revolutionary strategy more than to the future envisioned
or the account of human nature, upon which there is more likely to be agreement.
22
Cf. Marcuse, Social Implications, p. 232, Eros and Civilization 260, and Fromms claims about
the charge of preaching (AL 128; WW 19). Cf. also Marcuses claim that the goal of optimal
development of a persons potentialities and the realization of his individuality is impossible in
contemporary society and that curing the patient could only mean turning her into a rebel or
(which is saying the same thing) a martyr (Social Implications 231).
23
Of course, there are scattered exceptions, such as the famous passage in The German Ideology, in
which Marx waxes utopian-poetic about a future in which humans will hunt in the morning, fish
in the afternoon, and criticize after dinner. However, such descriptions are few and far between in
Marxs writing and should not be taken too literally.
24
One should be careful not to give too much weight to identifying Fromm as atheist. Although after
his abandonment of Orthodox Judaism he always insisted he was not a theist, and although he was
active in the American Humanist Association, an atheist organization, more than mere secular
humanism Fromms humanism aligns with Marxs early writings. Marx moves beyond the atheism
of Feuerbach, sublating atheism by turning from an emphasis upon nature to an emphasis upon
the human shaping of the world; the criticism of heaven [in Feuerbach], is transformed into the
criticism of earth (Early Writings 44).
Additionally, Fromm was ambivalent about religion. Fromms approach to the existence of God
walks a fine line between atheism and negative theology. He was likely aware of this. Perhaps if one
considers Spinoza (who profoundly influenced Fromm) as an atheist, one would consider Fromm
188
FROMMS CONCEPTS OF PROPHETIC AND CATASTROPHIC MESSIANISM
an atheist also; if one is uncertain about whether Spinoza is an atheist, one would probably have to
be uncertain about Fromm. Fromms account of hope, of the being mode, and of the X experience
suggest that the experience of transcendence is a genuine, mystical experience of blessedness that
expresses something about the nature of reality. At the end of his life, Fromm was working on a
manuscript arguing that Marx and Dominican mystic Meister Eckhart shared a common religious
concern and were both atheists. Fromm intentionally dances back and forth across these divides.
In Lordship, Bondage, and the Formation of Homo Religiosus, Todd DuBose contrasts Fromms
conception of religious experience with French Hegelian Marxist Alexandre Kojves, defending
Fromms against Kojves. Kojve, DuBose argues, confuses the concept of God for the experience
to which the concept points and consequently sees the experience of God as one of domination
and submission (217-8). Fromm, by contrast, distinguishes between the concept of God and the
experience of God. He holds that the experience of God is the source of our concept of God,
and the attempt to reduce God to a concept, failing to understand God as a human experience, is
idolatry (221). Consequently, what Kojve rejects as God, Fromm rejects as an idol (221, italics
DuBoses). Religious experience remains nameless for Fromm, designated simply by x, in order to
avoid idolatry of it (223). DuBoses critique of Kojve is influenced by Jaspers, under whom Fromm
studied (Funk, Introduction 4). Daniel Burston speaks of the similarity between Fromm and Jaspers
and states that Fromm, Jaspers, and Heidegger belong to a category of phenomenological thought
that is neither explicitly religious nor irreligious (Burston 201).
25
Note that by enlightenment, Adorno and Horkheimer mean neither (only) the historical, eighteenth
century Enlightenment, nor a category existing in abstraction from history. Rather, they conceive
enlightenment as a historical trend towards increasing instrumental reason, beginning with the
creation of myths that sought to offer rational explanations of human beings primal feelings of awe
and wonder (Horkheimer and Adorno 3). Despite the obscurity of the term enlightenment in The
Dialectic of Enlightenment, the book definitely expresses opposition to the historical, eighteenth
century Enlightenment along with opposition to enlightenment in the broader sense of the term
employed by Horkheimer and Adorno.
26
The other of these two areas is Fromms book on dream interpretation, The Forgotten Language,
which also makes significant use of myth. Although it is strongly humanistic and harshly anti-
Jungian, one would expect an argument that Fromm is a mythological, Gnostic thinker to employ
this text. Funk does not mention it in the chapter.
189
CONCLUSION
191
CONCLUSION
192
CONCLUSION
193
CONCLUSION
and utopian tendencies). According to Scholem, the coming messianic age would
mark an absolute break from all that preceded it and would be characterized by
complete otherness. The new apocalyptic, nihilistic, gnostic and antinomian
worldview, reflected in Scholems work, rejected the attempt to build support for
revolution among the masses and instead awaited an intervention of transcendence
that would come at a time of humanitys corruption and failure.
The apocalypticism of Scholem showed that a new option was emerging, although
its contours and implications were unclear. Bloch and Lukcs, however, evolved
in the opposite direction, from apocalyptic messianism to prophetic messianism.
For Lukcs, this transition took the form of a conversion experience, a kind of
Kierkegaardian leap of faith rather than the result of a philosophical argument.
Lukcss leap enabled him to comprehend Marxism practically and theoretically,
simultaneously. For Bloch, the shift was more subtle and gradual but nonetheless
significant. Bloch stood in a complex network of ideas and was drawn both by the
prophetic and apocalyptic tendencies, but he ended unquestionably in the socialist
humanist camp, a defender of the immanent action of human beings in history,
and his work on myth, at least after the 1930s, was aimed not at mystification or
obscurantism but at reclaiming for the revolutionary masses the stories that had long
been the property of the right-wing and finding in these stories tools for universal
human emancipation. Both Bloch and Lukcs evolved towards a greater emphasis
upon immanence and greater wariness of transcendent interventions, although
Bloch (unlike Fromm) continued to view the coming messianic age as the result of a
dramatic break leading to a future of total otherness.
At the opposite end of the political spectrum, as we saw, Stefan Georges circle
represented a restorative messianism seeking return to a past golden age and
viewing itself as the elite protectors of a mythical sacred Germany. Like the
Sabbatean doctrine of redemption through sin, the dramatic change that Georges
circle sought would be ushered in through ritualistic violation of social norms.
Although their conservative revolution was not intended for mass consumption,
this subculture in Schwabing and Heidelberg had broad appeal due to its challenge
to bourgeois social norms, its exultation of the mysterious soul and mythical past,
and its intentional distance from mainstream academic culture. This movement
intrigued Walter Benjamin, and it drew the interest of the young, pre-Marxist
Lukcs and Bloch. Herbert Marcuse may have also felt its pull; at any rate, as
we have seen, two quotations from Stefan George appear in One-Dimensional
Man, situated in such a way as to suggest that Marcuse was intentionally bringing
George and his cultural milieu back into discussion. This is further suggested by
Marcuses employment of a quotation from Heinrich von Kleist, a restorative-
messianic allusion to a return to the Garden of Eden. At the conclusion of the
chapter on the context of the messianism debates in Germany, we also touched
upon Walter Benjamins encounter with the George circle. At the very least
Benjamins encounter with the George circle should show us that Benjamins shift
to Marxism is not as uncomplicated as some suggest, since well into his later work,
194
CONCLUSION
he continues to draw upon a range of sources that make it difficult to pinpoint him
on the political and philosophical spectrum.
After the overview of Fromms early work and the context of the messianism
debates in Germany, we turned to a detailed explication of Fromms philosophical
account of the interconnected concepts of hope and prophetic messianism. We
began by exploring Fromms definition of hope. Fromm offers both a positive and
a negative definition of hope, with the latter being more substantive. According to
the negative definition, hope is not mere desiring or wishing, is not passivity or
inactivity, and does not force the Messiah. Hope is not mere desiring or wishing
because hope requires faith, is active, and is not indifferent to its objects, which
must not be trivial or self-destructive. Hope is not passive or inactive because its
activeness is deeply rooted in human nature, and activity is nested in a philosophical
tradition stretching back to Spinoza, Medieval mystics, and Aristotle, a tradition
according to which activity is not the same as being busy (like a consumer satisfying
impulses) but consists in being a flourishing subject. Finally, hope does not attempt
to force the Messiah; that is, hope neither announces the arrival of messianic
age before its time, nor attempts to make it come before the people are ready.
Forcing the Messiah can take the form of uncritical endorsement of the status quo
or nihilistic destructiveness. Hope is a patience-impatience, which resists both
complacency and nihilistic destructiveness. The positive definition of hope centers
around the concepts of life and potential, as expressed for example in the metaphor
of pregnancy. True hope is an awareness of the potential latent in all that is living or
becoming.
Hope for Fromm may be philosophically justified on the basis of an understanding
of human nature. In Man for Himself (1947) he distinguished between existential
dichotomies and historical contradictions. The key to social transformation
was to know the difference: to accept certain unchangeable paradoxes written into
human nature, while challenging historically contingent social injustices. After
Fromms rediscovery of the early Marx and his study of the 1844 Manuscripts in
the late 1950s and discovering the messianic element in Marx, he seemed to develop
hope that even existential dichotomies might be overcome through a messianic
fulfillment of human hopes. The basis for hope for Fromm became a faith that
nonetheless requires a minimal amount of empirical evidence. This evidence need
not suggest a high probability of success, but merely possibility; where there is any
possibility of avoiding collapse, hope is needed to galvanize efforts for change.
To sit by placidly when faced with potential catastrophe on a global scale is, for
Fromm, as neurotic as waiting to be rescued from a burning building when one
could escape via a stairwell.
Although Fromms argument for hope is grounded in his account of human
nature, he recognizes that philosophical arguments for hope are not the basis of
hope in actual experience. Gabriel Marcel seems to be saying what Fromm was
trying to say: the awareness provided by hope unveils truths that were unavailable
from other standpoints. Although hope may be philosophically justified by ethical
195
CONCLUSION
commitments and conceptions of human nature, hope is not attained as the result
of being convinced by a philosophical argument but through an experience so
mysterious that it seems more like a gift from life itself than a free, conscious choice.
Hope often arises in response to crisis and in response to the posing of alternatives
(one way leading out of the crisis, one way deeper in). The subject chooses to accept
hope and thus to progress to the uniquely revelatory standpoint it provides.
After the chapter on hope, the final chapter gave a careful exegesis of Fromms
prophetic messianism, showing how it is fundamentally opposed to the picture often
presented of the Frankfurt Schools messianism. The messianism of the Frankfurt
School, currently being rediscovered, has been misconstrued as wholly catastrophic,
partly because Fromms version has been excluded. In contrast to the prevailing
model influenced by Gershom Scholems interpretation, Fromms messianism
holds that the messianic age as the outcome of a dialectical synthesis of history
and prehistory: a movement from prehistoric harmony, through disobedience and
alienation in history, to the coming of the liberated humanity.
Unlike the apocalyptic or catastrophic model, Fromms messianism did not
posit an absolute rupture between the present and the future such that the future
is unimaginable and not even partly constructible within the present. Fromms
messianism discouraged mystical anamnesis of the past, instead warning of
the dangers of regression or melancholy. It did not reject the Enlightenment but
embraced it as a radical, unfinished project, while critiquing its excesses and failures.
Fromms messianism neither feared the concept of progress nor reveled in visions
of catastrophe. It did not envision utopia as a project that had ceased to be radical,
destroyed by the relentless march of technical advance. Rather, it found in utopian
thinking a tool for the creation of the future within the horizon of the present. The
chapter concluded with a discussion of the ways in which Fromms messianism
differs from Rainer Funks account of Fromm as advancing an ecstatic-cathartic
dialectic. Funks interpretation in The Courage to Be Human misunderstands
Fromms messianism as gnostic, failing to see the connection of the gnostic view to the
apocalyptic and catastrophic messianism Fromm adamantly rejected throughout his
career. Thus, even leading Fromm scholar Rainer Funks interpretation of Fromms
messianism relied too heavily on Gershom Scholems apocalyptic messianism and
on the Cold War interpretation of messianism as an irrational threat (as seen in his
use of Ernst Topitsch). This dependence on Scholems interpretation and on Cold
War critics is often a problem in the literature on messianism.
Like Fromms reputation broadly and the socialist humanist movement he
represents, prophetic messianic must be recuperated and revivified. It is direly
needed more now than ever. The prophetic messianic spirit provides the only
avenue forward in a society in lock-step advance towards economic and ecological
catastrophe. Now is the time to pose again a crucial alternative of life and death, hope
and despair, future and melancholic attachment to the past. The way forward is not
through the instigation of crises nor passive waiting for transcendence, but through
hopeful, expectant, and active political programs and utopian imaginational projects.
196
CONCLUSION
We need a return to the ideas of immanence, progress, and planning, and a rejection
of the obsession with transcendence, rupture, and suddenness. The latter set of ideas
may play some philosophical or theological role of importance, but transcribed into
the realm of politics they are more dangerous than helpful.
197
CONCLUSION
Hedgesa pessimist who, like Marcuse changed by the New Left, had his hopes
awakened by the Occupy movement:
There are no excuses left. Either you join the revolt taking place on Wall Street
and in the financial districts of other cities across the country or you stand on
the wrong side of history. Either you obstruct, in the only form left to us, which
is civil disobedience, the plundering by the criminal class on Wall Street and
accelerated destruction of the ecosystem that sustains the human species, or
become the passive enabler of a monstrous evil. Either you taste, feel and smell
the intoxication of freedom and revolt or sink into the miasma of despair and
apathy. Either you are a rebel or a slave. (Hedges 1)
At first, whether Occupy would lead to a rebirth of the prophetic messianic spirit or
to deeper levels of despair depended in large part upon whether it would be able to
embrace planning without devolving into reformism. Lack of planning seemed to be
more to the point, as the fear among some left occupiers that the movement might be
co-opted by the Democratic Party was rapidly nullified by events. Whether Occupy
would cede to despair and desperation in the face of police violence also was a
pertinent and urgent question.
Now that the Occupy movement has waned, at least in its initial form, the issue
becomes whether newly formed activists radicalized by Occupy or other movements
will learn that revolution requires a type of patience, not just impatient urgency. It is
not enough to try and failwe must want to win, and we must be in it for the long
haul. In my view, the chances are still good that the long anti-1960s is finally be at
an end. We may be in the midst of what the great prophet of socialist hope, Rosa
Luxemburg, would call a mass strike moment: Occupy was preceded by the Arab/
North African Spring, the uprising in Greece, and labor protests in Wisconsin, and
Occupys zenith was followed by upheaval in Montreal, with hundreds of thousands
of students and allies protesting illegally in the streets in what may have been the
largest act of civil disobedience in Canadian history, and Occupy-like resistance
in Turkey beginning at Gezi Park. As new such mass movements emerge, we also
face a frightening resurgence of the far right in Europe and the United States and
the accelerated march of capitalist globalization, imperialism, hyper-security, and
austerity measures punishing the poor. Nonetheless, great potential for resistance and
transformation exists. The present moment of hope and promise for the left means that
prophetic messianism is making a comeback, and it means all the more that we need
to be wary of the pitfalls presented by catastrophic messianism if we want to succeed.
Before Occupy
During the 2008 U.S. Presidential campaign, the word hope was on the lips of
millions of Americans. Liberals outpouring of affection for Barack Obama expressed
a sense of promise with regard to the future, a hope that the long Bush dynasty might
198
CONCLUSION
finally be at an end, that the war on terror would not rage on indefinitely, that
the U.S.s global image might somehow be salvaged, and that the economic crisis
could be remedied. It was a peculiar kind of hope, followed by very little change,
and arising in the midst of collective desperation and apocalyptic tendencies. Many
Americans felt certainand hope is a kind of certainty, Fromm tells usthat
things would get better after Bush was out of office, but they felt certain merely
because it seemed that things were not capable of getting worse.
Things were going to get better because of some basic principle of logicthe Iron
Law of Worst-ness: Since nothing is worse than what is worst, anything other than
the worst is betteror perhaps some fundamental law of physics: to every action,
an equal and opposite reaction. The pendulum had swung so far to the right that a
return to the left seemed inevitable. Without human assistance, things were about
to improve. This hope required no action. It required no leadership. It required
no protest. It required no new political party. It required no mass-mobilization,
organization, education, or strategy. This hope was passive, though it bore with
it a feeling of pleasure and release. As Angela Davis pointed out two days after
the election at the 2008 Radical Philosophy Association conference1 the election
culminated in a cautious, collective relief, not the full-fledged collective joy that
the media was claiming it was. This hope lacked audacity.
The hope of the Obama campaign was preceded by a growing spirit of
reactionary apocalypticism throughout the country. We were in an endless battle
against an elusive enemy (Terror and Evil). The global economic system
apparently enduring draconian punishment from the Invisible Hand, the almighty
god of the marketwas rapidly speeding towards collapse. Massive pollution
leading to global warmingas the polar bears devoured one another and the arctic
ice-shelf was riddled by avalanches and fissuresand a growing world population,
suggested to others that doom was imminent. Somewhere in the arctic, some primal,
natural force, its hour having come round at last, was moving its slow, furry thighs,
preparing to snuff out the progress of human civilization and reduce humanity to
cave-dwelling barbarism. (It was time for the golem, our own creation, to rise up and
crush us, Battlestar Galactica-style.) How were we suddenly so certain that things
were going to improve?
Americans hope seemed to rest upon a self-contradictory hope for catastrophe,
and this was true of both much of the left-wing and much of the right-wing. The
message of the day was: the worse things are now, the better the future will be. Such
a message is always clearly reactionary; it makes oppression tolerable by deferring
the dreams of the oppressed, who come to believe that their increasing oppression is
the merely birth-pangs of a liberation that will soon descend to them from above, if
they but bear their trials patiently. The right saw in catastrophe the beginning of the
second coming of Christ or a New American Century. Sarah Palin, George W. Bush,
and other right-wing evangelicals had preached the virtues of an apocalypseif only
things will get bad enough in the Middle East, Christ would return to save usand
the neo-cons in general hoped to ring in a future of unbridled U.S. hegemony on the
199
CONCLUSION
coattails of war and destruction. The worse things getthe right-wing thoughtthe
better they will be later.
The left also proved itself susceptible to apocalypticism, and this was particularly
evident throughout the Bush administrations rule. Economic crisis is good,
leftists often find themselves claiming: it means the workers will finally revolt.
A military draft is what we need, some despairing activists whispered or groaned
or even informed Congress: only then will Americans revolt against the Iraq war.
Environmental destruction on a vast scale, others murmured, has the potential to
wipe out our civilization, and then, just maybe, we could start all over with a clean
slate, and evolve the right way, this time around. Nature will rise up to crush us, if
we can just help it alongthis seems to be the vision of some anarcho-primitivists
and even somewhat of environmental theorist Derrick Jensen in his recent film
END:CIV, the resemblances to Ludwig Klages and the era of environmentalist
fascism notwithstanding. (This attitude toward environmental destruction parallels
some responses to the possibility of nuclear destruction during the Cold War that
Fromm critiqued.)
A deluge of Hollywood films presented the destruction of the world to audiences
hungry to observe the coming apocalypse: The Day the Earth Stood Still, 28 Weeks
Later, Quarantine, Apocalypto, Eleventh Hour, 2012, The Happening. The fall of the
twin towers was only the beginning of the catastrophic destruction that lay before us.
The traumatic experience of 9/11which awakened in the American unconscious
the dream of self-destructionwas a prcis, we were warned, the mere beginning
of the end. Films warned that New York City faced much more than a gaping hole
and the deaths of some few thousand people: New York would be wiped away in
a massive flood, followed by turning to ice (The Day After Tomorrow), would be
destroyed in another terrorist attack (Category 7), would turn into a wilderness
populated by ferocious animals and subhuman zombies (I am Legend), or would
face terrorist attacks against the subway system before finally being annihilated by
a solar flare (Knowing). Images abound on movie posters of the Statue of Liberty
toppling or dense city blocks submerged in water or consumed by fire.
Hollywood film Knowing is an interesting case in point. The plot: A strange young
girl begins hearing voices, apocalyptic whispers of future catastrophes. In a fit of
mania, she records a series of numbersthe dates, longitudinal coordinates, and
death tolls for various future catastrophes, beginning (not insignificantly) with 9/11.
Fifty years later, the list falls into the hands of an astrophysicist. The astrophysicist,
unrepentant atheist son of a Protestant minister (asked at the beginning of the film
whether he thinks there is a plan to the universe, he replies sadly, I think shit just
happens), discovers that he has stumbled upon a prediction that the world will end in
a week. In an effort to track down the woman who received the apocalyptic revelations
fifty years ago, he contacts and befriends her adult daughter (also unrepentantly
atheist), whose own young daughter befriends the young son of the astrophysicist.
As the two adultscaught between their parents faith and their childrens innocence
and naivetstruggle to comprehend the worlds impending doom, the two children
200
CONCLUSION
are to all appearances (and to the horror, not surprisingly, of their parents) stalked, by
what appear to be either aliens or pedophiles with superpowers, who whisper in the
childrens minds and try to lure them into strange cars.
At long last the astrophysicist discovers the source of the coming catastrophe:
a solar flare will soon wipe out all life on earth. His son and friends daughter are
rescued at the last minute by the aliens/pedophiles, who arrive from above in their
spaceship and are revealed (so to speak) as angels, suddenly transfigured from their
drab and business-like appearance into glowing, winged figures at the conclusion of
the film. Then the two children, each carrying a rabbit (Noahs ark style), board the
spaceship with the pedophiles/aliens/angels, who tell the astrophysicist that he cant
come; only those who heard the call are permitted to escape. (Those who heard the
call just happen to be two small, lily-white Protestant children from the northeastern
U.S.) The now-repentant astrophysicist returns home to his minister father and family,
who die in each others arms. The two children are shown in Paradise, approaching an
iconic tree. And New Yorkgrubby, dark, anti-social, and unsavedis annihilated in
a wave of light and heat, accompanied by nuclear-like explosions.
The film abounds in symbols of apocalypticism: references to number mysticism,
to the book of Ezekiel, to a new Adam and Eve. However, the most unsettling aspect
of the film is the feeling one gets that the audience is supposed to experience the
conclusion as a happy ending. As he prepares to die, the astrophysicist confidently
promises his family that a better life is coming. Good times ahead! Yet, jarringly,
the world is to all appearances gruesomely, mercilessly annihilated. The angels (or
aliens) are portrayed as cold, frightening, hurtful. They take a seemingly demonic
possession of those whom they claim to help, destroying the freedom of the saved,
transforming them into automatons who are forced to write lines of numbers
(apocalyptic predictions), over and over again against their will. (In one of the
early scenes, the young girl who received the initial prophecy is shown maniacally
scratching the numbers on the inside of a door, her fingers bleeding.) The aliens/
pedophiles/angels have no compassion for the two parents, who are terrified for
their lives and the lives of their children. They coldly tell the father to give up his
son and that he, not having believed, is doomed. There is next to nothing here of
the compassionate core of what Fromm would call humanistic religion. Although
nearly all the apocalyptic predictions in the Bible speak of the coming of justice for
the poor and oppressed, there is not even any indication that the righting of injustices
will come in the future. The apocalypse in Knowing is joyless and fraught with terror.
As Naomi Klein has masterfully articulated in her book The Shock Doctrine: The
Rise of Disaster Capitalism, in the 1950s the neo-conservative Chicago School of
Economics began to advocate a new and oddly apocalyptic strategy for spreading
neoliberalism. At a time when the majority of Western leaders supported some form
of Keynesian economics, the Chicago School advocated a radical break from all state
intervention in the market and the immediate establishment of completely laissez-
faire economies. The attempt to radically and immediately wipe out all vestiges
of a planned economyespecially in Chile, following Pinochets coup, when the
201
CONCLUSION
202
CONCLUSION
true longings and hopes of all remain unfulfilled. While liberals gaze awestruck
into the supernatural light of this apocalyptic moment of Obamas election (and
re-election), their vision gradually grows dimmer and their other senses less keen;
they do not observe the danger that underlies such casual reliance on the power of
another. Under Bushs regime, it had become commonplace in liberal and left circles
to point out the similarities between Bushs administration and Hitlers. Yet many
mainstream Democratic voters now seem remarkably comfortable with ceasing
being watchdogs and placidly trusting the new administration (even, we can add
post-Occupy, confidently accepting massive NSA surveillance and intrusion upon
personal privacy).
As Fromm pointed out, the German working class attempted to escape their
freedom in the wake of the horrific destruction following World War I, destruction
such as they had never before seenthings could not possibly be any worse!
through submission to the will of authorities. The same spirit is at work today in
the American populace. Eager to escape their awesome responsibility to stop the
global military, economic, and environmental catastrophe, they have consecrated
the catastrophe as an act of God, and they have retreated, allowing Obama to be
their decider. As Carl Schmitt pointed out, it is the role played by the decider, as
someone who is appointed to tell us who our enemies are, that is primary, and the
personality or values of the decider are largely irrelevant to creating the permanent
crisis-mentality (the permanent state of emergency) upon which state (and market)
power rests.
The sarcastic and dark tone of this polemical postscript should not be interpreted
to mean that all hope is lost. It means merely that a new kind of hope must be
sought. A revival of the prophetic-messianic spirit, over against the catastrophic-
messianic spirit, is the only solution to the current political crisis. Rather than relying
upon crises to spark revolt, the left must appeal to the prophetic-messianic spirit
still present in the working class (working class broadly construed) hope and
love-of-life. Our hope (politically, at any rate) lies not with an external savior who
will rescue us from catastrophe by bringing an end to history, but with ourselves,
who must be our own saviors. Fromms Feuerbachian move is still the solution
to the problem of our time. Religious eschatology that stands in the catastrophic
tradition need not be discarded entirely, but those who still see dignity in humanity
and subscribe to something like Fromms humanism must allow orthopraxis to take
precedence over orthodoxy and must choose to interpret their traditions in ways that
allow for revolution and progress. Prophetic messianism remains the best engine for
revolutionary praxis.
NOTE
1
This section was inspired by the Fall 2008 Radical Philosophy Association conference in San
Francisco, written largely as a response largely to (1) John Sanbonmatsus paper on messianic time
(Sanbonmatsu very kindly e-mailed me a copy of his paper at my request), (2) Angela Davis history-
203
CONCLUSION
making opening plenary talk, theorizing the election of Obama as, in the long run, yet another let-
down of the messianic hopes of African Americansmessianism came up in her talk, since she
mentioned W. E. B. DuBoiss discussion of the way that the newly emancipated ex-slaves expressed
a messianic hope that in some sense the Lord had come, only to have their hopes dashed, (3) Nick
Braunes paper responding to a comment about Fromms messianism in a Logos article by Kevin
Anderson, and (4) Eduardo Mendietas talk, which impressed me and led me to look up Mendietas
book on Enrique Dussel, in which I found his discussion of the Frankfurt Schools messianism.
204
REFERENCES
Abromeit, J. (2011). Max Horkheimer and the foundations of the Frankfurt School. New York, NY:
Cambridge University Press.
Adorno, T. (1973). Negative dialectics (E. B. Ashton, Trans.). New York, NY: The Seabury Press.
Adorno, T. (1974). Minima moralia: Reflections from damaged life (E. F. N. Jephcott, Trans.).
London,UK:NLB.
Anderson, K., & Richard, Q. (Ed.). (2000). Erich Fromm and critical criminology: Beyond the punitive
society. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press.
Anderson, K. B., & Russell, R. (2012). The Dunayevskaya-Marcuse-Fromm correspondence, 19541978:
Dialogues on Hegel, Marx, and critical theory. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.
Benjamin. W. (1969). Introduction (H. Zohn, Trans.). In H. Arendt (Ed.), Illuminations: Essays and
reflections (pp. 155). New York, NY: Schocken Books.
Assmann, A., Jan, A., & Wolf-Daniel, H. (2010). Introduction to the German edition (W. Rauscher,
Trans.). In E. Fonrobert & A. Engel (Eds.), From cult to culture: Fragments toward a critique of
historical reason, by J. Taubes (p. 456). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Avineri, S. (1985). Moses Hess: Prophet of communism and Zionism. New York, NY: New York
University Press.
Baeck, L. (1958). Judaism and Christianity (W. Kaufmann, Trans.). Philadelphia, PA: The Jewish
Publication Society of America.
Becker, C. L. (2003). The heavenly city of the seventeenth century philosophers. New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press.
Beidler, P. D. (1994). Scriptures for a generation: What we were reading in the 60s. Athens, GA:
University of Georgia Press.
Bellamy, E. (1960). Looking backward. New York, NY: The New American Library.
Benjamin, W. (1969). Illuminations: Essays and reflections (H. Zohn, Trans. & H. Arendt, Ed.). New
York, NY: Schocken Books.
Benjamin, W. (1978). Reflections: Essays, aphorisms, autobiographical writings (E. Jephcott, Trans.).
New York, NY: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.
Benjamin, W. (1997). Goethes elective affinities. In M. Bullock & M. W. Jennings (Eds.), Selected
writings: Volume 1, 19131926 (pp. 297360). Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard
University Press.
Benjamin, W. (1989). Surrealism: The last snapshot of the European intelligentsia. In S. E. Bronner & D.
M. Kellner (Eds.), Critical theory and society: A reader (pp. 172183). New York, NY: Routledge.
Berlin, I. (1969). Four essays on liberty. London, UK: Oxford University Press.
Berman, R., & Tim, L. (1978). Introduction (D. J. Parent, Trans.). In For Socialism (pp. 118), by G.
Landauer. St. Louis: Telos Press.
Biale, D. (1979). Gershom Scholem: Kabbalah and counter-history. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Biale, D. (1992). Gershom Scholem on Jewish messianism. In M. Saperstein (Ed.), Essential papers on
messianic movements and personalities in Jewish history (pp. 521550). New York, NY: New York
University Press.
Binswanger, H. (2009). Ayn Rand answers. Capitalism Magazine.
Bloch, E. (1918). Geist der Utopie. Mnchen, Bavaria: Verlag von Duncker & Humboldt.
Bloch, E. (1990). Heritage of our times (Neville & S. Plaice, Trans.). Berkeley, CA: Polity Press.
Bloch, E. (2009). Atheism in Christianity: The religion of the exodus and the kingdom (J. T. Swan, Trans.).
London: Verso.
Bloch, E., Michael, L., & Vicki, W. H. (1966). Man on his own: Essays in the philosophy of religion (E.
B. Ashton, Trans.). New York, NY: Herder and Herder.
Bloch, E., Michael, L., & Vicki, W. H. (1976). Interview by Ernst Bloch. New German Critique. JSTOR,
9, 3545.
205
REFERENCES
Bloch, E., Michael, L., & Vicki, W. H. (2000). The spirit of utopia (A. A. Nassar, Trans.). Stanford, CA:
Stanford University Press.
Bloom, H. (1975). Kabbalah and criticism. New York, NY: The Seabury Press.
Bloom, H. (1987). Scholem: Unhistorical or Jewish gnosticism. In H. Bloom (Ed.), Gershom Scholem
(pp. 207220). New York, NY: Chelsea House Publishers.
Blumenthal, M. (2009). Republican Gomorrah: Inside the movement that shattered the party. New York,
NY: Nation Books.
Bouretz, P. (2010). Witnesses for the future: Philosophy and messianism (M. B. Smith, Trans.). Baltimore,
MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Brandt, H. (1970). The search for a third way: My path between east and west (A. Salvator, Trans.).
Garden City, NY: Doubleday and Company, Inc.
Braune, J., Erich, F., & Thomas, M. (2011). Biophilia, necrophilia, and messianism. Fromm Forum, 15,
17.
Braune, N. (2011). Fromms biophilia: Insights from Sigmund Freuds mission. Fromm Forum, 15, 17.
Braune, N., & Joan, B. (2009). Erich Fromms socialist program and prophetic messianism. Radical
Philosophy Review, 12(12), 355389.
Bronner, S. (2002). Of critical theory and its theorists (2nd ed.). New York, NY: Routledge.
Buber, M. (1949). Paths in Utopia (R. F. C. Hull, Trans.). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Buck-Morss, S. (1989). The dialectics of seeing: Walter Benjamin and the arcades project. Cambridge,
MA: The MIT Press.
Buck-Morss, S., & Walter, B. (1984). An aesthetic of redemption. Rev. of Walter Benjamin: An Aesthetic
of Redemption, by R. Wolin. Theory and Society, 13, 743748.
Bucke, R. M. (1940). Cosmic consciousness: A study in the evolution of the human mind. New York, NY:
E. P. Dutton.
Burston, D. (2007). Reply to Pnina Shinebournes essay review in existential analysis 17.2 on The art of
loving by Erich Fromm. Existential Analysis 18(1), 198201.
Butler, J. (2010). Introduction (A. Bostock, Trans.). In J. T. Sanders, & K. Terezakis, Soul and form (pp.
115) by G. Lukcs. New York: Columbia University Press.
Cartwright, J. (2012). Prophet of doom. The Guardian, 15.
Cassirer, E. (2009). The philosophy of the enlightenment (F. C. A. Koelln & J. P. Pettegrove, Trans.).
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Cavanaugh, W. T. (2009). The myth of religious violence: Secular ideology and the roots of modern
conflict. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Chalubiksi, M. (2001). The sane society: Remarks on Utopianism by Erich Fromm (A. Rodziska-
Chojnowska, Trans.). Dialogue and Universalism, 7, 77104.
Cheliotis, L. K. (2010). Naricissism, humanism and the revolutionary character in Erich Fromms work.
In L. K. Cheliotis (Ed.), Roots, rites and sites of resistance: The banality of good. Basingstoke,
Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan.
Cocalis, S. L. (1978). The transformation of Bildung from an image to an ideal. Monatshefte, 70, 399
414.
Cohen, H. (1971). Reason and hope: Selections from the Jewish writings of Hermann Cohen (E. Jospe,
Trans.). Cincinnati, OH: Hebrew Union College Press.
Cohen, H. (1995). Religion of reason out of the sources of Judaism (S. Kaplan, Trans.). Atlanta, GA:
Scholars Press.
Colman, A. M. (2001). A dictionary of psychology. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Critchley, S. (2011). Is utopianism dead? The Harvard Advocate, Winter, 18.
De, M., & Sonja, G. The history of the International Federation of Psychoanalytic Societies.
Internationalen Erich Fromm Gessellschaft.
Derrida, J. (1994). Specters of Marx: The state of the debt, the work of mourning, and the new International
(P. Kamuf, Trans.). New York, NY: Routledge.
Deuber-Mankowsky, A. (2005). Hanging over the abyss: On the relation between knowledge and
experience in Hermann Cohen and Walter Benjamin. In R. Munk (Ed.), Hermann Cohens critical
idealism. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Springer.
206
REFERENCES
Deutscher, I. (1968). The non-Jewish Jew and other essays. London, UK: Oxford University Press.
DuBose, T. (2000). Lordship, bondage, and the formation of the homo religiosus. Journal of Religion and
Health, 39(3), 217226.
Dubnov, A. (2008). Priest or jester? Jacob L. Talmon (19161980) on history and intellectual engagement.
History of European Ideas, 34, 133145.
Dunham, K. (1969). Island possessed. Garden City, NY: Doubleday and Company, Inc.
Erich Fromm: The Mike Wallace interview. Retrieved from http://www.hrc.utexas.edu/multimedia/
video/2008/wallace/fromm_erich_t.html
Ers, F. (1992). Wilhelm Reich, Erich Fromm, and the analytical social psychology of the Frankfurt School.
Retrieved from http://www.erich-fromm.de/biophil/en/images/stories/pdf-Dateien/Eroes_F_1992.pdf
Farr, A. L. (2009). Critical theory and democratic vision: Herbert Marcuse and recent liberation
philosophies. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
Fedderson, J. (2007). Erich Fromm: Die Kunst der Abfuhr. Die Tageszeitung. Retrieved September 10,
2007 from http://www.taz.de/?id=start&art=4394&id=theorie-artikel&cHash=c1595411ff
Fiorato, P. (2005). Notes on future and history in Hermann Cohens anti-eschatological messianism. In M.
Reinier (Ed.), Hermann Cohens critical idealism (pp. 133160). Netherlands: Springer.
Fishman, S. M., & McCarthy. L. (2007). John Dewey and the philosophy and practice of hope. Urbana,
IL: University of Illinois Press.
Fleming, P. (2004). The secret Adorno. Qui Parle, 15(1), 97114.
Foa, R., & Meaney, T. (2011). The last word. The Utopian. Retrieved February 22, 2011 from http://www.
the-utopian.org/post/3217295807/the-last-word
Freire, P. (2006). Pedagogy of hope: Reliving pedagogy of the oppressed (R.R. Barr, Trans., & A. Maria
& A. Freire, Eds.). London: Continuum,
Friedman, L. J. (2013). The lives of Erich Fromm: Loves prophet. New York, NY: Columbia University
Press.
Fromm, E. (1951). The forgotten language: An introduction to the understanding of dreams, fairy tales,
and myths. New York, NY: Grove Press, Inc.
Fromm, E. (1955). The human implications of instinctivistic radicalism. Dissent, 2(4), 342349.
Fromm, E. (1955). The sane society. New York, NY: Rinehart and Company.
Fromm, E. (1956). The art of loving. New York, NY: Harper & Row.
Fromm, E. (1959). Sigmund Freuds mission: An analysis of his personality and influence. New York, NY:
Harper & Brothers Publishers.
Fromm, E. (1960). A foreword by Erich Fromm. In A.S. Neill (Ed.), Summerhill: A radical approach to
child rearing. New York, NY: Hart Publishing Company.
Fromm, E. (1960). Foreword. In E. Bellamy (Ed.), Looking backward (pp. 520). New York, NY: The
New American Library of World Literature, Inc.
Fromm, E. (1961). May man prevail?: An inquiry into the facts and fictions of foreign policy. Garden City,
NY: Doubleday and Co.
Fromm, E. (1963). Beyond the chains of illusion: My encounter with Marx and Freud. New York, NY:
Pocket Books, Inc.
Fromm, E. (1963) . War within man: A psychological enquiry into the roots of destructiveness.
Philadelphia, PA: American Friends Service Committee.
Fromm, E. (1964). The heart of man: Its genius for good and evil. New York, NY: Harper & Row.
Fromm, E. (1966). The dogma of Christ: And other essays on religion, psychology, and culture. Garden
City, NY: Anchor Books, Doubleday & Company.
Fromm, E. (1966). You shall be as gods: A radical interpretation of the old testament and its tradition.
New York, NY: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.
Fromm, E. (1967) . Martyrs and heroes. Retrieved from http://www.erich-fromm.de/data/pdf/1990s-e.pdf
Fromm, E. (1968). The revolution of hope: Towards a humanized technology. New York, NY: Harper &
Row.
Fromm, E. (1970). Foreword (H. Brandt, Trans.). In S. Attanasio (Ed.), The search for a third way: My
path between east and west. Garden City, NY: Doubleday.
207
REFERENCES
Fromm, E. (1968). Marxs contribution to the knowledge of man. In E. Fromm (Ed.), The crisis of
psychoanalysis: Essays on Freud, Marx, and social psychology (pp. 6276). New York, NY: Henry
Holt and Company.
Fromm, E. (1970). The crisis of psychoanalysis: Essays on Freud, Marx, and social psychology. New
York, NY: Henry Holt and Company.
Fromm, E. (1974). The anatomy of human destructiveness. New York, NY: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.
Fromm, E. (1978). Psychoanalysis and religion. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Fromm, E. (1980). Greatness and limitations of Freuds thought. New York, NY: Harper & Row.
Fromm, E. (1981). On disobedience and other essays. New York, NY: The Seabury Press.
Fromm, E. (1984). Afterword (pp. 257267) by G. Orwell.
Fromm, E. (1989). Politics and psychoanalysis. In S. E. Bronner & D. M. Kellner (Eds.), Critical theory
and society: A reader (pp. 213218). New York, NY: Routledge.
Fromm, E. (1989). Das jdische Gesetz: Zur Soziologie des Diaspora-Judentums: Dissertation von 1922.
Weinheim, Germany: Beltz Verlag.
Fromm, E. (1990). Man for himself: An inquiry into the psychology of ethics. New York, NY: Henry Holt
and Company.
Fromm, E. (1994). On being human. New York, NY: Continuum Publishing Company.
Fromm, E. (1994). The art of listening. New York, NY: Continuum.
Fromm, E. (2000). Autobiographical sidelights. International Forum of Psychoanalysis, 9, 251253.
Fromm, E. (2000). The social determinants of psychoanalytic therapy. International Forum of
Psychoanalysis, 9(34), 149165.
Fromm, E. (2004). Marxs concept of man. London, UK: Continuum.
Fromm, E. (2004). The art of being. New York, NY: Continuum.
Fromm, E. (2009). Being centrally related to the patient. In R. Funk (Ed.), The clinical Erich Fromm:
Personal accounts and papers on therapeutic technique. Amsterdam, Netherland: Rodopi.
Fromm, E. (2009). To have or to be? New York, NY: Continuum.
Fromm, E. (2010). Beyond Freud: From individual to social psychoanalysis. Riverdale, NY: American
Mental Health Foundation Inc.
Fromm, E. (2010). The pathology of normalcy (American Mental Health Foundation, Inc., Trans.).
Riverdale, NY: American Mental Health Foundation, Inc.
Fromm, E. (2012). Psychoanalysis and sociology. Retrieved February 18, 2012 from http://www.
philosophy.ru/upload/1158745816_file.pdf
Fromm, E. (Ed.) (1965). The application of humanist psychoanalysis to Marxs theory. Socialist
Humanism: An International Symposium. Garden City, NY.
Fromm, E. (2000). A letter from Erich Fromm to Jan Strezelecki. Dialogue and Universalism, 10(5/6),
175.
Fromm, E. (1972). Escape from freedom. New York, NY: Avon Books.
Fromm, E . The social philosophy of will therapy. Retrieved from http://www.erich-fromm.de/data/
pdf/1939a-e.pdf
Fromm, E., Hart, W. O., Davidson, W. C., Valentine, B., & Kempton, M. (1960). We have a visiona
deep faith: 5 statements on why join the Socialist Party-Social Democratic Federation. New York,
NY: Socialist Party-Social Democratic Federation.
Funk, R. (1982). Erich Fromm: The courage to be human (M. Shaw, Trans.). New York, NY: Continuum.
Funk, R. (1999). Introduction. In A. Kevin (Ed.), Erich Fromm and critical criminology: Beyond the
punitive society. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press.
Funk, R. (2000). Erich Fromm: His life and ideas: An illustrated biography. New York, NY: Continuum.
Funk, R. (2003). Major points in Erich Fromms thought (originally a talk at 1975 conference, Possibilities
of psychoanalysis: Retrospect and prospects in honor of Erich Fromms 75th birthday). Retrieved July
3, 2011 from http://www.erich-fromm.de/data/pdf/Funk,%20R.,%201975a.pdf
Funk, R. (2003). The Jewish roots of Erich Fromms humanistic thinking. Retrieved from http://www.
erich-fromm.de/data/pdf/Funk,%20R.,%201988f.pdf
Galli, B. E. (1999). Introduction. In A. Udoff & B. E. Galli. (Eds. & Trans.), Franz Rosenzweigs The new
thinking (pp. 141). New York, NY: Syracuse University Press.
208
REFERENCES
Gay, P. (2001). Weimar culture: The outsider as insider. New York, NY: W. W. Norton & Company.
Gertel, E. B. (1999). Judaism: Fromm, Freud, and Midrash. EBSCOHost, 48(4), 429439.
Geuss, R. (2004). Dialectics and the revolutionary impulse. In F. Rush (Ed.), The Cambridge companion
to critical theory (pp. 103138). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Goggin, J. E., & Eileen, B. G. (2001). Death of a Jewish science: Psychoanalysis in the third Reich.
Bloomington, IN: Purdue University Press.
Gray, J. (2007). Black mass: Apocalyptic religion and the death of utopia. New York, NY: Farrar, Straus
and Giroux.
Groiser, D. (2005). Jewish law and tradition in the early work of Erich Fromm. In M. Kohlenbach & R.
Guess (Eds.), The early Frankfurt School and religion. New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.
Gutierrez, G. (1991). A theology of liberation: History, politics, and salvation (S. C. Inda & J. E.
Maryknoll, Trans. & Eds.). New York, NY: Orbis Books.
Habermas, J. (2002). Religion and rationality: Essays on reason, religion, and modernity. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Hansen, J. (1956) . A psychoanalyst looks for a sane society. Fourth International, 17(2), 6569. Retrieved
May 18, 2009 from http://www.marxists.org/archive/hansen/1956/xx/psych.htm
Hartman, D. (2011). Sinai and Exodus: Two grounds for hope in the Jewish tradition. Religious Studies,
14(3), 373387. Retrieved February 10, 2011 from http://www.jstor.org/stable/pdfplus/20005502.
pdf?acceptTC=true
Hausdorff, D. (1972). Erich Fromm. New York, NY: Twayne Publishers.
Held, D. (1980). Introduction to critical theory: Horkheimer to Habermas. Berkeley, CA: University of
California Press.
Hooks, B. (2000). All about love: New visions. New York, NY: Harper Perennial.
Hooks, B. (2010). Surrendered to love: Martin Luther Kings legacy. Retrieved from http://mindful.org/
the-mindful-society/activism/surrendered-to-love-martin-luther-king%E2%80%99s-legacy
Horkheimer, M., & Adorno, T. W. (2002). Dialectic of enlightenment: Philosophical fragments (G. S.
Noerr Ed., & E. Jephcott, Trans.). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Hornstein, G. A. To redeem one person is to redeem the world: The life of Frieda Fromm-Reichmann.
New York, NY: The Free Press.
Hudson, W. (1982). The Marxist philosophy of Ernst Bloch. New York, NY: St. Martins Press.
Huffman, R. (2009). The gun speaks: The Baader-Meinhof at the dawn of terror. Retrieved August 29,
2009 from http://www.baader-meinhof.com/gunspeaks/gunintrochapter.html
Idel, M. (1988). Messianic mystics. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
International Federation of Psychoanalytic Societies (IFPS). (2011). Retrieved December 17, 2011 from
http://www.ifps-online.com/index.html
International Federation of Psychoanalytic Societies (IFPS). (2013). Retrieved August 10, 2013 from
http://www.ifp-s.org/
Jamison, A. (1994). Seeds of the sixties. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Janaway, C. (2002). Schopenhauer: A very short introduction. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Janik, A. (1973). Wittgensteins Vienna. New York, NY: Simon and Schuster.
Jay, M. (1973). The dialectical imagination: A history of the Frankfurt School and the Institute of Social
Research, 1923-1950. Boston, MA: Little, Brown and Company.
Jay, M. (1984). Marxism and totality: The adventures of a concept from Lukcs to Habermas. Berkeley,
CA: University of California Press.
Jay, M. (1993). Force fields: Between intellectual history and cultural critique. New York, NY: Routledge
Jay, M. (2009) . Walter Benjamin, remembrance, and the First World War. Retrieved July 13, 2009 from
http://www.march.es/ceacs/publicaciones/working/archivos/1996_87.pdf
Johnston, C. (2012). Starvation of a witness. Retrieved February 2012 from http://www.
southerncrossreview.org/15/weil.htm#ref10
Jonas, H. (1963). The gnostic religion: The message of the alien god and the beginnings of Christianity
(2nd ed.). Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
Kant, I. (1999). On the common saying: That may be correct in theory, but it is of no use in practice. In M.J.
Gregor (Ed. & Trans.), Practical Philosophy (pp. 273310). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
209
REFERENCES
Katz, M. S. (1987). Ban the bomb: A history of SANE, the committee for a sane nuclear policy. New York,
NY: Praeger.
Kellner, D. (n.d.). Erich Fromm, Judaism, and the Frankfurt School. Retrieved from http://www.gseis.
ucla.edu/faculty/kellner/essays/erichfrommjudaism.pdf
Kellner, D. (1984). Herbert Marcuse and the crisis of Marxism. Houndmills, UK: MacMillan.
Kellner, D. (1991). Introduction to the second edition. One-dimensional man: Studies in the ideology of
advanced industrial society by H. Marcuse. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
Klein, N. (2007). The shock doctrine: The rise of disaster capitalism. New York, NY: Henry Holt and
Company.
Kleist, H. (1976). Puppet theatre. Salmagundi, 33/34, 8388.
Knapp, G. P. (1989). The art of living: Erich Fromms life and works. New York, NY: Peter Lang.
Kohlenbach, M., & Guess, R. (Eds.). (2005). The early Frankfurt School and religion. Houndmills,
Basingstoke, Hampshire, UK: Palgrave MacMillan.
Kolakowski, L. (1968). Towards a Marxist humanism: Essays on the left today (J. Z. Peel, Trans.). New
York, NY: Grove Press, Inc.
Kolakowski, L. (2005). Main currents of Marxism (P. S. Falla, Trans.). New York, NY: W. W. Norton &
Company.
Koltun-Fromm, K. (2010). Material culture and Jewish thought in America. Bloomington, IN: Indiana
University Press.
Kouvelakis, S. (2003). Philosophy and revolution: Philosophy and revolution from Kant to Marx (G. M.
Goshgarian, Trans.). London: Verso.
La Vopa, A. (1997). The philosopher and the Schwrmer : On the career of a German epithet from Luther
to Kant. The Huntington Library Quarterly, 60(1/2), Enthusiasm and Enlightenment in Europe, 1650
1850, 85115.
Landauer, G. Aufruf zum Socialismus. Retrieved from http://www.anarchismus.at/anarchistische-
klassiker/gustav-landauer/108-gustav-landauer-aufruf-zum-sozialismus-teil-1 3/4/12
Landauer, G. Anarchism in Germany and other essays. Oakland, CA: AK Press.
Landauer, G. (1978). For socialism (D. J. Parent, Trans.). St. Louis, MO: Telos Press.
Landauer, G. (2010). Revolution and other writings: A political reader (G. Kuhn, Ed. & Trans.). Oakland,
CA: PM Press.
Lane, R. (2005). Reading Walter Benjamin: Writing through the catastrophe. Manchester, NY: Manchester
University Press.
Large, W. (2010). Time & money: Philosophy of religion and the critique of capital. Retrieved from http://
www.jcrt.org/archives/09.1/Large.pdf
Lazier, B. (2008). God interrupted: Heresy and the European imagination between the world wars.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Leaman, O. (2003). Jewish existentialism: Rosenzweig, Buber, and Soloveitchik. In D. H. Frank & O.
Leaman (Eds.), History of Jewish philosophy. London: Routledge.
Lebovic, N. (2006). The beauty and terror of Lebensphilosophie: Ludwig Klages, Walter Benjamin, and
Alfred Baeumler. South Central Review, 23, 2339.
Lebovic, N. (2004). Dionysian politics and the discourse of Rausch (pp. 19). Working Papers, UCLA
Center for European and Eurasian Studies.
Lebovic, N. (2008). The Jerusalem school: The theopolitical hour. New German Critique, 97120.
Lefebvre, H. (2008). Critique of everyday life. (Vol. 1). (J. Moore, Trans.). London: Verso.
Lilla, M. (2007). The stillborn God: Religion, politics, and the modern West. New York, NY: Alfred A.
Knopf.
Lilley, S., McNalley, D., Yuen, E., & Davis, J. (2012). Catastrophism: The apocalyptic politics of collapse
and rebirth. Oakland, CA: PM Press.
Lwenthal, L. (1987). An unmastered past: The autobiographical reflections of Leo Lowenthal. Berkeley,
CA: University of California Press, Ltd.
Lwith, K. (1949). Meaning in history. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Lowy, M. (1980). Jewish messianism and libertarian utopia in central Europe (19001933). New German
Critique, 20, 105115.
210
REFERENCES
Lowy, M. (1992). Redemption and utopia: Jewish libertarian thought in central Europe: A study in
elective affinity (H. Heaney, Trans.). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Lowy, M. (2001). Messianism in the early work of Gershom Scholem. New German Critique, 83, 177191.
Lowy, M. (2009). Capitalism as religion: Benjamin and Weber. Historical Materialism, 17, 6073.
Lowy, M. (2012) Anticapitalist readings of Webers Protestant ethic: Ernst Bloch, Walter Benjamin, Georg
Lukacs, Erich Fromm. Logos Journal, 9(1) . Retrieved January 26, 2012 from http://logosjournal.
com/2010/lowy/
Lukcs, G. (1971). History and class consciousness: Studies in Marxist dialectics (R. Livingstone,
Trans.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Lukcs, G. (1971). The theory of the novel: A historico-philosophical essay on the forms of great epic
literature (A. Bostok, Trans.). Cambridge, MA: The M.I.T. Press.
Lukcs, G. (1980). The destruction of reason (P. Palmer, Trans.). London: The Merlin Press.
Lukcs, G. (2010). Soul and form (A. Bostock, Trans.). J. T. Sanders & K. Terezakis, (Eds.). Introduction.
Judith Butler. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.
Lundgren, S. (1999). The fight against idols: Erich fromm on religion, Judaism, and the Bible. Frankfurt
am Main: Peter Lang.
Luxemburg, R. (1979). Socialism and the churches. Marxist internet archive. Retrieved March 3, 2009
from http://www.marxists.org/archive/luxemburg/1905/misc/socialism-churches.htm
Luxemburg, R. (1980). Theory & practice. Marxist internet archive. Retrieved February 1, 2011 from
http://www.marxists.org/archive/luxemburg/1910/theory-practice/ch05.htm
MacIntyre, A. (2006). Edith Stein: A philosophical prologue: 19131922. Lanham, MD: Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, Inc.
Magid, S. (2008). Gershom scholem. In E. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall
ed.). Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/scholem/
Marcel, G. (1951). Homo viator: Introduction to a metaphysic of hope (E. Crauford, Trans.). Chicago, IL:
Henry Regnery Company.
Marcuse, H. (1955). The social implications of Freudian revisionism. Dissent, 2(3), 221240.
Marcuse, H. (1965). Socialist humanism? In E. Fromm (Ed.), Socialist humanism: An international
symposium. Garden City, NY: Doubleday & Company, Inc.
Marcuse, H. (1966). Eros and civilization: A philosophical inquiry into Freud. Boston, MA: Beacon
Press.
Marcuse, H. (1969). An essay on liberation. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
Marcuse, H. (1991). One-dimensional man: Studies in the ideology of advanced industrial society.
Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
Marcuse, H. (1999). Reason and revolution: Hegel and the rise of social theory. Amherst, NY: Prometheus
Books.
Marcuse, H. (2005). The new left and the 1960s. In D. Kellner (Ed.), Collected papers of Herbert Marcuse
(Vol. 3). London: Routledge.
Marx, K. (1965). Early writings (T. B. Bottomore, Ed. & Trans.). New York, NY: McGraw-Hill.
Marx, K. (1977). In D. McLellan (Ed.), Karl Marx: Selected Writings. Oxford, UK: Oxford University
Press.
Marx, K. (2007). Introduction to the contribution to a critique of Hegels philosophy of right. Marxist
Internet Archive. Retrieved April 22, 2007 from http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1843/
critique-hpr/index.htm
Marx, K. (2011). Theses on Feuerbach. Marxist internet archive, 14. Retrieved July 14, 2011 from http://
www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1845/theses/index.htm
McLaughlin, N. (2012). Critical theory meets America: Riesman, Fromm, and the lonely crowd. Retrieved
January 23, 2012 from http://tucnak.fsv.cuni.cz/~hajek/ModerniSgTeorie/literatura/kritickateorie/
krit_teorie1.pdf
McLaughlin, N. (1998). How to become a forgotten intellectual: Intellectual movements and the rise and
fall of Erich Fromm. Sociological Forum, 13, 215246.
McLaughlin, N. (1999). Origin myths in the social sciences: Fromm, the Frankfurt School and the
emergence of critical theory. Retrieved July 6, 2009 from http://www.ualberta.ca/~cjscopy/articles/
mclaughlin.html
211
REFERENCES
Mendieta, E. (2007). Global fragments: Globalizations, Latinamericanisms, and critical theory. Albany,
NY: State University of New York Press.
Merleau-Ponty, M. (2003). Nature: Course notes from the Collge of France. Evanston, IL: Northwestern
University Press.
Merton, T. (1968). The answer of Minerva: Pacifism and resistance in Simone Weil. Retrieved February
12, 2011 from http://www.dartmouth.edu/~engl5vr/Merton.html
Merton, T., & Erich, F . Fromm/Merton letters. Archives at Bellarmine University, LA and at University
of Kentucky, KY.
Merton, T. (1988). A vow of conversation: Journals, 1964-1965. N. B. Stone (Ed). New York, NY: Farrar,
Straus, Giroux.
Milln, S., & Gojman, S. (2000). The legacy of Fromm in Mexico. International Forum of Psychoanalysis,
9, 207215.
Miri, S. J. (2010). Religion and social theory in the frommesque discourse. Islamic perspective, 4.
Retrieved January 26, 2012 from http://iranianstudies.org/wp-content/uploads/2010/12/Ipcss4-LAIS.
pdf
Miri, S. J. (2010) . Rereading Fromms conditions of the human situation. Transcendent Philosophy: An
International Journal for Comparative Philosophy and Mysticism. 11, 233. Retrieved January 26,
2012 from http://iranianstudies.org/wp-content/uploads/2010/04/Trans-Phil-Vol11-e3-Web.pdf
Mittelman, A. (2009). Hope in a democratic age: Philosophy, religion, and political theory. Oxford, UK:
Oxford University Press.
Morgan, M. (2001). Interim Judaism: Jewish thought in a century of crisis. Bloomington, IN: Indiana
University Press.
Moltmann, J. (1996). The coming of God: Christian eschatology (M. Kohl, Trans.). Minneapolis, MN:
Fortress Press.
Neumann, B. (2000). The National Socialist politics of life. New German Critique, 85, 107130.
Noll, R. (1994). The Jung cult: Origins of a charismatic movement. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Norton, R. E. (2002). Secret Germany: Stefan George and his circle. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Novalis. (1997). Philosophical writings (M. M. Stoljar, Trans.). Albany, NY: State University of New
York Press.
Ohana, D. (2010). Political theologies in the holy land: Israeli messianism and its critics. London:
Routledge.
Osborne, P., & Matthew, C. (2011). Walter Benjamin. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of
philosophy (Spring ed.). Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/benjamin
Pangilinan, R. (2009). Against alienation: The emancipative potential of critical pedagogy in Erich
Fromm. Kritike, 3(2), 2129. Retrieved from http://www.kritike.org/journal/issue_6/pangilinan_
december2009.pdf
Pietikainen, P. (2007). Alchemists of human nature: Psychological utopianism in Gross, Jung, Reich, and
Fromm. London: Pickering & Chatto.
Pollock, B. (2009). Franz Rosenzweig. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall
ed.). Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2009/entries/rosenzweig/
Poma, A. (1997). The critical philosophy of Hermann Cohen (J. Denton, Trans.). New York, NY: State
University of New York Press.
Rabinbach, A. (1997). In the shadow of catastrophe: German intellectuals between apocalypse and
enlightenment. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Rabinbach, A. (1985). Between enlightenment and apocalypse: Benjamin, Bloch and modern Jewish
messianism. New German Critique, 34, 103.
Rabinkow, S. B. (1987). The individual and society in Judaism. In L. Jung (Ed.), Sages and Saints (pp.
133155). Hoboken, NJ: The Jewish library, Vol. X. Ktav Publishing House, Inc.
Rand, A. (1966). Capitalism: The unknown ideal. New York, NY: The New American Library, Inc.
Rickert, J. (1986). The Fromm-Marcuse Debate Revisited. Theory and Society, 15, 351400. Dordrecht,
Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers. Retrieved February 11, 2012 from http://www.erich-
fromm.de/biophil/joomla/images/stories/pdf-Dateien/Rickert_J_1986.pdf
212
REFERENCES
Roazen, P. (2001). The exclusion of Erich Fromm from the IPA. Contemporary Psychoanalysis, 37(1),
542. Retrieved June 26, 2011 from http://www.erich-fromm.de/data/pdf/Roazen,%20P.,%202001.
pdf
Roazen, P. (2000). Fromms Escape from freedom and his standing today. International Forum of
Psychoanalysis, 9(3/4), 239240.
Rockmore, T. (1980). Fichte, Marx, and the German philosophical tradition. Carbondale, IL: Southern
Illinois University Press.
Rosenzweig, F. (1971). The star of redemption (W. W. Hallo, Trans). Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
Rothstein, E., Muschamp, H., & Marty, M. E. (2003). Visions of utopia. Oxford, UK: Oxford University
Press. Retrieved December 14, 2009 from http://www.scribd.com/doc/22472651/rothstein-et-al-
visions-of-utopia-2003
Saperstein, M. (Ed.). (1992). Essential papers on messianic movements and personalities in Jewish
history. New York, NY: New York University Press.
Saunders, F. S. (1999). The cultural cold war: The CIA and the world of arts and letters. New York, NY:
The New Press.
Schacter, J. J. (Ed.). (1987). Reminiscences of Shlomo Barukh Rabinkow. In L. Jung (Ed.), Sages and
saints (Vol. X, pp. 93132). Hoboken, NJ: The Jewish library, Ktav Publishing House, Inc.
Schaeder, G. (1996). Martin Buber: A biographical sketch (R. C. Winston & H. Zohn, Trans.). In N. M.
Glatzer & P. Mendes-Flohr (Eds.), The letter of Martin Buber: A life of dialogue (pp. 162). Syracuse,
NY: Syracuse University Press.
Scholem, G. (1954). Major trends in Jewish mysticism. New York, NY: Schocken Books.
Scholem, G. (1971). The messianic idea in Judaism and other essays on Jewish spirituality. New York,
NY: Schocken Books.
Scholem, G. (1973). Sabbatai Sevi: The mystical messiah (16261676). Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Scholem, G. (1976). On Jews and Judaism in crisis: Selected essays (W. J. Dannhauser, Ed.). New York,
NY: Schocken.
Scholem, G. (1980). From Berlin to Jerusalem: Memories of my youth (H. Zohn, Trans.). New York, NY:
Schocken Books.
Schroyer, T. (1973). The critique of domination: The origins and development of critical theory. Boston,
MA: Beacon Press.
Shannon, W. H. (2003). Thomas Merton and Judaism. In B. Bruteau (Ed.), Merton & Judaism:
Recognition, repentance, and renewal: Holiness in words. Louisville, KY: Fons Vitae.
Shell, S. (2009), To spare the vanquished and crush the arrogant: Leo Strauss lecture on German
Nihilism. In S. B. Smith (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Leo Strauss (pp. 171192). Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Siebert, R. J. (1985). The critical theory of religion: The Frankfurt School from universal pragmatic to
political theology. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter & Co.
Silver, A. S. (1999). Frieda Fromm-Reichmann and Erich Fromm. International Forum of Psychoanalysis,
8, 1923.
Specter, M. G. (2010). Habermas: An intellectual biography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Spirer, E. (2010). Candidates for survival: A talk with Harold Bloom. Boston Review, 15. Retrieved
September 13, 2010 from http://bostonreview.net/BR11.1/bloom.html
Susman, M. (1999). The exodus from philosophy. In A. Udoff & B. E. Galli (Ed. & Trans.), Franz
Rosenzweigs The New Thinking (pp. 105111). Syracuse, NY: Syracuse University Press.
Suzuki, D. T., Fromm, E., & De Martino, R. (1963). Zen Buddhism and psychoanalysis. New York, NY:
Grove Press, Inc.
Swedberg, R., & Reich, W. Georg Simmels aphorisms. Theory, culture, and society, 2451. Retrieved March
3, 2012 from http://www.soc.cornell.edu/faculty/swedberg/Georg%20Simmels%20Aphorisms.pdf
Tar, Z. (1977). The Frankfurt School: The critical theories of Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno.
New York, NY: John Wiley and Sons.
Taubes, J. (2010). From cult to culture: Fragments toward a critique of historical reason (E. Fonrobert &
A. Engel, Ed.). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
213
REFERENCES
Taubes, J. (2009). Occidental eschatology (D. Ratmoko, Trans.). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Taubes, S. A. (1967). Simone Weil: The absent God. In T. J. J. Altizer (Ed.), Toward a new Christianity:
Readings in the death of God theology (pp.107119). New York, NY: Harcourt, Brace & World, Inc.
Thomson, A. (2009). Erich Fromm: Explorer of the human condition. Houndmills, Basingstroke, UK:
Palgrave MacMillan.
Toscano, A. (2010). Fanaticism: On the uses of an idea. London: Verso.
Treanor, B. (2010). Gabriel (-Honor) Marcel. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of
philosophy (Fall ed.). Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/marcel/
Vickrey, D. (2010). Erich Fromm and the Baader-Meinhof. Dialog International. Retrieved August 28,
2010 from http://www.dialoginternational.com/dialog_international/2007/09/erich-fromm-and.html
Viviano, B. T. (1980). The kingdom of God in Albert the Great and Thomas Aquinas. Thomist: A
Speculative Quarterly Review, 44(4), 502522.
Waggoner, M. (2006). The Frankfurt School on religion. Journal of Cultural and Religious Theory.
Retrieved March 3, 2010 from http://www.jcrt.org/archives/08.1/waggoner.pdf
Watkins, M., & Shulman, H. (2008). Towards psychologies of liberation. Houndmills, UK: Palgrave
MacMillan.
Weil, S. (1986). Simone Weil: An anthology (S. Miles, Ed. & Trans.). New York, NY: Grove Press.
Whitebook, J. (2004). The marriage of Marx and Freud: Critical theory and psychoanalysis. In F. Rush
(Ed.), The Cambridge companion to critical theory (pp. 74102). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press.
Wheatland, T. (2009). The Frankfurt School in exile. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Whyte, W. H. Jr. (1956). The organization man. New York, NY: Simon and Schuster.
Wiggershaus, R. (1994). The Frankfurt School: Its history, theories, and political significance
(M.Robertson, Trans.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Wilde, L. (2001). Against idolatry: The humanistic ethics of Erich Fromm. Marxisms Ethical Thinkers.
L. Wilde. (Ed.), Houndmills, U.K.: Palgrave.
Wilde, L. (2004). Erich Fromm and the quest for solidarity. New York, NY: Palgrave MacMillan.
Wolin, R. (n.d.). Benjamin meets the cosmics. Retrieved from www.law.wisc.edu/.../wolin...benjamin_
meets_the_cosmics.doc
Wolin, R. (2006). The Frankfurt School revisited and other essays on politics and society. New York,
NY: Routledge.
Wolin, R. (2001). Heideggers children: Hannah Arendt, Karl Lwith, Hans Jonas, and Herbert Marcuse.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Wolin, R. (1995). Labyrinths: Explorations in the critical history of ideas. Amherst, MA: University of
Massachusetts Press.
Wolin, R. (2004). The seduction of unreason: The intellectual romance with fascism from Nietzsche to
postmodernism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Wolin, R. (1992). The terms of cultural criticism: The Frankfurt School, existentialism, poststructuralism.
New York, NY: Columbia University Press.
Wolin, R. (1994). Walter Benjamin: An aesthetic of redemption. Berkeley, CA: University of California
Press.
Zilbersheid, U. (2002). The idea of abolition of labor in socialist utopian thought. Utopian Studies, 13,
2142.
214
ABBREVIATIONS*
215
NAME INDEX
217
NAME INDEX
Buber, Martin, xviii, xxii, 12, 13, 48, DuBois, W.E.B., 204
55, 62, 6771, 73, 74, 81, 83, 85, DuBose, Todd, 189
90, 105, 110, 127, 156, 157, 159, Dunayevskaya, Raya, 40, 130, 161,
175, 193 187, 188
Buck-Morss, Susan, 51, 104 Dunham, Katherine, 15, 16
Bucke, Richard Maurice, 61, 133 Dussel, Enrique, 204
Buddha, 175, 186
Bukharin, Nikolai, 56 E
Bush, George W., 198200, 202, 203 Eckhart, Meister, xv, xvii, xxiv, 62, 75,
Butler, Judith, 90, xx, xxiv 85, 86, 108, 123, 179, 184, 189
Einstein, Albert, 69
C Engels, Friedrich, 9, 23, 24, 104
Camara, Dom Helder, 169 Erasmus, Desiderius, 169
Cameron, Ewen, 202 Eyerman, Ron, 41
Cassirer, Ernst, 167
Cavanaugh, William T., 165 F
Chaubiski, Mirosaw, 188 Farr, Arnold, 111
Cohen, Hermann, xvii, xviii, xxii, xxiii, Ferenczi, Sandor, 38
12, 13, 17, 48, 55, 58, 6367, Feuerbach, Ludwig, 83, 180, 188, 203
6973, 75, 7881, 83, 85, 86, Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, xvii, 8, 59, 91,
97, 107, 109, 110, 126, 147, 150, 134, 150, 167, 176
155, 156, 168, 178, 180, 184, Ficino, Marsilio, 169
188, 191, 193, 197 Fiorato, Pierfrancesco, 64, 66, 197
Comte, Auguste, 167, 175 Foucault, Michel, 20, 135
Condorcet, Marie Jean Antoine Nicolas Fourier, Charles, 104, 177
de Caritat, Marquis de, 167 Frank, Jacob, 49, 76, 90, 126, 170
Critchley, Simon, 197 Freire, Paulo, xi, 44, 192
Cusanus, Nicholas (Nicholas of Cusa), Freud, Ana, 39
169 Freud, Sigmund, xxi, xxiv, 11, 12,
Czieskowski, Count August, 109 1519, 2128, 3135, 3739,
42, 44, 45, 57, 125, 148, 164,
D 165, 168, 170, 192
Dahrendorf, Ralf, 152 Friedman, Lawrence, 16
Davis, Angela, 142, 199, 203 Friedman, Milton, 202
Davis, Mike, 42 Fromm (Freeman), Annis, 15
De Mirandola, Pico, 169 Fromm-Reichmann (Reichmann),
Derrida, Jacques, xx, xxiv, 163, 185 Frieda, 1417, 45, 67
Deutscher, Isaac, 53, 57, 58 Fukuyama, Francis, 197, 202
Dewey, John, 116 Funk, Rainer, xiii, xxi, xxiii, 1214,
Dilthey, Wilhelm, 50, 69 16, 17, 19, 35, 40, 45, 67, 69,
Dobson, James, 37 73, 103, 108, 127, 135, 169,
Dostoyevsky, Fyodor, 56, 84, 93 181185, 189, 196
218
NAME INDEX
219
NAME INDEX
K Lefebrve, Henri, 92
Kafka, Franz, 121, 181 Lenin, V.I., 9, 21, 26, 27, 31, 95, 154
Kahn, Herman, 172 Lessing, Gotthold Ephraim, xvii, 49,
Kant, Immanuel, 12, 42, 55, 78, 84, 116 150, 167
Kautsky, Karl, 19, 21, 59, 109 Levine, Bruce, 36
Kayser, Rudolf, 54 Liebknecht, Karl, 58, 74
Kellner, Douglas, 14, 41, 97 Lilla, Mark, 63, 79, 80
Kemper, Werner, 35 Lwenthal, Leo, xviii, 5, 1315, 17, 25,
Kierkegaard, Soren, 84, 91, 93 28, 45, 67, 70, 98, 171
King, Martin Luther, 40, 43 Lwith, Karl, 151, 167, 187
Kirchheimer, Otto, 29 Lwy (Lowy), Michael, xv, xviii, xx,
Kireyevski, Ivan, 109 xxi, xxv, 6770, 73, 78, 80,
Klages, Ludwig, 24, 26, 49, 50, 92, 93, 8284, 9092, 104106, 109,
9597, 100104, 110, 111, 126, 110, 151, 173, 202
156, 160, 200 Lucifer, 52, 85
Klein, Naomi, 174, 201202 Luhman, Niklas, 152
Kleist, Heinrich von, 96, 101103, 106, Lukcs, Georg, xxiii, 18, 30, 43, 4850,
156, 160, 161, 194 61, 81, 82, 84, 8693, 95, 97,
Koch, Richard, 67 99, 104, 105, 107, 108, 110, 134,
Koestler, Arthur, 152 135, 142, 146, 167, 173, 193,
Kojve, Alexandre, 189 194
Kommerell, Max, 103 Lundgren, Svante, 12, 13, 16, 68, 69,
Korsch, Karl, 18, 43, 44, 86 110, 127, xxv
Kracauer, Siegfried, 67 Luria, Isaac, 76
Kraus, Karl, 48, 94, 102, 111, 160, 163 Luther, Martin, 40, 43, 81
Kristeva, Julia, xx, xxv Luxemburg, Rosa, xv, xvii, 9, 48, 55,
Kropotkin, Peter, 74, 175, 188 5759, 74, 8789, 96, 97, 107,
109, 148, 150, 161, 167, 172,
L 173, 191, 193, 198
Lacis, Asja, 105 Lynd, Robert, 8, 31
Landauer, Gustav, xvii, xxii, 9, 50, 55, Lyotard, Jean-Franois, 165
56, 5863, 6671, 74, 81, 86,
107, 110, 111, 150, 157, 159, M
167, 175, 191, 193 MacDonald, Dwight, 8
Landauer, Karl, 17 MacIntyre, Alasdair, 78, 90, 91
Lane, Richard, 154, 173 Maimonides, Moses, 66, 73, 170, 179,
Lask, Emil, 86 188
Lazarsfeld, Paul, 32 Mann, Thomas, 108
Lazier, Benjamin, xx, 51, 52, 7377, Mannheim, Karl, 175
108110, 133 Marcel, Gabriel, xxiii, 115, 116, 119,
Lebovic, Nitzan, xxi, xxv, 24, 50, 69, 120, 134, 135, 141143, 145, 195
9395, 98, 103, 104, 108, 127 Marcion of Sinope, 51, 52
220
NAME INDEX
221
NAME INDEX
Rosenzweig, Franz, xviii, xxii, 13, 45, Stalin, Joseph, xix, 27, 30, 107
48, 52, 55, 67, 69, 74, 7881, 90, Stauffenberg, Claus von, 95
110, 193 Stein, Edith, 90
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 42, 156 Steiner, Rudolf, 52, 95, 126
Stirner, Max, 9, 61
S Strauss, Eduard, 67
Saint-Simon, Claude Henri de Rouvroy, Strauss, Leo, 52, 67
Comte de, xvii, 150, 167, 175 Sullivan, Harry Stack, 10, 34, 36, 187
Sartre, Jean-Paul, 92, 128 Susman, Margarete, 79
Saunders, Frances Stonor, 8, 40 Suzuki, D.T., 192
Scheler, Max, 82
Schiller, Friedrich, 42, 108 T
Schmitt, Carl, 49, 54, 104, 126, 127, Tar, Zoltn, 4, 5, 30, 44
151, 187, 188, 203 Taubes, Jacob, 49, 51, 53, 68, 71, 83,
Scholem, Gershom, xvi, xvi, xvii, xviii, 97, 108, 109, 127, 133, 185
xxi, xxii, xxv, 1315, 17, 45, 48, Teilhard de Chardin, Pierre, 133134
5153, 6769, 7179, 8182, Tertullian (Tertullianus), Quintus
97, 104105, 109110, 126128, Septimius Florens, 52
147, 152, 156, 170, 183, Thomas, Norman, 69
185186, 188, 191, 193194, Thomson, Annette, 36, 43, 46
196 Tillich, Paul, 167, 187
Schnberg, Arnold, 97 Tolstoy, Leo, 56, 63
Schopenhauer, Arthur, 18, 44, 84, 92, Topitsch, Ernst, 108, 181185, 196
93 Toscano, Alberto, 84, 165, 187, 188
Schroyer, Trent, 4, 5 Trotsky, Leon (and Trotskyists), 15, 17,
Schuler, Alfred, 24, 93, 95 21, 53, 5657, 106, 175
Schumpeter, J. A., 167
Schweitzer, Albert, 85, 123 U
Shelley, Mary, 77 Unger, Erich, 54, 109
Shulman, Helene, xxv, 36
Siebert, Rudolf, xxv, xv V
Simmel, Georg, 69, 86 Van der Bruck, Moeller, 151
Simon, Ernst, xviii, 1314, 67, 127 Verne, Jules, 155
Skinner, B.F., 36, 37
Sontheimer, Kurt, 152 W
Sorel, Georges, 54, 105, 128 Wagner, Richard, 51, 94
Spengler, Oswald, 50, 56, 108, 151, 173 Watkins, Mary, xxv, 36
Spinoza, Baruch (Benedict), xvii, 12, Weber, Alfred, 12, 32, 45, 167
52, 54, 57, 92, 105, 108, 123, Weber, Max, xxv, 12, 82, 86, 91, 110
133135, 137, 148, 150, 168, Weil, Simone, 62, 83, 92, 109
179, 182, 188, 189, 195 Wellman, David, 42, 43
Spock, Benjamin, 37 West, Cornel, xx, xxv
222
NAME INDEX
223