Action Knowledge
Action Knowledge
Action Knowledge
Introduction
Should action sciences exist, it is obvious what they would have to study; the
nature of human action, the kind of knowledge that actions generate, the
process of learning to perform different types of action and so forth.
Comparative anthropology, as a discipline, studies and contrasts, where such
contrasts are possible, the different ways in which human beings organize
their lives, think about and experience both themselves and world around
them. A culture is a form of life and, as such, it is a way of going about the
world. One would therefore expect to find a deep and intimate relation
between action sciences on the one hand, and studies of culture on the other. A
perusal of literature, however, shows the fact of the matter to be different.
Different in which way? It is not necessary to speak here about the attempt
of anthropologists to relate both their theoretical and ethnographic work to
theories of action; many anthropologists and few anthropological quasi-schools
have felt and continue to feel the need to integrate theories of human action in
their approaches to the study of society. The same, it would appear, cannot be
said of action theories. As a rough way of establishing the interest that action
theorists show in this matter, let us notice the kind of themes they take up for
investigation; the relation between action and intention, between actions and
events; the nature and properties of efficient and inefficient action, the rational
and irrational action etc. A great deal of familiarity with the literature in this
tradition is not required to observe that neither anthropological theories nor
ethnographic studies play any role in their discussion.
Why is this so? Here is one possible answer; the problems that are taken up
for scrutiny are invariant across cultures and, consequently, there is not much
that anthropology can contribute to this enquiry. This stance is implicitly
assumed by most; perhaps, if called for, they would also defend it explicitly.
There is, however, a second way of looking at this issue; the themes that action
theorists address themselves to are the deep and ground intuitions of one
specific culture, viz. The West. To the members of this culture, it is obvious
that human action, by virtue of being human, exhibits some typical, speciesspecific properties such as being intentional, goal directed, rational or
whatever else that you may want to attribute. Not only is it natural speak
about human action in these terms, but to look at it any other way would be so
creates action-knowledge, are examined in the third section. While at it, some
empirical hypotheses are generated to show the heuristic potential of this
approach. In the two parts that comprise the fourth section, I take up the
problem of comparison: How culture specific is the notion of actionknowledge? I examine one domain that belongs to the realm of human action,
viz., the ethical in the first part. In the second, I compare the notion of actionknowledge with the most familiar notions of knowing how and knowing that.
The problems that arise as a result of such a contrast function as the theme of
reflection in the last section.
As a part of an unconcluded project I am working on, this article merely
expresses some working hypotheses that appear rather productive. As a
project, it has the ambition of wanting to formulate the intuitions of one
culture within the language of an other. As an article, its aim is not to convince
but to persuade. Could it be, I want to ask, that we may fruitfully look at the
issues in a way we are not accustomed to? What would it be like; I want you to
ask yourselves by the end of this article, if cultures could learn to really look at
each other?
What, you may wonder, is problematic about the coexistence of these three
phenomena in any one society? The answer would be evident, if we were to
indulge in a comparison. Contrast the situation sketched above with that of the
West regarding some similar domain, say, that of the ethical. Consider, for
example, the total number of moral principles (or injunctions) in the West
with the amount of literature produced about them. These injunctions, each of
which is formulated and defended as a general principle, do not (probably)
number more than twenty. But the literature about them stretches to infinity.
With respect to India, it would be difficult to make any such claim; it is not
clear whether the 'injunctions' are general principles or not; one does not
know how many injunctions exist and, as I said, there is hardly any justificatory
literature.
What are we to make of this? Here are two possible responses from
among many:
(a) Because Indians have no comparable moral theories (comparable, that is, to
those of the West) they really have no notion of good and bad. Therefore,
they are immoral. Not many would say it in quite this fashion, even though
many still think so. This does not merit an answer.
(b) They are arrested at a primitive stage of moral development, even if they
have stumbled upon some fundamental moral principles. This is a selfdefeating response: if a culture has stumbled upon such principles and every
individual from each generation over thousands of years continues to stumble
upon it, moral practice does not require to be supported by ethical theories. By
the same token, the existence of theoretical treatises about moral practices in
a culture is hardly indicative of its maturity.
It is only by leaving such or similar responses aside that we are better able
to formulate the issue that a culture like India raises. Let us do so by looking at
some facts. The Indian caste appears to have survived (in whatever form, and
through whatever mechanisms) many fundamental upheavals: through
challenges posed by internal movements (like Buddhism etc.) to externally
imposed economico-political reorganizations (Islamic invasion, British
colonialism and subsequent integration into a world capitalist system). That is
to say, caste system appears to have adapted itself to changing environments
over the course of the centuries. This is a statement that one could make
without having to prejudge the desirability or otherwise of such an
organization.
Clearly, the minimum that is required for such an adaptive social
organization is that some kind of knowledge present in society and that it be
available to its members. Knowledge must be present, because the actions that
reproduce a way of living are knowledgeable actions and cannot be either
random or purely explanatory ones. Furthermore, because these actions
socialized, is a teaching process from the point of view of those responsible for
socializing that organism. The teachers, thus, draw upon the resources of the
culture to which they belong.
Consequently, the methods of teaching an organism will teach only to the
extent they dovetail with the process of learning. Because we, as human
beings, are not genetically determined to learn in any one particular way, it
could be safely held that the teaching processes give form to the way an
organism learns about environment. That is, the way one learns is non-trivially
dependent upon one's culture. We may, therefore, accept the idea that not only
the what but also how of learning is connected to the culture of an organisms
group. All of the above claims appear extremely reasonable. As we shall soon
see, it also appears possible to generate a culture-specific notion of learning,
which is able to shed light on a diverse set of phenomena that are
characteristic to a culture.
Several elements are of direct relevance to the way a culture teaches, and
to the way its members learn: the experience of self and others; the
experience of body and space; etc. Unable as I am to discuss any of these, I
shall restrict myself to just one element from the set, viz., the experience of
order.
are both descriptions of the same process but from two different points of
view; each generation preserves its experience of order by structuring the
experience of the next. A way of preserving a sense of order can structure an
experience of order, it appears to me, if it itself models or represents or
explicates that very order whose experience it is supposed to structure. In
other words, that which structures the experience of Cosmos as an order must
itself, in some way or another, exhibit or express the order of the Cosmos. I call
such a prototype of order, the primary root model of order. What distinguishes
cultures from one another, under this construal, would be the nature of their
paradigms of order.
My suggestion is that religion has been the paradigm of order for the
western culture. According to the account given above, it would mean that
religion both structures the experience of the universe and is itself an
instance of that order. Now, whatever religion might be, it is without doubt
true (If, that is, Judaism, Christianity and Islam are what religions are) that it is
explanatory. That means to say, the structure and the strategy of religious
explanations both structures and sustains an experience of order that that
universe is. Because the finer and subtler points about the nature of religious
explanations are not relevant for this paper, let me crudely outline the three
basic phases which culminate in the sense of order that I consider typical for, if
not unique to, the West.
There is the first phase, I suppose, of a pre-religious experience of the
world. In this phase, there is an experiencing of the constancy and regularity
of the universe. The second phase denies this experience of order and draws
the attention to the chaos the world actually is. In the third phase, there is a
discovery of a deeper and underlying order beneath the chaos of the
phenomenal world. What happens in this process is that the first experience,
the naive experience of order, is totally bracketed away, leaving behind only
the chaos that the phenomena experience is supposed to be until the deeper
order is discovered. The obviousness and the all pervasiveness of this attitude
is expressed in the way child development was conceived until recently, and in
the way the emergence of mythical and magical thinking is accounted for. A
child's world, it was surmised, is a bloomin, buzzin confusion until it learns
to conceptualize, categorize and speak. And we are told that our ancestors
attempted to find explanations for natural phenomena because they were
confronted by a chaotic world i.e. by the occurrence of random events. Even
the arguments for the existence of God took the form of arguments from
design in the hands of the medieval naturalists and theologians. The
fundamental attitude, in other words, is that if there are no laws or
principles underlying an experiential world, such a world will have to be a
chaotic and unordered world.
Consider now another culture, where such or similar paradigms of order do
not exist. To its members the above suggestion would appear strange: neither
chaos nor deeper laws are experiential units to this culture. The universe is
experienced as an order: neither a creator nor His design requires to be
invoked as the reason for this order. Explanations may try to say what the
order consists of; but the truth or otherwise of these explanations arc
irrelevant to the fact that the universe is an order. That is to say, the world
does not embody or express an order (or anything else): to speak of the world,
to experience it, is to experience order. For this to be true, it would require
that such a culture have a root or primary model of order which is not
explanatory in nature. Nevertheless, it must be ordered and that order must be
visible on the surface. The truth or falsity of the many different explanations
(interpretations would, perhaps, be a better word in this context) must be
irrelevant to answering the question whether such a root model is an order.
That is to say, in such a culture, the root or primary model of order must be
pre-linguistic (or non-linguistic) in nature. A set of actions, with a beginning
and an end (neither of which need be an absolute), following each other
contiguously in time would constitute such an order. India is one each culture,
I want to claim, and its paradigm of order is not religion but something else.
Call it, for the sake of convenience, Ritual.
Under this construal, Religion and Ritual are two fundamental paradigms of
order or two fundamental ways of structuring the experience of the universe.
This does not require that the other mode (ritual for one, religion for the other)
is absent in either of the two cultures: they exist, but as subordinate moments
and hence as almost unrecognizable counterparts. A religious ritual is as
different from Ritual as ritualistic religions are from Religion. We shall have an
opportunity to relive this problem again, but in another form later.
Given this, the problem that occupies the intellectual energies of one
culture is: given that the universe is an order, how to perform actions that
better fit the order? In an another, it takes a different form: What is the nature
of the order such that one may perform the action that require to be
performed? How, asks one culture, to perform actions and continue to improve
them such that the order does not disintegrate? In an another, the order is not
visible: it is a design; a law that lies hidden beneath. Knowledge of this
order would allow one to decide about the right action that requires to be
performed in indefinitely many contexts. These two paradigms of order, that
distinguish these two cultures, shed some light on the way the problem of
action is treated: to know one has to act in one culture; to act one has to know
in another.
My suggestion is that these paradigms of order, in their turn, enable the
emergence of culturally dominant modes of learning. In a culture like India,
this leads to a learning process whose main focus it is to develop the ability of
performing and improving actions. The knowledge that the members of such a
culture have is what I shall call action-knowledge. In the next two sections, I
shall go a bit deeper both into the kind of knowledge that action-knowledge is
and into the nature of learning process required to acquire such a knowledge.
Contrast and comparison with the West will be attempted subsequently.
Take, for instance, a group performing some ritual or the other, say, a rain
ritual. When asked about the significance of their actions, one gets to hear a
story. Such a story depicts a set of events which includes the performing of the
rain ritual in conjunction with some other events. Now it is not the case that
causal efficacy is attributed to the performance of such a ritual. That is, the
members of the group do not believe that their singing and chanting in some
specified fashion and the pouring of ghee into the fire altar cause the rains to
come. They are not justifying this belief by telling a story. What then are they
doing?
Because stories are models of a situation, as models they are neither true
nor false; it is only in models that statements come out as true or false. When
the group performs such a ritual and no rains come, all that can be said about
the story is that it is not a model for such a situation. If, on the other hand, we
look at the way the members of the group experience the situation, then quite
a lot could be explicated. When the ritual is performed and the rains do not
come, the group experiences this situation as something having gone wrong
somewhere. When the rains do come, it is experienced as everything is as it
should be. What are these experiences signalling?
Recollect, if you will, the suggestion I made earlier about experiencing the
world as an order. The truth or falsity of the explanations about the nature of
the order, I said, is irrelevant to the experience that the world is an order.
There is a question embedded in that suggestion that can be answered now: In
any such culture (including the Indian culture that I am talking about), at any
moment of time, hypotheses float around which purport to explain the order of
the universe: some or other-account of the pattern that ones culture and the
cosmos exhibit, and some explanation of the role of individual actions with
respect to sustaining or disrupting that order. Many such explanations have
come and gone: Why does the sense of order not follow suit?
This is best answered, if we ask how such cultures manage to sustain this
feeling in the absence of knowledge about the pattern. What mechanisms
preserve the sense of order without requiring the presence of knowledge about
the order, which the culture and cosmos exhibit? One such mechanism
admirably suited for the job is the stories and legends that a culture possesses.
Stories preserve patterns without saying what these patterns are. They
depict partial aspects of an order without specifying what the order consists of.
Performing the ritual, the coming of rains, etc., is a sequence of events
described in a story without specifying a relation between them. The
experience of something having gone wrong somewhere and that of
everything is as it should be are expressions of disturbance/appropriateness
accordingly as whether the story is not/is a model of the situation. Stories do
not explain anything because they do not model relations (causal or otherwise)
between events. In very simple terms, they just model a set of affairs.
What I have so far said about the stories allows roe to propose the following
idea: the representational aspect of stories is what makes them continuous
with other representational products known to us like philosophy, scientific
theories, etc. But, of course, there are also differences between them: whereas
theories claim to explain, stories make no such claim. Theories may justify
some belief that you have, stories do not. Nevertheless, stories are pedagogical
instruments in so far as they have the representational (or cognitive)
property. Therefore, I will now make a mild claim, which I hope to strengthen
later on in this article, that stories embody some kind of knowledge. Or,
slightly differently, they are units of learning.
What kind of knowledge is it that these stories embody? And in which kind
of a learning process are they its units? In order to begin answering this
question, I need to look at the second property of the stories as well.
Apart from exhibiting a cognitive, property, stories possess a practical one too.
By describing a way of going about the world, they are a way of going about
the world. They are models in a practical sense i.e. they can be emulated.
Stories are pedagogical instruments par excellence because of this additional
property. But how can stories leach us to do anything? How can they be
instructive, i.e. instruct us to do anything at all? How can a description of a
way of going about in the world be itself a way of going about in the world?
As stories, they do not come with any explicit morals attached: they do not,
for example, say that the moral of this story is... They are not structured as
manuals for practical action either: do X in order to achieve Y. If they can
teach, then it is because of the way learning occurs in India. Consequently, the
question becomes: What kind of a learning activity is required, if stories are
how one learns? My answer is that it is mimetic learning. As stories, they are
a set of propositions. What they depict are actions. Between these actions and
those of one's own, what obtains is a practical relation of mimesis. Only as
such can stories function as instructions for actions.
Stories combine this double function: they are theoretical and practical at
the same time. They are not straight forward instructions; nor are they only
representational. They entertain too: but not the way the The Little Red
both the religious and political authorities. Sociologists have often puzzled
over the fact that in India, religion, commerce, politics and education did
not fuse, for any length of time, into one centralized authority. I suggest to you
that the way learning process occurs in India might well begin to shed light on
this issue.
The second point that I want to make regards the public or social process of
mimesis. Both the process of learning and the knowledge that is acquired
presuppose social interaction, instead of arguing for it in the abstract, let me
illustrate by referring to, say, the moral domain once again. To be moral, in the
West, is to follow some or other moral principle. The relation is between an
individual, isolated subject and some injunction or the other. How the
community in which such an individual finds himself is? Is a question of no
moral significance to his moral behavior? By contrast, in a culture dominated
by mimesis (like India) the relation is between individuals (be they the really
existing community or the fictitious individuals portrayed in the stories). A
moral individual, in other words, presupposes a moral community.
Reformulated in different terms, the general point is this: Because mimetic
learning has a public dimension, epistemic problems will have to refer to the
community of learning subjects.
I would like to suggest that the activity performed at the old peoples home
functioned as an exemplar for you: that is, it functioned as a generative action.
This, in the first place, is what an exemplar is: it creates new, original actions.
If you are willing to accept this suggestion, I should now like to elaborate
further on this point.
There are two ways in which you could understand the statement made
above. You could say that the linguistic description of the action gave you a
new idea about the action that you can execute. But, there is also a second way
of construing the statement, which is what I am proposing. I am not saying
that the activity performed at the old peoples home gave you an idea of
another action that you could perform in your situation. No. You must read me
literally: that persons action generated a new action; you are now able to
perform a new action, something that you could not do before. While you may
be able to describe the activity, which you intend to perform, this
description/conception of the action is parasitic upon the ability to execute it.
In exactly the same way someones idea/thought/theory can create/generate
new idea/thought/theory in your head, someone's action, as an exemplar,
creates a new action. You may complain that this is spooky. Fair enough. But, I
put to you, it is no more spooky than the fact that ideas can give birth to new
ideas. Actions give birth to new and original actions in the way ideas create
novel ideas.
You have now, in other words, acquired action-knowledge. That is, when
described from your point of view, your ability to produce a new action now is
what it means to speak of you having acquired action-knowledge. In this case,
the exemplar happened to be a linguistic description of someones action.
Quite obviously, it need not be so in all cases. You may see someone doing
something, and that enables you to execute a new action as well. In both cases,
the learning process is the same: learning through an exemplar or mimetic
learning. As a consequence, it must be clear that mimesis, as a learning
process, is creative and dynamic.
Consider, now, the second property of action-knowledge. In our case, the
exemplar happened to be a very specific action undertaken by, a very specific
individual in a very specific context. And yet, it was able to create in you,
another specific individual in a totally different context, the ability to execute
an entirely different action. All exemplars are always context bound. But, they
are generative in totally different contexts. Or, put even more clearly, it is
precisely the context dependence of an action that makes it fertile in different
contexts.
Our general intuition regarding the nature of guidelines or decision
principles is that the more general, abstract and context independent they are,
the more useful and true they are. In fact, this is a demand that we make upon
all knowledge-claims: a moral principle, a. legal statute is acceptable if and
only if it enables you to choose and execute the right action in all/most
contexts. For that to happen, a moral principle requires to be context free.
However, for action-knowledge it appears to go the other way: Inter-contextual
applicability is directly proportional to contextual embeddedness and inversely
to context insensitivity and generality.
Consider, now, the third property of action-knowledge. Even though you
knew what it is that you wanted to achieve, the knowledge of this goal,
together with the knowledge about your present state, did not help you in
producing a new action. Also, your learning through the exemplar occurred
when you were not aware that you were learning. Even though each of these
two points enables me to argue the point independently, their conjunction
gives it a greater force: your ability to execute a new action is indifferent to
the presence or absence of goals. Or action-knowledge is not goal dependent.
One of the basic beliefs in the Western tradition is that human action is goal
oriented action, and that this constitutes an intrinsic property of human
actions. It I am right, just the opposite is true: intrinsically, human action is
goal-less. This does not, quite obviously, prevent you from finding a goal for an
action when you have action-knowledge. But mimesis, as a sub-intentional
learning that involves the ability to execute actions, does not require the
presence of goals. Practical activity, practical knowledge - as species of
knowledge - is not intentional and it is not goal-directed.
Consider the fourth and final property of action-knowledge. Here, I will be
brief because to argue the case would require bringing in other considerations
extraneous to the paper. The situation you were in was one where you did not
know what to do. It is not as though you had difficulty in choosing between the
alternatives that were open to you. It is not even the case, I would like to
suggest, that you chose between the action that you can now execute and
those action-alternatives that existed previously. Rather, acquiring the ability
of executing a new action was the same as knowing what to do.
In slightly more general terms, what I am driving at is this. Within the
western tradition, the dominant approach is to treat epistemic problems in
decision-theoretic terms or as decision problems. I believe that this is not the
case with respect to practical knowledge: epistemic problems regarding
action-knowledge ore not decision problems, but learning problems. Problems
of social interaction and social organization, under this construal, are problems
of learning.
By saying this, I do not deny that it is possible to describe them as decision
problems. (Why it is possible to do so is a theme I reflect upon in the last
section.). Besides, I am aware, that social sciences are increasingly turning
towards game theory and choice theories in their attempts to understand
social interactions.
learning process that is really not culture specific? The answers to these
questions are complex. In what follows, I merely try to take the first step in
exploring them.
At first sight, it would appear that mimesis is omnipresent in the West as
well. Children learn through imitation; an adult learns to eat with chopsticks or
learns to dance through imitative actions; an academic imitates his more
successful colleagues by trying to publish as many articles as he possibly can
etc. The list, it seems, is quite huge.
Not quite. Instead of arguing for the details, let me show what I take to be
the case in two ways. You would be willing to accept, I suppose, the
.suggestion that the moral domain is a domain of human actions. Let us,
therefore, look briefly at the presence or absence of exemplars in this domain
for the West. After having done this, let us see what the relationship is between
action-knowledge on the one hand, and the forms of knowledge theorized
about in the West on the other.
though this appears a decisive argument, it could be easily met thus: what it
means to speak of a skilled chess player, a skilled surgeon or a skilled driver is
precisely their ability to improvise in new situations and come up with new
actions. After all, skill is not an execution of drilled actions, even if some kind
of drill is required to acquire some skill.
However, it appears to me, that the new action that a skilled practitioner
can execute arises by a combination of actions, which he had already executed.
That is to say, it is like generating a new word out of an existing repertoire of
words. Secondly, even more importantly, the skill that one has in combining
familiar actions to produce new actions is not sufficient, in at least some
circumstances, to improvise. A skilled mountaineer stuck on the mountain
absently watching a monkey move from place to place is able to do something
as a result of taking the actions of the monkey as an exemplar. Prior to this
learning episode, there was an action that he could not generate out of the
repertoire of actions he had. If he could have, he would have not been stuck in
the first place. To be sure, he needed his skills in order to learn what he
learned from the monkey's movement: you and I watching the same monkey's
action would not be able to what the skilled mountaineer did. But, this is no
problem: what we can learn depends to a very great extent upon what we have
already learned. That one and the same kind of learning process can occur
both within the framework of exercising a skilled activity and elsewhere (that
does not involve an exercise of skill) suggest very strongly that learning
through exemplars cannot be seen as a skill to identify and use an exemplar.
There is a third reason, purely linguistic in nature, that suggests that
mimetic learning cannot be identified with knowing how. In the statement
skill to learn through exemplars, the word skill can be replaced by the word
learning without any obvious loss of meaning. This suggests that skill is
coextensive with learning. However, the same substitution does not work
elsewhere as far as I can see: He is a skilled tennis player, He is a skilled
surgeon, He is a skilled problem solver etc., would lose some of their
intended meaning if learning replaced skill everywhere. Consequently, we
could not be using skill with the connotations usually attached to it, when we
say the skill to learn through exemplars. Fourthly and finally, the knowing
how in its normal usage picks out a cluster of actions that are related to each
other. To do so with respect to learning through exemplars, it appears to me,
would not come easily and with the same degree of familiarity.
Even though these are some of the reasons for wanting to distinguish
between a learning process that is indifferent to what is learned and a skill
that is not so, none of them, as I see the situation, are decisive. With suitable
modifications, it is possible to absorb action-knowledge into the relatively more
familiar knowing how.
Why, you may wonder, is it important? The answer would become obvious
when we look into the way action-knowledge could be absorbed into
propositional knowledge.